Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2007 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/christianviewofgOOorrjrich THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF GOD AND THE WORLD. MORRISON AND GIBB, PRINTERS, EDINBURGH. THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF GOD^ AND THE WORLD AS CENTRING IN THE INCARNATION BEING THE KEBE LECTURES FOE 1890-91. By JAMES ORR, D.D., PBOFESSOH OK CHURCH HISTORY IN THE UNITED PRESBYTERIAN COLLEGE, EDINBURGH. For of Hi III, and throiujh Him, and unto Him, art all things. To Hint he the glory for ever. Arae/n." —l^m. xi. 36, i^ NEW YORK: ANSON I). F. RANDOLPH AND CO. 1893. Oj Gl^^<* THE KERE LECTURESHIP. The " Kere Lectukeship " was founded by the Trustees of the late Miss Joan Kerr, of Sanquhar, under her Deed of Settlement, and formally adopted by the United Presbyterian Synod in May 1886. In the following year. May 1887, the provisions and conditions of the Lectureship, as finally adjusted, were adopted by the Synod, and embodied in a Memorandum, printed in the Appendix to the Synod Minutes, p. 489. From these the following excerpts are here given : — "II. The amount to be invested shall be £3000. III. The object of the Lectureship is the promotion of the study of Scientific Theology in the United Presbyterian Church. The Lectures shall be upon some such subjects as the following, viz. : — A. Historic Theology — (1) Biblical Theology, (2) History of Doctrine, (3) Patristics, with special reference to the significance and authority of the first three centuries. B. Systematic Theology — (1) Chris- tian Doctrine — (a) Philosophy of Religion, (6) Comparative Theology, (c) Anthropology, (d) Christology, (e) Soteriology, (/) Eschatology ; (2) Christian Ethics— (a) Doctrine of Sin, (b) Individual and Social Ethics, (c) The Sacra- ments, {d) The place of art in religious life and w'orship. . . . Farther, the Committee of Selection shall from time to time, as they think fit, appoint as the subject of the Lectures any important Phases of Modern Religious Thought, or Scientific Theories in their bearing upon Evangelical Theology. The Committee may also appoint a subject connected with the practical work of the Ministry as subject of Lecture, but in no case shall this be admissible more than once in every five appointments. IV. The appointments to this Lecture- ship shall be made in the first instance from among the Licentiates or Ministers of the United Presbyterian Church of Scotland, of whom no one shall be eligible, who, when the appointment falls to be made, shall have been licensed for more than twenty-five years, and who is not a graduate of a British University, preferential regard being had to those who have for some time been connected with a Continental University. V. Appointments not subject to the conditions in Section IV. may also from time to time, at the discretion of the Committee, be made from among eminent members of the Ministry of any of the Nonconformist Churches of Great Britain and Ireland, America, and the Colonies, or of the Protestant Evangelical Churches of the Continent. VI. The Lecturer shall hold the appointment for three years. VIII. The Lectures shall be published at the Lecturer's own expense within one year after their delivery. IX. The Lectures shall be delivered to the Students of the United Presbyterian Hall. XII. The public shall be admitted to the Lectures." 871518 PEEFACE These Lectures, the first on the Kerr Foundation, are published in fulfilment of the conditions of the Trust under which they were delivered. Their publication has been delayed owing to the author's appointment to the Chair of Church History in the Theological College of the United Presbyterian Church, at the Synod of May, 1891. They have now been made ready for the press under the burden of labour and anxiety connected with the preparation of a second winter's course. This may excuse the minor over- sights which, in handling so large a mass of material, must inevitably occur. The Lectures are printed substantially as delivered in the spring of 1891 — the chief exception being that portions of the Lectures which had to be omitted in the spoken delivery, through the limits of time, are here restored in their proper connection. Material which could not conveniently be incor- porated in the Lectures has been wrought up into Appendices and Notes. The latter are designed to furnish, not simply references to authorities, but illustrations, corroborations, and what may be termed generally " assonances " of thought, drawn from a wide range of literature, which it is hoped will aid the reader who is disposed to pursue his study of the subject further, by guiding him to the best sources of knowledge. Since the Lectures were delivered, important books have appeared, both in this country and on the con- tinent, dealing with parts or aspects of the field here traversed, viii PREFACE. such, e.g. among English works, as Mr. Gore's valuable Bampton Lectures on The Incarnation, Principal Chapman's Pre-organic Evolution, Mr. Kennedy's Donnellan Lectures on Natural Theology and Modern Thought. Occasional references to these and some other works are likewise included in the Notes. The author's best thanks are due to the Eev. Professor Johnstone, D.D., of the United Presbyterian College, and to the Eev. Thomas Kennedy, D.D., Clerk of Synod, for their kind assistance in the revision of the proofs. Edinburgh, February, 1893. CONTENTS LECTUKE I. THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD IN GENERAL. Inteoductory- The term *' "Weltanschauung Need of comprehensive treatment, View of Christianity in the Lectures, . The "Weltanschauung" in history — Kant, etc., '- Causes of general views of the world, . Fondness of the age for general theories, / Relation of Christianity to world-theories, The Christian and " modern " views of the world, / The question of the supernatural in Christianity, Relation of Christianity to other systems not one of pure negation The Christian view of the world based on that of the Old Testament — uniqueness of the latter, .... General drift and scope of the Lectures, Objections in limine : — L From theology of feeling, .... Examination of sentimental theory — -Religion involves ideas, Religion not indifferent to the character of its ideas, / Religion implies belief in an objective counterpart to its ideas : -Esthetic views of religion, ... Need and room for a religion which can give us true know ledge of God, ...... Impossibility of extruding doctrine from Christianity, Objection to doctrine from the spirituality of Christianity, Objection to doctrine from the side of Christian positivism. The theology of Schleiermacher, Objection to doctrine drawn from progress in theology. 3 4 4 5 7, 8 9 10 11 12 15 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 28 CONTENTS. PAGE II. From the Ritschlian distinction of a "religious" and a "theo- retic " view of the world, . . . . . .29 Relative justification of this distinction, . . . .31 Error of the Ritschlian View— Impossibility of sundering faith and reason, . . . . . . .33 Religion itself has in it the impulse to theoretic knowledge, . 34 APPENDICES TO LECTURE I. Appendix I. SKETCH OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. Sketch of the Christian View, .... 37 Appendix II. IDEA OF THE "WELTANSCHAUUNG. Literature on the subject, ...... A. Baur : — Prevalence of the term, . . . . . Striving of the age after general views. The " Weltanschauung " a unity of natural and moral, . Relation of theoretic and practical motive, Views which recognise the practical motive alone — the Ritschlian school, ....... Ritschl on the origin of the " Weltanschauung," Hermann on the same, ..... Kaftan on the same, ...... 42 42 43 43 44 45 45 46 47 LECTURE 11. THE CHRISTIAN VIEW AND ITS ALTERNATIVES. Introductory — Magnitude of the assumption in the Christian view, . . .51 Rejection of the doctrine of the Incarnation by the "modern" mind, ........ 51 X^entral place of Christ's Person in His religion, . . .53 Differing estimates of the Person of Christ — methods of settlement, . 54 Method of this Lecture — appeal to history ; logical movement in history, ........ 55 Advantages of this method, . . . . . .56 CONTENTS. xi I. History a series of alternatives— the downioard movement, 1. First alternative — A Divine Christ or hiimanitarianism, Arianism, ..... Socinianism and the older Unitarianism, Christology of the school of Schleiermacher, New wave of mediating theology in the school of Ritschl The verdict of history against intermediate views, 2. Second alternative — A Divine Christ or Agnosticism, The weakness of Deism, .... Need of a living Theism, which has its correlate in Revelation, Insecurity of a Theism cut off from Christ— Rathboue Greg etc., ...... No logical resting-place short of Agnosticism, . 3. Third alternative — A Divine Christ or Pessimism, Depressing influence of Agnosticism ; cuts the nerve of rational belief in progress, ..... Rise of great Pessimistic systems. Pessimism in our literature — sadness of the sceptical spirit; II. The upward movement from Pessimism to Christ, Unsatisfactoriness of Pessimism as a theory of existence — it works back to Theism, ...... The dialectic of Pessimism, .... Schopenhauer and Hartmann, .... "Will" and "Idea" — their relation, Hartmann's "Unconscious" — attributes to it will, wisdom foresight, etc., ...... The "Unconscious" becomes a "Supra-conscious," -— ^ Moral attributes ascribed to it, . Transition in Karl Peters to explicit Theism, The alternative of Pantheism — its degradation to Materialism (Strauss, Feuerbach), .... The nobler movement— elevation to Theism, Fichte and Schelling, .... The Hegelian development, British Neo-Hegelianism — T. H. Green, ..... Prof. Seth and Theism, Theism impels to belief in Revelation^ Recognition in modern systems of idea of Revelation, Modern theory of Revelation — natural and supernatural different sides of the same process. Inadequacy of this theory ; its end does not correspond with its beginning, ..... The God of Jesus has direct access to the soul . Xll CONTENTS. II. The upward movement from Pessimism to Christ {continued) — Theism impels to belief in Eevelation {continued) — Martineau and Pfleiderer, .... Outcome of this theory — expectation of special Revelation, Vocation of Israel ; Christ the highest Revealer, Return to positive Revelation in school of Ritschl, Summary — Theism can only secure itself through belief in Christ, 77 78 79 79 80 Appendix to Lecture II. THE PESSIMISM OF SCEPTICISM. The prevalence of Pessimism, . 81 The Pessimism of Scepticism, ■ 81 Illustrations — Voltaire, 81 Goethe, . 82 Renan, 82 Professor Seeley, . 83 " Physicus " (in Candid Examination of Theism), . 83 Theodore Jouffroy, . . 84 Professor Huxley, . 85 Laveleye on The Future of Religion, 86 Madame Ackermann, . 86 F. "W. H. Myers on The Disenchantment of France, 87 J. Sully, • 87 LECTURE III. THE THEISTIC POSTULA TE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. Introductoey — Christianity a theistic system, ..... Only three monotheistic religions, .... Theism involves a supernatural view of the world, Froude and Carlyle, ...... The strength of Christian Theism is its connection with Revelation Christ's teaching embraces the affirmations of a complete Theism, The absoluteness of God, ..... The natural attributes, ..... The moral attributes, ...... The Divine Fatherhood, ..... This first postulate of the Christian view— how related to modern thought? ........ 91 91 92 93 93 94 94 94 95 96 CONTENTS. xiii PAGE I. The negation of the Christian view, . . . . .96 The Agnostic negation — why so regarded ? . . . .96 1. It negates the Christian view of God as self-revealing, . 97 2. The denial of evidence of God's existence tantamount to denial of His existence, . . . . .98 Mr. Spencer's admission of the Ultimate Reality or Power ; contra- dictions of his view, . . . . . .98 The " Inscrutable Power " of Mr. Spencer, not, after all, unknow- able, ........ 100 Development of the system by Mr. Fiske into Theism, . .102 The incomprehensibility of God recognised by Scripture and theology, . . . . . . . .102 The Agnostic Icnows that God cannot reveal Himself in relation, . 103 II. Positive evidence for the Christian view, .... 104 1. Concessions of the evolutionary philosophy, . . . 105 (1) Monotheism alone tenable, . . . .105 (2) The Power which works in the universe is the source of a rational order, . . . . .106 (3) It is the source also of a moral order, . . . 108 The term "Personal" as applied to God, . . . Ill 2. The theoretic ''proofs" for the existence of God — how far valid? . . . . . . .112 Meaning of ** proof" as applied to the Divine existence, . 113 (1) The cosmological argument, . . . .114 The world not the necessary Being shown — i. From the contingency of its existence, . . 115 ii. From the dependency of its parts, . .115 iii. From its temporal succession of effects. — Need for a First Cause, . . . .115 Objection to this argument : it does not show what the necessary Being is, . . . .116 The religious experience corresponding to this proof — the consciousness of absolute dependence, . .116 (2) The teleological or design argument, . . .117 Kant's criticism, . . . . .117 Argument against design from evolution, . .118 Evolution probable — what it implies, . . .119 Two views of evolution : criticism, . . .119 What the facts of evolution point to, . . .121 Wider form of this argument (order, plan, law, etc.), . . . . . .122 (3) The ontological argument, . . . .123 The Anselmic form, and Kant's criticism, . .123 XIV CONTENTS, II. Positive evidence for the Christian view {continiitd) — (3) The ontological argument {continued) — New form of this argument ; thought the necessary prins of existence, . . . . .124 "Rational Realism," . . . . .126 '""""^--The religious experience corresponding to the teleo- logical and ontological arguments — sense of the Divine in nature, . . . . .127 How is this sense of the Divine to be explained ? . 128 III. The moral argument — contrast with theoretic proofs, . . 129 ... Kant's statement of this argument, ..... 129 God a postulate of the "practical reason," . . . . 130 Moral law, moral principles, and ethical ideal, point back to an eternal ground, . . . . . . .131 Religious experience corresponding to the moral proof, . .132 Conclusion, . . . . . . . . 132 Appendix to Lecture III. GOD AS RELIGIOUS POSTULATE. God as a postulate of the soul, .... What is demanded in a theory of religion, . Definition of religion, ..... 1. The soul, as personal, demands a personal object, . 2. The soul, as thinking spirit, demands an infinite object, 3. The soul, as ethical, demands an ethical object, 4. The soul, as intelligence, demands a knowable object, 134 134 135 135 135 136 137 LECTUKE IV. THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD IN REGARD TO NATURE AND 31 AN. Introductory — Second postulate of the Christian view : man made in the image of God, 141 The kinship of God and man implied in every Christian doc- trine, ........ 141 Specially implied in the Incarnation, . . . . .143 The doctrine of man closely linked with the doctrine of nature, , 143 CONTENTS. XV I. The natural basis — tlie doctrine of creation, . Practical significance of this doctrine, The consonance of this doctrine with reason : three oppositions— 1. The opposition of Dualism (Martineau, Mill), etc., , 2. The opposition of Pantheism : logical derivation of the universe (Spinoza, Hegel, etc.), . 3. The opposition of Atheism : self- existence and eternity of the world, ..... Evidences of a beginning — (1) Primordial elements, .... (2) Evolution involves a beginning in time, (3) Breaks in the chain of development (Wallace, etc.] Difficulties of the doctrine of creation in time, Proposed solutions of these difficulties — (1) Theory of eternal creation, (2) Denial of the existence of time to God, (3) Solution to be sought in the right adjustment of the relations of time to eternity. The motive and end of creation (Kant, Lotze, etc.). PAGE 144 144 146 147 149 149 150 151 152 153 153 155 155 II. The nature of man, and his place in creation : man the final cause of the world, ........ 157 Agreement of Scripture and science on this point, . . . 158 Qualification of this position : man not the hoU end, . .159 Man the link between the natural and the spiritual : his body the link with nature, ....... 160 The spiritual nature of man : Biblical doctrine, . . .161 Man as bearing the image of God — 1. His rational image, ...... 164 ^^^.^^ 2. His moral image — (1) the power of moral knowledge, (2) the power of moral freedom, (3) the possession of moral affections, . . . . . . .164 3. His image in sovereignty, ..... 166 The potential infinitude of man's nature : a shadow of God's, . 166 ^^.^ The Christian view opposed to Materialism : materialistic tendency of modern science, . . . . . .167 Materialism and consciousness — 1. Grosser form of Materialism : mind and brain identified (Moleschott, Vogt, etc.), . . . .168 Rejection of this view by modern scientific writers, . 168 2. Newer form of Materialism — Monism (Strauss, Haeckel, etc.), 169 Use of materialistic terminology by British scientists, . 170 Ambiguity of the term " matter " in Tyndall, etc., . 173 xvi CONTENTS. PAGE II. The nature of man, and his place in creation {continued) — ^ The materialistic theory breaks down in three respects — 1. Inconsistency with " conservation of energy," . 172 2. Contrast of the two sets of phenomena in the laws of their succession, . . . . .173 3. Irreconcilability with self-consciousness and moral freedom, ...... 175 Ultimate refutation of Materialism : matter itself needs thought to explain it, . . . . . . . 176 III. Man as made in the image of God, constituted for immortality : Biblical aspect postponed, . . . . .177 Voice of nature on this subject, . . . . .177 Modern rejection of doctrine of a future life, . . .177 Scientific plea for this rejection ; its untenableness, . .179 Disposition on part of believers in Eevelation to minimise the natural evidence for immortality, . . . . .180 If man constituted for immortality, the fact must show itself in his nature and capacities, . . . . . .180 1. Universal prevalence of belief in a future state. Spencer's theory ; its inadequacy, . . . . .181 2. Rational grounds for this belief : nature of evidence, . 183 (1) The scale of man's nature too great for his present scene of existence, . . . . .184 (2) Immortality involved in the view of life as moral discipline, . . . . . .186 (3) Immortality the solution of the enigmas of life ; its incompleteness, inequities, etc., . . 186 (4) Only under the influence of this hope do the human faculties find their highest scope and play (J. S. Mill), 187 Conclusion, . . . . . . . .188 LECTURE Y. THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW IN REGARD TO THE SIN AND DISORDER OF THE WORLD. Introductory — Third postulate of the Christian view — the sin and disorder of the world, ....... The problem of natural and moral evil, — - Christianity does not create this problem, but helps to solve it, T^atural evil implicated with moral evil. The problem exists only for Theism, .... 193 193 194 194 194 CONTENTS. xvii PAOB I. The problem of moral evil : conflict of Christian and modern views on this subject, ....... 195 Respects in which the modern view comes to the support of the Christian view — 1. Stronger recognition of the universal prevalence of evil, . 195 2. Abandonment of shallow views of the inherent goodness of human nature, . . . . . .196 3. Recognition of the organic j)rinciple in human life : Heredity, 198 Modern view and the Ritschlian denial of original sin, . .199 Fundamental difference between the Christian and the modern view, ........ 200 The Christian idea of sin as that which absolutely ought not to be : its presuppositions, ...... 200 Sin as revolt from God, and setting up of false independence, . 201 Effects of sin : subversion of true relation of natural and spiritual, 201 Verification of the Christian view in consciousness, . . 202 Sin in the Christian view not something natural, necessary, and normal, but the result of a free act of the creature, . . 203 Theories of sin opposed to the Christian view — 1. Theories Avhich seek the ground of evil in the constitution of the world, . . . . . .204 2. Theories which seek the explanation of evil in the nature of man — (1) Metaphysical theories of sin, .... 205 (2) Ethical and would-be Christian theories, . . 205 (3) Evolutionary theories : lower and higher, . . 206 Sin in all these theories made something necessary, . . 207 Attempts to disclaim this conclusion : Hegel, ■ . 208 Schleiermacher, . . . . . . . 208 Lipsius, . . . . . . . .208 ■ Ritschl, ........ 208: Weakening or destruction ol idea of guilt, .... 209 Theories of Schleiermacher, Lipsius, and Ritsclil, . . . 209 Differences between the Christian and the modern view depend on theory of origin, ....... 210 Theory of man's original brutishness, .... 210 Impossibility of reconciling the Christian view with this theory : relation of narrative of Fall, ..... 212 Do facts of anthropology contradict the Christian view ? . . 213 The "missing link," . . . . . .213 No necessary conflict with theory of evolution, . . . 213 Man the beginning of a new kingdom, . . . .214 Does archaeology prove the originally savage condition of man ? .214 b xviii CONTENTS. PAOK I. The problem of moral evil (continued) — Do savages represent the original state ? . . . .214 Evidence of early ci^dlisations, ..... 214 Does religion progress from Fetishism to Monotheism ? . .215 Relation of Christian view to modem theories of the antiquity of man, ........ 215 Present state of this question, . . . . . 21 6 Science does not negative the idea of a pure beginning of the race : the Biblical account of primeval man, . . . .216 II. The problem of natural evil : connection with moral evil, . . 217 Natural evil in the inanimate world, .... 218 Natural evil in the organic world : (1) Non-sentient (vegetable), ..... 219 (2) Sentient (animal). . . . , . .219 Relation to justice and goodness of the Creator — - - .219 Is the world of sentient beings an unhappy one ? . . . 220 The Biblical view of nature predominatingly optimistic, . . 220 Real question — Is there to be room for gradation of existences ? . 221 The question altered when we come to self-conscious, rational man, 222 The disciplinary benefits of suffering, etc., not a complete solution : discussion of this theory, ...... 222 Connection of natural evil with sin : nature and admissibility of this connection, ....... 225 The deeper question — Is nature itself in a normal condition ? . 226 The Pauline view : what it implies — 1. Theory that nature had from the first a teleological relation to human sin, ...... 227 2. Paul's doctrine of the subjection of the creation to " vanity," 227 3. The earth in bondage to corruption through man's presence and sin upon it, ..... . 228 III. Culmination of this problem in the question of the relation of sin to death, ........ 228 This relation not an accident of the Christian view, but enters into its essence, ....... 229 The original mortality of man proved neither by death in the animal creation nor by its present universality, . .230 Distinction of man from the animals, .... 230 Man created for immortality, . . . • . . 230 Death the sundering of essential parts of his being : therefore abnormal, ....... 230 The Biblical doctrine of immortality rests — 1. On the Biblical doctrine of the nature of man as a compound being, . . . . . . .231 CONTENTS, XIX III. Culmination of this problem in the question of the relation of sin to death {continued) — The Biblical doctrine of immortality rests {continued) — 2. On the idea that it was no part of the Creator's design that body and soul should be separated, .... 3. On the thought that soul in separation from the body is in a state of imperfection and mutilation, 4. The true immortality is through Kedemption, and embraces the resurrection of the body, .... 232 232 232 Appendix to Lecture V. immortality : embraces THE OLD TESTAMENT DOCTRINE OF IMMORTALITY. Bearing on previous discussion on Old Testament doctrine of immortality, This doctrine has been sought for in a wrong direction, The Hebrew view of Sheol, . Egyptians, Babylonians, etc., Gloomy associations in Old Testament, Passages in illustration — Genesis, etc., . , . . Job, The Psalms, .... Hezekiah, .... Not in this direction we are to look for doctrine of idea of relation to God, and resurrection, Immortality in Eden, New inbreaking of a law of immortality in Enoch, This the type of Biblical immortality : embraces the whole personality, . Examination of view that the doctrine of Resurrection a late one among the Hebrews : derived from Parsism, etc., .... Counter thesis : this doctrine runs all through Old Testament, Beliefs of Egyptians, ....... The Babylonians and Assyrians, ...... The Persians. Doubtful if this doctrine is found in older parts of the Zend-Avesta, . . Few and ambiguous references in Zoroastrian writings do not explain the prominence of the doctrine in the Old Testament, Review of evidence : the earlier books, ..... Abraham, ......♦•• The words of Moses — " I am the God," etc., .... The later books : Job, Psalms, Prophets, ..... Book of Job picture of patriarchal conditions, .... Job xiv. : anticipation of resurrection, ..... 234 234 234 234 235 236 236 236 236 236 237 237 237 237 237 238 238 238 238 239 239 240 240 240 240 XX CONTENTS. Dr. Davidson's view, .... Job xix. 25-27 : resurrection again implied, " In " or *' without " the body, The Psalms : Dr. Cheyne's views, . The passages that teach immortality imply resurrection— Ps. xvi. 8-11, . Ps. xvii. 15, .... . Ps. xlix. 14, 15, . References to Enoch story, Ps. Ixxiii. 24, . The prophetic books : the idea of resurrection familiar — Hosea vi. 2, xiii. 14, . Isaiah xxv. 6, 8, xxvi. 19, etc., . Dan. xii. 2, .... . After all only a hope, founded on believer's relation to God Dr. Davidson quoted, ..... PACK 241 241 241 242 243 243 243 243 244 244 245 245 245 LECTURE VI. THE CENTRAL ASSERTION OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW— THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST. Introductoey — Completion of argument in second Lecture, .... 249 A"\Tiy cannot we rest in a lower conception of Christ ? . . . 249 A priori objection to the Incarnation based on Christ's lowliness, . 250 Comparison with the assertions of modern theologians and evolu- tionists, ........ 250 I. Testimony of the apostolic age as throwing light on Christ's own claims, ......... 251 Prerogatives which the early church assigned to Christ, . . 252 The claim to judge the world, ..... 253 Modern agreement as to general teaching of New Testament — the Johannine WTitings, ....... 253 Martineau on the teaching of the Fourth Gospel, . . . 253 The Epistles of Paul — 1. The undisputed Epistles, ..... 254 The " Heavenly Man " theory, .... 255 2. The later Epistles — Christology of Philippians, Colossians, etc., . . . . . . . .256 Substantial unity of doctrine in later and earlier Epistles, Paul assumes that his doctrine is the same as that of Churches to which he. writes, .... CONTENTS. XXI PAOB I. Testimony of the apostolic age [continued) — The Epistle to the Hebrews an independent witness, . . . 258 The Apocalypse as representing a Jewish- Christian standpoint, . 259 The doctrine of the Apocalypse as high as John's or Paul's — Reuss, Pfleiderer, . . . . . . . .259 The Petrine and Minor Epistles, — Peter, ........ 261 James, . . . . . . . . 261 Jude, ........ 261 Discourses in the Acts, ...... 262 Conclusion : — the supernatural view of Christ's Person established in first generation of believers, ...... 262 II. The testimony of the Gospels— Christ in the Fourth Gospel . 263 The question of genuineness ; relation to Philo, etc. , . . . 263 Do the Synoptics give a different view ? . . . . 264 The Christ of the Synoptics also a supernatural Being, . . 264 His humanity — higher aspects of His Person, . . . 264 Criticism cannot expunge the supernatural element, . . 265 It belongs to the essence of the representation, . . . 265 1. The claiTns of Jesus — the titles "Son of Man," and "Son of God," 265 Relation to kingdom of God, etc. , . , . . . 266 His eschatological claims, ..... 266 Peter's confession, etc., ..... 267 2. Representation of the character of Christ ; — His sinless- ness, ....... 267 Attested by the earliest witnesses, . . . 267 Borne out by the picture in the Synoptics, . . 267 Admitted by modern theologians — Vatke, Schleiermacher, Lipsius, etc., . . . . . . 268 3. The Works of Jesus in keeping with His claims, . • 268 4. The Resurrection of Jesus — the Trinitarian formula, etc. , 269 The Synoptic representation of Christ in keeping with the apostolic estimate of His Person, .... 270 The latter needs the former for its basis, .... 270 Conclusion : — The facts of Christ's Revelation require the super- natural view of His Person : impossibility of evading this claim, ........ 271 III. Doctrinal aspects of the Incarnation : proposed reconstructions, . 272 In what sense modern theories ascribe "Godhead " to Christ, . 272 Two questions in regard to these theories — 1. First question — Are these theories tenable on their own merits? . . . . . , .275 xxii CONTENTS. PACK III. Doctrinal aspects of the Incarnation {continued) — Two classes to be distinguished — (1) Those which do not presuppose a transcendental ground for the predicate "Godhead" applied to Christ — Rothe, Ritschl, Lipsius, etc., . . 275 (2) Those which do presuppose a transcendental ground — Rothe, Beyschlag, . . . .276 Inconsistencies of Rothe's theory, . . . 277 Adds a new Person to the Godhead, . . . 278 Difficulties of Beyschlag's theory of a heavenly humanity, . . . . . .278 2. Second question — Do these theories do justice to the facts of Christ's Revelation ? . . . . .278 "What is not, and what is, true Incarnation, . . .279 3. Consideration of Kenotic theories (Phil. ii. 7), . . 280 Central difficulty of these theories, .... 281 Relation of preceding discussion to the early Christological decisions — Has modern thought no further light to throw on Christological problems ? . . . . . . . . 282 Advances in modern speculation, ..... 282 The question of the impersonality of Christ's humanity, . . 282 Objections to the older view as affecting the reality and integrity of the humanity, ....... 283 Examination of these objections : 1. Can we attribute an independent personality to the humanity of Christ? .283 2. Does the Divine personality detract from the integrity and reality of Christ's human nature ? . . . . 284 Possible solution of these questions in the original relation of the Divine Logos to humanity, .... 284 This doctrine does not deny a true human personality to Christ, but only its non-identity with the Divine, . . 285 The Incarnation to be studied in the light of its revealed ends, . 285 Appendix to Lecture VI. THE SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS OF JESUS. Modern interest in this question, . . . . . .287 Main points discussed — 1. Fundamental fact in Christ's consciousness, .... 287 2. When did Christ realise His Messianic calling ? . . .288 3. Was Christ's "plan " one and the same throughout ? . .288 4. Import and origin of titles " Son of Man " and " Son of God," . 288 CONTENTS. xxiii PAGB Views of leading writers, — Beyschlag, . 289 H. Schmidt, . 291 Grau, . 293 Baldensperger, . 294 Wendt, . . 296 LECTURE VII. HIGHER CONCEPT OF GOD INVOLVED IN THE INCARNATION —THE INCARNATION AND THE PLAN OF THE WORLD. Introductory — The point now reached, ...... 301 Recapitulation of defective theories, ..... 301 I. Higher concept of God involved in the Incarnation— God as triune — The doctrine of the Trinity not a mere mystery : testimonies to its value, ........ 302 This doctrine the result of an induction from the facts of Revela- tion, . . . . . . . .303 How far is this doctrine anticipated in the Old Testament ? . 304 Significance of the plural Name, .... 304 1. The Angel of Jehovah, . . . . .305 2. The doctrine of the Spirit, . . . .305 3. The Divine Wisdom, etc., . . . .306 The doctrine of the Trinity as involving distinctions in the Divine essence, ........ 306 Objection on this score— "One and Three,". . . . 306 Unity and plurality in everything — substance and attributes, mind, life, etc., ....... 307 Ultimate ground of the universe not a distinctionless unity, . 307 Tlie Eleatic view in Greek philosophy and its results, . . 307 Attempts to overcome the difficulty in Philo, etc., . . . 307 Modern speculative philosophy, ..... 308 Real objection must be to the distinctions as personal, ., . 308 Drawbacks of the word "Person," ..... 308 Early use of terms : Augustine on this, .... 308 Need of the expression, ...... 309 Proof that distinctions of this kind are implied — The Trinitarian formula, ...... 309 The Incarnation of the Sou, ..... 309 Testimonies about the Spirit, . , . . . 309 xxiv CONTENTS. PAGE I. Higher concept of God involved in the Incarnation {continued) — Alternative view — an economical Trinity, . . . .310 Difficulties of this view : ancient and modern Sabellianisra, . 310 Relations of the doctrine to rational thought, . . .311 The admission of a rational element involved in the attempt to explain it from philosophy, . . . . .311 Psychological analogies in Augustine and others, . . .312 Their defects, 313 Suggested analogy in the mind's power of self-converse, . . ,313 Relation of the doctrine to self-consciousness, etc. Its value on this side, ........ 313 1. The deduction from knowledge, . . . .314 Theory that the Divine self- consciousness may be mediated by the idea of the world, ..... 314 Objections to this — (1) It makes God dependent on the world, . . 314 (2) The object only ideal, .... 314 (3) The object a finite one, .... 314 (4) The object not personal, .... 315 The Christian view — the Divine consciousness self-mediated through the Son and Spirit, . . . .315 2. The deduction from love, . . . . .315 The opposite hypothesis — love in a solitary God, . . 316 3. Deduction from the Divine Fatherhood — God eternally Father, . 317 R. H. Hutton on this, . . . . .317 4. Bearing of the Trinity on God's relation to the world, . 318 The safeguard against Deism and Pantheism, . .318 II. The Scripture view brings creation and Redemption into line — con- sequences of this, . . . . . . .319 Relation of the Incarnation to the plan of the world, . . 319 Would there have been an Incarnation had man not sinned ? .319 This question apt to be negatived as presumptuous, . . 320 But 1. It rises naturally from the subject, .... 320 2. Has often pressed itself on the mind of the Church, . 320 3. Not unsuggested by certain of the teachings of Scrip- ture, . . . . . . .320 The history of the question, ...... 320 Strong point against this theory — the constant connection of In- carnation with Redemption, ..... 321 Passages which suggest a wider view, .... 321 Difficulty arising from too abstract a view of the Divine plan, . 322 God's plan one throughout, and includes the foresight and per- mission of sin, ....... 323 CONTENTS, XXV PAGK II. The Scripture view brings creation and Redemption into line {continued) — Relation of Calvinist and Arminian to this question, . . 323 Creation built upon Redemption lines, .... 323 Great weight on this question to be attached to the revealed end — the gathering up of all things in Christ, . . . 324 This end not arbitrary, but one for which the universe must originally have been fitted, ..... 324 Dr. P. Fairbairn substantially agrees with this view, . .324 Harmony of Scripture with this view — 1. The Scriptures know of only one undivided purpose of God, 2. Assert a direct relation of the Son with creation, 3. Represent Christ as the final cause of creation, 4. God's purpose actually tends to the unification of all things in Christ, . Bishop Lightfoot on this. Summary and conclusion, This view reflects light on Christ's Person Is in harmony with previous postulates. 325 325 326 326 326 327 327 327 LECTURE YIII. THE INCARNATION AND REDEMPTION FROM SIN. Introductoey — Christianity a religion of Redemption, . . . .331 Views which this sets aside, . . . . . .331 Comparison and contrast with Buddhism, .... 332 Special question — The connection of Redemption with the suflerings and death of Christ, . . . . . .332 I. Scripture testimony on this subject — the apostolic witness, . . 333 Does Christ's teaching agree with that of the apostles ? Ground on which this is denied, ..... 334 Insufficiency of these grounds, . . . . .335 Proof that Christ attached a redemptive significance to His death, . . . . . . . .336 Grounds on which the apostolic Church proceeded — 1. The objective facts of Christ's death, resurrection, etc. These needed an explanation, .... 338 2. Christ's sayings on the meaning and necessity of His death, . 338 3. The teaching of the Old Covenant as throwing light on Christ's work, . . . . . .339 xxvi CONTENTS. PACK I. Scripture testimony on this subject (continued) — 3. The teaching of the Old Covenant (continued) — (1) Its prophecies — Isa. liii., .... 339 (2) The Law as begetting a sense of sin, and feeling of the need of Atonement, .... 339 (3) The sacrificial economy, .... 339 II. Explanation of the redemptive significance of Christ's death — theories of Atonement, ...... 340 Legitimacy of inquiry into this subject, .... 340 Elements of truth in all theories, ..... 341 Modern desire to connect the Atonement with spiritual laws, . 341 The Atonement considered from the point of view of the Incarna- tion— . . . . . . . .341 Theories which emphasise this point of view, . . . 342 Three points taken for granted in all Christian theories of Re- demption — 1. Removal of guilt — forgiveness, .... 343 2. Breaking down of sinner's enmity, . . . ,343 3. Fellowship of life with Christ, . . . .343 Theories differ as they attach themselves to one or another of these points of view, — 1. Redemption as reception into Christ's fellowship, . . 343 2. Christ's work as the supreme moral dynamic, . . . 344 3. Christ's work as an expiation, . . . .344 More detailed examination of theories — 1. Theories of fellowship : Schleiermacher, etc., . . . 344 Representative relation of Christ, .... 344 Sehleiermacher's view of Christ's sufferings, . . 345 2, Theories based on idea of sympathy : Bushnell, . .346 Real substitution involves sympathetic identification : Sub- stitutionary forces in life, ..... 347 Points in which this theory comes short, . . . 348 Sympathy shown — in doing what ? . . . . 349 Removes Christ's work from its unique position — non- 1 recognition of its expiatory character, . . . 350 ' Dr. Bushnell's later modification of his view, , , 350 Striking admissions in his earlier work, . . . 351 S. Theories based on idea of vocation : RitschI, . . . 352 Theories which recognise an objective element in the Atone- ment : in what does it consist ? . . . . 355| 4. Theories based on idea of self-surrender of holy will to God : Maurice, etc., ...... 355 True elements in these theories : their defects, . . 356 CONTENTS. xxvii PAOR II. Explanation of the redemptive significance of Christ's death (continued) — More detailed examination of theories (continued) — 5. Theories which recognise a relation to guilt : Dorner, etc., . 358 Campbell's theory of vicarious repentance and confession, . 358 Deeper elements in Campbell's view — the ''Amen" in response to God's judgment on sin, . . . 359' This response rendered under actual experience of the jienal consequences of sin, . . . . .360 Christ's sufferings viewed as expiatory, . . . 3&2 Objections to this view — the innocent suffering for the guilty, ....... 3^3 This, in itself a fact of common experience, springs from the organic connection of humanity, .... 363 The real question — How should such sufferings become expiatory for others ?..... 364 The answer suggested, . . . . .364 Recapitulation and conclusion, .... 364 The Incarnate Son alone could achieve Redemption, . 366 LECTUEE IX. THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY. Introductoey — Necessity of an eschatology, . . . , * . . ZQ^ Eschatology in philosophy and science, .... 369 The Christian view eschatological because teleological, , . 370 I. The astronomical objection to Christianity, Reply : Are the worlds inhabited ? The objection a quantitative one, The bearing of sin on this question, Mr. Spencer's objection, 371 372 374 375 375 The issues of Redemption not confined to this planet, . . 376 II. Principles of interpretation of eschatological prophecy, . . 376 Ritschl's rejection of eschatology, ..... 377 Ritschl and Kaftan on the kingdom of God, .... 377 The nearer aim of Christianity — the coming of the kingdom of God on earth, ....... 378 Relation of this to modern social movements, .... 378 History has its goal — transition to eschatology proper, . .379 The positive and bright side of the Christian view . . .379 XXVlll CONTENTS, II. Principles of interpretation of eschatological prophecy {continued) — Three things clear — 1. The aim of God is conformity to the image of the Son, . 380 2. This includes likeness to His glorious body : the resurrec- tion, . . . . . . .380 (1) The Redemption of the body not an accident, but an essential part of the Christian view, . . 380 (2) This doctrine not exposed to some of the objections made to it, . . . . . . 381 N True doctrine of the resurrection — bodily identity, what? . . . . . .381 Paul's analogy, . . . . .382 (3) Not a resurrection at death, but a future event, . 382 3. The perfecting of the Church carries with it the perfecting of nature, ...... 383 Pictorial and scenic elements : 1. The personal Advent — how to be interpreted ? . . 383 Beyschlag's view, ...... 383 The Coming a process in which many elements flow together, ....... 384 Still, a personal Coming is implied, . . . . 384 2. The general Judgment, ..... 385 Its certainty, ...... 385 Parabolic character of descriptions, .... 386 III. The dark side of this question — the destiny of the wicked, . . 386 Three theories on this subject — 1. Dogmatic Universalism, . . . . .386 2. The doctrine of Annihilation ; Conditional Immortality, . 387 3. The doctrine of Eternal Punishment, . . . 387 Fundamental positions laid down — 1. The principle of certain retribution for sin, . . . 388 2. Need for distinguishing between what Scripture teaches and subjects on which it is simply silent, . . 388 3. A larger calculus needed than we at present possess, . 389 Reasons for a large view of the issues of the Chiistian scheme, ....... 389 The question of the heathen, .... 389 Degrees of responsibility even under gospel teaching, . 389 Criticism of theories — 1. Scripture does not warrant dogmatic Universalism, . . 390 The passages adduced in favour of this view not decisive, . 391 2. Scripture does not warrant Annihilation, . . . 391 The hypothesis abstractly possible, but not scripturally justified, ...... 392 CONTENTS, xxix PACK III. Tlie dark side of this question (continued) — Criticism of theories {continued) — Edward White's theory criticised — (1) Its supposed scriptural support, . . . 392 Internal contradictions of the theory ; the wicked not destroyed at death, ..... 392 (2) Shuts out gradations of punishment, or escapes this only by inconsistency, .... 393 (3) Its non - biblical use of the terms "life" and "death," . . . . . .393 Mr. White not satisfied with his own theory— seeks relief in Future Probation, .... 393 Approximation to Universalism, . . . 394 3. The theory of Future Probation, .... 394 Its wide acceptance in recent times, .... 394 Based more on general principles than on definite scriptural information, ...... 395 Facts which suggest caution — (1) Concentration of every ray of exhortation and appeal into the present, ..... 395 (2) The judgment invariably represented as proceeding on the data of this life, .... 395 (3) The silence of Scripture on future probation : limits of the application of 1 Pet. iii. 19, 20 ; iv. 6, . 396 Yet the issues of life must somehow be brought to a bearing in the unseen, .... 396 Result — We have not the elements of a complete solution, ...... 397 Conclusion of Lectures, ...... 397 Appendix. the idea of the kingdom of god. Relation of this subject to the course, ..... 401 I. The place of this idea in theology — recent views, . . . 401 Reasons for not treating the kingdom of God as the all-embracing conception, ........ 402 1. It is not so presented in the New Testament, . . 402 2. Not an idea which can be treated as a fixed quantity, . 403 3. Found difficult in practice to bring all theology under it, . 404 4. The true place of this idea is as a teleological con- ception, ....... 404 XXX CONTENTS. II. The teaching of Jesus on the kingdom of God, 1. The kingdom, a present, developing reality, 2. The nature of the kingdom of God on earth, (1) The religious and ethical side of this kingdom alone is made prominent, (2) Yet a principle which affects society in all its rela- tions, .... The recognition of this by Christ, . (•a) The view of the Old Testament presup- posed — Christ's relation to the world and to society, .... (&) The world in its existing form hostile, but capable of Redemption and renewal, (c) Christ's positive recognition of the Divine order of society, and the duty of His disciples to work in it, and save it, (3) The relation of the idea of the kingdom of God to that of the Church, .... 405 405 406 406 407 407 407 408 408 409 III. The kingdom of God and the new life of humanity, . . . 410 1. The principle of this life is Christ risen and exalted, . 410 * 2. This new life is (1) a life in the individual soul, (2) in society, ....... 411 3. The kingdom of God as the centre of God's Providence, . 412 INDEX TO NOTES. Lecture I. PAOB fUustrations of the word "Weltanschauung" and related terms, . . 415 Classification of "Weltanschauungen," ..... 417 Unconscious Metaphysic, ....... 421 Scope of the modern Scientific Claim, . . . . .421 Antagonism of Christian and "Modern" views of the world — anti -super- naturalism of the latter, ....... 422 Internal conflicts of the "Modern" view, . . , . , 424 Uniqueness of the Old Testament view, . . . . .427 Origin of the Old Testament view — Relation to critical theories, . . 430 Nature and Definition of Religion, ...... 431 Undogmatic Religion, ....... 437 -^Esthetic theories of Religion, ...... 438 Schleiermacher on Dogmatics, ...... 439 Religious and theoretic Knowledge, ..... 440 Ritschl on Religion and Philosophy, ..... 441 The Hegelian theory of Religion, ...... 442 Lecture II. The central place of Christ in His Religion, . . . . 444 The defeat of Arianism, . . . . . . .445 Modern Unitarianism, ....... 446 Concessions of Ritschlians on the Person of Christ, . . . 448 The weakness of Deism, . . . . . . . 450 Weakness of modern Liberal Protestantism, . . . .451 Christianity and the idea of Progress, ..... 453 The prevalence of Pessimism, ...... 454 The literature of Pessimism, ...... 455 Transition from Pessimism to Theism — Hartmann and Karl Peters, . 456 Materialism in Germany, ....... 457 Fichte's later Philosophy, ....... 458 Modern theory of Revelation, . . . . . . 460 The reasonableness of Revelation, . . . . . .461 The Ritschliau doctrine of Revelation, ..... 462 XXXll INDEX TO NOTES. Lecture III. PAGE Primitive Fetisliism and Ghost worship, . . . . .466 Old Testament Monotheism, . 469 Hegel's idea of God, . 471 Defects of the Neo-Hegelian view, . . 471 Kant and the Cosmological Argument, . 474 Kant and the Teleological Argument, . 475 Schools of Evolutionists, . 476 Kant on the Ontological Argument, . 478 Rational Realism, .... . 479 Lecture IV. The Creation History, . . . . . . .480 Evolution in inorganic Nature— The Nebular Hypothesis, . 482 The Hypothesis of Cycles, ..... . 483 "Eternal Creation," . 485. Eternity and Time, . . 487 Man the head of Creation, . . 488 Mind and Mechanical Causation, . . 489 Mind and Cerebral Activity, . 490 Schleiermacher and Immortality, . . 493 Lecture V. Defects in Creation : an argument against Theism, . . . 495 Dualistic theories of the Origin of Evil, . 496 Hegel's Doctrine of Sin, . 497 Ritschl's Doctrine of Guilt, . . 498 Alleged primitive Savagery of mankind. . 499 Early Monotheistic Ideas, . . 501 The Antiquity of Man and Geological Time, . 504 The connection of Sin and Death, . . 506 Lecture VI. The doctrine of Pre-existence, ...... 508 Philo and the Fourth Gospel, . . . . . .510 The Resurrection of Christ and the reality of His Divine Claim, . . 512 Lecture VII. Recent theories of the Trinity, . . . . . .516 Dr. Martineau as a Trinitarian, . 521 Lecture VI 1 1. The Germ theory of Justification, . Lecture IX. Renan's Eschatology, The Gospel and the vastness of Creation, . Alleged Pauline Universalism, 524 527 528 530 LECTURE I. W(^t Cfjrtsttan Fieto of t|}e amorlti in ffinxeral "Jesus Christ is the centre of all, and the goal to which all tends."— Pascal. "If we carry back the antagonisms of the present to their ultimate principle, we are obliged to confess that it is of a religious kind. The way in which a man thinks of God and the world, and their relation to one another, is decisive for the whole tendency of his thought, and even in the questions of the purely natural life." — Luthardt. "Tlie Christian truth, with the certifying of which we have to do, is essentially only one, compact in itself, vitally interconnected, — as such at the same time organic, — and it is therefore not possible one should possess and retain a portion of the same, while yet not possessing, or rejecting, the other portions. On the contrary, the member or portion of the truth, which it had been thought to appropriate or maintain alone, would by this isolating cease to be that which it was or is in itself ; it would become an empty form or husk, from which the life, the Christian reality, has escaped."— F. H. R. Frank. "In no case can true Reason and a right Faith oppose each other." — Coleridge. LECTUKE I. THE CHPJSTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD IN GENERAL. I MIGHT briefly define the object of the present Lectures by The temi saying that they aim at the exhibition, and, as far as possible " ^^^^^^^-^ within the limits assigned me, at the rational vindication, of what I have called in the title, " The Christian view of the world." This expression, however, is itself one which calls for definition and explanation, and I proceed, in the first place, to give the explanation that is needed. A reader of the higher class of works in German theology — especially those which deal with the philosophy of re- ligion — cannot fail to be struck with the constant recurrence of a word for which he finds it difficult to get a precise equivalent in English. It is the word " Weltanschauung," sometimes interchanged with another compound of the same signification, " Weltansicht." Both words mean literally "view of the world," but whereas the phrase in English is limited by associations which connect it predominatingly with physical nature, in German the word is not thus limited, but has almost the force of a technical term, denoting the widest view which the mind can take of things in the effort to grasp them together as a whole from the standpoint of some particular philosophy or theology. To speak, therefore, of a " Christian view of the world " implies that Christianity also has its highest point of view, and its view of life con- nected therewith, and that this, when developed, constitutes an ordered whole.^ ^ See Note A. — Illustrations of the word "Weltanschauung" 4.. . TH^ CHRISTIAN. VIEW OF THE WORLD. Need of com- To some the subject which I have thus chosen may seem frehensive uiidulv widc and vague. I can only reply that I have treatment. . « •■ . ^ ^ '^ ^ ^ deliberately chosen it for this very reason that it enables me to deal with Christianity in its entirety or as a system, instead of dealing with particular aspects or doctrines of it. Both methods have their advantages ; but no one, I think, whose eyes are open to the signs of the times can fail to perceive that if Christianity is to be effectually defended from the attacks made upon it, it is the comprehensive method which is rapidly becoming the more urgent. The opposition which Christianity has to encounter is no longer confined to special doctrines or to points of supposed conflict with the natural sciences, — for example, the relations of Genesis and geology, — but extends to the whole manner of conceiving of the world, and of man's place in it, the manner of conceiving of the entire system of things, natural and moral, of which we form a part. It is no longer an opposition of detail, but of principle. This circumstance necessitates an equal extension of the line of the defence. It is the Christian view of things in general which is attacked, and it is by an exposition and vindication of the Christian view of things as a whole that the attack can most successfully be met. Viexv of Christ- Everything here, of course, depends on the view we take of 'LeluJl ^^'' Christianity itself. The view indicated in the title is that which has its centre in the Divine and human Person of the Lord Jesus Christ. It implies the true Divinity as well as the true humanity of the Christian Eedeemer. This is a view of Christianity, I know, which I am not at liberty to take for granted, but must be prepared in due course to vindicate. I shall not shrink from the task which this imposes on me, but would only at present point out that, for him who does accept it, a very definite view of things /emerges. He who with his whole heart believes in Jesus as the Son of God is thereby committed to much else besides. He is committed to a view of God, to a view of man, to a THE CHRISTIAN VIEW IN GENERAL. 5 view of SID, to a view of Eedemption, to a view of the purpose of God in creation and history, to a view of human destiny, — found only in Christianity. This forms a " Weltanschauung," or " Christian view of the world," which stands in marked contrast with theories wrought out from a purely philosophical . or scientific standpoint. The idea of the " Weltanschauung " may be said to have 77^^ **^F^//^w- entered prominently into modern thought through the influence ^fl'^^^^^s'' '« of Kant, who elevates what he calls the " Weltbegriff" to the Kant, etc, rank of the second of his Ideas of Pure Reason, assigning to it the function of the systematic connection of all our experiences into the unity of a world-whole (Weltganz).^ But the thing itself is as old as the dawn of reflection, and is found in a cruder or more advanced form in every religion and philosophy with any pretensions to a historical character. The simplest form in which we meet with it is in the rude, tentative efforts at a general explanation of things in the cosmogonies and theogonies of most ancient religions, the mythological character of which need not blind us to the rational motive which operates in them.^ With the growth of philosophy, a new type of world-view is developed — that which attempts to explain the universe as a system by the help of some general principle or principles (water, air, number, etc.), accompanied by the use of terms which imply the con- ception of an All or Whole of things (ra Trdvra, Koa-jno^; — ^ See Appendix II, — The Idea of the "Weltanschaimng." Kant says: "1 name all transcendental ideas, so far as they relate to the absolute totality in the synthesis of phenomena, world-notions (Weltbegriffe), partly because of this very unconditioned totality, on which also the notion of the world -whole (Weltganz) rests — which itself is only an idea, — partly because they relate only to the synthesis of phenomena, consequently to the empirical ; while, on the other hand, the absolute totality in the synthesis of the conditions of all y)ossible things will give rise to an ideal of pure reason, which is to be entirely distinguished from the Avorld-notion (Weltbegriff), although at the same time it stands in relation to it. " . . . " The cosmological idea (kosmologische Idee) of an absolute whole." — Kritik d. r. Vernimft, pp. 302, 360 (Bohn's trans, pp. 256, 310). The references to Kant throughout are to Erdmann's edition (1884). 2 Cf. Zeller on Hesiod's Theogony, Pre - Socratic Philosophy, pp. 88, 89 (Eng. trans.). 6 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. attributed to the Pythagoreans — mundus, universum, etc.)} An example from ancient thought may be given from Lucretius, who, in his famous poem, " De Eerum Natura," proposes " to discourse of the most high system of heaven and the gods, and to open up the first-beginnings of things, out of which nature gives birth to all things and increase and nourishment, and into which nature likewise resolves them back after their destruction." ^ The outlines of his system are well known. By the aid of certain first principles — atoms and the void — and of certain assumed laws of motion and development, he seeks to account for the existing universe, and constructs for himself a theory on the lines of Epicurus, which he thinks satis- fies his intellectual necessities. This is his " Weltanschauung " — the progeny of which is seen in the materialistic systems of the present day. A modern example may be taken from the philosophy of Comte, which, theoretically one of pure phenomenalism, only the more strikingly illustrates the necessity which thought is under to attempt in some form a synthesis of its experience. Comte's standpoint is that of despair of absolute knowledge. Yet he recognises the tendency in the mind which prompts it to organise its knowledge, and thinks it possible to construct a scheme of existence which shall give practical unity to life — imagina- tion eking out the deficiencies of the intellect. In the words of a recent interpreter, " Beneath and beyond all the details in our ideas of things, there is a certain esprit ■d'ensemhle, a general conception of the world without and the world within, in which these details gather to a head." ^ It would not be easy to get a better description of what is meant by a " Weltanschauung " than in these words. The centre of unity in this new conception of the universe is Man. Knowledge is to be organised solely with reference to its bearings on the well-being and progress of Humanity. 1 See Note B.— Classification of " Weltaiischaimngen." 2 Bk. I. LI. 54-57 (Munro's trans.). Cf. Lucretius and the Atomic Theory, by Professor John Veitch, p. 13. * 3 Caird's Social Philosophy of Comte, p. 21 THE CHRISTIAN VIE W IN GENERAL 7 A religion even is provided for the satisfaction of the emotional and imaginative wants of man in the worship of the same abstraction — Humanity, which is to be viewed with affection and gratitude as a beneficent providence in- terposed between man and the hard pressure of his outward conditions. In a moral respect the individual is to find his all-comprehensive end in the " service of Humanity." Thus, again, we have a " Weltanschauung " in which knowledge and action are knit up together, and organised into a single view of life. The causes which lead to the formation of " Weltan- Causes of schauungen," that is, of general theories of the universe, -^^^'^f"^^ "^,^-^ ^ ' ' o ' of the world, explanatory of what it is, how it has come to be what it is, and whither it tends, lie deep in the constitution of human nature. They are twofold — speculative and practical, corre- sponding to the twofold aspect of human nature as thinking and active. On the theoretical side, the mind seeks unity in its representations. It is not content with fragmentary knowledge, but tends constantly to rise from facts to laws, from laws to higher laws, from these to the highest generalisa- tions possible.^ Ultimately it abuts on questions of origin, purpose, and destiny, which, as questions set by reason to itself, it cannot, from its very nature, refuse at least to attempt to answer.^ Even to prove that an answer to them is impossible, it is found necessary to discuss them, and it will be strange if, in the course of the discussion, the dis- covery is not made, that underneath the profession of ne- science a positive theory of some kind after all lurks.^ But ^ Cf. Strauss— "We proceed from the isolated circles of phenomena around us, from the stable basis and the elementary forces, to vegetable and animal life, to the universal life of the earth, from this to that of our solar system, and so ever further, till at last we have grasped the entire range of existence in a single representation ; and this is the representation of the universe." — Der alte und der neue Glaube, p. 150. 2 "As science becomes more conscious of its problems and its goal, it struggles the more strenuously towards the region where physics melt into metaphysics." — Fairbairn, Studies in the Philosophy and History of Religion^ p. 88. ^ See Note C. — Unconscious Metaphysic. THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. Fondness of the age for general theories. there is likewise a practical motive urging to the considera- tion of these well-worn questions of the why, whence, and whither ? Looking out on the universe, men cannot but desire to know their place in the system of things of which they form a part, if only that they may know how rightly to determine themselves thereto.^ Is the constitution of things good or evil ? By what ultimate principles ought man to be guided in the framing and ordering of his life ? What is the true end of existence ? What rational justifica- tion does the nature of things afford for the higher senti- ments of duty and religion ? If it be the case, as the Agnostic affirms, that light absolutely fails us on questions of origin, cause, and end, what conception of life remains ? Or assuming that no higher origin for life and mind can be postulated than matter and force, what revision is necessary of current conceptions of private morality and social duty ? It is a singular circumstance that, with all the distaste of the age for metaphysics, the tendency to the formation of world-systems, or general theories of the universe, was never more powerful than at the present day. One cause of this, no doubt, is the feeling which modern science itself has done so much to engender of the unity which pervades all orders of existence. The naive Polytheism of pagan times, when every hill and fountain was supposed to have its special divinity, is no longer possible with modern notions of the coherence of the universe. Everywhere the minds of men are opening to the conception that, whatever else the uni- verse is, it is one — one set of laws holds the whole together — one order reigns through all. Everywhere, accordingly, we see a straining after a universal point of view — a ■^ **The question of questions for mankind, the problem which underlies all others, and is more deeply interesting than any other, is the ascertainment of the place which man occupies in nature, and of his relation to the universe of things. Whence our race has come, what are the limits of our power over nature, and of nature's power over us ? to what goal we are tending ? are the problems which present themselves anew, and with undiminished interest, to every man born into the world." — Huxley, Man's Place in Nature, p. 57. THE CHRISTIAN VIE W IN GENERAL. 9 grouping and grasping of things together in their unity .^ The philosophy of Mr. Spencer, for example, is as truly an attempt at the unification of all knowledge as the philosophy of a Hegel ; the evolutionist is as confident of being able to embrace all that is, or ever has been, or will be — all existing phenomena of nature, history, or mind — in the range of a few ultimate formulas, as if he had already seen how the task was to be accomplished ; the Comtist urges to an imaginative in default of a real and objective synthesis, and rears on this basis at once a social theory and a religion. The mind grows bolder with the advance of knowledge, and hopes, if not to reach a final solution of the ultimate mystery of existence, at least to bring thoroughly under its dominion the sphere of the knowable.^ What now, it may be asked, has Christianity to do with Relation of theories, and questions, and speculations of this sort ? As a ^/^^^^^^^J^'^y doctrine of salvation, perhaps, not much, but in its logical theories. presuppositions and consequences a great deal indeed. Christianity, it is granted, is not a scientific system, though, ^ if its view of the world be true, it must be reconcilable with all that is certain and established in the results of science. It is not a philosophy, though, if it be valid, its fundamental assumptions will be found to be in harmony with the con- clusions at which sound reason, attacking its own problems, independently arrives. It is a religion, historical in its origin, and claiming to rest on Divine Eevelation. But though Christianity is neither a scientific system, nor a philosophy, it has yet a world-view of its own, to which it stands committed, alike by its fundamental postulate of a personal, holy, self-revealing God, and by its content as a ^ Cf. Principal Fairbairn — "The search for causes, both efficient and ultimate, is being conducted with the most daring and unwearied enthusiasm. Science has become as speculative, as prolific of physico-metaphysical theories — as the most bewitched metaphysician could desire. . , . The consequent crop of cosmic speculation has been of the most varied and extensive kind, ranging from theories of the origin of species to theories as to the origin of the universe. " — Studies, p. 64. 2 See Note D. — Scope of the Modern Scientific Claim. lo THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. \ religion of Eedemption — which, therefore, necessarily brings it into comparison with the world- views already referred to.^ It has, as every religion should and must have, its own peculiar interpretation to give of the facts of existence ; its own way of looking at, and accounting for, the existing natural and moral order ; its own idea of a world-aim, and of that " one far-off Divine event," to which, through slow and painful travail, " the whole creation moves." ^ As thus binding together the natural and moral worlds in their highest unity, through reference to their ultimate principle, \ God, it involves a " Weltanschauung." The Christian It need not further be denied that between this view of and'' modern'' ^^ world involved in Christianity, and what is sometimes views of the "^ world. termed "the modern view of the world," there exists a deep and radical antagonism.^ This so -called "modern view of the world," indeed, — and it is important to observe it, — is, strictly speaking, not one view, but many views, — a group of views, — most of them as exclusive of one another as they together are of Christianity.* The phrase, nevertheless, does point to a homogeneity of these various systems — to a bond of unity which runs through them all, and holds them together in spite of their many differences. This common feature is their thoroughgoing opposition to the supernatural, — at least of the specifically miraculous, — their refusal to recognise anything in nature, life, or history, outside the lines of natural development. Between such a view of the world and Christianity, it is perfectly correct to say that there can be no kindred- ship. Those who think otherwise — speculative Theists, e.g. like Pfleiderer — can only make good their contention by fundamentally altering the idea of Christianity itself — robbing it also of its miraculous essence and accompaniments. Whether this is tenable we shall consider afterwards. 1 Cf. Dorner, Syst. of Doct. i. p. 155 (Eug. trans.). 2 Tennyson, In Memoriam. 2 See Note E. — Antagonism of Christian and " Modern " Views of the World. * See Note F.— Internal Conflicts of the "Modern " View. THE CHRISTIAN VIE W IN GENERAL, 1 1 Meanwhile it is to be noted that this at least is not the Christianity of the New Testament. It may be an improved ~ - and purified form of Christianity, but it is not the Christ- ianity of Christ and His apostles. Even if, with the newer criticism, we distinguish between the theology of Christ and that of His apostles — between the Synoptic Gospels and the Gospel of John — between the earlier form of the synoptic tradition and supposed later embellishments — it is still not to be disputed that, in the simplest view we can take of it, Jesus held and acted on a view of things totally different from the rationalistic conception ; while for him who accepts the view of Christianity indicated in the title of these Lec- tures, it has already been pointed out that a view of things emerges with which the denial of the supernatural is wholly incompatible. The position here taken, that the question at issue be- The question tween the opponents and defenders of the Christian view of °^^^^ ^^/f^' ^ ^ natural m the world is at bottom the question of the supernatural, Christianity, needs to be guarded against a not uncommon misconception. A good deal of controversy has recently taken place in \ regard to certain statements of Professor Max Miiller, as to whether " miracles " are essential to Christianity.^ But the issue we have to face is totally misconceived when it is turned into a question of belief in this or that particular miracle — or of miracles in general — regarded as mere ex- ternal appendages to Christianity. The question is not about isolated " miracles," but about the whole conception of Christianity — what it is, and whether the supernatural does not enter into the very essence of it ? It is the general question of a supernatural or non-supernatural conception of the universe. Is there a supernatural Being — God ? Is there a supernatural government of the world ? Is there a supernatural relation of God and man, so that God and man may have communion with one another ? Is there a super- 1 Cf. Max Miiller's Preface to liis Lectures on Anthropological Religion (Gilford Lectures), 1892. 12 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. natural Eevelation ? Has that Eevelation culminated in a supernatural Person — Christ ? Is there a supernatural work in the souls of men ? Is there a supernatural Eedemption ? Is there a supernatural hereafter ? It is these larger quest- ions that have to be settled first, and then the question of particular miracles will fall into its proper place. Neander has given admirable expression to the conception of Christianity which is really at stake in the following words in the com- mencement of his History of the Gliurck — " Now we look upon Christianity not as a power that has sprung up out of the hidden depths of man's nature, but as one that descended from above, when heaven opened itself anew to man's long alienated race ; a power which, as both in its origin and its essence it is exalted above all that human nature can create out of its own resources, was designed to impart to that nature a new life, and to change it in its inmost principles. The prime source of this power is He whose power exhibits to us the manifestation of it — Jesus of Nazareth — the Eedeemer of mankind when estranged from God by sin. In the devotion of faith in Him, and the appropriation of the truth which He revealed, consists the essence of Christianity and of that fellowship of the Divine life resultiug from it, which we designate by the name of the Church." ^ It is this conception of Christianity we have to come to an understanding with, before the question of particular miracles can profitably be \ discussed. 'Relation of While, from the nature of the case, this side of opposition to7thir^^ ^^ ^^ Christian view of the world to certain "modern" systems not Conceptions must necessarily receive prominence, I ought, on TegltfoZ^ ^^^® ^^^^^ ^^^^^' ^^ remark that it is far from my intention to represent the relation of Christianity to these opposing systems as one of mere negation. This would be to overlook the fact, which cannot be too carefully borne in mind, that no theory which has obtained wide currency, and held powerful sway over the minds of men, is ever wholly false ; 1 History of the Church, i. p. 2 (Eng. trans.). THE CHRISTIAN VIEW IN GENERAL. 13 that, on the contrary, it derives what strength it has from some side or aspect of truth which it embodies, and for which it is in Providence a witness against the suppression or denial of it in some counter-theory, or in the general doctrine of the age. No duty is more imperative on the Christian teacher than that of showing that instead of Christianity being simply one theory among the rest, it is really the higher truth which is the synthesis and com- pletion of all the others, — that view which, rejecting the error, takes up the vitalising elements in all other systems and religions, and unites them into a living organism, with Christ as head,^ We are reminded of Milton's famous figure in the " Areopagitica," of the dismemberment of truth, — how truth was torn limb from limb, and her members were scattered to the four winds ; and how the lovers of truth, imitating the careful search of Isis for the body of Osiris, have been engaged ever since in gathering together the severed parts, in order to unite them again into a perfect whole.2 If apologetic is to be spoken of, this surely is the truest and best form of Christian apology — to show that in Christianity, as nowhere else, the severed portions of truth found in all other systems are organically united, while it completes the body of truth by discoveries peculiar to itself. The Christian doctrine of God, for example, may fairly claim to be the synthesis of all the separate elements of truth found in Agnosticism, Pantheism, and Deism, which by their very ^ Cf. Baring-Gould — " In every religion of tlie world is to Le found, distorted or exaggerated, some great truth, otherwise it would never have obtained foot- hold ; every religious revolution has been the struggle of thought to gain another step in the ladder that reaches to heaven. That which we ask of Revelation is that it sliall take up all these varieties into itself, not that it shall supplant them ; and show how that at which each of them aimed, hoW' ever dimly and indistinctly, has its interpretation and realisation in the objective truth brought to light by Revelation. Hence we shall be able to recognise that religion to be the true one, Avhich is the complement and cor- rective of all the wanderings of the religious instinct in its elforts to provide objects for its own satisfaction." — Origin and Deceloj)ment of Reli(jious Belief, ii. Pref. p. 10. 2 Cf. Areopagitica, "English Reprints," p. 56. Clement of Alexandria has a similar ligure, Strom, i. 13. 14 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. antagonisms reveal themselves as one-sidednesses, requiring to be brought into some higher harmony. If Agnosticism affirms that there is that in God — in His infinite and absolute existence — which transcends finite comprehension, Christian theology does the same. If Pantheism affirms the absolute immanence of God in the world, and Deism His absolute transcendence over it, Christianity unites the two sides of the truth in a higher concept, maintaining at the same time the Divine immanence and the Divine transcendence.^ Even Polytheism in its nobler forms is in its own dark way a witness for a truth which a hard, abstract Monotheism, such as we have in the later (not the Biblical) Judaism, and in Mohammedanism, ignores — the truth, namely, that God is plurality as well as unity — that in Him there is a mani- foldness of life, a fulness and diversity of powers and mani- festations, such as is expressed by the word Elohim. This element of truth in Polytheism, Christianity also takes up, and sets in its proper relation to the unity of God in its doctrine of Tri-unity — the concept of God which is dis- tinctively the Christian one, and which furnishes the surest safeguard of a living Theism against the extremes of both Pantheism and Deism.^ Optimism and Pessimism are another pair of contrasts — each in its abstraction an error, yet each a witness for a truth which the other overlooks, and Christ- ianity is the reconciliation of both. To take a last ex- ample, Positivism is a very direct negation of Christianity ; yet in its strange " worship of Humanity" is there not that which stretches across the gulf and touches hands with a religion which meets the cravings of the heart for the human in God by the doctrine of the Incarnation ? ^ It is the pro- 1 Cf. Epli. iv. 6. Flint, Antl-Theistlc Theories, p. 339. 2 Cf. Dorner, Syst. of Doct. i. pp. 366, 367 (Eng. trans.). Even Ed. v. Hart- mann recognises the "deep metapliysical sense" of the doctrine of the Trinity, and the service done by it in reconciling the Divine immanence and transcend- ence.— iSciftsizerse^sMnj/ des Christerdhums, p. 108. 3 "Altruism " is another point of contact between Comtism and Christianity, though, indeed, it was first borrowed from the latter. THE CHRISTIAN VIEW IN GENERAL. 15 vince of a true and wise Christian theology to take account of all this, and to seek, with ever-increasing enlargement of vision, the comprehensive view in which all factors of the truth are combined. The practical inference I would draw — the very opposite of that drawn by others from the same premisses — is, that it is the unwisest way possible of dealing with Christianity to pare it down, or seek to sublimate it away, as if it had no positive content of its own ; or, by lavish compromise and concession, to part with that which belongs to its essence. It is not in a blunted and toned- down Christianity, but in the exhibition of the Christian view in the greatest fulness and completeness possible, that the ultimate synthesis of the conflicting elements in the clash of systems around us is to be found. / This is perhaps the place to point out that, whatever the The Christian character of the world-view involved in Christianity, it is not ^^^ ^^^^^ world based one in all respects absolutely new. It rests upon, and carries on that of the forward to its completion, the richly concrete view of the ^^^ Testanient — uniqueness world already found in the Old Testament. As an able of the latter, expounder of Old Testament theology, Hermann Schultz, has justly said — " There is absolutely no New Testament view "*^ which does not approve itself as a sound and definitive formation from an Old Testament germ — no truly Old Testament view which did not inwardly press forward to its New Testament fulfilment." ^ This is a phenomenon which, , I think, has not always received the attention it deserves. What are the main characteristics of this Old Testament conception ? At its root is the idea of a holy, spiritual, self -revealing God, the free Creator of the world, and its continual Preserver. As correlative to this, and springing out of it, is the idea of man as a being made in God's image, and capable of moral relations and spiritual fellowship with his Maker ; but who, through sin, has turned aside from the end of his creation, and stands in need of Kedemption. In the heart of the history, we have the idea of a Divine ^ Alttestamentliche Theologie, p. 48. 1 6 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. purpose, working itself out through the calling of a special nation, for the ultimate benefit and blessing of mankind. God's providential rule extends over all creatures and events, and embraces all peoples of the earth, near and remote. In view of the sin and corruption that have overspread the world. His government is one of combined mercy and judgment; and His dealings with Israel in particular are preparative to the introduction of a better economy, in which the grace already partially exhibited will be fully revealed. The end is the establishment of a kingdom of God under the rule of the Messiah, in which all national limitations will be removed, the Spirit be poured forth, and Jehovah will become the God of the whole earth. God will make a new covenant with His people, and will write His laws by His Spirit in their hearts. Under this happy reign, the final triumph of righteousness over sin will be accomplished, and death and all other evils will be abolished. Here is a very remarkable " Weltanschauung," the presence of which at all in the pages of the Hebrew Scriptures is a fact of no ordinary significance. In the comparative history of re- \ ligions, it stands quite unique.^ Speculations on the world and its origin are seen growing up in the schools of philo- sophy; but on the ground of religion there is nothing to compare with this. The lower religions. Fetishism and the like, have of course nothing of the nature of a developed world-view. The rudiments of such a view in the older nature-religions are crude, confused, polytheistic — mixed up abundantly with mythological elements. Brahmanism and Buddhism rest on a metaphysical foundation ; they are as truly philosophical systems as the atomistic or pantheistic theories of the Greek schools, or the systems of Schopenhauer and Hartmann in our own day. And the philosophy they inculcate is a philosophy of despair ; they contain no spring of hope or progress. Zoroastrianism, with its profound realisation of the conflict of good and evil in the universe, ^ See Kote G. — UiiicLueness of the Old Testament View. THE CHRISTIAN VIEW IN GENERAL. 17 perhaps comes nearest to the religion of the Old Testament, yet is severed from it by an immense gulf. I refer only to its pervading dualism, its reverence for physical elements, its confusion of natural and moral evil — above all, to its total lack of the idea of historical Eevelation.^ The Biblical conception is separated from every other by its monotheistic basis, its unique clearness, its organic unity, its moral character, and its teleological aim.^ It does not matter for the purposes of this argument what dates we assign to the books of the Old Testament in which these views are found — whether we attribute them, with the critics, to the age of the prophets, or to any other. These views are at least there many centuries before the Christian age began, and they are found nowhere else than on the soil of Israel. This is the singular fact the critic has to face, and we cannot profess to wonder that, impartially studying it, voices should be heard from the midst of the advanced school itself unhesitatingly declaring, Date your books when you will, this religion is not explicable save on the hypothesis of Eevelation ! ^ The general drift and object of these Lectures should now. General drift I think, be apparent. From the conditions of this Lecture- ^f • 1^°^^ ^^ ' ^^ the Lectures. ship, I am precluded from directly entering the apologetic field. I feel, however, that it would be useless to discuss any important theological subject at the present day without reference to the thought and speculation of the time. No other mode of thought would enable me to do justice to the Christian position, and none, I think, would be so interesting to those for whom the Lectures are primarily intended. This, however, will be subsidiary to the main design of showing that there is a definite Christian view of things, ^ Cf. the sketch of Zoroastrianism in Introduction to the Zenda vesta in Sacred Books of the East, See also Ebrard's Christian Apologetics, ii. pp. 186-232. Some interesting remarks will be found in Lotze's Mcrocoswws, ii. p. 459. 2 Dr. Dorner says — "Israel has the idea of teleology as a kind of soul." — Syst. of Doct. i. p. 274 (Eng. trans.). ^ See Note H. — Origin of the Old Testament View — Relation to Critical Theories. 1 8 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WO RID. which has a character, coherence, and unity of its own, and stands in sharp contrast with counter-theories and specula- tions, and that this world-view has the stamp of reason and reality upon itself, and can amply justify itself at the bar both of history and of experience. I shall endeavour to show that the Christian view of things forms a logical whole which cannot be infringed on, or accepted or rejected piecemeal, but stands or falls in its integrity, and can only suffer from attempts at amalgamation or compromise with theories which rest on totally distinct bases. I hope thus to make clear at least the true nature of the issues involved in a comparison of the Christian and modern views, and I shall be glad if I can in any way contribute to the elucidation of the former. Objections m Two objections may be taken in limine, to the course I '™"1^' propose to follow, and it is proper at this stage that I should logy of feeling, givc them somc attention. I. The first objection is taken from the standpoint of the theology of feeling, and amounts to a denial of our right to speak of a Christian " Weltanschauung " at all ; indeed, to assume that Christianity has a definite doctrinal content of any kind.^ This class of objectors would rule the cognitive element out of religion altogether. Keligion, it is frequently alleged, has nothing to do with notions of the intellect, but only with states and dispositions of the heart. Theories and doctrines are no essential part of it, but, on the contrary, a bane and injury, and hindrance to its free development and progress. Those who speak thus sometimes do so in the interests of a theory which would seek the essence of religion 'in certain instincts, or sentiments, or emotions, which are supposed to be universal and indestructible in the human race, and to constitute the imperishable and undecaying sub- stance of all religions — the emotions, e.g., of awe or wonder, or reverence or dependence, awakened by the impression of 1 See Note I. — Nature and Definition of Reliarion. THE CHRISTIAN VIEW IN GENERAL. 19 the immensity or mystery of the universe ; while the ideas and beliefs connected with these emotions are regarded as ~ ' but the accidents of a particular stage of culture, and as possessing no independent value. They are at best the variegated moulds into which this emotional life of the spirit has for the time being poured itself — the envelopes and vehicles through which it seeks for itself preservation and expression. All religions, from this impartial standpoint, Christianity included, are equally Divine and equally human. But even those who recognise a higher origin for the Christian religion sometimes speak of it as if in its original form it was devoid of all definite doctrinal content ; or at least as if the doctrinal ideas found in connection with it were only external wrappage and covering, and could be stripped off — altered, manipulated, modified, or dispensed with at the pleasure of the critic — without detriment to the moral and spiritual kernel beneath. Christianity is not given up, but there is the attempt to refine and sublimate it till it is reduced to a simple state of sentiment and feeling ; to purge it of the theoretic element till nothing is left but the vaguest residuum of doctrinal opinion. Agreeing with this party in their aversion to doctrine, yet occupying a distinct standpoint, are the ultra-spirituals, whose naturally mystical bent of mind, and fondness for the hazy and indefinite in theological as in other thinking, predispose them to dwell in the region of cloudy and undefined conceptions.^ It scarcely falls within my province to inquire how far Exammation this theory holds good in its general application to religion, ^ ^^^^ ^^^^ though even on this broad field it might easily be shown that sists only in it involves a number of untenable assumptions, and really ^^'^^^"^^^^ ^'^'^ ^ ' ^ feeling: re- contradicts the idea of religion. For what is meant by thorngion involves assertion that religion consists only in sentiment or feeling, ^^'^'^•^• and has nothing to do with doctrinal conceptions ? Not, surely, that religion can subsist wholly without ideaSy or cognitive apprehension, of some kind. Eeligion, in the ^ See Note J. — Undogmatic Religion. 20 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORID. lowest as well as in the highest of its forms, is an expres- sion of the relation of the soul to something beyond itself ; it involves, therefore, not one term, but two; it points to the existence of an object, and implies belief in the reality of that object. The element of idea, therefore, — or as the Germans would say, " Vorstellung," — is inseparable from it. No religion has ever been found which did not involve \ some rudiments of an objective view. We may learn here even from the pessimist Hartmann, who, in an acute analysis of the elements of religion, says, " How true so- ever it may be that religious feeling forms the innermost kernel of religious life, nevertheless that only is a true religious feeling which is excited through religious repre- sentations having a character of objective (if only relative) truth. Eeligion cannot exist without a religious 'Weltan- schauung,' and this not without the conviction of its tran- scendental truth." ^ Religion not / Nor, again, can it be contended that, while a cognitive indifferent to element of somc kind must be conceded, religion is indifferent the character *=' olits ideas. to the cliaracter of its ideas — that these have no influence upon the state of sentiment or feeling. The religion of a Thug, e.g., is a very different thing from the religion of a Christian, and will any one say that the ideas with which the two religions are associated — the ideas they respectively entertain of their deities — have nothing to do with this difference ? In what do religions differ as higher and lower, if not in the greater or less purity and elevation of the ideas they entertain of the Godhead, and the greater or ^ less purity of the sentiment to which these ideas give birth ? Religion im- Nor, finally, can it be held that it is a matter of unim- plies belief in , ,, .. ,., -..■, an objective P^^tancc whether these ideas which are connected with a counterpart religion are regarded as true — i.e., whether they are believed asthetic 7iews ^^ ^^^^^ ^^^ objective Counterpart. For religion can as little of religion. subsist without belief in the reality of its object, as it can dispense with the idea of an object altogether. This is the ^ Belir/hiisphilosophie, ii. p. 32. THE CHRISTIAN VIE W IN GENERAL. 2 1 weakness of subjective religious theories like Feuerbach's, in which religion is regarded as the projection of man's own egoistic consciousness into the infinite ; or of those poetic and aesthetic theories of religion which regard the ends of religion as served if only it furnishes man with elevating and inspiring ideals, without regard to the question of how far these ideals relate to an actual object. Ideas on this hypothesis are necessary to religion, and may be ranked as higher and lower, but have only a fictitious or poetic value. They are products of historical evolution, — guesses, specula- tions, dreams, imaginings, of the human mind in regard to that which from the nature of the case is beyond the reach of direct knowledge, probably is unknowable. They are therefore not material out of which anything can be built of a scientific character; not anything that can be brought to an objective test; not anything verifiable. Their sole value, as said earlier, is to serve as the vehicles and support of religious feeling.^ But it is obvious that, on this view, the utility of religious ideas can only last so long as the illusion in connection with them is not dispelled. For religion is more than a mere aesthetic gratification. It im- plies belief in the existence of a real object other than self, and includes a desire to get into some relation with this object. The mind in religion is in too earnest a mood to be put off with mere fancies. The moment it dawns on the thoughts of the worshipper that the object he worships has no reality, but is only an illusion or fancy of his own. — the moment he is convinced that in his holiest exercises he is but toying with the creations of his own spirit, — that moment the religious relation is at an end. Neither philosopher nor common man will long continue bowing down to an object in whose actual existence he has ceased to believe.^ Nor is ^ See Note K. — ^Esthetic Theories of Religion. 2 Cf. Dorner — "Faith does not wish to be a mere relation to itself, or to its representations and thoughts. That would simply be a monologue ; faith desires a dialogue." — Syst. of Doct. i. p. 123 (Eng. trans.). Martineau — "No: if religious communion is reduced to a monologue, its 22 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WO RID, the conclusion which seems to follow from this — that the illusion of religion is one which the progress of knowledge is destined to destroy — evaded by the concession that there is some dim Unknowable, the consciousness of which lies at the basis of the religious sentiment, and which the mind can still please itself by clothing with the attributes of God. For what is there in this indefinite relation to an Unknow- able, of which we can only affirm that it is not what we think it to be, to serve the purposes of a religion ? And what avails it to personalise this conception of the Absolute, when we know, as before, that this clothing with personal attributes is only subjective illusion ? Need and No objection, therefore, can fairly be taken from the side room for a q£ ^^ frencral "Science of Eeligions " to the supposition religion which ^ ^ "^ can give us that a religion may exist which can give us a better know- true knowledge \^^^^ ^f Qq^ \\^2,\). is to be found in the vague and uncertain conjectures and fancies of minds left to their own groping after the Divine. If such a religion exists, furnishing clear and satisfying knowledge of God, His character, will, and ways, His relations to men, and tlie purposes of His grace, there is plainly great room and need in the world for it ; and the consideration of its claims cannot be barred by the assumption that the only valuable elements in any religion must be those which it has in common with all religions — which is the very point in dispute. The only question that can be properly raised is, Whether Christianity is a religion of this nature ? And this can only be ascertained by actual inspection. Impossibility Turning next to those within the Christian pale who would "docVinefrfm ^^^® *^® doctrinal element out of their religion, I confess I Christianity, find it difficult to understand on what grounds they can essence is extinct, and its soul is gone. It is a living relation, or it is nothing— a response to the Supreme Reality,"— /fZm^ Substitutes for God, p. 19. Strauss— '* None but a book student could ever imagine that a creation of the brain, woven of poetry and pliilosophy, can take the place of real religion." — In Kaiser Julian, p. 12 (quoted by Martineau). Cf. also Hartmann, Religionsphilosophie, ii. pp. 6-9. THE CHRISTIAN VIEW IN GENERAL. 23 justify their procedure. If there is a religion in the world, which exalts the office of teaching, it is safe to say that it is the religion of Jesus Christ. It has been frequently remarked that in pagan religions the doctrinal element is at a minimum — the chief thing there is the performance of a ritual.^ But this is precisely where Christianity distinguishes itself from other religions — it does contain doctrine. It comes to men with definite, positive teaching ; it claims to be the truth ; it bases religion on knowledge, though a knowledge which is only attainable under moral conditions. I do not see how any one can deal fairly with the facts as they lie before us in the Gospels and Epistles, without coming to the conclusion that the New Testament is full of doc- trine. The recently founded science of " New Testament Theology," which has already attained to a position of such commanding importance among the theological disciplines, is an unexceptionable witness to the same fact. And this is as it should be. A religion based on mere feeling is the vaguest, most unreliable, most unstable of all things. A strong, stable, religious life can be built up on no other ground than that of intelligent conviction. Christianity, therefore, addresses itself to the intelligence as well as to the heart. It sounds plausible indeed to say, Let us avoid all doctrinal subtleties; let us keep to a few plain, easy, simple propositions, in regard to which there will be general agreement. But, unfortunately, men will think on those deep problems which lie at the root of religious belief — on the nature of God, His character, His relations to the world and men, sin, the means of deliverance from it, the end to which things are moving, — and if Christianity does not give them 1 Cf. Professor R. Smith's Religion of tlie Semites — "The antique religions had for the most part no creed ; they consisted entirely of institutions and practices. ... In all the antique religions mythology takes the place of dogma, that is, the sacred lore of priests and people, so far as it does not consist of mere rules for the performance of religious acts, assumes the form of stories about the gods ; and these stories afford the only explanation that is offered of the precepts of religion and the prescribed rules of ritual."— P. 18. Objection to doctrine from the spiritualit)) of Christ ianity. f 24 THi: CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. an answer, suited to their deeper and more reflective moods, they will simply put it aside as inadequate for their needs. Everything depends here on what the Revelation of the Bible is supposed to be. If it is a few general elementary truths of religion we are in search of, it may freely be con- ceded that these might have been given in very simple form. But if we are to have a Eevelation such as the Bible pro- fesses to convey, — a Eevelation high as the nature of God, deep as the nature of man, universal as the wants of the race, which is to accompany man through all the ascending stages of his development, and still be felt to be a power and inspiration to him for further progress, — it is absurd to expect that such a Revelation will not have many profound and difficult things in it, and that it will not afford food for thought in its grandest and highest reaches. " Thy judg- ■' ments are a great deep." ^ A religion divorced from earnest and lofty thought has always, down the whole history of the Church, tended to become weak, jejune, and unwholesome ; while the intellect, deprived of its rights within religion, has sought its satisfaction without, and developed into godless rationalism. ^ Christianity, it is sometimes said, is a life, not a creed ; it is a spiritual system, and has nothing to do with dog- matic affirmations. But this is to confuse two things essen- / tially different — Christianity as an inward principle of conduct, I a subjective religious experience, on the one hand, and Christianity as an objective fact, or an historic magnitude, on the other. But can even the life be produced, or can it be sustained and nourished, without knowledge ? Here I cannot forbear the remark that it is a strange idea of many who urge this objection in the interests of what they conceive to be a more spiritual form of Christianity, that " spirituality " in a religion is somehow synonymous with vagueness and indefiniteness ; that the more perfectly they can vaporise or volatilise Christianity into a nebulous haze, ^ Ps. xxxvi. 6. THE CHRISTIAN VIE W IN GENERAL 25 in which nothing can be perceived distinctly, the nearer they / bring it to the ideal of a spiritual religion.^ This, it is safe to ) ^ — - — — , say, was not Paul's idea of spirituality — he by whom the distinction of " letter " and " spirit " was most strongly em- phasised. The region of the spiritual was rather with him, as it is throughout Scripture, the region of clearest insight and most accurate perception — of full and perfect knowledge {eirl'yvMai';). His unceasing prayer for his converts was, not that their minds might remain in a state of hazy in- distinctness, but that God would give them " a spirit of wisdom and revelation in the knowledge of Him, having the eyes of (their) heart enlightened," that they might grow up in this knowledge, till they should " all attain unto the unity of the faith, and of the knowledge of the Son of God, unto a full-grown man, unto the measure of the stature of the fulness of Christ." 2 / But the objection to the recognition of doctrine in Christ- Objection to ianity may be raised from the side of Christian positivism, do<:trinefrom as well as from that of Christian mysticism. Christianity, christian it will be here said, is a fact-revelation — it has its centre in a positivism, living Christ, and not in a dogmatic creed. And this in a sense is true. The title of my Lectures is the acknowledg- ment of it. The facts of Eevelation are before the doctrines built on them. The gospel is no mere proclamation of " eternal truths," but the discovery of a saving purpose of God for mankind, executed in time. But the doctrines are the interpretation of the facts. The facts do not stand blank and dumb before us, but have a voice given to them, and a meaning put into them. They are accompanied by living speech, which makes their meaning clear. When John declares that Jesus Christ is come in the flesh, and is the Son of God,^ he is stating a fact, but h^ is none the less enunciating a doctrine. When Paul affirms, " Christ died for our sins according to the Scriptures," * he is proclaiming a ^ Cf. Bartlett's The Letter and the Spirit (Barnpton Lectures, 1888). 2 Eph. i. 17, 18 ; iv, 13. '^ 1 John iv. 2, 15. ^ 1 Cor. xv. 3. 26 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. The theology of Schleier- mac her. fact, but he is at the same time giving an interpretation of it. ISTo writer has laid more stress on the fact, and less on the doctrine, in primitive Christianity than Professor Har- nack, yet he cannot help saying, " So far as the God and Father of Jesus Christ is believed in as the Almighty Lord of heaven and earth, the Christian religion includes a definite knowledge of God, of the world, and of the world-aim." ^ This concedes in principle all that I maintain. It affirms that the facts of Christianity rightly understood and inter- preted, not only yield special doctrines, but compel us to develop out of them a determinate " Weltanschauung." This is precisely the assertion of the present Lectures. If I refer for a moment in this connection to Schleier- macher, who may be named as the most distinguished representative of the theology of feeling, it is because I think that the position of this remarkable man on the question before us is frequently misunderstood. Schleier- macher's earlier views are not unlike some of those we have already been considering, and are entangled in many diffi- culties and inconsistencies in consequence. I deal here only with his later and more matured thought, as represented in his work Der christlicJie Glauhe. In it also piety is still defined as feeling. It is, he says, neither a mode of knowing, nor a mode of action, but a mode of feeling, or of immediate self-consciousness. It is the consciousness of ourselves as absolutely dependent, or, what comes to the same thing, as standing in relation with God.^ In his earlier writings he had defined it more generally as the immediate feeling of the infinite and eternal, the immediate consciousness of the being ^ Gi'undriss der Dogmengeschichte, i. p. 1. I have used tlie word 'doctrine' in these discussions, and kept clear of ' dogma, ' which is often used with a prejudice. * Dogma ' I take to be a formulation of doctrine stamped with some ecclesiastical authority. If there are doctrines, no objection can reasonably be taken to the formulation of them. It is beyond my purpose to discuss the wider question of the utility and necessity of creeds for church purposes. Cf. Lect. VI. in Dr. Rainy's Delivery and Development of Christian Doctrine (Cunningham Lectures). 2 Der Christ. Glauhe, Sects. 3 and 4. THE CHRISTIAN VIEW IN GENERAL 27 of all that is finite in the infinite, of all that is temporal in the eternal, awakened by the contemplation of the universe.^ But along with this must be taken into account Schleier- macher's view of the nature of feeling. According to him feeling is less the opposite of knowledge than that pure, original state of consciousness — prior to both knowledge and action — out of which knowledge and action may subsequently be developed.^ In Christianity this raw material of the religious consciousness receives, as it were, a definite shaping and content. The peculiarity in the Christian consciousness is that everything in it is referred back upon Jesus Christ, and the Eedemption accomplished through Him.^ This moving back from the religious consciousness to the Person of the sinless Eedeemer as the historical cause of it is already a transcending of the bounds of a theology of mere feeling. Theology is no longer merely a description of states of consciousness, when it leads us out for an explanation of these states into the region of historic fact. But an equally important circumstance is that, while describing the Christian consciousness mainly in terms of feeling, Schleiermacher does not deny that a dogmatic is implicitly contained in this con- sciousness, and is capable of development out of it. His DcT christliclie Glaube is, on the contrary, the unfolding of such a dogmatic. His position, therefore, is not ofi'hand to be identified with that of the advocates of a perfectly un- dogmatic Christianity. These would rule the doctrinal ele- ment out of Christianity altogether. But Schleiermacher, while he lays the main stress in the production of this con- sciousness of Eedemption in the believer on the Person of the Eedeemer, and only subordinately on His teaching, yet recognises in Christian piety a positive, given content^ and out of this he evolves a clearly defined and scientifically arranged system of doctrines.^ It is to be regretted that in ^ Cf. Pfleiderer's Eeligionsphilosophie, i. p. 308 (Eng. trans.). 2 Der Christ. Glaube, Sect. 3. 2. ^ Der christ. Glaube, Sect. 11. * See Note L. — Schleiermacher on Dogmatics. 2 8 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WO RID. the foundation of his theology — the doctrine of God — Schleiermacher never broke with his initial assumption that God cannot be known as He really is, but only as reflected in states of human consciousness, and therefore failed to lift his theology as a whole out of the region of subjectivity. Objection to A chief reason probably why many entertain a prejudice doctrine drawn against the admission of a definite doctrinal content in y>-^;;/ progress . ,,..,. . i -i in theology. Christianity is that they think it militates against the idea of " progress " in theology. How does the matter stand in this respect ? Growth and advance of some kind, of course, there is and must be in theology. It cannot be that the other departments of knowledge unceasingly progress, and theology alone stands still. No one familiar with the history of theology will deny that great changes have taken place in the shape which doctrines have assumed in the course of their development, or will question that these changes have been determined largely by the ruling ideas, the habits of thought, the state of knowledge and culture of each particular time. The dogmatic moulds which were found adequate for one age have often proved insufficient for the next, to which a larger horizon of vision has been granted ; and have had to be broken up that new ones might be created, more adapted to the content of a Eevelation which in some sense transcends them all. I recognise therefore to the full the need of growth and progress in theology.^ Bit by bit as the ages go on we see more clearly the essential lineaments of the truth as it is in Jesus ; we learn to disengage the genuine truths of Christ's gospel from human additions and corrup- tions ; we apprehend their bearings and relations with one another, and with new truths, more distinctly ; we see them in new points of view, develop and apply them in new ways. All this is true, and it is needful to remember it, lest to temporary points of view, and human theories and formu- Cf. Dr. Rainy's Delivery and Development of Doctrine (Cunningham Lectures). On the position criticised see, e.g.y Bartlett's The Letter and the Spirit (Bampton Lectures, 1888). THE CHRISTIAN VIE W IN GENERAL. 29 lations, we attribute an authority and completeness which in no way belong to them. But it does not by any means — - follow from this that, therefore, everything in Christianity is fluent, — that it has no fixed starting-points, no definite basal lines, no sure and moveless foundations, no grand determinative positions which control and govern all thought within distinctively Christian limits, — still less that, in the course of its long history, theology has achieved nothing, or has reached no results which can fairly be regarded as settled. This is the exaggeration on the other side, and so far from being helpful to progress in theology, it is in reality the denial of its possibility. Progress in theology implies that there is something to develop — that some truths at all events, relating to God and to Divine things, are ascertainable, and are capable of scientific treatment. It is easy to speak of the attempt to " limit infinite truth within definite for- mulae " ; but, on the other hand, unless some portion at least of this infinite truth can be brought within range of the human faculties, theology has nothing to work on. It is a pseudo-science, and to speak of progress in it is idle. II. The recent tendency in continental theology, however, //, DisHnc- is not so much to deny the existence of a definite ^^^'^ between a ^^ religious''^ "Weltanschauung" in the Bible, as rather to lay stress on and a '' t/ieo- the distinction between a " religious " and a " theoretic " view of ^^^^^ " ^^^ ^f the world — tlie world — ascribing to Christianity the former but not the ^/^^ RitschUan latter. This is the position of the school of Bitschl, and tJ^eology. truth and error are so intimately blended in it that it is necessary to give it our careful consideration.^ That a sound distinction underlies the terms " religious " and " theoretic " is not to be disputed, and it is important that its nature should be rightly understood. But under the plea of expelling metaphysics from theology, the tendency is at present to revive this distinction in a form which practically amounts to the resuscitation of the old doctrine of a " double truth" — the one religious, the other philosophical; and it ^ See Note M. — Religious and Theoretic Knowledge. 30 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. is not held necessary that even where the two overlap they should always be found in agreement. It is not simply that the two kinds of knowledge have different spheres, move in different orbits, and have to do with a different class of objects ; for this Eitschl at least denies.^ But they set out from different starting-points, judge by different standards, and as a consequence frequently lead to different results. Keligious knowledge, Pdtschl holds, moves only in the sphere of what he calls worth- or value -judgments. That is to say, it judges of things, not according to their objective nature and relations, but according to their value for us — according to their fitness to meet and satisfy religious necessities.'^ This, logically, would lead to pure subjectivism, and in the hands of some of Eitschl's followers actually does so.^ This tendency is strengthened by the theory of knowledge to which this school generally has committed itself, — a theory Kantian in its origin, — which, denying to the mind any power of knowing things as they are, limits it within the sphere of phenomenal representations. Eitschl himself tries hard to ward off this reproach of subjectivity from his system, and makes more than one attempt to find a bridge from the practical to the theoretic, but with no real success. He never quits the ground that it is not the objective truth of things — which would carry us into the region of theoretic knowledge — which forms the subject- matter of our inquiry in theology, but solely their subjective aspects as related to our own states of pleasure and pain, or as helping or hindering the ends sought in religion. In his doctrines of God and Christ, of Providence and miracle, of sin and Eedemption, as we shall afterwards see, it is constantly this subjective aspect of things, which may be very different from our actual or scientific judgment upon them, which is brought into prominence. Eeligion requires, for example, 1 See passages quoted in Note N.— Eitschl on Religion and Philosophy. '^ See Ritschl's discussion in Eecht. uiid Versohmmg, iii. 3rd ed. pp. 192-202; an 1 in his Theolocfie U7id Metaphysik. 3 E.g. Bender of Bonn. THE CHRISTIAN VIEW IN GENERAL. 31 that we view the universe from a teleological and not from a causal standpoint, and therefore that we postulate God and ~ ~ Providence. But these are only practical, not theoretic notions, and the mechanical and causal view of the universe may stand alongside of them intact. "Miracle" is the religious name for an event which awakens in us a powerful impression of the help of God, but is not to be held as interfering wdth the scientific doctrine of the unbroken connection of nature.^ Not only are the two spheres of knowledge to be thus kept apart in our minds, but we are not to be allowed to trace any lines of relation between them. We are not to be allowed, e.g., to seek any theoretic proof of the existence of God ; or to ask how special Providence, or the efficacy of prayer, or supernatural Eevelation, or miracle, or even our own freedom, is to be reconciled with the reign of unbroken natural causation. All such inquiries are tabooed as a mixing up of distinct spheres of knowledge ; with the result, however, that they are not really kept apart, but that all in the ideas of Providence, miracle, prayer, etc., which con- flicts with the theoretic view, is explained away. It should scarcely require much argument to convince us Criticism of that this proposal to divide the house of the mind into two ^^'.^ ^'^''^'Z'^'' ^ ^ view — rehgi- compartments, each of which is to be kept sacredly 2i^d,Y\, ous and theo- from the other, is a perfectly illusory and untenable one. ^^^^^ 'f"^^' relative truth ' ^ Cf., e.g., Ritschl's remarks on "Miracle" in his Unterricht in der christ. of this distinc- Religion, pp. 14, 15 — "We entirely change the religious representation of the tio7i. miracle if we measure it by the si-ientific acceptation of a connection through law of all natural occurrences. Since this idea lies outside the horizon of the men of the Old and the New Testaments, the miracle never means for them an event contrary to nature, or a breaking through natural law by Divine caprice. For this reason, faith in miracles, in the sense above indicated of a gracious Providence of God, is throughout reconcilable with the probability of the connection through natural law of the whole world. If certain narratives of miracles in the books of the Bible appear to collide with this order, it is neither a task of science to explain this appearance, or hold fast the event as fact ; nor is it a religious task to recognise these related occurrences as Divine effects contrary to natural laws. . . . But out of his religious faith will each man experience a miracle in himself, and in comparison with this nothing is less necessary than that he should grub over the miracles which others have experienced." 32 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. It might have some meaning in an aesthetic theory of rehgion, in which the religious conceptions are avowedly treated as pure ideals, but it can have none where the speech is of religious " knowledge." There are indeed different modes of cognising the same object, as well as different stages and degrees of real knowledge. If by " theoretic knowledge " is meant only knowledge gained by the methods of exact science, or by philosophical reflection, then, apart from religion altogether, there are vast fields of our knowledge which will not come under this category. The knowledge, for example, which we have of one another in the common intercourse of life, or the knowledge which the ordinary man gathers from his experience of the outward world, is very different in purity of theoretical character from the kind of knowledge aimed at by the psychologist or metaphysician, or by the student of science in his investigations of nature. It is as far removed as possible from the disinterested character which Eitschl ascribes to the knowledge he calls " theo- retical." Yet there is no part of this knowledge in which theoretic activities are not present. The same processes of thought which are employed in philosophy and science are implied in the simplest act of the understanding. In like manner, we may grant that there is a distinction of character and form — not to speak of origin — between religious and what may be called theoretic knowledge ; and that thus far the distinction insisted on by Eitschl and his school has a certain relative justification. Eeligion, assuredly, is not a theoretical product. It did not originate in reasoning, but in an immediate perception or experience of the Divine in some of the spheres of its natural or supernatural mani- festation ; for the reception of which again a native capacity or endowment must be presupposed in the human spirit. Even Eevelation implies the possession of this capacity in man to cognise the manifestations of the Divine when they are set before him. Originating in this way, religious knowledge — at least in its first or immediate form — is dis- THE CHRISTIAN VIE W IN GENERAL 33 tinguished by certain peculiarities. For one thing, it is distinguished from strictly theoretic knowledge by the prac- tical motive which obtains in it. /Theoretic knowledge aims at a representation of objects 'in their purely objective character and relations. Eeligion, on the other hand, seeks to set its objects before it in those lights, and under those aspects, which directly subserve religious ends. With this difference of aim is connected a difference of form. Theo- retic knowledge is cool, clear, and scientifically exact. Eeligious knowledge is touched with emotion, and moves largely in the region of figurative conception, or what the Germans would call " Vorstellung." In the first place, religion, as having to do with the personal relation of the soul to God, moves in a sphere in which the affections and emotions are necessarily allowed large play. Its modes of apprehension are therefore warm, lively, impassioned, intuitiva It groups its material under the influence of the dominant feeling ; lays holds of those sides and relations of the object which affect itself, and lets the others drop out of view ; leaps over intermediate links of causation, and seeks to grasp the object at once in its essential reality and inner signifi- cance — in its relation to its ultimate cause and final end. A second cause which leads to the same result is that the objects with which religion has to deal are largely tran- scendental — that is, they lie beyond the range and conditions of our present experience. A certain amount of figurative representation necessarily enters into the purest conceptions we are able to form of such objects.,^ To the extent now indicated we may agree with Eitschl Error oj the that religion moves — if he chooses to phrase it so — in the ^]^^^^^^^^^ view — im- ■ f sphere of value-judgments, and not in that of scientific ^^^^^^27//;/ ^/ [^ apprehension. But this is not to be interpreted as if •^«^^^'?^«^ faith and religion did not affirm the objective truth of the ideas it reason, or re- entertains — as if its judgments of value were not at the Hgious and theoretic. ^ I may refer for further discussion of tliis subject to an article of my own on *'Tlie Ritschlian Theology" in The Thinker for August 1892. 3 34 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW 01 THE WORLD. A theoretic element ini- plied in all theology. same time judgments of truth. Still less is it to be con- ceded that there is any necessary divorce between the mind in its practical and the mind in its theoretical activities, so that propositions may be affirmed in the one sphere which have no relation to, can receive no corroboration from, may even be contradicted by, propositions affirmed in the other. Thus to tear asunder faith and reason is to render no service to religion, but is to pave the way for theoretical scepticism. It is in truth the same reason which works in both spheres ; the results, therefore, must be such as admit of comparison. If Eitschl would raise a bar against any such comparison of the results of religious thinking with the conclusions reached by philosophy and science — leaving each to work in its own domain — a more just view of the subject will recognise that this is impossible. We cannot have two spheres of truth lying side by side in the same mind without some effort to arrive at an adjustment between them. Still less is it possible for the mind to find itself in conflict with itself, — on the one side, for instance, affirming the personality of God, on the other denying it ; on the one side affirming freedom, Eevelation, miracle, on the other unbroken natural causation, — and not do what it can to annul the discrepancy. Nor will reason in practice be content to remain in this state of division with itself. It will insist on its knowledge being brought to some sort of unity, or, if this cannot be done, in regarding one or other of the conflicting propositions as illusive. Finally, it is not sufficiently recognised by Eitschl and his school that religion itself, while in the first instance prac- tical, carries in it also the impulse to raise its knowledge to theoretic form. Faith cannot but seek to advance to know- ledge — that is, to the reflective and scientific comprehension of its own contents. Just because its propositions are held to be not only " judgments of value," but to contain objective truth, they must be capable of being submitted to theoretic treatment. Eitschl himself recognises the necessity of con- THE CHRISTIAN VIEW US GENERAL. 35 structing a theology which shall be adequate to the contents of the Christian Eevelation. Only he would have it move solely within the region of faith-propositions, or, as he calls them, "judgments of value." Its task is ended when it has faithfully collected, purely expressed, and internally co- ordinated these religious affirmations.^ It is not observed how much theoretic and critical activity is already implied in this very process of collating, sifting, and co-ordinating ; or how largely, in Eitschl's own case, the results are dependent on the theoretic presuppositions with which he sets out in his (metaphysical) doctrine of knowledge, and his general theory of religion. But, waiving this, it is surely vain to ask theology to go so far, and then say it is to go no further. Christian science has many tasks beyond those which the Eitschlian limitation would prescribe for it. How, for example, can it refuse the task of investigating its own grounds of certainty ? How can it help raising the question of how far these religious conceptions, now brought to expression and co-ordinated, answer to objective truth ? How can it avoid asking if this content of the Christian Eevelation receives no verification from the laws of man's spiritual life, or in what this verification consists ? Can it help going back on its own presuppositions, and asking what these are, and what kind of view of God and man they imply ? How can it lielp connecting this truth given in Eevelation with truth in other departments ? And this investigation is not a mere matter of choice in theology ; it is forced on it as a necessity. For in the very process of collation and criticism questions arise which can only be solved by going further down. Antinomies arise within theology itself ; the different sides of Biblical truth have to be harmonised in a wider conception ; unity of view has to be sought in a field where only parts are given, and much is left to be inferred. All this involves a large amount of theoretic treatment in theology, and may — I should rather ^ Cf. Ritschl, Rtclit. und Ver. iii. pp. 14-16. 36 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. say must — result in showing that the truths of Eevelation have also a theoretic side, and are capable of theoretic veri- fication and corroboration.^ I conclude, therefore, that it is legitimate to speak of a Christian " Weltanschauung," and that we are not debarred investigating its relations to theoretic knowledge. ^ See Kote 0. — The Hegelian Theory of K^ligion. APPENDICES TO LECTURE L APPENDIX I. SKETCH OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. It may conduce to clearness if, having indicated the general scope and purport of these Lectures, I now give in this Appendix a brief statement in prepositional form of what I consider the Christian view of the world to be, and sketch on the basis of this the course to be pursued in the succeeding Lectures. I. First, then, the Christian view affirms the existence of a Personal, Ethical, Self-Eevealing God. It is thus at the outset a system of Theism, and as such is opposed to all systems of Atheism, Agnosticism, Pantheism, or mere Deism. II. The Christian view affirms the creation of the world by God, His immanent presence in it^ His transcendence over it, and His holy and wise government of it for moral ends. III. The Christian view affirms the spiritual nature and dignity of man — his creation in the Divine image, and destination to bear the likeness of God in a perfected relation of sonship. IV. The Christian view affirms the fact of the sin and ^ disorder of the world, not as something belonging to the 38 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORID. Divine idea of it, and inhering in it by necessity, but as something which has entered it by the voluntary turning aside of man from his allegiance to his Creator, and from the path of his normal development. The Christian view of the world, in other words, involves a Fall as the presupposi- tion of its doctrine of Eedemption ; whereas the *' modern " view of the world affirms that the so-called Fall was in reality a rise, and denies by consequence the need of \ Eedemption in the scriptural sense. V. The Christian view affirms the historical Self-Eevelation of God to the patriarchs and in the line of Israel, and, as brought to light by this, a gracious purpose of God for the salvation of the world, centring in Jesus Christ, His Son, and the new Head of humanity. / VI. The Christian view affirms that Jesus Christ w^as not mere man, but the eternal Son of God — a truly Divine Person — who in the fulness of time took upon Him our humanity, and who, on the ground that in Him as man there dwells the fulness of the Godhead bodily, is to be honoured, worshipped, and trusted, even as God is. This is the tran- scendent " mystery of godliness " ^ — the central and amazing assertion of the Christian view — by reference to which our relation is determined to everything else which it contains. Pausing for a moment on this truth of the Incarnation, we have to notice its central place in the Christian system, and how through its light every other doctrine is illuminated and transformed. 1. The Incarnation sheds new light on the nature of God, and, in conjunction with the work of the Spirit, reveals Him as triune — Father, Son, and Spirit — one God. 2. The Incarnation sheds new light on the doctrine of creation — all things being now seen to be created by Christ, as well as for Him. 1 1 Tim. iii. 16. SKETCH OF THE CHRISTIAN VIE W. 39 3. The Incarnation sheds new light on the nature of man, alike as respects its capacity for union with the Divine, its possibilities of perfection, and the high destinies awaiting it in the future. 4. The Incarnation sheds new light on the purpose of i God in the creation and Eedemption of man — that end being, in the words of Paul, "in the dispensation of the fulness of times to gather together in one all things in Christ, both which are in heaven, and which are on earth, even in Him." ^ 5. The Incarnation sheds new light on the permission of j sin by showing the possibility of Eedemption from it, and how, through the Eevelation of the Divine purposes of mercy, a far grander discovery is made of the Divine character, and far higher prospects are opened up for humanity. VII. The Christian view affirms the Eedemption of the world through a great act of Atonement — this Atonement to be appropriated by faith, and availing for all who do not wilfully withstand and reject its grace. VIII. The Christian view affirms that the historical aim of Christ's work was the founding of a Kingdom of God on earth, which includes not only the spiritual salvation of individuals, but a new order of society, the result of the action of the spiritual forces set in motion through Christ. IX. Finally, the Christian view affirms that history has a goal, and that the present order of things will be terminated by the appearance of the Son of Man for judgment, the resurrection of the dead, and the final separation of righteous and wicked; final, so far as the Scriptures afford any light, or entitle us to hold out any hope. Beyond this are the eternal ages, on whose depths only stray lights fall, as in that remarkable passage : " Then 1 Eph. i. 10. 40 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. Cometh the end, when He shall have delivered up the kingdom to God, even the Father . . . then shall the Son also Him- self be subject unto Him that put all things under Him, that God may be all in all," ^ — and on the mysterious blessed- ness or sorrow of which, as the ease may be, it is needless to speculate. I have for clearness' sake exhibited this outline of the Christian view in a series of propositions, but I need hardly say that it is not my intention to attempt to exhaust this outline, or anything like it, in this brief course of Lectures. In the actual treatment of my subject, I shall be guided very much by the way in which the main positions of the Christian view are related to current theories and negations. 1. It is plain that the Christian view of the world is theistic, and as such is opposed, as already said, to all the views which deny a living personal God, and also to Deism, which denies Eevelation. 2. The Christian views of nature and man come into conflict with many current theories. They involve, for example, the ideas of creation, and of the spirituality, freedom, and immortal destiny of man — all of which the thoroughgoing " modern " view of the world opposes. 3. The Christian view of sin is irreconcilable with modern theories which represent sin as a necessity of development, and nullify its true conception by starting man off at a stage but little removed from that of the brutes. At least I take this to be the case, and shall endeavour to give reasons for my opinion. The above denials, if logically carried out, involve the ' rejection of the Christian view as a whole. We reject the Christian view in toto, if we deny the existence of God, the spiritual nature and immortality of man, or destroy the idea of sin. In what follows we are rather in the region of Christian heresy ; at least the total rejection of the Christian 1 1 Cor. XV. 24-28. SKETCH OF THE CHRISTIAN VIE W. 41 view is not necessarily implied, though in its mutilation it is found that neither can that which is preserved be per- manently maintained. 4. The assertion of the Incarnation may he met by a lower estimate of Christ's Person than the full Christian doctrine implies; or by the complete denial of the super- natural dignity of His Person. 5. The Christian view may be met by the denial of the need or the reality of Atone-ment, or by inadequate or unscriptural representations of that great doctrine. 6. There may be unscriptural denials, as well as un- warrantable dogmatisms, in the matter of eschatology. My course then, in view of the various antitheses, will shape itself as follows : — First, keeping in mind that it is the Incarnation which is the central point in the Christian view, I shall look in the second Lecture at the alternatives which are historically presented to us if this doctrine is rejected. Next, in the third, fourth, and fifth Lectures, I shall con- sider in order the three postulates of the Christian view — God, Nature and Man, and Sin. The sixth Lecture will be devoted to the Incarnation itself, and the seventh to the consideration of some related topics — the higher Christian concept of God, and the relation of the Incarnation to the plan of the world. The eighth Lecture will treat of the Incarnation and Ee- demption from sin, and the concluding Lecture will treat of the Incarnation and human destiny.^ ^ The original plan embraced a Lecture between Lectnre VIII. and what is now IX. — on " Tlie Incarnation and New Life of Humanity : the Kingdom of God." The subject is touched on in Lecture IX., and dealt with more fully in an Appendix. APPENDIX II. IDEA OF THE " WELTANSCHAUUNG." The litera- The liistory of this term has yet to be written. The best tureofthe gpecial Contribution to the discussion of the idea I have met subject. ^ with is in a book entitled, Bic Weltanschauung des Qhristen- thums, by August Baur (1881), which I regret I did not come across till my own work was finished. The same writer has contributed an article on " The Notion and Ground-plan of the ' Weltanschauung ' generally, and of the Christian in particular," to the Jahrhilcher d. jprot. Theologie, vol. iii. A valuable examination of the subject is contained also in an able work published in 1887, Das menschliclie Erltennen, Grund- linien der Erkenntnisstheorie, und Metaphysik, by Dr. A. Dorner. I might further refer to Hartmann's Religionsjpliilosopliie. Zweiter Theil : Die Religion des Gcistes, which, on this particu- lar subject, contains a good deal of most suggestive matter (pp. 1-55). As may be gathered from the remarks in the close of the Lecture, the idea has a large place in the writings of the Eitschlian school. It is discussed with special fulness and care in Hermann's Die Religion im Verhaltniss zum Welterhennen und zur SittlichJceit, the last section of which bears the heading, " The Task of the Dogmatic Proof of the Christian ' Weltanschauung.' " Lipsius also devotes considerable attention to it in the first part of his Dogmatik (sects. 16-115). A. Baur— A. Baur, in the book above named, expresses his surprise prevalence of ^^^ yqioxq, has not been done for the elucidation of a term the term. which has become one of the favourite terms of the day ; IDEA OF THE " WELTANSCHA UUNGP 43 and alludes to the absence of any explanation of it (a fact which had struck myself) in books professedly dealing with the terminology of philosophy and theology, as, e.g., Rud. Eucken's Geschiclite und Kritik cler Grundbegriffe der Gegenwart (1878), and Geschiclite der philosopMschen Terminologie (1879)/ He remarks — " From all sides the word ' Weltanschauung ' sounds out to meet us, and we may, without impropriety, say that the conflict in the culture-movement of the present is a conflict of ' Weltanschauungen.' ^ But how entirely is there wanting a clear and intelligible, universally valid notion of the word itself ! . . . But the power which this word has in our time, which is so strong that scientific thought also has been compelled to recognise and come to an understanding with it, awakens a predisposition to a favourable judgment, and leads to the hope that the word will become a per- manent possession of scientific work." ^ He refers not only to Striving of the the prevalence of the term, but to the striving in our own ao^e ^^^ ^•'^^!' . ^ ' o o general Views. after the formation of " Weltanschauungen." " The earnest- ness," he says, " with which, even on the side of Materialism, search is made for a ' Weltanschauung ' which shall be satis- fying, and at the same time comprehensive of moral relations, taken in connection with the general devotion to the problem of the ' Weltanschauung,' is highly significant and deserving of attention for the present." * A valuable service of the The " Welt- book is the corroboration it affords of the truth that a com- ^''''^^<^^^^/" a unity of plete ' Weltanschauung ' cannot be based on the natural alone, nattcral and or the theoretic alone, but implies a unity of the natural and ^<'^^^- the moral, which can only be ultimately accomplished on the ^ Eucken himself, however, uses it, as when he says, ' * Bohme strives after an expression for the notion of consciousness and self-consciousness, which has a central place within his ' Weltanschauung ' " {Gesch. der phil. Term, p, 128) ; and has recently published an admirable historical and critical work, elsewhere referred to, bearing the kindred title. Die Lehensanschauungen der grossen Denker (1890). This work contains a valuable section on " Die christliche Welt and die Lehensanschauungen Jesu" (pp. 154-205). 2 Cf. Karl Peters, Willemwelt, etc., p. 107 — " It is certain that the conflict of * Weltanschauungen ' burns to-day more vehemently than ever." See also the brochure, Im Kampf um die Weltanschauung, referred to in Note A. 3 Pp. 1-4. 4 p. 24. 44 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. "basis of religion.^ He says, " The ' Weltanschauung ' is not a purely theoretical relation to nature, although the theoretic moment is undeniably contained in it, — not a purely dis- interested apprehension and knowledge of the world, for the sake of the principle of knowledge itself ; it relates generally not to the world as a sum of particulars, as if it were de- pendent on the comprehension of particulars ; it includes much more a personal, practical interest of the onlooker as a funda- mental element in itself ; for it is a judgment of worth upon the world as a whole, as a single given magnitude in space and time, in relation to the life-aim, to the life-determination of the viewing subject. This judgment upon the world can indeed be excited through the peculiarity of personal experi- ence in the world, nay, must be, in view of the social relations in which man stands, but it does not originate from sensuous perception, or from physical existence, but is a direction of the disposition and will, and on that account belongs not to physics but to ethics. . . . The * Weltanschauung ' is a consideration and valuation of exist- ence in space and time in the light of our proper life-aiin, which in the most general sense of the word we are able to designate a moral one." ^ Relation of Probably Baur underrates too much the strength of the practical Purely theoretic or rational impulse in disposing man to seek motive. the unity of his experiences in a " Weltanschauung," though it is granted that in every concrete case, even where there is most appearance of disinterestedness, theoretical and practical ^ The headings of the chapters of Baur's book will suffice to show its import- ance for our subject. They are — 1. The general notion of the "Weltanschauung." 2. Characterisation and criticism of the objections of the modern spirit against religion and the religious " Weltanschauung." 3. Possibility and necessity of an ideal, supersensible " Weltanschauung." 4. The supersensible, ideal ""Weltanschauung" according to its essence, and in its transition to the religious *' Weltanschauung" generally. 5. The "Weltanschauung" of Christianity. In theology A. Baur is a folloAver of Alex. Schweitzer, of whom a good notice may be seen in Pfleiderer' s i^eve^opmen^ of Theology ^ pp. 125-130. 2 Pp. 21-25. . . IDEA OF THE " WELTANSCHA UUNGP 45 motives are mixed, and that on the basis of the theoretic alone a complete or satisfying view is not attainable. Baur, however, is not alone in this. The Eitschlian school carries Views which this insistence on practical motive to much greater lengths, ^^^^i^"^ ^^^ ^ & b 'practical and will allow no origin for the " Weltanschauung " but that motive alone— which springs from religion or moralitv. Eitschl, e.g., traces ^^^ Ritsckhan school. the tendency to the formation of general views of the world „. ,, solely to the religious impulse. Philosophy also, he says, origin of the " raises the claim to produce in its own way a view of the " ^^^^^«- schauung. world as a whole ; but in this there betrays itself much more an impulse of a religious kind, which philosophers must dis- tinguish from their method of knowledge." ^ This is con- nected with his view that religion itself originates in the need which man feels of help from a supernatural power to enable him to maintain his personality against the limitations and hindrances of natural existence.^ Since, however, he allows that philosophy has as part of its task " the aim of compre- hending the world- whole in a highest law," and that " the thought of God which pertains to religion is also employed in some form in every philosophy which is not materialistic," ^ ^ Die Christ. Lehre von der JRecJitfertigung und Versohnung, iii. p. 197 (3rd ed.). It is not observed that the motive of the "Weltanschauung" is some- times, as with Lucretius, to get away from religion. 2 " In all religions, " says Ritschl, "there is striven after, with the help of the exalted spiritual Power which man worships, the solution of the contra- diction in which man finds himself as part of the natural world, and as spiritual personality, which makes the claim to rule the world. For in the former position he is a part of nature, unable to withstand it, dependent and limited by other things ; but as spirit he is moved by the impulse to make good his independence against it." — Eecht. und Ver. iii. p. 189. More explicitly, "The religious 'Weltanschauung' is in all its forms grounded on this, that man in some degree distinguishes himself in worth from the natural appearances surrounding him, and from the workings of nature pressing upon him. Religion is the interpretation of the course of nature, to whatever extent it is recognised, in this sense, that the exalted spiritual powers (or spiritual Power) which rule in and over nature maintain and confirm to the personal spirit its claims, or its independence against the limitations arising from nature or the natural workings of human society." — Ibid. p. 17. At an earlier period, Ritschl had even spoken of God as a " help-conception" (Hilfs- vorstellung) for the attainment of his practical ends. This theory of religion is referred to in Note I. 3 P. 194. Cf. Note N.— Ritschl on Religion and Philosophy. 46 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WO RID. what he really contends for would seem to amount to no more than this, that theoretic knowledge alone cannot attain to that highest view of God which is given in the Christian religion, and which is necessary for the completion of a satisfactory view of the universe as a whole.^ The truth is, Eitschl's views vary very widely on these topics in the different editions of his chief work, and it is no easy task to reduce his statements to unity. Hermann In quite a similar spirit to Eitschl, his disciples Hermann on the same. ^^^ Kaftan conceive of the "Weltanschauung" as due only to the operation of the practical or religious motive. Hermann is the nearer to Eitschl, only that in his treatment the moral aim is made more prominent than the religious, and behind both stands the " feeling of self " (Selbstgefuhl), to which morality and religion are alike related as means. " It is not the purely theoretic in natural knowledge which produces that thought, but the practical impulse residing in it." 2 " From the person the representation of a world- whole is inseparable, since without the conviction of the reality of the same his own existence, with its inalienable claim, must appear meaningless." ^ The " Weltanschauung " is born out of " the self -feeling of man, his feeling of his worth, and the desire proceeding from this to see his worth established through the course of the world, in which he finds himself unceasingly involved." * " If I seek to represent a w^orld- whole, because, as a person conscious of my highest good, I will not to lose myself in the multitude of things, I thus maintain the impulse to religious faith. Whether the world- whole which I sketch for this end is thought of as theistic, ^ Ritsclil's own words, with which we heartily agree, are : ** If theoretical thought is ever to solve the problem of the world as a whole, it will have to fall back on the Christian view of God, of the world, and of human destiny " (2nd ed. p. 210). The variations in his positions are pointed out and adversely criticised by Pfleiderer in his papers on Die RitscliVsche Theologie (1891) ; by vStahlin in his Kant, Lotze, unci Ritschl (translated, 1889) ; by Bertrand in his Une Nouvelle Conception de la Redemption (1891), and by most of Eitschl's other critics. 2 Die Religion, etc., p. 37. ^ Ihid, p. 40. "* P. 82. IDEA 01^ THE ''WELTANSCHAUUNG:' 47 pantheistic, or materialistic, does not affect its general reli- gious character (!). Eeligion remains the conviction of such a world-whole in all its forms." ^ On the unsatisfactoriness of Hermann's view of the connection of religion with morality, and of both with the idea of the world-whole, see Pfleiderer in his BdigionspMlosoijJiie (Eng. trans, vol. ii. pp. 192-202), and Die RitscliVsclie Theologie, pp. 84-1 00.^ Kaftan is equally explicit. " The question is reasonable," Kafian on the he says, " how we are led to strive after a highest knowledge. "^^''^^* . . . The highest knowledge, I would recall, is identical with that which otherwise we well term the ' Weltanschauung ' of a man, and in it lies, at least for him who recognises a highest knowledge, the ultimate ground of decision for his con- duct. Manifestly, therefore, the highest knowledge has always equally a practical significance. But we cannot stop there. It must not less be said that it is a practical interest which lies at the foundation of this whole striving. We ask after the first cause and the last end of the world, because we ourselves belong to the world, and our fate is bound up with the world's. Whence come I ? and whither go I ? On these questions man seeks clearness, because, according to the answer which these questions find, he must direct his life. And this answer it is for the sake of which he concerns him- self about a higher knowledge."^ On the place of the religious motive in the formation of the " Weltanschauung " Kaftan is not so clear ; but he is explicit on the fact that religious faith demands the idea of the world as a whole. " The thought," he says in his earlier work, " of a world- whole belongs, as is well known, not to the customary experience which we have of the world ; neither does it ever 1 P. 86. 2 With the Ritschlian theologians religion and morality sustain only an external relation to each other. The deepest impulse is not religion, but self- maintenance (Hermann), or self-satisfaction (Kaftan). Religion is but a means to this end. ^ Die Wahrheit d. christ. Religion, p. ^389. See the whole discussion, pp. 383-435. 48 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WORLD. originate in the reflective elaboration of such experience, however far that may be carried. It has, therefore, been supposed that the thought of a world-whole is religious in its origin and character. ... Be this as it may, at all events religious faith relates to the world in its totality, since it is this which in our consciousness stands over against God, and to be distinguished from this belongs to the inalienable nature of God." ^ The peculiarity of the Christian " Weltanschauung " Kaftan sums up in the two positions — " that the world is perfectly dependent on God, and that He orders everything in it in conformity with the end of His holy love." ^ ^ Da^ Westn d, ckrisL Religion, p. 395. ^ Ihid. p. 393. LECTURE II. W(\t C})risttan mt'm antr its aiternattbes. " There has seldom been an age more irreligious than ours, yet it will be difficult to find one in which religious questions have been more pro- foundly discussed."— Hartmann. "In the history of systems an inexorable logic rids them of their halfness and hesitancies, and drives them straight to their inevitable goal. "— Martineau. " Conjecture of the worker by the work : Is there strength there ? — enough : intelligence ? Ample : but goodness in a like degree ? Not to the human eye in the present state, An isoscele deficient in the base. What lacks, then, of perfection fit for God But just the instance which this tale supplies Of love without a limit ? So is strength, So is intelligence ; let love be so. Unlimited in its self-sacrifice, Then is the tale true and God shows complete." E. Browning. LECTUKE 11. THE CHEISTIAN VIEW AND ITS ALTERNATIVES. It is the fundamental assumption of these Lectures that the Magnitude of central point in the Christian view of God and the world is ^^f asmmp- the acknowledgment of Jesus Christ as a truly Divine Person christian. — the Son of God made flesh. How is this assumption to be ^'^'^^• vindicated ? I do not conceal from myself that the issues involved in such an assertion are very stupendous. The belief in Jesus as the Son of God is not one to be lightly taken up, but, when it is taken up, it practically determines, as has already been said, a man's views on everything else in Christianity. No one will dispute that, if Jesus Christ is what the creeds declare Him to be — an Incarnation of the Divine — His Person is necessarily central in His own religion, nay, in the universe. Christianity, on this assump- tion, is correctly described as the Eeligion of the Incar- nation. On the other hand, this is precisely the view of the Person Rejection of of Christ which, we are told, the modern view of the world ^^'^ 'doctrine of compels us to reject. No doctrine stumbles the modern ^/^^^ ^^ ^,5^ mind so completely as this. It is flatly pronounced incredible ''modem''' and absurd. That Jesus was the holiest of men — the Divinest of the race, the most perfect exhibition of the god-like in humanity — may well be conceded ; but of literal Incarnation it is not permitted to the modern intelligence to speak. Science has to investigate the origin of tlie dogma ; to show how it arose from the powerful impression made by Jesus on His followers ; how it was shaped by Hebrew and Hellenic 52 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW modes of thought ; but it cannot for a moment entertain the possibility that the idea which it represents is true. As strenuously is our right resisted to speak of this doctrine as an essential and integral part of Christianity. Short of this conception, it is said, there are many grades of belief in Christ, and we are not entitled to un christianise any of them. To identify the essence of Christianity with the Incarnation is, it is held, to make a particular dogmatic interpretation of Christianity equivalent to Christianity itself. It is not, indeed, among the extremer sceptics that we find any difficulty in getting the acknowledgment that the Incarnation is central in Christianity. " It is," says Strauss, " certainly the central dogma in Christianity. Here the Founder is at the same time the most prominent object of worship ; the system based on Him loses its support as soon as He is shown to be lacking in the qualities appropriate to an object of religious worship." ^ " In Him alone," says Feuerbach, " is concentrated the Christian religion." - Quite logically, from his point of view, Strauss draws the conclusion, that since the Incarnation is untenable, Christianity falls to the ground with it. But others will not go thus far. They distinguish between Christianity and its accidents, and put this doctrine in the category of the accidents. Nay, it is ostensibly in the interests of what is supposed to be a purer and more primitive form of Christianity, that in many quarters the demand for the surrender of this doctrine is made. The cry is, " Back from Christianity to Christ " — back from the Christianity of the creeds, from the Christianity even of Paul and John — to the Christ of the simple Galilean gospel, who never dreamt of making Himself God. As Lessing, in a famous passage, distinguishes between " the religion of Christ " and " the Christian religion," meaning by the former the religion which Christ Himself professed and practised, and by the latter the superstructure of dogma subsequently ^ De,r alte und der neue Glauhe, pp. 43, 44. ^ Das Wesen des Chriatenthums, p. 147 (Eiig. trans.). AND ITS ALTERNA JIVES. 53 reared on this ; ^ so an analogous distinction is drawn between the Pauline and Johannine Christ, with His halo of super- ^^ natural attributes, and the meek and lowly Jesus, so intensely human, of the Synoptic gospels. Nevertheless, the ablest theology of the century will Central place sustain me in the cjeneral assertion, that the central principle ^^ ^^^^-^^'-^ ^ _ ^ ^ Person tn His of Christianity is the Person of its Pounder. Whatever religion. may be thought of the great speculative movement in the beginning of the century, connected with the names of Pichte and Schelling and Hegel, it cannot be denied that at least it rendered an essential service to theology in overcoming the shallow rationalism of the preceding period, and in restoring to its place of honour in the Christian system the doctrine of Christ's Person, which it had become customary to put in the background. Still more influential in this direction was the powerful impulse given to theology by Schleiermacher. Since that time all the best theology in Germany may be said to be Christoloo-ical. That Christ sustains a different relation to His religion from that of ordinary founders of religion to the faiths they have founded; that in Him there was a peculiar union of the Divine and human ; that His appearance and work were of decisive importance for the Church and for humanity — these are thoughts which may be said to be common to all the greater systems, irrespective of schools. They are found among theologians as widely separated in dogmatic standpoint and tendency as Eothe and Dorner, Biedermann and Lipsius^ Beyschlag and Eitschl, Luthardt and Frank. It is only outside the circles of really influential theology that we find a reversion to the loose deistic concep- tion of Christ as simply a Prophet or moral Teacher, like Moses or Confucius or Buddha.^ It is indeed a powerful proof of the view that the Person of Christ is of unique importance in His religion that, whenever a new breath of life passes over theology, and an attempt is made to gain a ^ Cf. Pfleiderer, JReligionsphilosopJiie, i. p. 141 (Eng. trans.). " See Note A. — The Central Place of Christ in His Religion. 54 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW profounder apprehension of Christianity, there is a recurrence to this idea, and the necessity is felt of doing justice to it ; thus testifying to the truth of Dorner's remark, " A Christian system which is unable to make Christology an integral part of itself has pronounced its own judgment ; it has really given up the claim to the title of Christian." ^ Differing At the same time, this acknowledgment of the central and estimates of unique place of the Founder of Christianity in His religion the Person of , , . « i • • Christ— does not settle the question of the precise estimate we are to methods of take of His Terson. Is He merely human, or is He Divine as well ? Or if Divine, in what sense do we attach this predicate to Him ? Is it, as with the Hegelians, the mere expression of a metaphysical idea — of that identity of the Divine and the human which is as true of all men as it is of Christ, only that it came first to clear consciousness in Him ? Or is it, as with Pdtschl, the mere expression of a value- judgment of the believer — a predicate denoting the worth which Christ has for the believing soul as the supreme Eevealer of God's character and purpose ? Or is it, as with others, an ethical Divinity that is ascribed to Christ — such participation in the Divine nature and life of Sonship as may be experienced also by the believer ? ^ Or shall we hold, in agreement with the general faith of the Church, that Christ is more than all this — that in Him the Divine pre-existing Word truly and personally became incarnate, and made our nature His own — that therefore He is the Son of God, not simply as we are, but in a high and transcendental sense, in which wc cannot compare ourselves with Him ? This question, in the present state of controversy, is not so easily settled as might at first sight appear. It is vain, of course, to appeal to the great ecclesiastical creeds, for it is they which are in dispute. It is vain also, at this stage, to attempt to settle the question by the simple method of citation of proof texts. The facts of Christ's self-revelation, 1 Doct. of Person of Christ, v. p. 49 (Eng. trans.). 2 Thus, e.g., AVendt in his Inhalt der Lehrx Jesu. AND ITS ALTERNATIVES. 55 and His witness to His own Person, must indeed, in the last resort, be the ground on which our faith in Him rests, and it ~ _ will be necessary at a later stage to examine this self-wdtness of Christ, as well as the apostolic doctrine, with considerable care.^ But at the outset this method is attended by obvious disadvantages. It is easy to say — the original documents of Christianity are before us ; let us examine them. But, for one thing, some of these documents — the Fourth Gospel, e.g.^ and some of the Pauline epistles — are themselves in dispute among our opponents ; and, even if genuine, their authority is not accepted as decisive. In the next jDlace, there is the question, w^hether there are not traces of development in the doctrine of the Person of Christ even within the JSI'ew Testament — whether all the sacred writers teach the same view. There are many, as I have already said, who will admit that Christ's Divinity is taught by Paul and John, who would deny that it is taught by Christ Himself. These are difficulties which cannot be satisfactorily met by mere assertion, and the question recurs, whether — as a provisional expedient at least — any other course is open to us ? There is another method which I propose to apply in this The method of Lecture, one which appears to me to have the advantaoje of ^^"^ Lecture— ^^ ^ ^ appeal to dealing with all these issues at once, and at the same time history. The deals with issues of a wider character. It is the method of %^^^^ ^^o^^- 7ne7it in appeal to history. The individual judgment may err in the history. opinions it forms, and in the conclusions it deduces from tliem. It is not given to any man to see all the consequences that follow from his own thinking. He may quite conceiv- ably hold in the scheme of his beliefs propositions that are inconsistent with each other, and, if logically carried out, would destroy each other, and not be aware of the fact. In history things get beaten out to their true issues. The strands of thought that are incompatible with each other get separated ; conflicting tendencies, at first unperceived, are brought to light ; opposite one-sidednesses correct each other ; 1 Cf. Lecture VI. 56 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW and the true consequences of theories reveal themselves with inexorable necessity. As Socrates, in Plato's BepuUic^ inves- tigating the nature of Justice, proposes to study it first as " writ large " in the collective magnitude of the State, that thereafter he may return with better knowledge to the study of it in the individual, so the movements of thought are best studied on the broad scale in which they present themselves over large periods of time. It is to this test I propose to bring the great question of Christianity — the same that was proposed by Jesus to the Pharisees eighteen hundred years ago — " What think ye of Christ ? Whose Son is He ? " "^ I shall ask what aid history affords us in determining the true estimate to be put upon the Person of Christ, and the place held in the Christian system by the doctrine of the Incar- nation. Advantage of It is One advantage of this method that, as I have said, it thismeihod. ^^^vug^ all the issucs into court at once. The verdict of history is at once a judgment on the answers which have been given to the theological question ; on their agreement with the sum - total of the facts of Christianity ; on the methods of exegesis and New Testament criticism by which they have been supported ; on their power to maintain them- selves against rival views ; on how far the existence of Christianity is dependent on them, or bound up with them. /. History a I. History, then, as it seems to me, presents us with a series ^alternatives— ^^ alternatives of a deeply interesting character, by studying the downward which we may find our bearings on this question, " What movement. ^^-^^^ ^^ ^^ ^j^^.^^ ^ „ ^^ ^^ ^^^ .^ ^^ ^^^^^ ^^^^ I. First alter-' 1. The first essential service which history has rendered native— a ^g ^^^ \iQ,QVL in the, elimination of intermediate mews — in Divine Christ, ^ _ -^ or humani- making it clear as a first alternative that the real issue on tarianism. ^j^^g q^^stion IS between a truly Divine Christ and pure \ humanitarianism. Intermediate views on Christ's Person have from time to time arisen, and still go on arising, in the 1 Book ii. 2 ;^iatt. xxii. 42. AND ITS ALTERNATIVES. 57 Church ; but, like the intermediate species of plants and animals Mr. Darwin tells us of, which are invariably driven to the wall in the struggle for existence, they have never been able to survive. There is, e.g., the Arian view, which Arianism. has appeared again and again in the history of the Church in times of spiritual decadence. To find a place for the high attributes ascribed to Christ in Scripture, a lofty supernatural dignity is in this view assigned to Him. He was a sort of supreme angel, God's First - born, His instrument in the creation of the w^orld, etc. But He was not eternal ; He was not of Divine essence. It is safe to say that this view is now practically extinct. It would be a shallow reading of history to attribute the defeat of Arianism in the early Church to the anathemas of councils, the influence of court favour, or any other accidental circumstances. It perished through its own inherent weakness.^ If the Arians admit all they profess to do about Christ — that He was pre-existent, God's agent in the creation of the world, etc. — there need be little difficulty in admitting the rest. On the other hand, if they stop short of the higher view to which the Scriptures seem to point, they entangle themselves in difficulties and contradictions, exegetical and other, which make it impossible for them to remain where they are. In reality, these high - sounding attributes which they ascribe to Christ are an excrescence on the system ; for on this theory no work remains for Christ to do which could not have been accomplished equally well by a highly endowed man. Historically, therefore, Arianism has always tended to work round to the Socinian or strictly Unitarian view of Christ, where it has not gone upwards, through semi- Arianism, to the recognition of His full Divinity. But this Socinian or Unitarian view of the Person of Socimanism and the older 1 See Note B.— The Defeat of Arianism. Dorner says : "Not merely did it U^itarianisnu tend back to Ebionitism ; not merely was it unable, with its Docetism and its doctrine of a created higher spirit, to allow even the possibility of an Incarna- tion ; but, by putting a fantastical under-God between God and man, it separated the two quite as much as it appeared to unite them." — Person of Christ, ii. p. 261 (Eng. trans.). 58 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW Christ — I refer to the older Unitarianism of the Priestley and Channing type — is another of those intermediate views which history also may now be said to have eliminated. Christ, on this view, is the greatest of inspired teachers, a true Prophet. He had a Divine mission ; He wrought miracles in confirmation of His doctrine ; He rose from the dead on the third day ; He is expected to return to judge the world. Here also there is a great deal of the halo of the supernatural about Christ. He is supernatural in history, if not in nature, and men saw again that they must either believe more or believe less. The rationalistic leaven, which was already working in the rejection of the higher aspects of Christ's Person and work, made itself increasingly felt. As the miraculous adjuncts were retained only in deference to the representations of Scripture, they were readily abandoned when criticism professed to show how they might be stripped off without detriment to Christ's moral image. Be the cause what it may, it is undeniable that Unitarianism of this kind has not been able to maintain itself. It has constantly tended to purge itself of the remaining supernatural features in the portrait of Christ, and to descend to the level of simple humanitarianism, i.e., to the belief in Christ as simply a great man, a religious genius of the first rank, one in whom the light which shines in all men shone in an eminent degree — but still a mere man, without anything supernatural in His origin, nature, or history.^ Christoiogy oj A further example of the difficulty of maintaining an \lhiekr intermediate position on the doctrine of the Person of Christ macher. may be taken from the long series of intermediate views which have sprung up on the soil of Germany as the result of the great intellectual and theological movement inaugurated by Hegel and Schleierm acker in the beginning of the century. Passing by the speculative Christologies^in which, when the veil was stripped off, it was found that the idea was every- thing, the historical Christ nothing — I may refer here to the ^ See Kote C. — Modern Uiiitarianism. AND ITS ALTERNATIVES. 59 Christology of Schleiermacher and his school. Schleier- niacher recognises to the full " a peculiar being of God in Christ."^ He affirms Christ's perfect sinlessness, and the unique significance of His Personality for the Church and for the race. He is the Head, Archetype, Eepresentative, and Eedeemer of mankind. Only through Him is Eedemption from sin and fellowship of life with God possible. But w^hen we come to inquire wherein consists this " peculiar being of God " in Christ, it proves, after all, to be only an exceptionally constant and energetic form of that God-con- sciousness which exists germinally in all men, and indeed lies at the root of religious experience generally. The difference betw^een Christ and other men is thus in degree, not in kind. In Him this Divine element had the ascendency, in us it has not. He is a miracle, in so far as the Divine dwelt in Him in this unique and exceptional fulness and power, constituting Him the Eedeemer and second Adam of the race ; but there is no entrance of God into humanity such as w^e associate with the idea of Incarnation. When, further, we investigate the nature of Christ's saving activity, we find that the exalted, high-priestly functions which Schleiermacher ascribes to Christ shrink, on inspection, into very meagre dimensions. Christ's continued saving activity in His Church is pre- supposed, but it is not the activity of One who still lives and reigns on high, but rather the perpetuation of a posthumous influence, through the preservation of His image in the Gospels, and the fellowship of the Christian society.^ Ultim- ately, therefore, Christ's saving activity is reduced to example and teaching ; at most, to the spiritual influence of a great and unique historic Personality.^ When we have got this length, we are clearly back on the road to simple humani- tarianism. Accordingly, none of Schleiermacher's followers have been able to stop exactly where he did. They have felt the inexorable compulsion of the less or more ; and while 1 Der Christ. Glauhe, sect. 94. - Thus also Pdtsclil. ^ On Sclileierraacher's Christology cf. Donier, Person of Christ, v, pp. 174-213. 6o THE CHRISTIAN VIEW New wave of mediating theology in school of Ritschl. The verdict of history against inter- mediate views 2. Second alternative — a Divine Christy or Agnosticism. some have gone back to rationalism, the great majority, as Kothe acknowledges/ have pressed on to more positive views, and have come into substantial harmony with confessional orthodoxy. A new wave of mediating theology has recently arisen in the school of Eitschl ; but the fundamental principle of this school — the denial of the right of the theoretic reason to have anything to do with religion or theology — is not one that can permanently be approved of, and would, if followed out, end in boundless subjectivity. In this school also, accordingly, the necessity of less or more is asserting itself. Already the members of the school have begun to move off on different and irreconcilable lines — some in a more negative, the greater number in a more positive direction. The attempt of Eitschl to bar off all inquiry into the nature of Christ's Person by resolving His " Godhead " into a mere value-judgment of the believer is felt not to be satisfactory ; and the admission is increasingly made that consistency of Christian thinking demands the acknowledgment of a tran- scendental basis.^ The general verdict of history, therefore, is clearly against the permanence of these attempts at a middle view of Christ's Person, and warns us whither they tend. The liberal school in Germany, Holland, and France, are clearly right in saying that the only alternative to Christ's true Divinity is pure humanitarianism ; and that, if the former doctrine is rejected, the supernatural view of His Person must be altogether given up. This is a clear issue, and I think it is well to have matters brought to it without shrinking or disguise. I desire now to show that this first alternative soon lands us in a second. 2. The first alternative is between a Divine Christ and a purely human one — the second is between a Divine Christ and pure Agnosticism. Many of those who take the humani- 1 He says : "Since Schleiermacher's death, the school proceeding from him has generally gone back into the way of the Church doctrine." — Dogmatik, i. p. 162. 2 See Note D. — Concessions of Ritschlians on the Person of Christ. AND ITS ALTERNATIVES. 6i tarian view of Christ's Person are very far from wishing to deny that a great deal of what Christ taught was true. ~ ~ They do not wish to deny the existence of God, or the fact of a future life, or the essentials of Christian morality. In not a few cases they strongly uphold these truths — maintain them to be the true natural religion in opposition to revealed. They account it Christ's greatest glory that He saw so clearly, and announced so unambiguously, the Fatherhood of God, the dignity of the soul, the certainty of immortality, and the dependence of happiness here and hereafter on virtue. It is a plausible view to take, for it seems to secure to those who hold it all that they take to be essential in Christianity, while at the same time it leaves them unbounded liberty to accept or reject what they like in modern " advanced " views — to get rid of miracles, go in with progressive theories of science, accept the newest criticism of the Gospels, etc. It is a plausible view, but it is an illusive one ; for if there is one thing more than another which the logic of events makes evident, it is, that with the humanitarian view of Christ we cannot stop at simple, abstract Theism, but must go on to pure Agnosticism. This is indeed what the larger number of the more logical minds which have rejected supernatural Christianity in our own day are doing. Nor is the process which leads to this result difficult to follow. The Deism of The weakness the last century rejected Christianity and sought to establish of Deism. in its place what it called " Natural Eeligion," i.e., a belief in God, in the future life, in a state of rewards and punishments, etc., based on reason alone. But however congruous with reason these doctrines may be in the place which they hold in the religion of Jesus, it was not really reason which had discovered them, or which gave assurance about them ; nor did it follow that reason could successfully vindicate them, when torn from their context, and presented in the meagre, abstract form in which they appeared in the writings of the deists. What the deists did was to pick these doctrines out of the New Testament, separating them from the rest of the 62 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW doctrines with which they were associated, and denuding them of everything which could make them real and vital to the minds and consciences of men ; then to haptise this cafut mortimm with the name of " Natural Eeligion." They were doctrines that had their roots in the Christian system, and the arguments from reason with which they were supported were not the real grounds of belief in them. In the present century men are not so easily satisfied.^ They see clearly enough that all the objections which have been levelled against the God of Eevelation tell just as powerfully against / the God of nature ; that to admit Christ's doctrine of a Heavenly Father, of a soul made in God's image, of a special providence, of prayer, of forgiveness of sins, of a future life of happiness and misery, is already to have crossed the line which separates a merely natural from a supernatural view \ of things ; and that to reject Christ's doctrines on these great questions makes it difficult to retain a Theism of any kind.^ Need of a This is not because a theistic view of the world is in itself living Theism, ^^^^ reasonable than a non-theistic view — to admit this would which has its correlate in be to give up the whole case on behalf of Christianity. But Revelation. j|. ^g "because the kind of Theism that remains after the Christian element has been removed out of it, is not one fitted to satisfy either the reason or the heart. It is a pale, emasculated conception, which, finding no support in the facts or experiences of the spiritual life, can never stand against the assaults made on it from without. It is here that Pantheism has its advantage over Deism. It is indeed more reasonable to believe in a living personal God, who created and who controls the universe, than in the " One and All " of the pantheist ; but it does not follow that it is more reason- able to believe in an abstract Deity — a mere figment of the intellect — who stands in separation from the world, and yields no satisfaction to the religious life. Theism is a 1 See Note E.— The Weakness of Deism. 2 This is Avhere not only Deism, but also the so-called Liberal Protestantism, fails, in rejecting supernatural Christianity. See Note F.— The Weakness of Modem Liberal Protestantism. AND ITS ALTERNATIVES. 6^ reasonable view of the universe, but it must be a living Theism, not a barren and notional one. If, to avoid this bankruptcy, the attempt is made to deal insecurity oj in earnest with the conception of a personal God, and to ^J^^^^^^^j^t ^ ■■; ^ ' ^ off from Christ reclothe the Deity with the warm, gracious attributes which —Rathbone belong to the Father-God of Christ, then we have indeed ^^^^' ^*^' a Being whom the soul can love, trust, and hold communion with, but the difficulty recurs of believing Him to be a God who remains self-enclosed, impassive, uncommunicative, towards creatures whom He has dowered with a share of His own rational and moral excellences, who has so shut Himself out by natural law from direct contact with the spirits that seek Him that He can neither speak to them, answer their prayers, help them in trouble, nor even reach them by inward succours — a silent God, who can no more enter into personal relations with His creatures than if He were ^mpersonal. Such a conception is self-contradictory, and cannot maintain itself. One feels this incongruity very powerfully in dealing with the Theism of such writers as the late Mr. Eathbone Greg, or Dr. Martineau, or the authoress of Jlohcvt Elsmere. None of these writers will admit the possibility of miracle ; logically, therefore, they shut out the possibility of direct communication between God and man. Yet none of them can rest with the cold abstract God of Deism ; or with the immanent impersonal spirit of Pantheism ; or with the comfortless negation of Agnosticism. God is with them a personal Being ; His will is ethical ; communion with Him is longed after, and believed in. Let Mr. Greg's own pathetic words tell how insecure is the Theism thus cut off from positive Eevelation. "My own conception," he says, " perhaps from early mental habit, perhaps from incurable and very conscious metaphysical inaptitude, approaches far nearer to the old current image of a personal God than to any of the sublimated substitutes of modern thought. Strauss's Universum, Comte's Humanity, even Mr. Arnold's Stream of Tendency that makes for Righteousness, excite in me 64 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW No logical resting-place short of Agnosticism, 3. Third alternative- a Divine Christ, or FessimisfH, no enthusiasm, command from me no worship. I cannot pray to the ' Immensities ' and the ' Eternities ' of Carlyle ; they proffer me no help ; they vouchsafe me no sympathy ; they suggest no comfort. It may be that such a personal God is a mere anthropomorphic creation. It may be — as philosophers with far finer instruments of thought than mine affirm — that the conception of such a Being, duly analysed, is demonstrably a self-contradictory one. But, at least in resting in it, I rest in something I almost seem to realise ; at least, I share the view which Jesns indisputably held of the Father whom He obeyed, communed with, and worshipped." ^ Surely it need hardly be said that a view which, even while holding it, one doubts may be only a result of "early mental habit," "a mere anthropomorphic creation," a "self-contradictory" con- ception, cannot long stand as a basis for life ; nor will the trust which Jesus had help much, when one has already rejected as delusion His doctrine of prayer, of special providence, of forgiveness of sins, and His own Messianic claims and expectations. Already we tremble on the verge of Agnos- ticism, if we have not actually passed its bound. I think, accordingly, I am justified in saying that when the ground of Divine Eevelation is once left behind, we have no logical halting-place short of Agnosticism ; not because a theistic view of the universe is unreasonable, but because a living Theism requires as its complement belief in Eevelation. / "We have these alternatives : either to revivify our Theism till it approaches in the humane and loving attributes it ascribes to God the Christian conception of the Heavenly Father — in which case we are back to a supernatural view of the universe ; or, if this is thought baseless, to dispense with the idea of God altogether, and try to explain the world without reason, ^ without final cause, without spiritual assumptions of any kind. 3. Agnosticism is, however, far from representing the end ' of this road along which we had begun to travel in rejecting the Divine in Christ. The final alternative — one which we ^ Creed of Christendom, Introd. 3rd ed. pp. 90, 91. AND ITS AL TERN A TIVES. 65. may trust the world at large will never be called upon to face — is a Divine Christ or Pessimism. Agnosticism is not a> state in which the mind of an intelligent being can perman- ently rest. It is essentially a condition of suspense — a confession of ignorance — an abdication of thought on the highest subjects.^ It is not, in the nature of things, possible for the mind to remain persistently in this neutral, passive attitude. It will press on perforce to one or other of the^ views which present themselves as alternatives — either to Theism, or to Materialism and dogmatic Atheism.^ I do not speak, of course, of the individual mind, but of the general historical development. But even Agnosticism has brought Depressing with it a train of baleful results. With the loss of certainty ^*'?/^^^«^^ ^f Agnosticism : on the highest questions of existence there comes inevitably cuts the ne>-ve a lowering of the pulse of human endeavour all round — a of^^^^onai belief in loosening of certainty even about morals, for why should ^^^^^^^j., these remain uuaffected when everything else is going — and as we see to-day, in much of the speculative thought of France and Germany, a hopelessness about the future. Eor, obviously, when this point is reached, the rational ground is taken away even from belief in progress.^ When the idea of God, which is equivalent to the idea of a reason at the foundation of things, is surrendered — whether in Agnosticism, or in some form of dogmatic denial, makes little difference — it becomes a wholly unwarranted assumption that things must certainly go on from better to better. The opposite may quite as well be the case, and progress, now that a given height is reached, may rather be from better to worse. The^ analogy of nature shows that this is the law in regard to ^ Generally, however, under the surface of professed Agnosticism, there will be found some more or less positive opinions about the origin and nature of things, all of them agreeing in this, that they negate the belief in God. 2 On the continent there are fewer agnostics, but more atheists and materialists, than with us. **In Germany," says Karl Peters, "things are come to such a pass that one is obliged to ask a sort of absolution if one does not swim with the prevailing atheistic-monistic stream." — Willenswelt and WeltwUle, p. 350. 2 See Note G. —Christianity and the Idea of Progress. 5 66 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW Transition to Pessimism — use of great pessimistic systems. natural life. The plant blooms, reaches its acme, and dies. So, it may be plausibly argued, it will be with humanity. The fact that some progress has been made in the past does not guarantee that this progress will go on indefinitely; rather, the spur to this progress consisted in what we are now told are illusions, and when these are exploded the motives to progress are gone. A more highly evolved society may lead to an increase of misery rather than of happiness ; the growth of enlightenment, instead of adding to men's enjoyments, may result in stripping them successively of the illusions that remain, and may leave them at last sad, weary, disappointed, with an intolerable consciousness of the burden and wretchedness of existence.^ All this is not fancy. The despairing, pessimistic spirit I am speaking of has already taken hold of extensive sections of society, and is giving startling evidences of its presence. For the first time on European soil we see large and influential systems springing up, and gaining for themselves wide popularity and accept- ance, which have for their root idea exactly this conception of the inherent irrationality and misery of existence. There have always been individual thinkers with a tendency to take a prejudiced and hopeless view of life, but their reveries have not been much regarded. But here, strange to say, under the very shadow of this boasted progress of the nineteenth century — in the very midst of its enlightenment and civilisa- tion and wealth — we see Pessimism raising its head as a serious, carefully thought-out philosophy of existence, and, instead of being scouted and laughed at as an idle dream, it ^ Pessimism reverses Pascal's saying that the greatness of man consists in thought. Thought, according to Pessimism, is the fatal gift. "Well for those," Schopenhauer thinks, "who have no consciousness of existence. The life of the animal is more to be envied than that of man ; the life of the plant is better than that of the fish in the water, or even of the oyster on the rock. Non-being is better than being, and unconsciousness is the blessedness of what does exist. The best would be if all existence were annihilated."— Cf. Luthardt, Die mod. Welt. p. 189. "The height of misery is not that of being man ; it is, being man, to despise oneself sufficiently to regret that one is not an animal."— Caro, Le Pessimisme, p. 135. AND ITS ALTERNATIVES. €7 meets with passionate acceptance from multitudes.^ The same Pessimism in spirit will be found reflected by those who care to note its ^^^ literature — sadness of symptoms, in much of our current literature, in the serious the sceptical raising and discussion, for example, of the question already ^^^^^^' familiar to us — Is life worth living ? Specially noticeable is the tone of sadness which pervades much of the nobler sceptical thinking of the present day — the tone of men who do not think lightly of parting with religion, but feel that with it has gone the hope and gladness of earlier days. ThisN Pessimism of scepticism is to me one of the saddest and most significant phenomena of modern times.^ And granting the premises it starts from, what other conclusion is possible ? Deprive the world of God, and everything becomes an insol- uble mystery, history a scene of wrecked illusions, belief in progress a superstition, and life in general ''A tale Told by an idiot, full of sound and fury, Signifying nothing." ^ ^ II. The descent from faith in Christ has landed us in the //. The up- abyss of Pessimism. But just at this lowest point, where the "^^^ .^fl^^ light of religious faith might seem utterly extinguished, a Pessimism to return movement is felt to be inevitable. For Pessimism, \^^^^"^' no more than Theism, can escape the necessity laid upon it of giving to itself some account of things as they are — of constructing a " Weltanschauung " ; and the moment it attempts to do this, making naked the principle on which it rests, its own insufficiency as a philosophy of existence and of life stands glaring and confessed. Possibly the attempt to ^Unsatisfactori- work out Pessimism as a system will never be made with '^^"^"^^^^'^f^'''' ism as a tneor much more thoroughness, or with better chances of success, of existence— than has already been done in the monumental works of ^^ '^°^^! ^^^^ to Theism. Schopenhauer and Hartmann. * But the very thorough- ^ See Note H. — The Prevalence of Pessimism. ^ See Appendix to Lecture — The Pessimism of Scepticism. ^ "Macbeth," act v. scene 5. ^ See Note I.— The Literature of Pessimism. 68 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW The dialectic of Pessimism — Schopen- hauer and Haj'tmann. goingness of the attempt is the demonstration of its futility. Of all theories, that which explains the origin of the universe by a mistake — which accounts for it by the blind rushing into existence of an irrational force, call it " Will " or what we please — is surely the most incredible.^ How came this irrational will-force to be there ? What moved it to this insensate decision ? In what state was it before it committed this enormous blunder of rushing into existence ? How came it to be possessed of that potential wealth of ideas which now are realised in the world ? Of what use were they if they were never intended to be called into existence ? What I am at present concerned with, however, is not to refute Pessimism, but rather to show how, as a first step in an upward movement back to Christ, by its own immanent dialectic it refutes itself — inverts, in fact, its own starting- point, and works itself round into a species of Theism. Schopenhauer and Hartmann both recognise that there is in the universe not only " Will " but " Idea," and the manner in which they deal with this element of " Idea " is one of the most curious examples of the inversion of an original starting- point in the history of philosophy. For, in the course of its development. Pessimism has actually adopted as its leading principle the thought of a rational teleology in the universe, and as a consequence, as above remarked, has worked itself back to Theism. How this comes about it is not difficult to show. The crucial point for all systems of Pessimism is the ^ These Pessimistic theories are not without their roots in the philosophies of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. Cf. Fiehte's view of the Absolute as "Will" ; and Schelling's "irrational" ground of the Divine nature (after Bohme). In his Philosophie und Religion (1804), Schelling boldly describes the creation as the result of an " Abfall" — the original assertion by the Ego of its independence. "This inexplicable and timeless act is the original sin or primal fall of the spirit, which we expiate in the circles of time — existence " (cf. Professor Seth's From Kant to Hegel, p. 65). Hegel also, in his own way, speaks of creation as an "Abfall." "It is in the Son," he says, "in the determination of dis- tinction, that progressive determination proceeds to further distinction. . . . This transition in the moment of the Son is thus expressed by Jacob Bohme — that the first-born was Lucifer, the light-bearer, the bright, the clear one ; but he turned in upon himself in imagination, i.e. he made himself independent, passed over into being, and so M\"—PhiL d. Pel. ii. p. 251 ( WerJce, vol. xii.). AND ITS ALTERNATIVES. 69 presence of reason in the universe. How, if the basis of the _ universe is irrational, does reason come to find a place in it at all ? For, manifestly, account for it as we may, there is reason in the universe now. The universe itself is a law- connected whole ; there is order and plan, organisation and system, utility and beauty, means and ends. Above all, in man himself, if nowhere else, there is conscious reason — the very instrument by which this irrationality of the universe is discovered. There is evidently more here than blind, purposeless will. How is its existence to be explained ? ^ Schopenhauer postulates " Idea." In accounting for nature, " war and he has to suppose that in this blind, purposeless will there "-^^Jf "— ^'^^^''' lies potentially a whole world of ideas, representing all the stages and kingdoms through which nature advances in the course of its history.^ Hartmann unites " Will " and " Idea " yet more closely, regarding them as co-ordinate attributes of the Absolute, though still, somehow, the will is supposed to be in itself a purely irrational force. It is only when the will has made the mistake of rushing into existence that it lays hold on the " Idea " as a means of delivering itself from the unblessedness of its new condition. To this end the universe is represented as ordered with the highest wisdom, the goal of its development being the production of the conscious agent, man, through whom the Eedemption of the world-spirit is to be accomplished. I do not pursue these " metaphysics of wonderland " further. I only notice the extraordinary contradictions in which Hartmann involves himself in his conception of the Absolute — " the Unconscious," Hartmann: s as he prefers to term it — and the extraordinary transforma- 'Unconscious ^ •' — attributes to tion it undergoes in his hands. The Absolute is unconscious, ?v, intelligence, and needs to create for itself an organ of consciousness i'^'^^sdom, fore- sight, purpose. 1 Die Welt als Wille und Vorstelhmg, i. pp. 185, 206 (Eng. trans, pp. 203, 219 ff.). Karl Peters remarks : "If the alone Will bears in itself the stages of the World-All as eternal ideas — how can Schopenhauer call it an absolutely- irrational Will ? And, if he conceives of it as a radically blind Will, as an insane and altogether groundless 'Drang,' how can he vindicate for it these eternal ideas?" — Willenswelt, p. 129. 70 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW man before it can attain deliverance from its unblessedness. Yet it knows, plans, contrives, orders everything with con- summate wisdom, works out its designs with a precision that is unerring, etc.^ The contradiction here is too patent. Tor, if unconscious, how can we speak of this Absolute as un- blessed ? Or how can we think of it as knowing and planning? Hartmann, therefore, changes his ground, and The " Uncon- speaks in other places of his Absolute rather as siipra- •^^^f"^"^^^^^^-^ conscious; 2 elsewhere, aorain, in terms akin to those of Mr. a ^ supra- ° conscious." Spcuccr, as an "Unknowable" — incapable of being repre- sented in forms of our intelligence.^ But if the Absolute is supra-conscious, i.e., exists in a state higher than the ordinary- consciousness, why should it need the latter to help it out of its misery ? The climax is reached when, in a later work — while still holding to the view that the Absolute is not a self-conscious Personality — Hartmann invests it with most Moral attri- pi the attributes characteristic of Deity, sees in it, e.g., the butes ascribed rrround, not onlv of a natural, but of a moral order, makes it to the Absolute o ' •/ ' ' —now called the objcct of rcligious worship, attributes to it, not simply God. omnipotence and wisdom, but righteousness and holiness, views it as a source of Revelation and grace, expressly names it God 1 * We are here far enough from the original assump- tion of a primitive, irrational will — in fact, what we see is Pessimism passing over in all but the name into Theism. It ^ ' ' The Unconscious wills in one act all the terms of a process, means and end, etc., not before, beside, or beyond, but in the result itself." — Ptiil. d. Unbewussten, ii. p. 60 (Eng. trans.). ^ "The Unconscious, it now appears, has, after all, a kind of consciousness — is *a transcendent supra-mundane consciousness,' 'anything but blind, rather far-seeing and clairvoyant,' 'superior to all consciousness, at once unconscious and supra-conscious' (!), its 'mode of thinking is, in truth, above conscious- ness."— PA«7. d. Unbewussten, pp. 246, 247, 258, etc. (Eng. trans.). ^ Phil. d. Unbeivussten, pp. 49, 223, 246, etc. (Eng. trans.). Schopenhauer also declares his "Will" to be in itself, i.e. apart from its phenomenal mani- festations, an Unknowable, possibly possessing "ways of existing, determina- tions, qualities, which are absolutely unknowable and incomprehensible to us, and which remain ever as its nature when it has abrogated its phenomenal character, and for our knowledge has passed into empty nothingness." — Die Welt als Wllle (Eng. trans.), ii. p. 408. * Jieligionsphilosophie : Part II., Phil, des Geistes, pp. 74-89. AND ITS ALTERNATIVES, 71 remained only that this transition should be explicitly made. Transition in and this has been done by a disciple of the school, Karl ^<^^^-^Jt^^ from Fessim- Peters, whose work, Willenswelt und Weltwille, is one of the ism to explicit acutest criticisms of previous Pessimism I know. With him Iheism. we finally leave the ground of the philosophy of the " Uncon- scious," and come round to a Theism in which we have the full recognition of God as a self-conscious, wise, good, holy Personality, whose providence is over all, and whose ends all things subserve.^ The theories of Schopenhauer and Hartmann, though Theaiter- pessimistic, might with equal propriety have been classed in "p^^J/^^{^^_ the family of pantheistic systems. When dealing at an its degradation earlier stage with the downward movement from faith in ^o Materialism " {Strauss, Christ, through Agnosticism to Pessimism, I purposely re- Feuerback). served this alternative of Pantheism. This was not because the subject is in itself unimportant, but because it comes at last to the old dilemma, and can best be treated in its higher aspect as a stage in the upward advance to Theism. Pan-^ theism shares the fate of every incomplete system, in being compelled to pass judgment on itself, and either to sink to something lower, or to pass up to something higher. I refer • for proof to Germany, which has given birth to some of its noblest forms, but where also history shows how possible it is to descend at one step from the loftiest heights of over- strained Idealism to gross Materialism. Fichte and Schelling and Hegel were followed by Strauss and Feuerbach.^ The logic of the process is again not difiEicult to trace. If universal reason is the all, and the finite in comparison with it nothing, in another point of view it is the finite that is all, and reason that is nothing, seeing that in the finite only it attains to actual existence. Concede the premiss, the Absolute has reality only in the universe, and it is but a short step to the conclusion, the universe alone is real.^ Interpret ^ See Note J. — Transition from Pessimism to Theism — Hartmann and Karl Peters. ^ See Note K. — Materialism in Germ.any. ^ " If,' says Dorner, "God be once defined as the essence of the world, it is a 72 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW The nobler movement — elevation to Theism. Fichte and Schelling. the universe now, in accordance with the " modern " concep- tion, in terms of matter and motion, and Feuerbach's dictum is reached — " Man is what he eats." The goal of this is the old plunge into Nihilism and Pessimism, in which we have just seen that the mind cannot remain. The other alternative is, however, possible to Pantheism, by holding fast to the rational element contained in it, to correct and purify itself by a return to Theism ; and this is the movement we see taking place in the later forms of the philosophies of Fichte and Schelling, and in the speculative Theism of the later Hegelians. In judging of these systems we must not be misled by too narrow a use of the word " Theism." The Theism of the writers I refer to is in many respects imperfect, and bears throughout the marks of its / speculative origin. Yet, in principle, the line between Pan- theism and Theism is crossed whenever God is conceived of no longer as an impersonal Force or Idea, but as a spiritual, self-conscious principle at the basis of the universe — as a knowing, willing Being, with whom man can sustain, not only ^ natural, but moral and spiritual relations. There may be difficulties at this stage as to whether the term " personal " is a suitable term to apply to the Divine ; but it is, never- theless, a theistic conception of God which is shaping itself, and the purgation of the system from remaining pantheistic elements is only a question of time. What, for instance, but an approximation to Theism is implied in such words as Fichte's in his fine apostrophe, — " Sublime and Living Will ! named by no name, compassed by no thought ! I may well raise my soul to Thee, for Thou and I are not divided ! Thy voice sounds within me, mine resounds in Thee ; and all my thoughts, if they be but good and true, live in Thee also. . . . Thou art best known to the childlike, devoted, transposition of subject and predicate logically allowable, when Feuerbacli, taking the idea seriously, counted the essence of the world to be a part of the world, raade the world the subject, and reduced God to a mere predicate of the world. The transition was thus made to Anthropologism, the forerunner of Materialism."— PersoTi of Christ, v. p. 160. AND ITS AL TERN A TIVES. 73 simple mind. To it Thou art the searcher of hearts, who seest its inmost depths ; the ever-present witness of its truth, who knowest though all the world know it not. Thou art the Father who ever desirest its good, who rulest all things for the best. . . . How thou art, I may not know. But, let me be what I ought to be, and Thy relations to me — the mortal — and to all mortals, lie open before my eyes, and surround me more clearly 'than the consciousness of my own existence. Thou workest in me the knowledge of my duty, of my vocation in the world of reasonable beings ; — how, I know not, nor need I to know. Thou knowest what I think and what I will : — how Thou canst know, through what act thou bringest about that consciousness, I cannot understand. . . . Thou wiliest that my free obedience shall bring with it eternal consequences : — the act of Thy will I cannot com- "^ prehend, I only know that it is not lik-e mine. Thou doesf, and Thy will itself is the deed ; but the way of Thy working is not as my ways — I cannot trace it."^ If this is Pantheism, are we not all pantheists ? If this is Agnosticism, is it not an Agnosticism in which we must all ^ share ? The moment in spiritual Pantheism which impels ^ to this development is of course the recognition of the fact that the universe has its ground in reason. If this position is to be safeguarded against the lapse into Materialism, it must free itself from the internal contradiction of supposing that there can be thought without a thinker f reason without a subject to which the reason belongs ; rational ends posited and executed without intelligent and self-conscious purpose ; 1 "The Vocation of Man" (Die Beatimmvng des Menschen) in Fichte's "Popular Works," p. 365 (Eng. trans.). — See Note L. — Fichte's Later Philosophy. ^ "In spite of Fichte's imperious tone," says Professor Seth, "and his vvai-ning that we are merely setting the seal to our own philosophic incom- petency, we must summon up all our hardihood, and openly confess that to speak of thought as self-existent, without any conscious Being whose the thought is, conveys no meaning to our minds. Thought exists only as the thought of a thinker ; it must be centred somewhere." — Hegelianism and Personality, p. 73. He had formerly expressed himself differently. — From Kant to Hegel, p. 76. 74 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW British Neo- Hegelianism — T. H. Green, j ^ moral order without a moral will. In the case of Fichte and Schelling, this revolution in their philosophies is seen taking The Hegelian place within their lifetime ; in the case of Hegel, it is seen development. -^^ ^^ development of his philosophy, in the hands of his disciples, into a speculative Theism. In Yatke and Bieder- mann — two prominent representatives — the Theism is still very shadowy and incomplete ; in I. H. Fichte and Pfleiderer of Berlin, it attains to full and explicit recognition. The latter writer, in particular, takes strong ground, and from his own point of view may be regarded as one of the ablest defenders of theistic positions in recent times. In our own country we have the Neo-Hegelian movement, best represented by the late Mr. Green, of Oxford, and in him also the specu- lative spirit is seen allying itself very closely with the spirit of religion, with the result that his philosophy almost inevit- ably passes over into Theism. On the metaphysical side, God is already to Mr. Green an " Eternal Self-Consciousness " ^ — the author and sustainer of the system of relations which we call the universe. But, on the religious side. He is thought of much more positively as a conscious Being who is in eternal perfection all that man has it in him to come to be — " a Being of perfect understanding and perfect love " — an infinite Spirit, present to the soul, but other than itself, towards whom " the attitude of man at his highest and completest could still only be that which we have described as self-abasement before an ideal of holiness." ^ The meta- physical contradictions which still inhere in the Neo-Hegelian theory have been well pointed out by one — formerly an ardent Hegelian — who has himself lived through the theory he criticises — Prof. Seth of Edinburgh. In him, in the line of this development, we reach at length a perfectly unambig- uous position. " It must not be forgotten," he says, " that if Prof. Seth. ^ Prolegomena to Ethics, passim. 2 Pp. 93, 142 of " Memoir " by Nettleship, Professor Green's profound Christian feeling, Christianity, are well brought out in the same ' works. in Green's Works, vol. iii. with his ideological views of 'Memoir," and accompanying AND ITS ALTERNATIVES. 75 we are to keep the name God at all, or any equivalent term, subjectivity — an existence of God for Himself, analogous to our own personal existence, though doubtless transcending it infinitely in innumerable ways — is an essential element of the conception. . . . God may be, must be, infinitely more — we are at least certain that He cannot be less — than we I know ourselves to be."^ ' The Theism we have thus gained embraces the two notions Theism hnpeh of God as self - conscious reason, and God as moral will. ^ ^ \\!^ Revelation. Once, however, this ground of Theism is reached, we are compelled, in order to secure it, to advance a step further, viz., to the thought of God as self - revealing. We have*^ already seen that Theism can only be secured if God is thought of as standing in a living relation to m.ankind — that is, as interesting Himself in their welfare, and capable of entering into moral and spiritual fellowship with them. How can one earnestly believe in a living, personal God, \ and, on the other hand, in man, as a being constituted for moral ends, and not also believe that it is the will of God that man should know Him, and be guided by Him to the fulfilment of his destiny ? It is, accordingly, a most note- worthy fact, that in all the higher theology of the time — even rationalistic theology — the attempt is made to come to a right understanding with this concept of Eevelation. Strange General recog- as it may sound to many, there is no proposition on which ^"^^^^^ "^ theologians of all schools at the present day are more willing systems of to agree than this — that all knowledge of God, and con- ^^^ ^^^^ ^-f Revelation. sequently all religion, rests on Eevelation ; and that, if the true idea of God is to be maintained, He must be thought of as self - revealing. This truth is emphasised, not in the orthodox systems alone, but in the theologies, e.g., of Bieder- mann, of Lipsius, of Pfleiderer, of Kitschl — even, as I said before, of the pessimist Hartmann, who, in his book on ^ Hegelianism and Personality, pp. 222-224. Mr. Green's theory is discussed more fully in Professor Veitch's Knowing and Being, which touches many vital points. Cf. Lect. III.— Note D. 76 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW religion, has, with curious irony, his chapters on faith and Eevelation. The point of difference arises when we inquire into the nature of Eevelation, and specially when we pass from the sphere of natural to that of supernatural Eevelation. Modern theory Supernatural Eevelation the theologians of the liberal school of Revelation— — pfleidercr, Lipsius, etc. — will not allow us to speak of ; or natural and supernatural rather, natural and supernatural are with them but different different sides gj^jgg ^f ^^ ^^^^ proccss. That which, on the Divine side, of the same -r^ , . . • t • ^ ^ process, IS Viewed as Eevelation, is, on the human side, simply the natural development of man's moral and religious conscious- ness, and vice versa. In the same way, every truly original moment in the life of a man, every birth-moment of a new truth in his soul, every flash of insight into some new secret or law of nature, is a Eevelation. This, which is the subtlest view of Eevelation at present in the field, is not to be set aside without an attempt to do justice to what is true in it.^ I am, for my part, not concerned to deny that there is a side of truth, and a very important one, in this theory. If it sounds deistical to say, " Eevelation is only through the natural activities of mind," it may, on the other hand, be a whole- some corrective to a deistic view to say that God is immanent in these activities, and that through them He mediates His Eevelation to the human spirit — that what we call the " natural " development of mind involves, when rightly under- stood, a factor of Eevelation. Nor can the line ever be drawn so finely between natural and supernatural Eevelation as to enable us to say, " Here precisely the natural ends and the Inadequacy ojF^ supernatural begins." The theory in question, therefore, I its end does' ^^^^^ ^^ disposcd to Call inadequate, rather than false; or not correspond false Only as it professes to cover the whole field of Eevelation. ^^. ^ f For in the latter, it must be contended that we have more than can be accounted for by mere natural development. Taking it even on its own ground, this theory involves the ^ Cf. on tins theory Biedermann, Christ. Dogmatik, i. pp. 264-288 ; Lipsius, Dogmatik, pp. 41-68 ; Pfleiderer, Religlonsphilosophie, iv. pp. 46-94, specially pp. 64-75 (Eng. trans.), and Grwidriss, pp. 17-22. See Note M.— Modern Theory of Revelation. AND ITS ALTERNATIVES. 77 valuable admission that it is the will of God to make Himself ^ known to man, and that He has provided in the constitution of things for giving him the knowledge that is necessary for him. The only criticism I shall make at present upon this theory is — and I think it is one which goes to the heart of the matter — that in some sense the end of the theory is the refutation of the beginning of it. The point from which we start is, that God can be known only through the natural activities of the mind. He is present in these activities as He is present in all the other functions of our mental, moral, and even physical being ; and He is present in no other way. But the peculiarity of this theory is that it ends in a view of God which affirms the possibility of that with the denial of which it set out — the possibility of direct communion between The God of God and the soul. It is not disputed by any of the advocates v^"^, ^^ , ^ ./ ./ dzrect access to of these views that the highest point in this self-revelation of the souls of God is the Eevelation given to men through Jesus Christ. ^'^'^* But the God and Father of our Lord Jesus Christ is not a Being who communicates with man only in the indirect way which this theory supposes. He is a Being who Himself draws near to man, and seeks fellowship with him ; whose relations with the spirits He has made are free and personal ; who is as lovingly communicative as man, on his part, is expected to be trustfully receptive ; to whom man can speak, and He answers. The simply natural is here transcended, and we are in the region of direct intercourse of spirit with ^ spirit. And this view of God is not disjjuted by the writers I am here referring to, who deny supernatural Eevelation. Dr. Martineau says, in words of deep wisdom, " How should Martineau related spirits, joined by a common creative aim, intent on ««^^^«^^''^''- whatever things are pure and good, live in presence of each other, the one the bestower, the other the recipient of a sacred trust, and exchange no thought and give no sign of the love which subsists between them ? " ^ Pfleiderer again says, "And ^ Study of JReligion, ii. p. 48. Cf. the following sentences from his Hours of Tkowjht: — "Whatever else may be incladed in the truth that ' God is a Spirit,' 78 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW / why should it be less i^ossible for God to enter into a loving fellowship with us, than for men to do so with each other ? I should be inclined to think that He is even more capable of doing so. For as no man can altogether read the soul of another, so no man can altogether live in the soul of another ; hence all our human love is and remains imperfect. But if we are shut off from one another by the limits of individu- ality, in relation to God it is not so ; to Him our hearts are as open as each man's own heart is to himself; He sees through and through them, and He desires to live in them, and to fill them with His own sacred energy and blessedness." ^ True, why not ? But if this is admitted, what becomes of the theory that the action of God in Eevelation is necessarily bound up within the limits of strict natural law ? If the gates of intercourse are thus open between the human soul and God, is it either natural or probable that God will not enter in at them, and that, instead of leaving men simply to feel after Him, if haply they may find Him, He will not at some point give them what supernatural light and aid they need to bring them to the true knowledge of Himself, and fit them for the attainment of the highest ends of their existence ? Certainly, in light of the above admissions, no ci "priori objec- \ tion can be raised to the principle of supernatural Eevelation. Outcome of The legitimate outcome of this theory is, that in addition ins theory-- ^^ ^encral Ecvclation through reason, conscience, and nature, an expectation ^ o ' r, f J f this at least is implied, that He is free to modify His relations to all dependent minds in exact conformity with their changes of disposition and of need, and let the lights and shadows of His look move as swiftly as the undulating wills on which they fall."— ii. p. 29. "Passing by this poor mockery, I would be understood to speak of a direct and natural communion of spirit with spirit, between ourselves and God, in which He receives our affection and gives a responsive breathing of His inspiration. Such communion appears to me as certain of reality as the daily intercourse between man and man ; resting upon evidence as positive, and declaring itself by results as marked. The disposition to throw doubt on the testimony of those who affirm that they know this is a groundless prejudice, an illusion on the negative side as complete as the most positive dreams of enthusiasm." — P. 224. 1 Beligionsphilosophie, iii. p. 305 (Eng. trans.). See Note N. — The Reason- ableness of Revelation. AND ITS ALTERNATIVES. 79 there is to be expected some special Eevelation ; and even this, in a certain way, is admitted, for it is conceded by nearly all the writers I have named, that in the providential plan of the world a peculiar function was assigned to Israel ; that, as The vocation the different nations of the world have their several provi- ^t^^'^.^^^~ ^ Chnst the dential tasks (Greece — art, culture, philosophy ; Eome — law, highest government, etc.), to Israel was given the task of developing R^^^^^^- the idea of God to its highest perfection in ethical Mono- theism.^ And, finally, it is conceded that this self-revelation of God reaches its culmination in Jesus Christ, whose Person has world-historical significance, as bearing in it the principle of the perfect relation between God and man — of the absolute religious relation.^ The line between natural and super- natural Eevelation is here, surely, becoming very thin ; and it is therefore, perhaps, not greatly to be wondered at that the latest school in German theology — that of Eitschl — should Return to take the short remaining step, and be marked by precisely -^f'^^^T^^J^''^' this tendency to lay stress on the need and reality of positive of Ritschu Eevelation. The general position of this school may be fairly summed up by saying that God can only be truly known to us by personal, positive Eevelation, in which he actually enters into historical relations with mankind ; and that this Eevela- tion has been given in the Person of His Son Jesus Christ. Through this Eevelation alone, but in it perfectly, we have the true knowledge of God's character, of His world-aim in the establishing of a kingdom of God on earth, and of His gracious will of forgiveness and love.^ Whatever theory of Eevelation we adopt, Jesus Christ must be pronounced to be the highest organ of it. On this point all deep and serious thinkers of our age may be held to be agreed. Thus, then, we are brought back to Christ, are led to recognise in Him the medium of a true Eevelation ; and it only remains to ask, ^ Thus, e.g., Kuenen, Wellhausen, Pfleiderer, Martineaii {Stat of AutlioritVy pp. 116-122). 2 This is the general position of the higher class of theologians, of whatever schools. 2 See Note M.— The Ritschlian Doctrine of Revelation. 8o THE CHRISTIAN VIEW, What do the facts of this Eevelation, and of Christ's own self- testimony, properly construed imply ? We have already seen what the verdict of history is on this point, to what alter- natives it shuts us up in our treatment of this subject. We shall afterwards see by examination of the facts themselves how this verdict is justified. Summary^ To sum up, wc have sccn that two movements are to be Theishc belief (Jigcemed in history : the one a downward movement leading leads up to -i i • p t i • i !• belief in away from Christ, and resulting from the denial of, or ChHst, and tampering with. His full Divinity ; the other, an upward '^itself through movement, retracting the stages of the earlier descent, and ^t' bringing us back to the confession of Thomas, " My Lord and my God." ^ The former movement ends in the gulf of Nihilism and Pessimism ; the latter begins from the impossibility of the mind abiding permanently in the denial of a rational basis for the universe. But here, as in the downward move- ment, the logic of history asserts itself. Belief in a rational basis of the universe can only secure itself through return to Theism ; a living Theism can only secure itself through belief in God as self-revealing ; belief in Eevelation leads historically to the recognition of Christ as the highest organ of God's self-revelation to mankind ; belief in Christ as Kevealer can only secure itself through belief in His Divinity. " Ye believe in God," said Jesus ; " believe also in Me."^ Belief in God — theistic belief — presses on to belief in Christ, and can only secure itself through it. On the other hand, belief in Christ is the legitimate outcome of belief in God. The two beliefs, as history demonstrates, stand or fall together. 1 John XX. 28. ^ John xiv. 1. APPENDIX TO LECTUEE II. THE PESSIMISM OF SCEPTICISM. All the writers on Pessimism dwell on the strangeness of Prevalence of the fact that a century like our own, so marked by mental and material progress, by vigour and enterprise, should witness a revival of this gospel of despair ; ^ and bear emphatic testimony to the breadth and depth of the influence which the pessimistic systems are exercising. Apart, however, from the definite acceptance of Pessimism as a creed, it is instruct- iv^e to note the many indications which literature ajffords of the sad and hopeless spirit which seems the necessary out- come of the surrender of religious faith. A few illustrations of this Pessimism of scepticism, culled almost at random, will perhaps not be out of place. Voltaire was not happy. Dr. Cairns writes regarding Pessimism of him : " How little he himself was contented with his own f; •. ^ ^ -loi is infinite, it is eternal, it is omnipresent ; ^ it is an infinite and eternal Energy from which all things proceed ; ^ it is the Cause of the universe, standing to it in a relation similar to that of the creative power of the Christian conception.^ Numerous other statements might be quoted all more or less implying knowledge, — as, e.g., that "the Power manifested throughout the Universe distinguished as material, is the same Power which in ourselves wells up under the form of conscious- ness " ; while the " necessity we are under to think of the external energy in terms of the internal energy gives rather a spiritualistic than a materialistic aspect to the Universe." * This, I take leave to say, so far from being Agnosticism, would more correctly be described as a qualified Gnosticism.^ Mr. Spencer's so-called Agnosticism is not an agnostic system at all, but a system of non - material, or semi - spiritual ^ First Principles, p. 99. ^ Ecclesiastical Institutions, p. 843. " But one truth," he says, " must grow- ever clearer — the truth that there is an Inscrutable Existence everywhere mani- fested, to which he can neither find, nor conceive either beginning or end. Amid the mysteries which become the more mysterious the more they are thought about, there will remain the one absolute certainty that he is ever in presence of one Infinite and Eternal Energy, from which all things proceed." ^ *' I held at the outset, and continue to hold, that this Inscrutable Existence which science, in the last resort, is compelled to recognise as unreached by its deepest analysis of matter, motion, thought, and feeling, stands towards our general conception of things in substantially the same relation as does the Creative Powder asserted by Theology." — Nineteenth Century, July 1884, p. 24. Mr. Spencer tells us that the words quoted in the last note were originally written — " one Infinite and Eternal Energy by which all things are created and sustained." — Ihid. p. 4. * Ecclesiastical Institutions, pp, 839, 841. ^ Mr. Spencer, when pressed in controversy by Mr. Harrison, takes great pains to show how positive his conception of the ' ' Unknowable " is. He is astonished that his opponent should assert that "none of the positive attributes which have ever been predicated of God can be used of this Energy"; maintains that, instead of being an Everlasting No, Agnosticism is " an Everlasting Yea"; denies that Agnosticism is " anything more than silent with respect to person- ality," seeing that "duty requires us neither to affirm nor deny personality"; holds that the Unknowable is not an " All-nothingness" but the ** All-Being," reiterates that this Reality '* stands towards the universe and towards ourselves in the same relation as an anthropomorphic Creator was supposed to stand," and '* bears a like relation with it not only to human thought, but to human feeling," etc. — Nineteenth Century, July 1884, pp. 5-7, 25. Mr. Harrison has no diffi- culty in showing in what contradictions Mr. Spencer entangles himself by the use of such language. — Ihid. Sept. pp. 358, 359. 10^ : y 5 f} ^p^ THklSTIC POSTULATE Pantheism. If we know all that these statements imply about the Absolute, there is no bar in principle to our know- ing a great deal more. A significant proof of this is the Development development which the system has received in the hands of b m'^^F'\ ^^^ °^ ^^' Sp^^c^r's disciples, Mr. Fiske, who in his Cosmic into Theism. Philosophy, and still more in his book on The Idea of God, has wrought it out into a kind of Theism. He discards the term " Unknowable," and writes : " It is enough to remind the reader that Deity is unknowable, just in so far as it is not manifested to consciousness through the phenomenal world ; knowable, just in so far as it is thus manifested ; unknowable, in so far as infinite and absolute ; knowable, in the order of its phenomenal manifestations ; knowable, in a a symbolic way, as the Power which is disclosed in every throb of the mighty rhythmic life of the universe ; knowable, as the eternal Source of a Moral Law, which is implicated with each action of our lives, and in obedience to which lies our only guaranty of the happiness which is incorruptible, and which neither inevitable misfortune nor unmerited obloquy can take away. Thus, though we may not by searching find out God, though we may not compass infinitude, or attain to absolute knowledge, we may at least know all that it concerns us to know, as intelligent and responsible beings." ^ The incom- It has not been left for Mr. Spencer to discover that, in %^ God reco - ^^^ depths of his absolute Being, as well as in the plentitude nised by Scrip of the modcs of his revealed Being, there is that in God ture and Theo- ^\^{q\^ m\x^t always pass our comprehension, — that in the present state of existence it is only very dimly and distantly, and by large use of " symbolic conceptions," that we can approximate to a right knowledge of God. This is affirmed in the Bible quite as strongly as it is by the agnostic philo- sophers. " Canst thou by searching find out God ? Canst thou find out the Almighty to perfection ? " ^ "0 the depth of the riches, both of the wisdom and knowledge of God ! how unsearchable are His judgments, and His ways past finding 1 Cosmic Philosophy, ii. p. 470 ; Idea of God, Pref. p. 28. 2 j^^ ^i. 7. OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW, 103 out ! " ^ " Now I know in part." ^ In this sense we can speak of a Christian Agnosticism.^ This incomprehensi- ~ - bility, however, is held in Scripture to arise, not from any inherent or incurable defect in the human faculties, but simply from the vastness of the object, in the know- ledge of which, nevertheless, the mind may continually be growing. The universe itself in its immeasurable extent vastly transcends our present powers of knowledge ; how much more the Author of the universe ! This, accordingly, is not the point we have in dispute with Mr. Spencer. The point is not whether, in the depths of His absolute existence, there is much in God that must remain unknown to us ; but whether He cannot be known by us in His revealed relations to ourselves, and to the world of which we form a part ; whether these relations are not also in their measure a true expression of His nature and character, so that through them we come to know something of Him — even of His absolute Being — though we cannot know all ? When, now, the Agnostic tells us that knowledge of this kind is impossible The Agnostic to us, see in what contradiction he lands himself. Here {^^^f ^^^w Lroci to be able a man who says — " I know nothing of God ; He is absolutely to affirm a beyond my ken ; I cannot form the faintest conception of P"°" ^^^"-^ ^^ cannot reveal what He is." And yet he knows so much about God as to Himself in re- be able to say beforehand that He cannot possibly enter into ^<^iion. relations with human beings by which He might become known to them. This is a proposition of which the Agnostic, on his own showing, can never have any evidence. If God is unknowable, how can we know this much about Him — that He cannot in any mode or form enter into relations with us by which He might be known ? Only on one supposition can this be maintained. If, indeed, as Mr. Spencer thinks, 1 Kom. xi. 33. 2 j Qqj.. xiii. 12. ^ "God," says A-agustine, "is more truly thought than He is uttered, and exists more truly than He is thought." — De Trinitate, Book vii. ch. 4. " Not the definitely-known God," says Professor Veitch, "not the unknown God, is our last word, far less the unknowable God, but the ever-to be-known God." — Knowing and Being, p. 323. 104 THE THEISTIC POSTULATE the nature of God and the intelligence of man are two things absolutely disparate, — if, as Spinoza said, to speak of God taking on Him the nature of man is as absurd as to speak of a circle taking on it the nature of the square,^ — then not only is God unknowable, but the whole Christian system is a 'priori ruled out of consideration. This, however, is a pro- position which can never be proved, and we have seen that the attempt to prove and work with it only entangled Mr. Spencer in a mass of difficulties. There is really, on his own principles, no reason why he should not admit the possibility of a relative knovv^ledge of God, as true in its way as the knowledge which we have of space, time, matter, force, or cause, — all which notions, as well as that of the Absolute, he tells us are prolific of intellectual contradictions.^ Why, for instance, should we more hesitate to speak of God as Intel- ligence than to speak of Him as Power ; why shrink from attributing to Him the attribute of Personality any more than that of cause ? ^ The whole objection, therefore, falls to the ground with the intellectual theory on which it is founded. For once grant that the nature of God and the intelligence of man are not thus foreign to each other, as Spencer supposes ; grant that man is made in the image of God, and bears in some measure His likeness — then man's mind is not wholly shut up within the limits of the finite — there is an absolute element in it, kindred with the absolute reason of God, and real knowledge both of God and of the nature of things without us is possible. //. Positive II. The a priori bar with which Agnosticism would block evidence for ^^ ^^^ ^^ ^^ knowledge of God being thus removed, we the Christian '' o o » view. niay proceed to inquire how it stands with the theistic postulate of the Christian view, in respect of the positive evidence in its behalf. It has been shown that, if the ^ Letter to Oldenburg, Epist. xxi. 2 pi^gi Principles, pp. 159-171. ^ Cf. Fiske, Idea of God, Pref. p. 15 ; and Chapman's Pre-Organk Evolution, p. 254. OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW, 105 Christian view be true, it must, up to a certain point, admit of verification by reason. The doctrine of God's existence must be shown to be in accord with reason, and to be in harmony with and corroborated by the facts of science and of the religious history of mankind. Science, indeed, has not for its object the determination of anything supernatural. Yet in its inquiries — dealing as it does with laws and forces, and with the widest generalisations of experience — it must come to a point at which the questions with which religion and philosophy deal are forced upon it, and it has to take up some attitude to them. The facts which it brings to light, the interpretations which it gives of these facts, cannot but have some bearing on the hypotheses we form as to the ultimate cause of existence. If it does not cross the border- land, it at least brings us within sight of truths which do not lie within its proper sphere, and points the way to their acceptance. 1. I may begin with certain thiDgs in regard to which it is i. Concessions possible to claim a large measure of agreement. And — tionar^^tri (1) It may be assumed, with little fear of contradiction, sophy. that if the idea of God is to be entertained, it can only be in (i) The Mono- the form of Monotheism. The Agnostic will grant us this ^'^^^'"^^^ ^^^"^ ° alone tenable. much. Whatever the Power is which works in the universe, it is one. " As for Polytheism," says a writer in Lux Mundi, " it has ceased to exist in the civilised world. Every theist is, by a rational necessity, a monotheist." ^ The Christian assumption of the unity and absoluteness of God — of the dependence of the created universe upon Him — is thus con- ^ Lux Mundi, p. 5S. J. S. Mill has said : ** The reason then, why Mono- theism may be accepted as the representative of Theism in the abstract is not so much because it is the Theism of all the more improved portions of the human race, as because it is the only Theism which can claim for itself any footing on scientific ground. Every other theory of the government of the universe by supernatural beings is inconsistent either with the carrying on of that government through a continual series of natural antecedents, according to fixed laws, or with the interdependence of each of these series upon all the rest, which are two of the most general results of science." — Three Essays on Bellgion, p. 133. io6 THE THE I STIC POSTULATE firmed. It is to be remembered that this truth, preached as a last result of science and of the philosophy of evolution, is a first truth of the Biblical religion. It is the Bible, and the Bible alone, which has made Monotheism the possession of the world. The unity of God was declared on the soil of Israel long before science or philosophy had the means of declaring it.^ Through Christianity it has been made the possession of mankind. On the soil of paganism, we see reason struggling towards this idea, striking out partial glimpses of it, sometimes making wonderful approximations to it, but never in its own strength lifting itself clear away from Polytheism to the pure conception of the one spiritual God, such as we find it in Christianity, still less making this the foundation of a religion. It is through Christianity, not through philosophical speculation, that this truth has become the support of faith, a light to which the investigations of science themselves owe much, and a sustaining principle and power in the lives of men.^ (2) The Power (2) This Powcr which the evolutionist requires us to w tc wor s pg(3QCTnise as the oritjin of all things is the source of a rational m the universe o & & is the source order. This is a second fact about which there can be no dispute. There is a rational order and connection of things in the universe. Science is not only the means by which our knowledge of this order is extended, but it is itself a standing proof of the existence of this order. Science can only exist on the assumption that the world is not chaos but cosmos, — that there is unity, order, law, in it, — that it is a coherent and consistent whole of things, construable through our intelligence, and capable of being expressed in forms of human speech. And the more carefully we examine the universe, we find that this is really its character. It is an ^ See Note B. — Old Testament Monotheism. 2 Cf. Naville's Modern Physics — " The Philosophy of the Founders of Modern Physics," pp. 154-243 (Eng, trans.) ; Fairbairn's Studies in the Phil, of Pel. and Hist. — " Theism and Scientific Speculation," pp. 66-71 ; and an article by Dr. Alex. Mair, on " The Contributions of Christianity to Science," in Presbyterian Review, Jan. 1888. of a rational order. OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. 107 harmonious universe. There is orderly sequence in it. There is orderly connection of part and part. There is that determinate connection we call law. There is the harmonious adjustment of means to ends, which again are embraced in higher ends, till, in the nobler systems, the teleological idea is extended to the whole system.^ In many ways does Mr- Spencer express in his writings his trust that this Power of which he speaks — inscrutable as he proclaims it to be — may be depended on not to put him, as the authors of the " Unseen Universe " phrase it, " to intellectual confusion." ^ To give only one instance — he bids the man who has some highest truth to speak, not to be afraid to speak it out, on the ground that " it is not for nothing that he has in him these sympathies with some principles, and repugnance to others. . . . He, like every other man," he says, " may properly consider himself as one of the myriad agencies through whom works the Unknown Cause ; and when the Unknown Cause produces in him a certain belief, he is thereby authorised to profess and act out that belief. For to render in their highest sense the words of the poet — * Nature is made better by no mean, But Nature makes that mean ; over that art Which you say adds to Nature, is an art Which Nature makes.' N"ot as adventitious, therefore, will the wise man regard the faith that is in him." ^ Who does not see in these remarkable sentences that, notwithstanding his reiteration of the words "Unknown Cause," "Unknowable," Mr. Spencer's latent faith is that this Power which works in the world and in men is a Power working according to rational laws and for rational ends — is on this account an object of trust — we might almost add, a source of inspiration ? But now, if this is so, can the conclusion be avoided that the Power on 1 So Mr. Spencer speaks of "the naturally-revealed end towards which the Power manifested throughout Evolution works."— i)ato of Ethics, p. 171. 2 Unseen Universe, 5th ed., p. 88. ^ First Principles^ p. 123. io8 THE THEISTIC POSTULATE which we thus depend rationally is itself rational ? It is knowable at least thus far, that we know that it is the source of a rational order — of an order construable through our intelligence. If now it is asserted that the source of this rational order is not itself rational, surely the proof rests, not on him who affirms, but on him who denies.^ If Mr. Spencer replies, as he does reply, that it is an " erroneous assumption that the choice is between personality and something lower than personality, whereas the choice is rather between personality and something higher," and asks — " Is it not just possible that there is a mod-e of being as much transcending intelligence and will, as these transcend mechanical motion?" ^ — the answer (not to dwell on the utterly disparate character of the things compared) is ready — this higher mode of being cannot at least be less than conscious. It may be a higher kind of consciousness, but it cannot be higher than con- sciousness. Nor is there the slightest ground for the assumption that there can be anything higher than self- conscious intelligence or reason.^ If we find in the universe an order congruous to the reason we have in ourselves, this is warranty sufficient for believing, till the contrary is proved, that the Pow^r which gives rise to this order is not only Power, but Intelligence and Wisdom as well. (3) The Power (3) Again, this Power which the evolutionist compels us which works ^Q recognise is the source of a moral order. Butler, in his in the universe is the source of ^'i^cc^ogy, undertook to prove that the constitution and course a moral order. Qf things is on the side of virtue. His argument is some- times spoken of as obsolete, but it is not so much obsolete as simply transformed. It is a new-fashioned phrase which Matthew Arnold uses when he speaks of a "Power not our- ^ Cf. Chapman's Pre-Organic Evolution, pp. 226, 227, 251, 282. ^ First Principles, p. 109. ^ Prof. Seth has justly said—** Nothing can be more certain than that all philosophical explanation must be explanation of the lower by the higher, and not vice versa ; and if self-consciousness is the highest fact we know, then we are justified in using the conception of self-consciousness as our best key to the ultimate nature of existence as a whole.''— Hegelianism and Personality/, p. 89. OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. 109 selves that makes for righteousness," but it means just what Butler meant, that the make and constitution of things in the universe is for righteousness, and not for its opposite. Righteous conduct works out good results for the individual and for society ; vicious conduct works out bad results. But what I wish to point out at present is the new support which this view receives from the theory of agnostic evolution, which is supposed by many to overthrow it. No philosophy, which aims at completeness, can avoid the obligation resting on it of showing that it is capable of yielding a coherent theory of human life. The construction of a system of ethics, therefore, Mr. Spencer justly regards as that part of his work to which all the other parts are subsidiary. The theological basis of ethics is rejected ; utilitarianism also is set aside as inadequate ; and in room of these the attempt is made to establish the rules of right conduct on a scientific basis by deducing them from the general laws of evolution. You find a Power evolving itself in the universe. Study, says Mr. Spencer, the laws of its evolution : find " the naturally revealed end towards which the Power manifested throughout evolution works " ; then, " since evolution has been, and is still, working towards the highest life, it follows that conforming to these principles by which the higher life is achieved, is furthering that end."^ And when a system is constructed on this basis, what is the result ? Why, that we are simply back to the old morality — to what Mr. Spencer himself calls '* a rationalised version of the ethical principles " of the current creed.^ The ethical laws which are deduced from the observations of the laws of evolution are identical with those which Christian ethics and the natural conscience of man in the higher stages of its development have always recognised.^ What is the inference ? These principles were 1 Data of Ethics, p. 171. ^ Data of Ethics, p. 257. 3 Cf. article by Professor Laidlaw on " Modern Thought in Relation to Christ- ianity and the Christian Church," in Presbyterian Eevieiv, 1885, p. 618. no THE THEISTIC POSTULATE not originally gained by scientific induction. They were the expressions of the natural consciousness of mankind as to distinctions of right and wrong, or were promulgated by teachers who claimed to have received them from a higher source. In either case, they were recognised by man as principles independently affirmed by conscience to be right. And now that the process of evolution comes to be scienti- fically studied, we are told that the principles of conduct yielded by it, in light of the end to which evolution naturally works, absolutely coincide with those which spring from this " work of the law " written in men's hearts. What else can we conclude, assuming that the evolutionist is right in his deduction, but that the universe is constructed in harmony with right ; that the laws which we have already recognised as of binding authority in conscience are also laws of the objective world ; that the principles of right discovered in conscience, and the moral order of society based on these principles, are productions of the one great evolutionary cause, which is the Force impelling and controlling the whole onward movement of humanity ? There is certainly nothing here to conflict with, but everything to support the view that the Power which is above all, and through all, and in all things, is not only Intelligence and Wisdom, but also an Ethical Will. At least, to most persons who dispassionately study the subject, I think it will appear reasonable that a Power which has an ethical end must be an ethical Power. If, further, this ethical end embraces, as Mr. Spencer seems to believe, the highest perfection and happiness of man,^ it is still more difficult to conceive how it should have a place in the nature of things unless the Supreme Power were itself benevolent and good. It is not, it should be remembered, as if this ethical end were an after-thought or accident. It is, according to the theory, the final and supreme goal to which the whole process of evolution for countless millenniums has been working up, and only when it is reached will the 1 Data of Ethics, pp. 253-257. OF THE CHRISTIAN VIE W. 1 1 1 ripest fruit of the whole development be gathered. But how is this possible, except on a teleological view of things ; and ~ - what teleology can yield a moral result which does not postulate at the other end a moral cause ? Mr. Spencer may deprecate as he will the imposing of moral ideas generated in our consciousness upon the Infinite which transcends consciousness. But it is only his own arbitrary denial of consciousness to the Absolute, and his arbitrary assumption that there can be no kindredship between that absolute consciousness and our own, which prevents him from drawing the natural conclusion from his own premises. But if to Mr. Spencer's definition of the Absolute, as " an Infinite and Eternal Energy from which all things proceed," we add, as I think we are entitled to do, the predicates of infinite Intelligence and of Wisdom, and of Ethical Will, we have all the fundamental theistic positions affirmed. If the First Cause of the universe is proved by its mani- The term festations to be at once rational Intelligence and Ethical T^f^?, ° as applied to Will, there should be no excess of scrupulosity in applying to God. it the term " Personal." I have thus far reasoned on the assumptions of Mr. Spencer, and have spoken of his Ultimate Eeality as he does himself, as "Power," "Eorce," "Cause," etc. But I cannot leave this part of the subject without remarking that Mr. Spencer is far from having the field of thought all to himself on this question of the nature of the Ultimate Existence. It was shown in last Lecture how, starting from a different point of view, the higher philosophy of the century — the Neo-Kantian and Neo-Hegelian — reaches, with a very large degree of certainty, the conclusion that the ultimate principle of the universe must be self-conscious. It is well known that the Personality of God was a point left in very great doubt in the system of Hegel.^ God was conceived of as the Absolute Eeason, but the drift of the system seemed to point rather to an impersonal Eeason which first becomes conscious of itself in man, than to a 2 See Note C— Hegel's Idea of God. 112 THE THEISTIC POSTULATE self-consciousness complete and perfect from the beginning. Whatever its other defects, the later Hegelianism has shaken itself clear of this ambiguity, and affirms with emphasis that the principle at the basis of the universe is self-conscious.^ The other line of development — the Neo-Kantian — is, in the person of its chief representative, Hermann Lotze, explicitly theistic. I only notice here that after a careful discussion of all the arguments against ascribing Personality to the Divine Being, on the ground that personality implies the limitations of the finite, Lotze arrives at this conclusion, diametrically the opposite of Mr. Spencer's — " Perfect personality is recon- cilable only with the conception of an infinite Being; for finite beings only an approximation to this is attainable." ^ It is interesting, further, to notice that even Neo-Spencer- ianism — if I may coin such a term — has come round, in the person of Mr. Fiske, to a similar affirmation. "The final conclusion," he says, " is, that we must not say that ' God is Force,' since such a phrase inevitably calls up those pantheistic notions of blind necessity, which it is my express desire to avoid ; but always bearing in mind the symbolic character of the words, we may say that ' God is Spirit.' How my belief in the personality of God could be more strongly affirmed without entirely deserting the language of modern philosophy and taking refuge in pure mythology, I am unable to see." * 2. The theoretic 2. It is now ncccssary to come to closer quarters, and to "/''^^^V''^''^^ ask whether the ordinary proofs for the existence of God, the existence of •' ^ God— question which havc been so much assailed since the time of Kant, of their valid- ^Yy 1 See Lecture II. p. 74. The Neo-Hegelian theory, however, is far from satisfactory from the point of view of Theism in other respects. See Note D. — Defects of the Neo-Hegelian View. '^ Outlines of the Pliil. of Religion, ^. 69 (Eng. trans.). See the whole dis- cussion (chap, iv.), and the fuller treatment in the Microcosmus, ii. pp. 659- 688. Lotze's closing words in the latter are: "Perfect Personality is in God only, to all finite minds there is allotted but a pale copy thereof ; the finiteness of the finite is not a producing condition of this Personality, but a limit and a hindrance to its development." ^ Idea of God, p. 17. Cf. the instructive treatment of this subject of Per- sonality in Professor Iverach's Is God Knowable ? pp. 7, 12-37, 223-233. OF THE CHRISTIAN VIE W. 1 1 3 still retain their old cogency, and if not, what modifications require to be made on them. The time-honoured division of these proofs — which have recently received so able a re- handling at the instance of Dr. Hutchison Stirling in his " Gilford Lectures " — is into the cosraological, the teleological, and the ontological, to which, as belonging to another category, falls to be added the moral. Besides these, Kant thinks, there are no others.^ This, however, must be taken with qualification, if the remark is meant to apply to the old scholastic forms in which these proofs have customarily been put. Not only is there no necessity for the proofs being confined to these forms — some of which are clearly inadequate — but they are capable of many extensions, and even transformations, as the result of advancing knowledge, and of the better insight of reason into its own nature. I may add that I do not attach much importance in this con- nection to objections to these proofs drawn from Kant's peculiar theory of knowledge.^ If it can be shown that in the exercise of our reason as directed on the world in which we live — or on its own nature — we are compelled either to cease to think, or to think in a particular way, — if we find that these necessities of thought are not peculiar to in- dividuals here and there, but have been felt by the soundest thinkers in all ages, and among peoples widely separated from each other, — we may be justified in believing that our reason is not altogether an untrustworthy guide, but may be depended on with considerable confidence to direct us to the truth. Neither shall I waste time at this stage by discussing in Meaning of what sense it is permissible to speak of "proof" of ^o''^^^!^-^ ^^ transcendent a reality as the Divine existence. We remem- Divine ber here the saying of Jacobi that a God capable of proof ^^^^^^f^'^'^- would be no God at all ; since this would mean that there is something higher than God from which His existence can be 1 Kritik d. r. Vernunft, p. 416 (Eng. trans, p. 363). - See an acute criticism of Kant's Theory of Knowledge in Stalilin's Kant^ Lotze, und Bitschl, pp. 6-83 (Eng. trans.). 8 114 THE THEISTIC POSTULATE deduced. But this applies only to the ordinary reasoning of the deductive logic. It does not apply to that higher kind of proof which may be said to consist in the mind being guided back to the clear recognition of its own ultimate pre- suppositions. Proof in Theism certainly does not consist in deducing God's existence as a lower from a higher ; but rather in showing that God's existence is itself the last postulate of reason — the ultimate basis on which all other knowledge, all other belief rests. What we mean by proof of God's existence is simply that there are necessary acts of thought by which we rise from the finite to the infinite, from the caused to the uncaused, from the contingent to the necessary, from the reason involved in the structure of the universe to an universal and eternal Eeason, which is the ground of all, from morality in conscience to a moral Lawgiver and Judge. In this connection the three theoretical proofs constitute an inseparable unity — " constitute together," as Dr. Stirling finely declares, " but the three undulations of a single wave, v/hich wave is but a natural rise and ascent to God, on the part of man's own thought, with man's own experience and consciousness as the object before him." ^ (i) The COS' (1) Adopting the usual arrangement, I speak first of the mo ogica cosmological proof, which, from the contingency and mutability of the world, — from its finite, dependent, changeful, multiple character, — concludes to an infinite and necessary Being as its ground and cause. That this movement of thought is necessary is shown by the whole history of philosophy and religion. Kant, who subjects the argument to a severe criticism, nevertheless admits — " It is something very remark- able that, on the supposition that something exists, I cannot avoid the inference that something exists necessarily." ^ The ^ Philosophy and Theology, p. 45. On the theistic proofs generally, and Kant's criticism of them, cf. Caird's Philosoj)hy of EeUg!on, pp. 133-159, Professor E. Caird's Philosophy of Kant, ii. pp. 102-129; and Dr. Stirling's work cited above. 2 Kritik, p. 431 (Eiig. trans, p. 378). See Xote E.— Kant on the Cosmo- logical Argument. OF I HE CHRISTIAN VIEW. 115 question then arises — Is the world this necessary Being ? The cosmological proof on its various sides is directed to showing that it is not, — that it is not sufficient for its own explanation, — that, therefore, it must have its ground and origin in some other being that is necessary. Whatever exists has either the reason of its existence in itself, or has it in something else. But that the world has not the reason of its existence in itself — is not, in Spinoza's phrase, causa sui, is not a necessarily existing being — is shown in various ways. T/ie world not i. By the, contingency of its existence. — A necessary Being, ^^^ ^^<^^^^^^y as Kant himself defines it, is one the necessity of whose i. By the con- existence is given through its possibility, i.e. the non-existence ^^^^s^^^y ^f^^^^ cxistcttcc ' of which cannot be thought of as possible.^ But the world is not an existence of this character. We can think of its non- existence without contradiction — as, e.g., we cannot think of the non-existence of space and time. We can think away all the contents of space and time, but we cannot think away space and time themselves. ii. By the dependency of its several parts. — It is made up ii. By the de- of finite parts, each of which is dependent on the others, and^^'^'^'^T'^''-^^^'' ■^ several pai-ts ; sustains definite relations to them ; its parts, therefore, have not the character of self -subsistence. But a world made up of parts, none of which is self-subsistent, cannot as a whole be self-subsistent, or the necessary Being.^ iii. By its tem]poral successio7i of effects. — The world is in iii. By its constant flux and change. Causes give birth to effects, and ^^''^A^'^^/«^^- ^ ° cess/on of effects depend on causes. Each state into which it passes /?^gf/j. has its determining conditions in some immediately preceding state. This fact, apart from the general proof of contingency, suggests the need of conceiving not only of a necessary ground, but likewise of a First Cause of the universe. The alternative supposition is that of an eternal series of causes and effects — a conception which is unthinkable, and affords no resting-place for reason. What can be more self-con- 1 Kritik, p. 102 (Eng. trans, p. 68). 2 Cf. Dr. Stirling, in Phil, and T/ieoI. p. 126. ii6 THE THEISTIC POSTULATE Objection to this proof— it does not show what the necessary Beinz is. The religious experience cor- responding to this proof— consciousness of absolute dependence. tradictory than the hypothesis of a chain of causes and effects, each link of which hangs on a preceding link, while yet the whole chain hangs on nothing.^ Eeason, therefore, itself points us to the need of a First Cause of the universe, who is at the same time a self-existing, necessary, infinite Being. It is, since Kant's time, customarily made an objection to this argument, that it only takes us as far as some necessary being, — it does not show us in the least degree what kind of a being this is — whether, e.g., in the world or out of it, whether the world-soul of the Stoics, the pantheistic sub- stance of Spinoza, the impersonal reason of Hegel, or the personal God of the theist. This may be, and therefore the cosmological argument may need the other arguments to com- plete it. It will be found, however, when we go more deeply (in the ontological argument) into the conception of necessary being, that there is only one kind of existence which answers to this description, and with this more perfect conception the cosmological argument will then connect itself. As thus presented, the cosmological argument is a process of thought. I cannot leave it, however, without pointing out that it stands connected with a direct fact of consciousness, which, as entering into experience, changes this proof to some extent from a merely logical into a real one. Not to speak of the immediate impression of transitoriness, finitude, con- tingency, vanity, which, prior to all reasoning, one receives from the world,^ and which finds expression, more or less, in all religions, there is, at the very root of our religious consciousness, that "feeling of absolute dependence" which ^ Dr. Stirling says, replying to Hume : " No multiplication of parts will make a whole potent if each part is impotent. You will hardly reach a valid conclusion where your every step is invalid. ... It will be vain to extract one necessity out of a whole infinitude of contingencies. Nor is it at all possible for such infinitude of contingencies to be even conceivable by reason. If each link of the chain hangs on another, the whole will hang, and only hang, even in eternity, unsuppoi,-ted, like some stark serpent, unless you find a hook for it. Add weakness to weakness, in any quantity, you will never make strength. " —Phil, and Theol. p. 262. ^ Cf. Caird, Phil, of Religion, p. 135. OF THE CHRISTIAN VIE W. 117 Schleiermacher fixes on as the very essence of religion;^ and which reappears in Mr. Spencer's philosophy in a changed — - form as the immediate consciousness of an absolute Power on which we and our universe alike depend. This feeling of dependence, so natural to man and interweaving itself with all his religious experiences, is the counterpart in the practical sphere of the cosmological argument in the logical. Both need their explanation in something deeper than them- selves, namely, in the possession by man of a rational nature, which makes him capable of rising in thought and feeling above the finite. And as, in the theoretic sphere, the cosmo- logical argument presses forward to its completion in another and a higher, so in the religious sphere the rational nature of man forbids that this sense of dependence should remain a mere feeling of dependency on a blind Power.^ Eeligion must free, bless, inspire, strengthen men. From the first, there- fore, the soul is at work, seeking in its depths, and in obedience to its own laws, to change this relation of depend- ence into a free and personal one. (2) The second argument for the Divine existence is \h^{2)Teleologicai teleological, — better known simply as the design argument. ^^ ^^^^^ Kant speaks of this oldest and most popular of the theistic Kant's arguments with great respect ; and the objections which he <^^'^^^^^^^^' makes to it affect more its adequacy to do all that is expected from it than its force so far as it goes. It does not, he thinks, prove a Creator, but only an Architect, of the world ; it does not prove an infinite, but only a very great Intelligence, etc.^ I may remark, however, that if it proves even this, it does a great deal ; and from an intelligence so great as to hold in its ken the plan and direction of the universe, the step will not be found a great one to the Infinite Intelligence which we call God. But the argument, in the right conception of it, does more than Kant allows, and is a step of transition to the final one — the ontological. ^ D&r christ. Glauhe, sees. 3 and 4. " See Note F. — Kant on the Teleological Argument.. . ii8 THE THEISTIC POSTULATE Argument A new argument against design in nature has been found against design -^^ recent times in the doctrine of evolution. The proof we from evolu- i • e tion. are considering turns, as everyone knows, on the existence or ends in nature. In Kant's words — " In the world we find everywhere clear signs of an order which can only spring from design — an order realised with the greatest wisdom, and in a universe which is indescribably varied in content, and in extent infinite." ^ In organisms particularly we see the most extraordinary adaptations of means to ends — structures of almost infinite complexity and wonderful perfection — con- trivances in which we have precisely the same evidence of the adjustment of the parts to produce the ends, as in human works of art.2 From this the inference is drawn that a world so full of evidences of rational purpose can only be the work of a wise and intelligent mind. But this argument is broken down if it can be shown that what look like ends in nature are not really such, but simply results — that the appearance of apparently designed arrangements to produce certain ends can be explained by the action of causes which do not imply intelligence. This is what evolution, in the hands of some of its expounders, undertakes to do. By showing how structures may have arisen through natural selection, operat- ing to the preservation of favourable variations in the struggle for existence, it is thought that the aid of intelligence may be dispensed with, and that a death-blow is given to teleology.^ The eye, for example, may have resulted from the gradual accumulation of small variations, each of them accidental, and arising from unknown laws in the organism, but each, as 1 Kritlh, p. 436 (Eng. trans. 384). ^ No recent school 1ms done more to elaborate the proof of teleology in Nature than that from which the opposite might have been expected — the pessimistic school. Cf. Schopenhaner's, Die, Welt ah Wille und Vorstellung (Book ii. chap. 26, ** On Teleology"), and Hartmann's Phil, d. Unhewussten, passim. 2 Thus, e.g. Strauss, Haeckel, Helmholtz, G. Romanes, "Physicus." Helm- lioltz, as quoted by Strauss, says : " Darwin's theory shows how adaptation of structure in organisms can originate without any intermixture of intelligence, through the blind operation of a natural law." — Der alte und der neue Glauhe, p. 216. Mr. Romanes says : " If [plants and animals] were specially created, the evidence of supernatural design remains unrefuted and irrefutable, whereas OF THE CHRISTIAN VIE W. 1 1 9 it arises, giving to its possessor some slight advantage in the struggle for existence. It is a simple case of the survival ~ ~ of the fittest. Instead of the advantage resulting from a designed arrangement, the appearance of arrangement results from the advantage. In reality, however, the facts of evolution do not weaken the proof from design, but rather immensely enlarge it by showing all things to be bound together in a vaster, grander plan than had been formerly conceived. Let us see how the matter precisely stands. On the general hypothesis of evolution, as applied to the EvoluHonpro organic world, I have nothing to say, except that, within ^^^^^—"^^^^^ ^' ° ^ ' o J^ t > implies. certain limits, it seems to me extremely probable, and sup- ported by a large body of evidence. This, however, only refers to the fact of a genetic relationship of some kind between the different species of plants and animals, and does not affect the means by which this development may be supposed to be brought about. On this subject two views Two views: may be held.^ The first is, that evolution results {^q^ ^^oiu^ion as development development from within; in which case, obviously, \hQ from within, argument from design stands precisely where it did, except ^^'^ evohawn . ... as result of that the sphere of its application is enormously Qx.iQi\&Qdi. fortuity. The second view is, that evolution has resulted from fortuitous ^^^^^'"'•^^^' ^f ,.T., . „ ^ 1 ' 1 ' latter vieiv. variations, combined with action ot natural selection, laying hold of and preserving the variations that were favourable. This is really, under a veil of words, to ask us to believe that accident and fortuity have done the w^ork of mind. But the facts are not in agreement with the hypothesis. The variations in organisms are not absolutely indefinite. In if they were slowly evolved, that evidence has been utterly and for ever destroyed." — Organic Evolution, p. 13. On the bearings of evolution on design, and on the design argument generally in its present relations to science, see Janet's Final Causes (Eng. trans.); Stirling's Philosophy and Theology; Kennedy's Natural Theology and Modern Thought (1891) ; Eow's Cftristian Theism (1890) ; Martineau's Study of Religion (i. pp., 270-333) ; Flint's Theism; Mivart's Lessons from Nature; Conder's Basis of Faith ; Murphy's Habit and Intelligence ; Ebrard's Christian Apologetics, ii. pp. 1-56 (Eng. trans.); Argyll's Reign of Law, etc. On Kant's views on evolution and on final causes as connected therewith, cf. Caird's Phil, of Kant, ii. 495-499. ^ See Note G. — Schools of Evolutionists. I20 THE THEISTIC POSTULATE the evolution of an eye, for example, the variations are all more or less in the line of producing the eye. When the formation of an eye has begun, the organism keeps to that line in that place. It does not begin to sprout an ear where the eye is being developed. There is a ground plan that is adhered to in the midst of the variations. Could we collect the successive forms through which the eye is supposed to have passed in the course of its development, what we would see (I speak on the hypothesis of the theory) would be a succession of small increments of structure, all tending in the direction of greater complexity and perfection of the organ — the appearance of new muscles, new lenses, new arrangements for adjusting or perfecting the sight, etc. But the mere fact that these successive appearances could be put in a line, however extended, would throw no light on how the development took place, or how this marvellously complex organ came to build itself up precisely after this pattern.^ The cause invoked to explain this is natural selection. Now the action of natural selection is real, but its influence may be very easily overrated. It is never to be forgotten that natural selection 'produces nothing. It acts only on organisms already produced, weeding out the weakest, and the least fitted structurally to survive, and leaving the better adapted in possession of the field.^ It is altogether to exaggerate the influence of natural selection, to attribute to it a power to pick out infallibly on their first appearance the infinitesimal variations in an organism which are to form the foundations of future useful organs, though, in their initial stage, they cannot be shown to confer any benefit on their possessors, and may be balanced or neutralised by fifty or sixty other variations in an opposite direction, or by differences of size, strength, speed, etc., on the part of the competitors in the struggle ; and still more a power to preserve each of these ^ Cf. Jevons, Principles of Science, ii. p. 462 ; J. S. Mill, Three Essays on Religion, p. 171. Mill concludes that "the adaptations in Nature afford a large balance of probability in favour of creation by intelligence." — P. 174. ^ See i)assages in Note G. OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. 121 slight variations till another and yet another of a favourable kind is added to it after long intervals, in a contest in which numbers alone are overwhelmingly against the chance of its survival.^ Taking the facts of evolution as they really stand, What the facts what they seem to point to is something like the follow- ^ . J^ ^' ^^" point to. i. An inner power of development of organisms. ii. A power of adjustment in organisms adapting them to environment. iii. A weeding out of weak and unfit organisms by natural selection. iv. Great differences in the rate of production of new species. Ordinarily, species seem to have nearly all the characters of fixity which the old view ascribed to them. Variation exists, but it is confined within comparatively narrow limits. The type persists through ages practically unchanged. At other periods in the geological history of the past there seems to have been a breaking down of this fixity. The history of life is marked by a great inrush of new forms. New species crowd upon the scene. Plasticity seems the order of the day.^ We may call this evolution if we like, but it is none the less creation, — the production out of the old of something new and higher. All that we are called ^ Mr. Spencer shows that Natural Selection fails as an explanation in pro- portion as life grows complex. "As fast," he says, "as the faculties are multiplied, so fast does it become possible for the several members of a species to have various kinds of superiority over one another. While one saves its life by higher speed, another does the like by clearer vision, another by keener scent, another by quicker hearing, another by greater strength, another by unusual power of enduring cold and hunger, another by special sagacity, another by special timidity, another by special courage, and others by other bodily and mental attributes. Now it is unquestionably true that, other things being equal, each of these attributes giving its possessor an extra chance of life, is likely to be transmitted to posterity. But there seems no reason to suppose that it will be increased in subsequent generations by natural selection . . . If those members of the species which have but ordinary shares of it nevertheless survive by virtue of other superiorities which they severally possess, then it is not easy to see how this particular attribute can be developed by natural selection in subsequent generations," etc. — Principles of Biology, sec. 166. Cf. Alfred W. Bennett in Martineau's Study of Religion, i. 280-282. 2 Cf. Dawson, Modern Ideas of Evolution, pp. 106, 107 ; The Chain of Life THE THEISTIC POSTULATE The design argument too narro7v. Wider argu- ment from order, plan, law, etc. upon to notice here is that it in no way conflicts with design, but rather compels the acknowledgment of it. The chief criticism I would be disposed to make upon the design argument, as an argument for intelligence in the cause of the universCi is that it is too narrow. It confines the argument to final causes — that is, to the particular case of the adaptation of means to ends. But the basis for the inference that the universe has a wise and intelligent Author is far wider than this. It is not the marks of purpose alone which necessitate this inference, but everything which bespeaks order, plan, arrangement, harmony, beauty, rationality in the connection and system of things. It is the proof of the presence of tlioiiglit in the world — whatever shape that may take.^ As we saw in a former part of the Lecture, the assumption on which the whole of science pro- ceeds — and cannot but proceed — in its investigations, is, that the system it is studying is intelligible, — that there is an intelligible unity of things. It admits of being reduced to terms of thought. There is a settled and established order on which the investigator can depend. Without this he could not advance one step. Even Kant's objection that this argument proved only an architect of the universe, but not a creator of its materials, is seen from this point of view to be in Geol. Time, p. 229. " The progress of life," he says, "in geological time has not been uniform or uninterrupted. . . . Evolutionists themselves, those at least who are willing to allow their theory to be at all modified by facts, now perceive this ; and hence we have the doctrine advanced by Mivart, Le Comte, and others, of 'critical periods,' or periods of rapid evolution alternating with others of greater quiescence." — Mod. Ideas, pp. 106, 107. See in both works the examples given of this " apparition of s))ecies." ^ Principal Shairp says : *' To begin with the outward world, there is, I shall not say so much the mark of design on all outward things as an experience forced in upon the mind of the thoughtful naturalist that, penetrate into nature wherever he may, thought has been there before him ; that, to quote the words of one of the most distinguished, * there is really a plan, which may be read in the relations which you and I, and all living beings scattered over the surface of our earth, hold to each other. ' " — Studies in Poetry and Philosophy, p. 367. Cf. also on this aspect of the subject, M'Cosh, Method of Divine Government, \)^. 75-151; and on the argument from Beauty and Sublimity in Nature, Kennedy's Natural Theology and Modern Thought, Lecture IV. (Donnellan Lectures). OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. 123 .invalid.^ The very materials of the universe — the atoms which compose it — show by their structure, their uniformity, their properties, their mathematical relations, that they must have a Creator ; that the Power which originated them, which weighed, measured, and numbered them, which stamped on them their common characters, and gave them their definite laws and relations, must have been intelligent. I admit, however, that as the design argument presupposes the cosmo- logical, to give us the idea of an infinite and necessary Being at the basis of the universe, so both of these arguments need the ontological, to show us in the clearest and most con- vincing manner that this Being and Cause of the universe is infinite, self-conscious Eeason. (3) I come, accordingly, in the third place, to the onto- (3) The onto- logical argument — that which Kant, not without reason, ^-^^^^f ^^''^"' ^ ^ ' ' ?nent. affirms to be at the foundation of the other two, and to be the real ground on which the inference to the existence of a necessary and infinitely perfect Being rests. It is an argu- ment which in these days, owing largely to his criticism upon it, has fallen much into disrepute, though a good deal has also been done by able thinkers to rehabilitate it, and to The Anseimk show its real bearings. It must further be admitted that \xiJ'Z"^\^^^'^ the form in which it was wont to be put in the schools, criticism upon the strictures which Kant makes on it are in the main just.- ^^* In the earlier form, it is an argument from the idea of God as a necessary idea of the mind, to His real existence. I have, reasons Anselm, the idea of a most perfect Being. But this idea includes the attribute of existence. For if the most perfect Being did not exist, there could be conceived a greater than He, — one that did exist, — and therefore He would ^ Cf. Lecture IV. on Creation. It maybe asked, besides, if it is so certain, as Kant assumes, that only a finite power is needed to create — I do not say a universe, but even an atom ; whether there are not finite eff"ects, such as crea- tion, to which only Omnipotence is competent ? The point is not that it is an atom, but that it is created. 2 Krxtik, pp. 417-424 (Eng. trans, pp. 364-370). See Note H.— Kant on the Ontological Argument. 124 THE THEISTIC POSTULATE not be the most perfect. The most perfect Being, therefore, is one in the idea of whom existence is necessarily included. In this form the argument seems little better than a logical quibble, and so Kant has treated it. Kant grants the necessity of the idea — shows how it arises — names it Tim Ideal of Pure Reason — but argues with cogency that from an idea, purely as such, you cannot conclude to real existence. It would be strange, however, if an argument which has wielded such power over some of the strongest intellects were utterly baseless; and Dr. Hutchison Stirling has well shown that when we get to the kernel of Anselm's thought, as he himself explains it, it has by no means the irrational character which might at first sight appear to belong to it.^ Anselm's form of the argument, however, it must now be observed, is neither the final nor tlie perfect one. Kant himself has given the impulse to a new development of it, which shows more clearly than ever that it is- not baseless, but is really the deepest and most comprehensive of all arguments — the argument implied in both of the two pre- ceding. New form of The kernel of the ontological argument, as we find it put, this argument f^^. example, by Prof. Green, is the assertion that thought —thought the , ^ , necessary ^xm%\.^ the necessary ^rms of all that is — even of all possible or of existence, conceivable existence. This assertion is not arrived at in any o. 'priori way, but by the strict and sober analysis of what is involved in such knowledge of existence as we have. If we analyse the act of knowledge, we find that in every form of it there are implied certain necessary and universal conditions, which, from the nature of the case, must be conditions of experience also, otherwise it could never be experience for us at all. Thus, any world we are capable of knowing with our present faculties must be a world in space and time, — a world subject to conditions of number and quantity, — a world apprehended in relations of substance and accident, cause and effect, etc. A world of any other 1 Phil, and Theol pp. 182-193. OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. 125 kind — supposing it to exist — would be in relation to our thought or knowledge, unthinkable. These conditions of knowledge, moreover, are not arbitrary and contingent, but universal and necessary. They spring from reason itself, and express its essential and immutable nature. Thus we feel sure that there is no world in space or time to which the laws of mathematics do not apply; no world possible in which events do not follow each other according to the law of cause and effect ; no world in which the fundamental laws of thought and reasoning are different from what they are in our own. Mr. J. S. Mill, indeed, thought there might be worlds in which two and two do not make four ; or in which events succeed each other without any causal relation. But in this he will get few to agree with him. In like manner, there are moral principles which our reason recognises as universally and unconditionally valid. We cannot conceive of a world in which falsehood would really be a virtue, and truth-speaking a vice. We hold it, therefore, for certain that reason is the source of universal and necessary principles which spring from its essence, and which are the conditions of all possible knowledge. But this, its own essential nature, reason finds reflected back from the world around it. A world does exist, constituted through these very principles which we find within ourselves, — in space and time, through number and quantity, substance and quantity, cause and effect, etc., — and therefore knowable by us, and capable of becoming an object of our experience. We arrive, therefore, at this — that the world is constituted through a reason similar to our own ; that, in Mr. Green's words, " the under- standing which presents an order of nature to us is in principle one with an understanding which constitutes that order itself."^ And that such a reason not only does but must exist, I see not simply by inference from the exist- ence of the world, which is the higher form of the cosmo- logical argument, but by reflection on the necessary character 1 Prol. to Ethics, p. 23. Realism 126 THE THEISTIC POSTULATE of the principles of reason themselves. For whence these laws of thought — these universal and necessary conditions of all truth and knowledge — which I discover in myself; which my own reason neither makes nor can unmake ; which I recognise to be in me and yet not of me ; which I know must belong to every rational being in every part of the universe ? They are necessary and eternal in their nature, yet they have not the ground of their existence in my individual mind. Can I conclude otherwise than that they have their seat and ground in an eternal and absolute Eeason — the absolute Priiis of all that is, at once of thought and of existence ? It is but a further extension of the same argu- ment when I proceed to show that thought is only possible in relation to an I, to a central principle of self-conscious- ness, which unifies and connects all thinking and experience. Rational This argument, which has been called that of " Eational Eealism," is one which in varied forms has been accepted by the deepest thinkers, and finds widespread acknowledg- ment in literature.^ It is not liable to the objection made to the Anselmic form, of involving an illicit inference from mere idea to real existence ; but it has this in common with it that the existence of an Eternal Eeason is shown to be involved in the very thinking of this, or indeed of any thought. In the very act of thinking, thought affirms its own existence. But thought can perceive, not only its own existence, but the necessity of its existence — the necessity of its existence, even, as the 'prius of everything else. What is affirmed, therefore, is not simply my thought, but an Absolute Thought, and with this the ex- istence of an Absolute Thinker ; in the words of Dr. Harris, who has done much to give popular expression to this argument, of "an Absolute Eeason energising in perfect wisdom and love " in the universe.^ I cannot but maintain, therefore, that the ontological argument, in the kernel and ^ See Note I. — Rational Realism. 2 The Phil. Basis of Theism, p. 3 ; cf. pp. 82, 143, 560, etc. OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW, 127 essence of it, is a sound one, and that in it the existence of God is really seen to be the first, the most certain, and the most indisputable of all truths. We saw in connection with the cosmological argument The religious that there was a direct fact of consciousness which turned ^■^P^^^^<^^ ^(>^- . . responding to the logical argument mto a real one, — which translated, if I the tehologicai may so speak, the abstract proof into a living experience. ^'^^ ^'^^^" It is worth our while to inquire, before leaving these theoretic merits— tie ' proofs, whether there is anything of the same kind here ; i^^mediate , 1 . . , 1 T • . 1.1 sense of ^^ the anything m actual religious consciousness which answers to EtenmiPower that demonstration of a rational element in the world which and Divinity' is given in the two remaining arguments. I think there is. ^ ^^ reator. I refer to that very real perception which mankind have at all times manifested of a spiritual presence and power in nature, which is the effect of the total unanalysed impression which nature in its infinite variety and complexity, its wondrous grandeur, order, beauty, and fulness of life and power, makes upon the soul. The more carefully facts have been examined, the more narrowly the history of religions has been scrutinised, the clearer has it become that under- lying all the particular ideas men have of their deities, — underlying their particular acts of worship to them, — there is always this sense of something mysterious, intangible, infinite, — of an all-pervading supernatural Presence and Power, — which is not identified with any of the particular phenomena of nature, but is regarded rather as manifested through them.^ It is this which Paul speaks of when he says that "the Eternal Power and Divinity" of God are manifested since the creation of the world in the things that ^ This is true of the lowest as well as of the highest religions,— cf. Waitz on The, Religion of the Hegroes, in Max Miiller's Hibbert Lectures, pjo. 106-107,— but is much more conspicuous in the oldest forms of natural religion, e.g. in the Vedic, Babylonian, and Egyptian religions. On the general facts, cf. Max Miiller's works, Reville's Hist, of Religions, Sayce's Hibbert Lectures on The lieligion of the Ancient Babylonians, Renouf's Hibbert Lectures on The Religion of Ancient Egypt, Fairbairn's Studies, Loring Brace's The Unknown God, Pressense's The Ancient World and Christianity (Eng. trans.), etc., and see Note F. to Lecture V. 128 THE THE I STIC POSTULATE How is this sense of the Divine to be explained ? are raade.^ It is Max Mliller's " perception of the infinite,"' Schleiermacher's "consciousness of the infinite in the finite," the seiisus numinis of the older writers, Wordsworth's " sense of something far more deeply interfused " — " Whose dwelling is the light of setting suns, And the round ocean, and the living air, And the blue sky, and in the mind of man." ^ Such a sense or perception of the Divine is the common substratum of all religions, and the theory of religion which fails to take account of it is like the play of Hamlet with Hamlet left out. But how is this sense of the Divine in nature — which is the stronghold of the theology of feeling — to be accounted for ? It is certainly not the result of logical argument, and goes beyond anything that logical argument could yield. Yet it may easily be shown that rational elements are implicit in it, and that the rational elements involved are precisely those which the foregoing arguments have sought explicitly to unfold. To understand the impression of the Divine which nature makes on man, we have to remember how much the mind of man has already to do with nature. We have to do here with nature, not primarily as an objectively existing system of laws and forces, but as it exists for man as an object of actual knowledge and experience. And how has it come to be this to him ? Not without help from the thinking mind which collates and connects the separate impressions made on it through the senses, and gradually reads the riddle of the universe by the help of what it brings to it out of its own resources. We speak of the immaturity of the savage mind, but there is an intense mental activity in the simplest conception which the savage (or the child) can form of the existence of nature, or of a world around him. He sees changes, but he finds the interpretation of these changes in the idea of causality which he brings to it from his own mind. He groups 1 Rom. i. 20. 2 Wordsworth's Tintern Abbey. OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. 129 attributes and forms objects, but he does this through the mental law of substance and accident. He perceives the operation of vast forces in nature, but whence does he get the idea of force ? He gets it from the consciousness of power within himself, and through this puts meaning into the scene of change and movement which he finds around him. Is it wonderful, then, that man, who has put so much of himself into nature, even when constructing it as an object of thought, should again receive back the reflection of his own spiritual image from nature — receive it back on a grander, vastly enhanced scale, proportionate to the great- ness and immensity of the universe on which he looks, and should be filled with awe and reverence in presence of this Other- Self, and Higher-than-Self, as that of a Eeason, Power, and Will essentially akin to his own, though infinitely greater ? Eeason does not create this sense of the Divine ; it can only follow in its train, and seek to lay bare and analyse — as is done in the theoretic proofs — the rational elements which it involves. III. There remains the moral argument, which deserves a III. The place by itself, and which I must briefly consider before I ^''^^^ ^^£^\, , . inent. Kant s close. The theoretic proofs, as Kant rightly said, can ^n^ statement of it. us no knowledge of God as a moral Being — as a Being who sets before Him moral ends, and governs the world with reference to these ends. For this we are dependent on the Practical Eeason, which shows us not what is, but what ought to he, and is the source of laws of moral conduct which we recognise as of binding force for every rational agent. The way in which Kant works out his argument from this point is one of the most interesting parts of his system. Nature in itself, he thinks, knows nothing of a highest end. This is given only in the Practical Eeason, which sets before us ends of unconditioned worth, and requires us, if our view of the world is to be consistent, to regard these as supreme, i.e. to view the world as a moral system, in which natural 9 130 THE THEISTIC POSTULATE God a pos- tulate of the Practical Reason, ends are everywhere subordinated to moral. But such a moral teleology is only possible if there is one principle of the natural and of the moral order, and if nature is so arranged as to secure a final harmony of natural and moral conditions ; in other words, if the world has a moral as well as an intelligent cause. God, therefore, is a postulate of the Practical Eeason.^ I quote in further illustration of this argument, Professor Caird's fuller statement of it, in his excellent exposition of the Critique of Judgment, in which he follows Kant. " The principle of moral determination in man," he says, " carries with it the idea of a highest end, after which he should strive ; in other words, the idea of a system in which all rational beings realise their happiness tliroiigh their moral perfection, and in proportion to it. But such realisation of happiness through morality, is no natural sequence of effect on cause ; for there is nothing in the con- nection of physical causes that has any relation to such an end. We are forced, therefore, by the same moral necessity which makes us set before us such an end, to postulate outside of nature a cause that determines nature, so as finally to secure this result ; and from this follows necessarily the idea of an all-wise, all-powerful, all-righteous, all-merciful God. We have a ' pure moral need ' for the existence of such a Being ; and our moral needs differ from physical needs in that they have an absolute claim to satisfaction. . . . Furthermore, we are to remember that the principle which leads us to postulate God is a practical principle, which does not give us, strictly speakiug, a knowledge of God, but only of a special relation in which he stands to us and to nature ; while, therefore, in order to find in God the principle which realises the highest good, we are obliged to represent Him as a rational Being, who is guided by the idea of an end, and who uses nature as means to it, we are to remember that 1 Cf. Kritik d. r. Vernunft, pp. 548-557, on " The Ideal of the Highest Good as a Determining Ground of the last end of Pure Reason " (Eng. trans, pp. 487-496) ; and the Kritik d. praktischen Vernunft, Part II. 5— "The Being of God as a Postulate of the Pure Practical Reason." OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW, 131 this conception is based on an imperfect analogy. . . , 'AH that we can say is that, consistently with the nature of our ~ ' intelligence, we cannot make intelligible to ourselves the possibility of such an adaptation of nature to the moral law and its object as is involved in the final end which the moral law commands us to aim at, except by assuming the existence of a Creator and Governor of the world, who is also its moral Legislator.' " ^ It is to this view of God as a postulate of the Practical Moral law, Eeason, and as satisfying a " pure moral need," that the ^.^7^^?'^' Eitschlian theology specially attaches itself ; but it must be ethical ideal, remarked that such an origin of the idea of God, abstracted ^^'"''^'^^'^/'' " an eternal from direct experience of dependence on Him, would furnish ground. no adequate explanation of the religious relation. We may, however, accept all that Kant says of God as a postulate of the moral consciousness, and yet carry the argument a good deal further than he does. God is not only a postulate of the moral nature in the sense that His existence is necessary to secure the final harmony of natural and moral conditions, but it may be held that His existence is implied in the very presence of a morally legislating and commanding Eeason within us, — ^just as an eternal self-conscious Eeason was seen to be implied in the universal and necessary principles of the theoretic consciousness. That moral law which appears in conscience — the " categorical imperative " of duty for which Kant himself has done so much to intensify our reverence — that ideal of unrealised goodness which hovers constantly above us, awakening in us a noble dissatisfaction with all past attainments, — these are not facts which explain them- selves. Nor are they sufficiently explained as products of association and of social convention. Moral law is not com- prehensible except as the expression of a will entitled to impose its commands upon us. The rules and ideals of conduct which conscience reveals to us, and which bind the will with such unconditional authority, point to a deeper ^ Philosophy of Kant, ii. pp. 504, 505. 132 THE THEISTIC POSTULATE source in an eternal moral Reason. The ethical ideal, if its absolute character is to be secured, points back to an eternal ground in the Absolute Being. It takes us back to the same conception of God as the ethically perfect Being, source and ground of moral truth, fountain of moral law, which we found to be implied in Christianity.^ Religious ex- And let me observe, finally, that here also we have more tertencecor- ^j^g^^^ logical argument — we have experience. The moral responding to ^ ^ ^ the moral consciousucss is One of the most powerful direct sources of proof. man's knowledge of God. In the earliest stages in which we know anything about man, a moral element blends with his thought. There grows up within him, — he knows not how, — a sense of right and wrong, of a law making its presence felt in his life, prescribing to him moral duties, and speaking to him with a " thou shalt " and " thou shalt not " in his soul which he dare not disregard. His thoughts, meanwhile, accuse or else excuse each other. This law, moreover, presents itself to him as something more than a mere idea of his own mind. It is a real judging power in his soul, an arbiter invested with legislative, but also with judicial functions. It has accordingly from the first a sacred character. It is a power not himself making for righteous- ness within him. He instinctively connects it with the Power he worships, whose existence is borne in on him from other sources. As conscience develops, his duties come to be more invested with a moral character, and are feared, honoured, or propitiated accordingly. It is the moral con- sciousness particularly which safeguards the personality of God — the Divine tending to sink back into identity with nature in proportion as the ethical idea is obscured. Conclusion, The conclusion we reach from the various arguments and considerations advanced in this Lecture is, that the Christian view of a personal and holy God, as the Author ^ Cf. on the moral argument, Conder's Banis of Faith, pp. 383-431 ; Mar- tineau's Study of Religion, ii. pp. 1-42 ; Kennedy's Natural Theology and Modern Thought, Lecture VI., "Kant and the Moral Proof"; and M 'Cosh's Divine Government, Book i. chap. 3. OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW, 133 of the universe, and its moral Legislator and Euler, is the only one in which the reason and the heart of man can permanently rest. I do not say that reason could have reached the height of the Christian conception for itself; I do not even think it can hold to it unless it accepts the fact of Eevelation and the other truths which Christianity associates with it. But I do say that, with this view as given, reason is able to bring to it abundant corroboration and verification. It is not one line of evidence only which establishes the theistic position, but the concurrent force of many, starting from different and independent standpoints. And the voice of reason is confirmed by the soul's direct experiences in religion. At the very least these considera- tions show — even if the force of demonstration is denied to them — that the Christian view of God is not w^ireasonable ; that it is in accordance with the highest suggestions of reason applied to the facts of existence ; that there is no bar in rational thought or in science to its full acceptance. And this is all that at present we need ask. APPENDIX TO LECTUEE III. GOD AS EELIGIOUS POSTULATE. Godasapos- If wg are to speak of God as a postulate of the soul, we J!T "^^^^ ^^"^^ ^P^^^ ^^ -^^^ ^^ ^ postulate for the wlioU need of the soul — for its religious and its rational, not less than for its moral need. We must speak of Him also in such a way as to show that this postulate is not an arbitrary one, but springs necessarily from the soul's rational and moral con- stitution, and so as to explain the conviction of its truth by which it is accompanied. But this can only be done by showing that there are laws of man's spiritual nature which imperatively demand such and such an object, and by making it clear what these are. In like manner What is I would lay it down as a first principle, as against all demanded in a psychological and empirical theories of religion, which pro- reiigion, posc to account for mcn's religious ideas and beliefs from natural causes (hopes and fears, animism, ghosts, etc.), without raising the question of how far they correspond with any outward reality, that no theory of religion can be adequate which does not cast light on the deepest ground of the soul's movement towards God, and on the nature of the object which alone can adequately satisfy it. This again assumes that there are laws of the spiritual nature which determine beforehand what the character of the object must be which alone can satisfy the religious necessity, and which impel the soul unceasingly to a search after that object. This, however, is precisely what I consider the truth about religion to be, as a survey of its manifestations bersonal^ iemands a bersonal object. GOD AS RELIGIOUS POSTULATE. 135 in history reveals its nature to us. Eeligion is not an arbitrary product of the soul. Even in the lowest and poorest religions, we see something struggling into consciousness, — a want, a desire, a need, — which is not measured by the extent of its actual knowledge of the Divine. Eeligion vfQiDeftnifion of might define from this point of view as the search of thef ^ ^^^'^'^^ soul for an adequate spiritual object to rest in, combined with the consciousness that there is such an object, and with the impulse to seek after it, and when found, to surrender itself to it. Now what kind of object is it which the soul thus demands ? This can only be determined by the study of its laws, as these spring from its essential nature, and are exhibited on the field of historical religion. And here, I think, we are warranted to say — 1. That the soul, as itself personal, demands for the satis- i. The soul, as faction of its religious need, a personal object. From what- ever sources it derives its idea of the Divine (sense of dependence, outward impressions of nature, moral conscious- ness), it invariably personalises it. Over against its I, it seeks a Thou, and will rest satisfied with nothing less. 2. That the soul, as thinking spirit, demands an infinite 2. The soul, object. This is a proposition of some importance, and ^^ ^^y^^J*^s requires more careful consideration. We cannot err in mands an seeking with Hegel the deepest ground of man's capacity for ^^fi^^^^ °^J^^^' religion in his possession of the power of thought. The power of thought is not the whole of religion, but it is that which gives man his capacity for religion. The lower animals are irrational, and they have no religion. Thought, in this connection, may be described as the universalising principle in human nature. It is that which leads us to negate the limits of the finite. It is that which impels man from fact to principle, from law to wider law, from the collection of facts and laws in the universe to the principle on which the whole depends. It is the element of boundlessness in imagination, of illimitableness in desire, of insatiableness in the appetite for knowledge. On the side of religion we see 136 THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. it constantly at work, modifying the idea of the object of religion, and bringing it more into harmony with what it is felt that an object of worship ought to be. One way in which this is done is by the choice of the grander objects of nature — the sky, sun, mountains, etc. — as the embodiments and manifestations of the Divine. Another way is by the mere multiplication of the objects of idolatry — the mind seeking in this way, as it were, to fill up the gap in its depths. Another way is physical magnitude — hugeness. "Nebuchadnezzar the king made an image of gold, whose height was three- score cubits, and the breadth thereof six cubits ; he set it up in the plain of Dura." ^ This love of the colossal is seen in most oriental religions (e.g. Egyptian, Assyrian). Another way is by what Max Miiller calls Henotheism — fixing on one special deity, and treating it for the true being as if it was alone and supreme. Another way is by creating a " system," placing one deity at the head of the Pantheon, and making the rest subordinate. We have examples in the position held by Zeus and Jupiter in the Greek and Eoman religions — a position described by Tiele as one of " Monarchism allied to Monotheism." Another way is by tracing back the origin of the gods, as in Hesiod, to some uncreated principle ; or by placing behind them a fate, necessity, or destiny, which is a higher power than they. Finally, in the philosophical schools, we have reasoned Theism, or Pantheism, or some cosmic theory in which the universe itself becomes God. Through all, the search of the soul for an infinite is clearly discernible. 3. The soul, [ 3. That the soul, as itself ethical, demands an etJdcal as ethical^ I object. It docs this in all the higher forms of religion. demands an' . ethical object. It may be observed that once the idea of an ethical God has been brought home to the mind — no lower conception of the Deity can be accepted. The agnostic himself — strongly as he protests against the knowableness of God — will yet be the first to maintain that it is impossible to 1 Dan. iii. 1. GOD AS RELIGIOUS POSTULATE. 137 entertain, even as hypothesis, any idea of God which repre- sents him as false, cruel, tyrannical, revengeful, unjust. He knows enough about God, at any rate, to be sure that He is not tills, 4. I may add that the soul, as itself an intelligence demands a knowalle object. It has previously been shown that, for purposes of religion, an unknowable God is equivalent to no God at all. Eeligion seeks not only a knowledge of its object, but such a knowledge as can be made the basis of communion. Here, again, we are led by the very idea of religion, to the expectation of Eevelation. [ The bearing of all this on the Christian view is very obvious. It gives us a test of the validity of the Christian view, and it explains to us why this view comes home to the spirit of man with the self-evidencing power that it does. It comes to the spirit as light — attests its truth by its agreement with the laws of the spirit. The worth of this attestation is not weakened by the fact that the Christian religion itself mostly creates the very capacity by which its truth can be perceived — creates the organ for its own verification. It makes larger demands upon the spirit, calls forth higher ideas than any other ; but, in doing so, reveals at the same time the spirit to itself. Brought to the foregoing tests, it discovers to us a God personal, infinite, ethical, and knowable, because self- revealing, and in this way answers the demands of the religious spirit. 4. The souly as intelligence demands a hzowable object. LECTURE IV. Efje Postulate of tlje Cfjrfettan SJieto of tf)e SKorlU in regartf to Nature antJ fSan. "By faith we understand that the worlds have been framed by the word of God, so that what is seen hath not been made out of things which do appear." — Epistle to Hebrews. "Man is neither the master nor the slave of Nature ; he is its inter- preter and living word. Man consummates the universe, and gives a voice to the mute creation." — Ed. Quinet. "He who believes in God must also believe in the continuance of man's life after death. Without this there could be no world which would be conceivable as a purpose of God." — Rothe. " I trust I have not wasted breath ; I think we are not wholly brain. Magnetic mockeries ; not in vain, Like Paul with beasts, I fought with Death ; Not only cunning casts in clay : Let Science prove we are, and then What matters Science unto men, At least to me ? I would not stay." Tennyson. " Does the soul survive the body ? Is there God's self, no or yes ? " R. Browning. LECTURE IV. THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW OF THE WOELD IN EEGAED TO NATURE AND MAN. The Christian doctrine of God as personal, ethical, and self- Second postu- revealing, carries with it a second postulate as to the nature ^j ^f!!^^ of man. The Christian doctrine of God and the Christian vie%v—man doctrine of man are in fact correlatives. For how should ^^"^^ ^^ ^^^^ ii7tage of God. man know that there is a personal, ethical, self-revealing God, — how should he be able to frame the conception of such a Being, or to attach any meaning to the terms employed to express His existence, — unless he were himself rational and moral — a spiritual personality. The two views imply each other, and stand or fall together. We may express this second postulate of the Christian view in the words, Man made in the image of God.^ This truth of a natural kinship between the human spirit The kinship of and the Divine, is at once the oldest declaration in the Bible ^^^^'^ !"'''' tnipltea in about man, and is implied in every doctrine of the Christian every Christ- system. It is implied, as already said, in the knowledge of ^^'^ dodrme. God, and in the call to fellowship with Him in holiness and love. It is implied in the Christian view of sin ; for sin in the Christian view derives its tragic significance from the fact that it is a revolt of the creature will against the Divine will, to which it is by nature bound, that it cuts the soul off from its true life and blessedness in union with God. It is 1 Gen. i. 27. Dorner says truly : "The absolute personality of God, and the infinite value of the personality of man, stand and fall with each other." — Person of Christy v. p. 155. 142 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW implied in regeneration, and in the capacity of the soul to receive the Spirit of God. For the Spirit of God does not enter the soul as something foreign and extraneous to it. He enters it as the principle of its true life. What, on the one side, we call the operations of the Spirit, or the presence of the Spirit in the soul, we call, on the other, the new life itself. The Divine and human here are but one and the same thing on two different sides. It is implied also in the call of man to a Divine sonship. It is the case, no doubt, — and the fact is one to be carefully considered, — that in Christ's teaching God is not called the Father of all men indiscrimin- ately, nor is the title " son of God " given to all men indis- criminately. It is used only of those who are the subjects of spiritual renewal, and who bear in some measure the moral and spiritual likeness of the Father.^ It does not denote a merely natural or physical relationship, but a moral bond as well. Deliberate and hardened transgressors are spoken of, not as children of God, but rather as children of the devil.^ But this is only because these wicked persons have turned their backs on their own true destination. As made by God, and as standing in his normal relation to Him, man is with- out doubt a son. Hence, in the Gospel of Luke, though not by Christ Himself, Adam is called " the son of God," ^ and Paul does not scruple to quote the saying of the heathen poet, " For we also are His offspring." * The fact that the title " son of God " should belong to awy, already implies a natural kinship between God and man, else the higher relationship would not be possible. If there were not already a God- related element in the human spirit, no subsequent act of grace could confer on man this spiritual dignity."^ 1 Matt. V. 9, 45 ; John i. 12, 13. Cf. Schmid's TUol. of the Neio Testament, p. 101 (Eng. trans.). 2 Matt, xxiii. 15 ; John viii. 44. ^ Luke iii. 38. Yet only through the context — 'A^a^, toZ Qiou. * Acts xvii. 28. •^ On the nature of man's sonship, cf. Candlish's Fatherhood of God, and Dr. Crawford's work in reply (same title) ; Bruce's Kingdom of God, chaps, iv. and v. ; Wendt's Die Lehre Jesu, ii., pp. 145-151 ; 453-464. IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN 143 Not only in the Christian view in general, but specially in specially im- the great central doctrine of the Incarnation, is this truth of ^^^^^ ^'^ ^^^^ Incarnatio7i. man made in the image of God seen to be implied. I have already referred to certain services which the German speculative movement in the beginning of the century rendered to Christianity in laying stress on the essential kin- ship which exists between the human spirit and the Divine, a thought never since lost sight of in theology. So long as the world is conceived of in deistic separation from God, it is inevitable that the Divine and the human should be regarded as two opposed essences, between which true union is im- possible. Once this point of view is overcome, and it is seen that the bond between God and man is inner and essential — that there is a God-related element in the human spirit which makes man capable of receiving from the Divine, and of becoming its living image — a great step is taken towards removing objections to the Incarnation. A union between the Divine and human is seen to be possible, to the intimacy of which no limits can be set, — which, indeed, only reaches its perfection when it becomes personal. The Incar- ^ nation has not only this doctrine of man as its presupposition — it is, besides, the highest proof of its truth. Christ, in His own Person, is the demonstration of the truth of the Bible doctrine about man. To get a knowledge of the true essence of anything we do not look at its ruder and less perfect specimens, but at what it is at its best. Christ is the best of humanity. He is not only the Eevelation of God to humanity, but the Eevelation of humanity to itself. In Him we see in perfect form what man in the Divine idea of Him is. We see how man is made in the image of God, and how humanity is constituted the perfect organ for the Eevelation of the Divine. ^ It is evident that in the Christian view the doctrine of The doctrine man links itself very closely with the doctrine of nature — of ^f^^*^^ closely . linked xvith the creation. It is not merely that man is related to nature by doctrine of his body, but he is in Scripture, as in science, the highest «^^«''^- 144 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW basis — the doctrine of creation. being in nature. He is, in some sense, the final cause of nature, the revelation of its purpose, the lord and ruler of nature. Nature exists with supreme reference to him; is governed with a view to his ends ; suffers in his fall ; and is destined to profit by his Eedemption.^ I propose to begin with the natural basis — the doctrine of creation. /. The natural I. The Bible affirms, and perhaps it is the only book that does so, that all things, visible and invisible, have originated from God by a free act of creation.^ The Bible doctrine of creation is something more than the Mosaic cosmogony. For my present purpose it is indifferent how we interpret the first chapter of Genesis — whether as the result of direct Eevelation, or as the expression of certain great religious truths in such forms as the natural knowledge of the age admitted of. I believe myself that the narrative gives evi- dence of its Divine original in its total difference of character from all heathen cosmogonies, but this is a view I need not press.^ The main point is the absolute derivation of all things from God, and on this truth the Scripture as a whole gives no uncertain sound. Discussions have been raised as to the exact force of the Hebrew word (bdrct), used to express the idea of creation,* but even this is of subordinate import- ance in view of the fact, which none will dispute, that the uniform teaching of Scripture is that the universe had its origin, not from the fashioning of pre-existent matter, but directly from the will and word of the Almighty.^ " He spake, and it was done ; He commanded, and it stood fast." ^ Not only is this doctrine of creation fundamental in 1 See pp. 226-229. ^ cjen. i. 1 ; John i. 2 ; Col. i. 16 ; Heb. xi. 3, etc. 3 Note A.— The Creation History. * Cf. Delitzsch's New Commentary on Genesis on chap. 1. 1 (Eng. trans. ) ; and Schultz's AUtestamentlicJie Theologie, pp. 570-571. ^ " Creation out of nothing," says Eothe, " is not found in express words in Holy Scripture. . . . The fact itself, however, is expressed in Scripture quite definitely, since it teaches throughout with all emphasis that, through His word and almighty will alone, God has called into being the world, which be- fore did not exist, and this not merely in respect of its form, but also of its matter." — Dogmatik, i. 133. ^ Ps. xxxiii. 9. Practical significance of this doctrine. IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN 145 Scripture, but it is of great practical significance. It might be thought, of what practical importance is it to us to know- how the world originated ? Is not this a question of purely speculative interest ? But a moment's reflection will con- vince us that it is not so. The vital thing in religion is the relation of dependence. To feel that we and our world, that our human life and all that we are and have, absolutely depend on God, — this is the primary attitude of rehgion. For if they do not thus depend, — if there is anything in the universe which exists out of and independently of God, — then what guarantee have we for the unfailing execution of His purposes, what ground have we for that assured trust in His Providence which Christ inculcates, what security have we that all things will work together for good ? But to affirm that all things depend on God is just in another way to affirm the creation of all things by God. They would not depend on Him if He were not their Creator. They do depend on Him, because they are created by Him. The doctrine of creation, therefore, is not a mere speculation. Only this conviction that it is " the Lord that made heaven and earth " ^ — that " of Him, and through Him, and to Him, are all things " ^ — that He has created all things, and for His pleasure they are and were created,^ — can give us the con- fidence we need in a holy and wise government of the universe, and in a final triumph of good over evil. If the doctrine of creation is the only one which meets The conson- the wants of our religious nature, it may now further be ^^'^^ of this ^ '' ^ doctrine with affirmed that it is a doctrine consonant with reason, and reason : thr consistent with all true knowledge. It is opposed, first, to oppositions. all forms of dualism ; secondly, to a merely logical derivation of the universe ; and thirdly, to the atheistic assertion of the self-subsistence and eternity of the universe. Let us glance briefly at these various oppositions. ce 1 Ps. cxxi. 2. 2 j^ojn. xi. 36. ^ Rev. iv. 11. Revised Version reads: "For Th aud because of Thy will they are and were created." ^ Rev. iv. 11. Revised Version reads: "For Thou didst create all things 10 146 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW I. Theopposi- 1. Partly on metaphysical, partly on moral grounds, some tionof \i ceases to exist, they have perished ; relatively to the thought which, as eternal, holds past, present, and future together, they are permanent ; their very transitoriness is eternal." — Works, iii. p. ]59. ^ Hegel, indeed, says : " Within the range of the finite we can never see that the end or aim has really been secured. The consummation of the infinite aim, therefore, consists merely in removing the illusion which makes it seem yet unaccomplished. ... It is this illusion under which we live. ... In the course of its process the Idea makes itself that illusion, by setting an antithesis to confront it ; and its action consists in getting rid of the illusion which it has created." — Wallace's Logic of Hegel, p. 304. ^ Cf. Veitch's Knoicing and Being, chap. vii. ; Seth's Hegelianism and IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN 155 What other solution, then, is possible ? The solution must (3) Solution lie in getting a proper idea of the relation of eternity to \ hi^adLt-^ time, and this, so far as I can see, has not yet been satis- ment of the factorily accomplished. The nearest analogy I can suggest ^f ^^"''^"^ '^-^ is that of the spiritual thinking principle within ourselves, eternity. which remains a constant factor in all the flux of our thoughts and feelings. It is in the-midst of them, yet it is out of the flux and above them. It is not involved in the succession of time, for it is the principle which itself relates things in the succession of time — for which, therefore, such succession exists. I would only venture to remark, further, that even if the universe were conceived of as originating in an eternal act, it would still, to a mind capable of tracing it back through the various stages of its development, present the aspect of a temporal beginning. Before this beginning, it would be possible for the mind to extend its vision indefinitely backwards through imaginary ages, which yet had no existence save as its own ideal construction. But God's eternity is not to be identified with this thought of an indefinitely extended time. Eternity we may rather take to be an expression for the timeless necessity of God's existence ; and time, properly speaking, begins its course only with the world.^ A few words before leaving this part of the subject on the The motive motive and end of creation. If we reject the idea of meta- ^^^^^"^^f •^ creation : physical necessity, and think of creation as originating in a Kant, Lotze, free, intelligent act, it must, like every similar act, be con- ^^'^^ ceived of as proceeding from a motive, which includes in it at the same time a rational end. And if God is free, personal Spirit, who is at the same time ethical Will, what motive is possible but goodness or love, or what end can be thought of but an ethical one ? In this way it may be held that though the universe is not the product of a logical or metaphysical Personality, pp. 180-184; Pfleiderer, Beligionsphilosophie, iii. pp. 293-295 (Eng. trans.); Lotze, Microcosmus, ii. p. 711 (Eng. trans.) ; and see Note D to Lect. III. 1 See Note E.— Eternity and Time. 156 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW necessity, it arises from the nature of God by a moral neces- sity which is one with the highest freedom, and thus the conception of creation may be secured from arbitrariness. It is an old thought that the motive to the creation of the world was the goodness of the Creator. Plato expresses this idea in his Timmus} and points to a yet more comprehensive view when, in the BepuUic, he names " the Good " as the highest principle both of knowledge and of existence.^ Since the time of Kant, philosophy has dealt in very earnest fashion with this idea of " the Good " — now conceived of as ethical good, but likewise as including in it the highest happiness and blessedness — as at once the moving cause and end of the world. Start from the postulate of Kant, that moral ends are alone of absolute worth, and the inference is irresistible that the world as a whole is constituted for moral ends, and that it has its cause in a Supreme Original Good, which pro- duces the natural for the sake of the moral, and is guiding the universe to a moral goal.^ Hence, from his principles, Kant arrives at the notion of an ethical community or " King- dom of God," having the laws of virtue as its basis and aim, as the end to which creation tends.* Lotze takes up the same thought of a world ordered in conformity with the idea of " the Good," and having its source in a Highest-Good Personal, and from him chiefly it has entered into Eitschlian theology.^ But Christian theology from its own standpoint arrives at a similar result. We have but to ask, with Dorner, What is the relation of the ethical nature of God to the other dis- tinctions we ascribe to Him ? to see that " the non-ethical ^ Timceus, p. 29 — " Let me tell you, then, why the Creator created and made the universe. He was good, and no goodness can ever have any jealousy of anythiug. And being free from jealousy, he desired that all things should be as like Himself as possible." — Jowett's Plato, iii. p. 613. 2 EejmbUc, Bk. vi. ^ See last Lecture, pp. 129-131. "^ In his Religion innerhalh der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft, Bk. iii. Cf. Seth's From Kant to Hegel, pp. 123, 124; Caird's Philosophy of Kant, pp. 611-613. ^ Cf. Microcosmus, ii. p. 723 (Eng. trans.) ; Outlines of Metayhysic, pp. 151, 152 (Eng. trans.). IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN. 157 distinctions in the nature of God are related to the ethical as means to an end; but the absolute end can only lie in morality, for it alone is of absolute worth." ^ In the graduated system of ends of which the universe consists, the moral, in other words, must be presumed to be the highest. And this is precisely what Christianity declares when it teaches that Christ and the kingdom of God are the consummation of God's world- purpose ; that the government of the world is carried on for moral ends ; and that " all things work together for good to them that love God." ^ II. From the point now reached, the transition is easy to //. Nature of the Scripture doctrine of the nature of man, and of his ^''"' '^'''^'^" ... . 1 . -I place in position m creation. I may begin here with man's place in creation : ' creation, which of itself is a testimony which nature bears ^^'^ the final .1 • 1 r. ^ -I . , . . cause of the to the meaning and purpose of God m that creation. Assum- ^orld. ing that final cause is to be traced in the world at all, we can get no better clue to it than by simply observing whither the process of development tends — what, as Mr. Spencer says, is " the naturally revealed end " towards which evolution works.^ Here is a process of development, of evolution, going on for millenniums — what, as a matter of fact, do we find to be the outcome of it ? At the base of the scale is inorganic matter ; then we rise to organic life in the vegetable world ; as a next round in the ladder of ascent we have animal and sentient life ; we rise through all the gradations of that life — through insect, fish, reptile, bird, mammal — till at length, at the close of the long line of evolution, we find — What ? Man, a self-conscious, personal, rational moral being; a being capable of entering not only into moral relations with his fellowmen, but, infinitely higher, into spiritual and moral relations with his invisible Creator. Man's creation, it is true, is only the starting-point of a new line of evolution, but that evolution is one of moral life. So far as the teach- ^ Christian EtJilcs, p. 65 (Eng. trans.). 2 j^oni. viii. 28. ^ Ifata of Ethics, p. 171. 158 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW ing of evolution goes, then, man is the crown and masterpiece of this whole edifice of creation, and this also is the teaching of the Bible. I have been frequently struck with this in reading the works of Mr. Spencer and of other evolutionists, that none of them supposes that evolution is ever to reach a higher being than man ; that whatever future development there is to be will not be development beyond humanity, but development within humanity. In this it is implied that man is the end of nature, and that the end of nature is a moral one. In man, if we may so speak, mute and unin- telligent nature attains to consciousness of itself, gains the power of reading back meaning into its own blind past, and has a prophecy of the goal to which its future tends. At the summit of nature's gradations — of her inorganic kingdom and plant kingdom and animal kingdom — ^there stands a being fitted for the kingdom of God. Agreement of The agreement of Scripture and science up to this point is Scripture and patent and incontestable. In the original picture in Genesis science on this point. we have, as in nature, a gradually ascending series of creations. We have man at the top of the scale ; man as the latest being of all, and distinguished from all by the fact that he alone bears his Creator's image ; man set at the head of the lower orders of creatures, as God's rational vicegerent and representative. Science corroborates all this. It gives to man the same place in the ascending series of creations as Scripture gives him ; declares him to be the last and final product of nature ; links him intimately with the past through his physical organisation, in which the whole of nature, as physiology shows, recapitulates itself ; and at the same time acknowledges that he stands alone, and far removed from the other creatures, in his powers of thought and language, in his capacity for a self-regulated moral life under general rules, in his religious nature, in his capability of progress, and of boundless productivity in arts, sciences, laws, and institutions. Nay, looking at creation as a whole, from the vantage-ground which our present knowledge gives us, we can feel that its IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN 159 plan would have remained incomplete, its pyramid would have lacked a summit, had man not appeared upon the scene. For man not only stands at the head of creation, but, in virtue of his rational nature, he occupies a position in relation to it different from every other. The animal, however high in the scale of development, is a mere creature of nature ; man has a life above nature. He is a being of " large discourse, looking before and after." ^ He is capable of reflection on himself ; on the meaning and causes of things in the world around him ; on the ends of his own existence. He can rise above momentary impulse and passion, and guide his life by general principles of reason, and so is capable of morality. For the same reason he is capable of religion, and shows his superiority over nature through the thoughts he cherishes of God, of infinity, of eternity. Till a mind of this kind appeared, capable of surveying the scene of its existence, of understand- ing the wisdom and beauty displayed in its formations, and of utilising for rational purposes the vast resources laid up in its treasuries, the very existence of such a world as this is remained an inexplicable riddle : an adequate final cause — an end for self — was not to be found in it.^ It would, indeed, be an exaggeration to view creation Necessary solely from the standpoint here taken. The position that ^^'^^^'^^^^" •* . ma7i not man IS tlie final cause or creation must obviously be \i.^^ the sole e7td of with certain qualifications. Were we to attempt to maintain c'^£o,tion. that the world exists solely for man's use and benefit, we would be met by unanswerable objections. Because man is the supreme end of nature, it does not follow that there are not lower ends — the happiness of the sentient creatures, e.g., and many others that we do not know. This world, again, is part of a wider system, and there may be not only lower ends, but wider ends, than those prescribed by man's existence. There is a delight which creative wisdom has in its own productions, which is an end in itself. God saw the works that He had made, and behold they were good ; though ^ Hamlet, act iv. scene 4. ^ g^e Note F. — Man the Head of Creation. i6o THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW not till man appeared upon the scene were they declared " very good." ^ But this in no degree militates against the position that the main use and end of nature is to subserve the purposes of man's existence. Is not this to a thinking mind implied in its very dispositions and arrangements, in its distribution of land and sea, in its river plains and ocean communication, in its supplies of mineral and other wealth stored up in its recesses, in the forces it puts at man's dis- posal for the accomplishment of his purposes, in the very obstacles it interposes in the way of his advancement, stimulating his mental activity, summoning forth his powers to contend with difficulties, and in this way rousing him up to further conquests ? There are yet higher teleological relations which nature sustains to man, on which I cannot now dwell — the part, e.g., which natural conditions play, as in Greece, in the development of the character and spirit of peoples ; the food which the study of nature affords to his intellect ; the beauty which delights, and the sublimity which awes him, both speaking to his spirit of things higher than themselves ; the suggestions it gives of the infinite and eternal, etc. Taking it all in all, we may rest in the view that man, as nature's highest being, is the key to the under- standing of the whole development ; that nature does not exist for its own sake, but supremely for the sake of the moral ; that its chief end is to furnish the means for such a development as we now see in the mental and moral history of mankind.^ Mmi a com- As a compound being, made up of body and of spirit, man pound being— -^ ^j^^ \yi^ which unitcs the natural and the spiritual worlds.^ the link • i i i i • i between the The direct link between man and nature is the body, which natural and the spiritJial: his body the ' ^en. i. 31. ,, ^ , ,_ . I'nk %vith '^ ^^ ^^® teleological relations of nature to man, see Kant, Kritik a. Urtheil- nature Tcroft, sect. 83 — "Of the last end of nature as a teleological system," and sect. 84 — "Of the final end of the existence of a world, i.e. of the creation itself;" and cf. Caird, Philosophy of Kant, ii. pp. 545-557. 2 See this thought worked out in Herder's Ideen zur Phil. d. Gesch. der Mf:nschheit (cf. Book v. 6, quoted in Note F). . IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN. i6i in its erect posture, its highly evolved brain, its developed limbs, and its countenance lifted up to the heavens, bears witness, as already Ovid reminds us,^ to the dignity of the soul within. As Materialism ignores the rights of the spirit, and would reduce thought, feeling, and will, to functions of matter; so an ultra-spirituality is too apt to ignore the rights of the body, and to regard it as a mere accident of man's personality. Materialism quite rightly protests against this one-sidedness ; and the whole tendency of modern inquiry is to draw the two sides of man's nature — the material and the spiritual, the physical and the metaphysical, the physio- logical and the mental — more closely together. The Bible avoids both extremes. Materialism gets all its rights in the Bible doctrine of the body. The abstract spirituality of a Plotinus, or of a hyper-refined idealism, which regards the body as a mere envelope of the soul, dropped off at death without affecting its entirety, is quite foreign to it. I do not dwell on this now, as I shall have occasion to refer to it in the following Lectures. Enough to remark that the Bible history of man's creation ; the remarkable honour it places on the body as God's workmanship and the temple of the Holy Ghost ; its doctrines of sin, with death as the penalty ; of the Incarnation — " forasmuch as the children are partakers of flesh and blood, He also Himself likewise took part of the same " ; ^ of Eedemption, which includes " the Eedemption of the body " ; ^ of the future life in a glorified corporeity — all warn us against an undue depreciation of the body. I go on to remark that if the Bible gives its rightful place The spiritual to the body, much more does it lay stress on the possession '^"^^"''^ j( •^ '' ^ ^ man — dis- by man of a spirit, which is the true seat of his personality, cussion of and the link which unites him with the spiritual world, and Bibhcal tcnns. with God. Psychological questions would be here out of ^ Metamoiyhofies, i. 2 : ' ' Pronaque qunm specteiit animalia cetera terram, Os honiini sublime dedit, coelumque tueri Jussit, et erectos ad sidera tollere vultus." '^ Heb. ii. 14. •'' Rom. viii. 23. 1 62 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW place, and I can only enter into a very brief examination of the Biblical terms used to express the different aspects of man's spiritual nature, relegating the further discussion of these to their proper sphere in Biblical theology or psy- chology.^ I would first remark that the Biblical usage of psychological terms can only be understood if we keep strictly to the Biblical point of view. In the Old Testament, it is the unity of the personality which is the main fact, and not the distinction of an immaterial and a material part, as in our modern usage. NepTiesh or. soul does not in the Old Testament stand opposed to body, but is rather the principle of " life " which manifests itself on the one hand in the cor- poreal functions (" the life is in the blood "^), and on the other in the conscious activities of the mind. The real contrast in the Old Testament is between " flesh " (hasar) and " spirit " (rHach), and the " soul " is the middle term between them, the unity of them.^ This does not mean that " soul " and " spirit " are separable elements in the same way that " soul " and " body " are, but it means that the " soul," as inbreathed by God, is the source or seat of a double life. On the one side, it is the animating principle of the body ; the source of all vital functions. It is its presence in the body which constitutes the latter " flesh," On the other side, it is the principle of self-conscious life. Various names are em- ployed to denote the kinds of these self-conscious activities ; but they may be grouped generally under the name " spirit." More explicitly, all the activities of the " spirit " belong to the " soul " ; but the converse is not true, that all the activities of the "soul" belong to the "spirit." For the vital functions of the body, with the appetites, desires, impulses, ^ Cf. on this subject the works of Delitzsch and Beck on Biblical Psychology ; Oehler and Schultz on Old Testament Theology ; Wendt's Inhalt der Lehre Jesu; Heard on the Tripartite Nature of Man ; Laidlaw's Bible Doctrine of Man ; Dickson's Flesh and Spirit (Baird Lectures), etc. 2 Lev. xvii. 11. ^ Another word for Spirit is N^shdmdh — used twice in Old Testament, once in a noteworthy passage for the principle of self-consciousness (Prov. xx. 27), as in 1 Cor. ii. 11. IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN. 163 etc., which belong to this side of our nature, likewise are traceable to it as their source. It is only the higher activities of the " soul " — those which we still denominate " spiritual " — I speak of general usage, for probably there is no dis- tinction we can make which has not some exception — which are described by the term " spirit." Thus, we read of a spirit of wisdom, of knowledge, of understanding, of an upright spirit, a free spirit, a contrite spirit, etc.^ That the " soul," essentially considered, is also spiritual, is implied in its origin from the Divine Spirit. In the New Testament we have a distinction of " soul " and " body " much more akin to our own, though the influence of Old Testament usage is still very marked. " Soul " ('^v'^rj) still includes a higher and a lower life ; and the higher life is still denoted by the term " spirit " (irvev/jia) ; while the implication of a body is still always conveyed in the term " soul." There is no " soul " which is not intended to animate a " body " ; there are incorporeal spirits (angels, demons), but they are not called by the name " souls." On the other hand, the " soul " is recognised as spiritual in its essence, and in its disembodied state is classed among " spirits," e.g. " the spirits in prison." ^ I need not discuss the cognate terms heart (KapBla), mind (vov<;), understanding (BidvoLo), etc., but content myself with saying that, except in the sense above explained, I do not see how a trichotomous view of man's nature can be maintained. The distinction of " soul " and " spirit " is a distinction within the one indivisible spiritual nature ; and the antithesis " soul " and "body" really covers all the facts of man's personal life. The highest functions of the " spirit " are in the New Testament ascribed also to the " soul " ; ^ and the " soul " in turn is used by Jesus as a name for man's highest imperish- able life. " He that hateth his life (irvxv) in this world shall keep it unto life eternal." * ^ Isa. xi. 2 ; Ps. li. 10-12. Some of the references are to the Divine Spirit, but as the source of spiritual powers in man. ^ 1 Pet. iii. 19. ^ ^_^^ j^^tt. xxii. 27 ; Luke i. 46. ^ John xii. 25. 1 64 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW Man as FroHi this digression, I return to the fact that it is in his bearing the « g^^j » ^^ « spirit " that man peculiarly bears the Divine ima^e of God. i i . image. In a threefold respect is man the personal image of his Maker. 1. iV/> rational 1. He bears first of all the rational image of God. We wiage. have a proof of this in the fact formerly referred to, that man can understand the world God has made. How is science possible, except on the assumption that the reason we find in ourselves is the same in kind as the reason which expresses itself in the universe. The argument is the same as if we were set to translate a book written in a foreign language. The first condition of success in that attempt — the postulate with which we set out — is similarity of intelligence between the man who wrote the book, and ourselves who seek to decipher its meaning. If his reason were of a totally different kind from ours, the attempt to understand him would be hopeless. Precisely the same condition applies to the possibility of our knowledge of the world. Eeason in man and the reason expressed in nature must be the same in kind, or no relation between them could be established. Christian theology expresses this by saying that the world is created by the Logos, a term which means at once reason and word. 2. His moral 2. Man bears God's moral image, nob now in the posses- tmage. g-^^ ^^ actual righteousness, but in the possession of the (i) The power indestructiblc elements of a moral nature. (1) He is a being of mora ^\^ the powcr of moral knowledge ; reason, in other words, is knowledge. ^ & > ' ' the source to him, not only of principles of knowledge but of laws of duty. The idea of the good, and with it the moral "ought" or ethical imperative, is part of his constitution. His moral ideal may vary with the degree of his development and culture ; but, throughout, man is a being who distinguishes good and evil, and who recognises the obligation to obey the good and to eschew the evil. In this he proclaims himself a subject of moral law, and a being with a moral destiny. (2) Thepower (2) He is a free, spiritual cause, i.e. he has moral freedom. of moral j speak again not of man as at present he actually is, with IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN. 165 his freedom sadly impaired through sin, but of man in the constitutive elements of his nature. And as a free, spiritual, self-determining cause, standing at the summit of nature, man is again in a very marked sense the image of his Maker. It is this power of will and self-decision in man which most of all constitutes him a person. Through it he stands out of and above nature's sequences, and can react on and modify them. He is, as some have chosen to regard him, a super- natural cause in the order of nature.^ It is surely of little use to deny the possibility of miracle, when every human volition is a species of miracle — a new, hyperphysical cause interpolated in the chain of physical events, and giving them a new direction. (3) Man is a being with moral affections. (3) The Without these he would not be a true imaj^e of the God who P^^^^^^^^^ ^f . . moral IS love. Summing up these points, we recognise in man a affections. conscience which reveals moral law, a will which can execute moral purposes, and affections which create a capacity for moral love. This relates only to formal attributes ; but it is now to be remarked that the bearing of God's moral image in the full sense implies not only the possession of these attributes, but an actual resemblance to God in character, in holiness and love. In the primeval state — the status in- tcgritatis of the Biblical account ^ — this possession of the image of God by man can only be viewed as potentiality, though a pure potentiality, for the perfected image could not be gained except as the result of self-decision and a long process of development, if even then without the appearance of the second Adam from heaven.^ It is Christ, not the first Adam, who is the ideal here, the model after which we are to be renewed in the image of Him who created us. Only in Christ do we see what a humanity perfectly conformed to the Divine idea of it is. 1 Cf. Bushnell, Nature and Supernatural, pp. 23-25. 2 See next Lecture. 3 This is a view already enunciated with great clearness by Irenneus. Cf. Dorner, Person of Christ, i. pp. 314-316 ; Art. "Irenseus" in Diet, of Christ. Biog. vol. iii. ; and Harnack, Dogmengeschichte, i. p. 499. 1 66 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW 3. His image 3. Man bears the image of God in his deputed sovereignty 7;z sovereignty. ^^^^ ^^ creatures, a sovereignty which naturally belongs to him in virtue of the attributes just enumerated, and of his place at the head of creation already adverted to. To the reality of this sovereignty, all man's conquests over material conditions, his achievements in art and civilisation, his employ- ment of nature's laws and forces for his own ends, his use of the lower creatures for service and food, etc., abundantly testify.^ The potential I might add One other mark of the possession of the Divine infinitude of j^j^gg j^y j^g^j^ likewise involved in his self-conscious person- man s nature <=> ^ ' 1. —a shadow of ality. I refer to what may be called the ^potential infinitude Goers Q^ j^lg nature. It has often been remarked that man could attributes. 11. not even know himself to be finite, if he were not able m thought to transcend the finite, and frame an idea of the Infinite. It is the strange thing about him, yet not strange once we realise what is implied in the possession of a thinking nature, that though finite, hedged round on every side by the limitations of the finite, he yet shows a constant impulse to transcend these limitations, and ally himself with the Infinite. Through this peculiarity of his nature, there is none of God's infinite attributes which does not find a shadow in his soul. How else could Carlyle, e.g., fill his pages with references to the eternities, the immensities, etc., in which man's spirit finds its awful home ? Is a being w^ho can form the idea of eternity not already in affinity with the Eternal, in a sense His image ? Man is not omnipresent, but is there not a shadow of God's omnipresence in those thoughts of his that roam through space, and find a satisfaction in the contemplation of its boundlessness % He is not omniscient, but is not his desire for knowledge insatiable ? The same spurning of bounds, the same illimitableness, is seen in all his desires, aims, ideals, hopes, and aspirations. This shows the folly of the contention that because man is finite, he is cut ^ On the whole subject of the image of God in man, cf. Laidlaw's Bihle. Doctrine, of Man, Lect. III. (Cunningham Lectures). IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN. 167 off from the knowledge of the Infinite. The objection seems to turn on the thought that there is a physical bigness in the idea of infinity which prevents the mind from holding it. It might as well be contended that because the mind is cooped up within the limits of a cranium only a few inches in diameter, it cannot take account of the space occupied, say by the solar system, or of the distance between the earth and the sun ! In thus affirming the spiritual nature and dignity of man, The Christian and a sonship to God founded thereon, it was inevitable that ""^^"^fPP^^^^ ^ itself to the Christian view should meet with keen opposition ixom. Materialism: the modern anti-supernaturalistic tendency, which resrards ^^^^^'^^^^^^^^^ tendency of with extreme disfavour any attempt to lift man out of the modem ranks of nature, and the prevailing bias of which is strongly ^^^^^f^^- towards Materialism. In this spirit Professor Huxley has told us that " anyone who is acquainted with the history of science will admit that its progress has, in all ages, meant, and now more than ever means, the extension of the province of what we call matter and causation, and the concomitant banishment from all regions of human thought of what we call spirit and spontaneity." ^ The materialistic hypothesis has wide currency at the present day, though it is difficult to see how any sober mind, reflecting on the patent difference between mental and physical phenomena could ever suppose that it was adequate, or could imagine that by its aid it had got rid of " spirit." As involving the denial of the existence of a spiritual principle in man, distinct from the body, this hypothesis is manifestly in contradiction with the Biblical doctrine just explained, and on this account claims a brief consideration. The great fact on which every theory of Materialism strikes Materialism is, of course, the fact of consciousness. Life, unattended ^^^\^^ °^^ ^ ^ ' ' ' ^ rock of by sensation, presents a great enough difficulty to the theorist consciousness. who would explain everything on mechanical principles,^ 1 Lay Sermons, "On the Physical Basis of Life," p. 156. 2 Kant has said that the attempt to explain the world on mechanical prin- ciples is wrecked on a caterpillar. 1 68 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW I. Grosser form of Materialism — mind and brain ide7iti- fied {Mole- schotiy Vogt^ etc. ). but when consciousness enters the difficulty is insuperable.^ It is, at the same time, no easy matter to bind down the advocates of the materialistic theory to a clear and con- sistent view. 1. There is the crass, thorough -going Materialism which literally identifies brain with mind, and the movements of the brain with the thoughts and feelings of which we are aware in consciousness. Brain action, on this hypothesis, is thought and feeling. " The brain," says Cabanis, " secretes thought, as the liver secretes bile." This is the crude theory of writers like Moleschott, Yogt, and Biichner, but it is too manifestly absurd — it too palpably ignores the striking differences between mental and physiological facts — to be accepted by more cautious scientists without qualification. Brain movements are but changes of place and relation on the part of material atoms, and, however caused, are never more than motions ; they have nothing of the nature of thought about them. " It is absolutely and for ever incon- ceivable," says the distinguished German physiologist, Du Bois-Eeymond, " that a number of carbon, hydrogen, nitrogen, and oxygen atoms should be otherwise than indifferent to their own positions or motions, past, present, or future. It is utterly inconceivable how consciousness should result from their joint action." ^ There is, accordingly, general agreement among scientific thinkers that the physical changes and the mental phenomena which accompany them are two distinct 1 Du Bois-Reymond, who himself favours Materialism, specifies, in his Die Sleben Weltrdthsel (The Seven Enigmas of the World), seven limits to the materialistic explanation of Nature. These are : 1. The Existence of Matter and Form. 2. The Origin of Motion. 3. The Origin of Life. 4. The Appearance of Design in Nature. 5. The Existence of Consciousness. 6. Intelligent Thought and the Origin of Speech. 7. The Question of Free- Will. See the account of this work in Kennedy's Natural Theology and Modern Thoiujht, from which I take the list (p. 52). Enigmas 1, 2, and 5, Du Bois- Reymond regards as insoluble. ^ Lecture on Die Grenzen des Naturerhennens. Leipsic, 1872. IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN. 169 sets of facts, which require to be carefully kept apart. *' The - - passage from the physics of the brain to the corresponding facts of consciousness/' says Professor Tyndall, "is unthink- able."^ "I know nothing, and never hope to know anything," says Professor Huxley, " of the steps by which the passage from molecular movement to states of consciousness is effected." ^ " The two things are on two utterly different platforms," says Professor Clifford, "the physical facts go aloDg by themselves, and the mental facts go along by them- selves." ^ So far as this goes, it is clearly in favour of spiritualism, and would seem in consistency to require the abandonment of Materialism.* 2. An escape, however, may seem to be afforded from this 2. Newer dilemma by consentinpc to re<2:ard matter as itself but the^^^^^-^ "^ . ° . ° Materialism phenomenal manifestation of some unknown power, as —Monism therefore not the ultimate reality, but only a form or appear- ^^t^^^^ss, ance of it to our senses. This is the view held by Strauss, ' Lange, Haeckel, Spencer, and the scientific professors whose words I have just quoted. "I have always," says Strauss, " tacitly regarded the so loudly proclaimed contrast between Materialism and Idealism (or by whatever terms one may designate the view opposed to the former) as a mere quarrel about words. They have a common foe in the dualism which has pervaded the view of the world (Weltansicht), through the whole Christian era, dividing man into body and soul, his existence into time and eternity, and opposing an '^Fragments of Science, "Scientific Materialism," p. 121. In the sixth edition the words arc — "is inconceivable as a result of mechanics" (vol. ii. p. 87). He goes on to say that could we "see and feel the very molecules of the brain ; were we capable of folloAving all their motions, all their groupings, all their electric discharges . . . the chasm between the two classes of pheno- mena would still remain intellectually impassable." ^Article on "Mr. Darwin's Critics," in Contemporary Review, Nov. 1871, p. 464. Mr. Spencer expresses himself similarly: "Can the oscillation of a molecule," he says, "be represented in consciousness side by side with a nervous shock, and the two be recognised as one ? No effort enables us to assimilate them." — Principles of Psychology, i. sec. 62. ^ "Body and Mind," in Fortnightly Revieio, December 1874. ^ Cf. Herbert's Modern Realism Examined, pp. 89-94 ; Kennedy's Natural Theology and Modern Thought, pp. 64-66. 170 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW eternal Creator to a created and perishable universe." ^ But whatever the change in the theoretic groundwork, this view in practice comes to very much the same thing as the other. It will not be disputed that it does so with Strauss and his Use of German allies, whose Materialism is most pronounced.^ But materia istic ^^^ English savants also, while disclaimino; the name terminology by ° ^ British " materialists," while maintaining in words the distinction saentists. between the two classes of facts (mental and physical), while careful to show that a strict interpretation of the daio. would land us rather in a subjective Idealism than in Materialism,^ none the less proceed constantly upon the hypothesis that mental facts admit of being translated (as they call it) into terms of matter, and that thus only are they capable of being treated by science.* Thus, Professor Huxley speaks of our thoughts as " the expression of mole- cular changes in that matter of life which is the source of our other vital phenomena,"^ of consciousness as " a function of nervous matter, when that matter has attained a certain degree of organisation."^ This is carried out so far as to deny the existence of any freedom in volition, or indeed of any ^ Der alte und der neue Glaube, p. 212. ^ Strauss declares his thorough agreement with Carl Vogt in his denial of any special spiritual principle, p. 210. ^ Thus, e.g., Huxley: "For after all, what do we know of this terrible 'matter,' except as a name for the unknown and hypothetical cause of states of our own consciousness?" ("On the Physical Basis of Life"). . . . "It follows that what I term legitimate Materialism ... is neither more nor less than a shorthand Idealism." — "On Descartes," Lai/ Sermons, pp. 157, 374. On the relation of extreme Materialism to Idealism, cf. Kennedy's Natural Theology, pp. 64-66. ^ That at least this terminology is preferable. Professor Huxley says : "In itself it is of little moment whether we express the phenomenon of matter in terms of spirit, or the phenomenon of spirit in terms of matter. . . . But with a view to the progress of science, the materialistic terminology is in every way to be preferred." — Lay Sermons, " On the Physical Basis of Life," p. 160. ^ Lay Sermons, " On the Physical Basis of Life," p. 152. In the same essay he tells us : "As surely as every future gi-ows out of past and present, so will the physiology of the future extend the realm of matter and law, till it is co- extensive with knowledge, with feeling, and with action." — P. 156. ^Article on "Mr. Darwin's Critics," in Contemporary Review, Nov. 1871, p. 464. In his Lecture on "Descartes," he says: "Thought is as much a function of matter as motion is." — Lay Sermons, p. 371. IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN 171 influence exercised by consciousness at all upon the train of physical events. One advantage of this materialistic-idealistic form of the Ambiguity oj theory is, that it enables the theorist to play fast and loose ^^'^ ^^X/?^ with language in matter and mind, and yet, when called to etc. account, to preserve an appearance of consistency by putting as much or as little meaning into the term '' matter " as he pleases. Professor Tyndall is eloquent on the " opprobrium " which we, in our ignorance, have heaped on matter, in which he prefers to discern " the promise and potency of every form of life." ^ But he has to admit that, before he can do this, he has to make a change in all ordinarily received notions of matter. " Two courses and two only are possible," he says. " Either let us open our doors freely to the con- ception of creative acts or, abandoning them, let us radically change our notions of matter." ^ To which Dr. Martineau very justly replies, " Such extremely clever matter, matter that is up to everything, even to writing Hamlet, and finding out its own evolution, and substituting a moral plebiscite for a Divine government of the world, may fairly be regarded as a little too modest in its disclaimer of the attributes of mind." ^ My chief objection to Dr. Tyndall, however, is that practically he does not change his notion of matter, but ignoring his own admission of the " chasm intellectually impassable " * between the two classes of phenomena, persists in treating mind as if it were capable of being adequately represented by molecular changes of matter, in the ordinary acceptation of the word. Instead, however, of supporting the view that molecular changes and mental functions are convertible terms, science, with its doctrine of the " con- servation of energy," has furnished, as we shall now see, a demonstration of the opposite. There are three points at which, in the light of modern ^ " Belfast Address," Fragments of Science, ii. p. 193. 2 lUd. ii. p. 191. ^ Religion as affected by Modern Materialism, pp. 14, 15. * Fragments of Science, ii. p. 87. 172 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW The material- science and philosophy, the argument for Materialism is seen istic theory utterly to break down. breaks down in three 1. The first is that which I have just alluded to, the im- respects. possibility of accounting for the phenomena of consciousness sistent with ^^ Consistency with the scientific doctrine of the " conserva- ♦* conservation tion of energy." As already remarked, none but the very oj energy. crasscst materialists will maintain that the molecular changes in the brain are themselves the thoughts and feelings which we are aware of in consciousness. What the physicist will say is, that these changes are attended by certain conscious phenomena as their concomitants. You have the motions, and you have the conscious fact — the thought or feeling — alongside of it. This is the way in which the matter is put by writers like Huxley and Tyndall, who frankly confess, as we have seen, the unbridgeable gulf between the two classes of phenomena. But, once this is admitted, the assertion that mental phenomena are products of cerebral changes is seen to come into collision with the scientific law of conservation. If mental phenomena are produced by material causes, it can only be at the expense of some measure of energy. This, indeed, is what is affirmed. Physical energy, it is supposed, is transformed into vital energy, this again into thought and feeling. But this, it can be shown to demonstration, is pre- cisely what does iiot take place. Every scientific man admits that energy in all its active forms is simply some kind of motion ; and that what is called " transformation of energy " (heat into light or electricity, etc.) is merely change from one kind of motion into another. What, then, becomes of the energy which is used when some change takes place in the matter of the brain, accompanied by a fact of sensation ? It is all accounted for in the physical changes. No scientific man will hold that any part of it disappears, passes over into an " unseen universe." With keen enough senses you could track that energy through every one of its changes, and see its results in some physical effect produced. The circuit is closed within the physical. Motions have produced motions, IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN. 173 nothing more, and every particle of energy present at the beginning is accounted for in the physical state of the brain at the end. There has been no withdrawal of any portion of it, even temporarily, to account for the conscious phenomenon.^ This is a new outside fact, lying beyond the circle of the physical changes, a surplusage in the effect, which there is nothing in the expenditure of energy to explain. It is a fact of a new order, quite distinct from physical motions, and apprehended through a distinct faculty, self- consciousness. But apart from the nature of the fact, there is, as I say, no energy available to account for it. What energy there is, is used up in the brain's own motions and changes, and none is left to be carried over for the production of this new conscious phenomenon. If this is true of the simplest fact of consciousness, that of sensation, much more is it true of the higher and complex activities of self-conscious life.2 2. The second point on which Materialism breaks down 2. Contrast is the impossibility of establishincj any relation between the ?, ^^ ^^ ^ . ^ •' T phenomena in two sets of phenomena in respect of the laws of their laws of their succession. The mental facts and the physical facts, we are ^^^'^'^^^^^°^^- told, go along together. But it is not held that there is no relation between them. And the relation is, according to Professor Huxley, that the mental order is wholly determined by the physical order, while, conversely, consciousness is not allowed to exercise the slightest influence on the physical series. ^ "Motion," says Da Bois-Reyraond, *' can only produce motion, or transform itself into potential energy. Potential energy can only produce motion, main- tain statical equilibrium, push, or pull. The sum-total of energy remains constantly the same. More or less than is determined by the law cannot liappen in the material universe ; the mechanical cause extends itself entirely in mechanical operations. Thus the intellectual occurrences which accompany the material occurrences in the brain are without an adequate cause as contem- plated by our understanding. They stand outside the law of causality, and therefore are as incomprehensible as a mobile perpetuum would be." — Ueber die Gi-enzen des NaturerJcennens, p. 28 (in Kennedy's Natural Theology, p. 48). 2 On this argument, see Herbert's Modern Realism Examined, pp. 43, 57 ; Kennedy's Natural Theology and Modern Thought, pp. 48, 49, 79, 80 ; Harris's Philosophical Basis of Theism, pp. 439-442. 174 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW Consciousness he thinks, in men as in brutes, to be " related to the mechanism of their body simply as a collateral product of its working, and to be as completely without any power of modifying that working as the steam-whistle which accom- panies the work of a locomotive engine is without influence upon its machinery." ^ The physical changes, in other words, would go on precisely as they do, in obedience to their own laws, were there no such thing as consciousness in existence ; and consciousness is simply a bye-product or reflex of them without any counter - influence. Similarly, Mr. Spencer says, " Impossible as it is to get immediate proof that feeling and nervous action are the outer and inner faces of the same change, yet the hypothesis that they are so har- monises with all the observed facts " ; ^ and again, " While the nature of that which is manifested under either form proves to be inscrutable, the order of its manifestations throughout all mental phenomena proves to be the same as the order of its manifestations throughout all material phenomena." ^ The one point clear in these statements is that in the materialistic hypothesis the order of mental phenomena is identical with an order of physical phenomena, determined by purely mechanical conditions.* Is this according to fact, or is it not precisely the point where a materialistic explanation of mind must for ever break down ? On the hypothesis, the one set of phenomena follow purely physical (mechanical, chemical, vital) laws ; but the other set, or a large part of the other set (the mental), follow laws of rational or logical connection. Suppose a mind, for example, following out the train of reasoning in one of the propositions in Euclid — or, better still, think of this demonstration as it was first wrought out in ^ "The Hypothesis that Animals are Automata," in Fortnightly Review, Nov. 1874, pp. 575-576. This "steam-whistle" illustration fails, as his critics all point out, in the essential respect that a steam -whistle does subtract a portion of the energy available for working the machinery, while the production of a conscious phenomenon does not. Cf. Herbert, pp. 46, 47 ; Kennedy, p. 79, etc. - Principles of Psychology, i. sec, 51. '^ Ibid. i. sec. 273. * See Note G. — Mind and Mechanical Causation. IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN 175 the discoverer's own mind. What is the order of connection here ? Is it not one in which every step is determined by the perception of its logical and rationally necessary connec- tion with the step that went before ? Turn now to the other series. The laws which operate in the molecular changes in the brain are purely physical — mechanical, chemical, vital. They are physical causes, operating to produce physical effects, without any reference to consciousness. What pos- sible connection can there be between two orders so distinct, between an order determined solely by the physical laws, and the foregoing process of rational demonstration ? The two orders are, on the face of them, distinct and separate ; and not the least light is cast by the one on the other. To suppose that the physical laws are so adjusted as to turn out a product exactly parallel to the steps of a rational demon- stration in consciousness, is an assumption of design so stupendous that it would cast all other proof of teleology into the shade. I am far, however, from admitting that, as the materialistic hypothesis supposes, every change in the brain is determined solely by mechanical, chemical, and vital laws. Granting that cerebral changes accompany thought, I believe, if we could see into the heart of the process, it would be found that the changes are determined quite as much by mental causes as by material. I do not believe, for example, that an act of will is wholly without influence on the material sequence. Our mental acts, indeed, neither add to nor take from the energy stored up in the brain, but they may have much to do with the direction and distribution of that energy.^ 3. A third point on which the materialistic hypothesis 3. irrecon- breaks down is its irreconcilability with what is seen to be ^^^^^^^^^y '^^^^ self-conscioiis- implied in self-consciousness, and with the fact of vnoYdX ness and moral freedom. To constitute self-consciousness it is not enough Z''^^^^''^- that there should be a stream or succession of separate impressions, feelings, or sensations ; it is necessary that there ^ See Note H. — Mind and Cerebral Activity. 176 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW should be a principle which apprehends these impressions, and relates them (as resembling, different, co-existent, succes- sive, etc.) to one another and to itself, a principle which not only remains one and the same throughout the changes but is conscious of its self-identity through them. It is not merely the mental changes that need to be explained, but the consciousness of a persistent self amidst these changes. And this ego or self in consciousness is no hyperphysical figment which admits of being explained away as subjective illusion. It is only through such a persistent, identical self, that knowledge or thought is possible to us ; it is implied in the simplest analysis of an act of knowledge. Were we simply part of the stream we could never know it.^ As another fact of our conscious life incompatible with subjec- tion to mechanical conditions, I need only refer to the con- sciousness of moral freedom. In principle. Materialism is the denial of moral freedom, or of freedom of any kind, and with its triumph moral life would disappear.^ Ultimate These considerations are sufficient of themselves to refute refutation of Materialism, but the final refutation is that which is given by Materialism— ' , , ., , • , i • n i i • « i i matter itself the general philosophical analysis oi the relation of thought needs thought to existence, a subject on which I do not enter further than to explain it. i i i • i • t mi i t I have already done m the previous Lecture. Thought, as 1 tried to show there, is itself the 'prius of all things ; and in attempting to explain thought out of matter, we are trying to account for it by that which itself requires thought for its explanation. Matter, which seems to some the simplest of all conceptions to work with, is really one of the most difficult ; and the deeper its nature is probed, whether on the ^ Cf. Green's Prolegomena to Ethics, Book i. ; Lotze's Microcosnms, pp. 157, 163 ; cf. Seth's Hegelianism and Personality, pp. 3-5. Lotze puts the point thus : "Our belief in the soul's unity rests not on our appearing to ourselves such a unity, but on our being able to appear to ourselves at all. . . . What a being appears to itself to be is not the important point ; if it can appear anyhow to itself, or other things to it, it must be capable of unifying manifold pheno- mena in an absolute indivisibility of its nature." — Microcosmus, p. 157. ^ Cf. Ebrard's Christian Apologetics, ii. pp. 77-98 ; Dorncr's Christian Ethics, pp. 105-106 ; Kennedy's Natural Theology, Lecture V. IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN, 177 physical or on the metaphysical side, the more does it tend to disappear into something different from itself ; the more, at any rate, is it seen to need for its explanation facts that are spiritual. It was remarked above how, even in the hands of Professors Huxley and Tyndall, matter tends to disappear in a subjective Idealism ; the only escape from this is a rational theory of knowledge, which again explains the con- stitution of the world through rational categories. To explain thought out of matter is, from a philosophical point of view, the crowning instance of a hysteroii proteron.^ III. From the distinction thus shown to exist between ///. A/an, as the spiritual and the material parts of man's nature, there "^^^^ "^ ^^^ iJ7iage of God, results the possibility of the soul surviving death, and the constituted for foundation is laid for the doctrine of Immortality. The ^''^mortaiity; . •! T 1 1 • Biblical aspect consideration of the Biblical aspect of this subject will "^^"i^^^ postponed. properly be reserved for next Lecture, where I treat of the Voice of nature connection of sin and death. Here I will only ask how far nature and reason have a voice to utter on these two ques- tions : Is man constituted for immortality ? And is there a presumption that the soul will survive death ? These ques- tions, it ought to be observed, are not identical. The pro- position that man, as a being made in God's image, is naturally destined for immortality, is not immediately convertible with the other, the soul will survive death ; for it is no part of the Biblical view, as we shall see afterwards, that death is a natural condition of man. Now, however, that death has super- vened, the question arises. Does the soul still survive ? To this question also, as I hope to show, both Old and New Testaments give an affirmative answer ; but the complete Scripture doc- trine of immortality means a great deal more than this. It is a significant circumstance that the modern unbeliev- Modem insj view of the world has no hope to give us of a life ^J^^^^^'^ ^f ^ . doctrine of a beyond the grave. With the obscuration of the idea of Q^q^, future life. and the loss of the sense of the spiritual, there has gone ^ Cf. Caird's Philosojphy of Religion, pp. 94-101. 12 178 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIE W also faith in immortality.^ Materialism, of course, is bound to deny a future life. The theories of Huxley, Tyndall, and Spencer hold out just as little hope of it,^ though Mr. Fiske, developing a Theism out of the principles of Mr. Spencer, has developed also a doctrine of immortality, another evidence of the connection of these two beliefs.^ The hope proposed to us in lieu of individual immortality is that of " corporate immortality," the privilege of joining the " choir invisible" of those who have laboured in the service of humanity, though they live now only in the grateful memory of posterity.* Pantheism, likewise, forbids the thought of personal immortality, exalting instead the blessedness of absorption in the Infinite.^ We cannot, however, part with 1 Renan has said : " No one in business would risk a hundred francs with the prospect of gaining a million, on such a probability as that of the future life." — Dialogues, p. 31. Cf. Strauss, Der alte und der neue Glaube, pp. 123-134. *' In fact," he says, "this supposition is the most gigantic assumption that can be thought of ; and if we ask after its foundation, we meet with nothing but a Avish. Man would fain not perish when he dies ; therefore he believes he will not perish."— Pp. 126, 127. 2 The contrast is again marked with the attitude of the last century " Natural Religion," which regarded the "immortality of the soul" as one of its most certain articles. How little assurance even Theism, apart from Revelation, can give on this subject is seen in Mr. Greg's statements in Creed of Christendom^ chap, xvii.; and Preface to his Enigmas of Life. 3 Fiske's Man's Destiny. Dr. Martineau tells the story that on a report of the arguments of this book being read to an English friend, a Positivist, on its first appearance, his exclamation was : "What? John Fiske say that? Well ; it only proves, what I have always maintained, that you cannot make the slightest concession to metaphysics, without ending in a theology ! " — Preface to Study of Beligion. * "0 may I join the choir invisible Of those immortal dead who live again In minds made better by their presence. . . . This is life to come, Which martyred men have made more glorious For us to strive to follow." George Eliot, Juhal, and other Poems, pp. 301-303. ^ Thus in the Indian systems, but also in modern times. Spinoza's Pan- theism has no room in it for personal immortality. In Hegel's system the question was left in the same ambiguity as the question of the Divine person- ality (cf. Stirling's Secret of Hegel, ii. pp. 678-580 ; Seth's Hegelianism and Personality, pp. 149, 150). On Schleiermacher's views, see Note I. — "Schleier- macher and Immortality." IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN 179 the hope of immortality without infinitely lowering the - - whole pulse and worth even of present existence.^ The only scientific plea on which the possibility of im- Scientific plea mortality can be denied to us is based on the fact that-^^^^^'^"-^^^^^^" Hon — its mind in this life is so intimately bound up with physio- untmabieness. logical conditions. Once grant, however, that the thinking principle in man is distinct from the brain which it uses as its instrument, and no reason can be shown, as Bishop Butler demonstrated long ago, why it should not survive the shock of the dissolution we call death. Death need not even be the suspension of its powers. " Suppose," says Cicero, " a person to have been educated from his infancy in a chamber where he enjoyed no opportunity of seeing external objects but through a small chink in the window shutter, would he not be apt to consider this chink as essential to his vision ? and would it not be difficult to persuade him that his pros- pects would be enlarged by demolishing the walls of his prison ? " ^ It may turn out, as Butler says, that existing and bodily conditions are rather restraints on mind than laws of its essential nature.^ Even so rigid a critic of evidence as the late J. S. Mill admits that this argument against immor- tality from the present dependence of thought and feeling on some action of the bodily organism, is invalid. " There is, therefore," he says, " in science, no evidence against the immortality of the soul, but that negative evidence which consists in the absence of evidence in its favour. And even the negative evidence is not so strong as negative evidence often is. " * It may, at the same time, be questioned, as w^e have seen, whether there are not limits to the extent to which science has demonstrated the dependence of the higher mental operations on cerebral changes.^ 1 Cf. p. 188. 2 Quoted by Dugald Stewart, Active and Moral Powers^ i. p. 72 (Collected Works). Cf. Tusculan Disputations, Book i. 20. ^ Ajialogy, i. chap. 1. ^ Three Essays, p. 201. ^ See Professor Calderwood's views in Note H. i8o THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW Disposition on Science, therefore, cannot negative the idea of immortality, part of -^^^ j^^g reason no positive utterance to ^\nq on this great believers in ^ . Revelation to and solemn question of future existence ? It is not men of viinimise the gcje^cg only, but some believers in Eevelation also, who show natural evidence for ^ disposition to minimise the indications and corroborations immortality, which nature affords of man's immortal destiny. Mr. Edward White does this in support of his theory of conditional im- mortality ; ^ but many others also have held the opinion that this is a question on which reason has little or nothing to say, and which must be determined solely by the light of If man con- Eevelation. This position seems to me a hazardous one for stitute for ^ believer in Eevelation to take up. Just as in speaking of tvimortality^ ^ . . the fact must Theism I ventured to say that, if God exists, it is inconceiv- show Itself in ^^^ ^^^ nature should afford no evidence of His existence ; ^ his 7iature and capacities, SO I would Say here that if liuman immortality be a truth, it is impossible that it should be only, or merely, a truth of Eevelation. If, as he came from his Creator's hand, it was man's destiny to be immortal, his fitness and capacity for that destiny must reveal itself in the very make and con- stitution of his being, in the powers and capabilities that belong to him. If it could really be shown that in man's nature, as we find it, no trace of anything exists pointing to a higher sphere of existence than earth affords, no powers or capabilities for which this earthly scene did not offer full employment or satisfaction, this alone, without any other argument, would be a cogent disproof of immortality. For the same reason, immortality cannot be viewed, as in Mr. White's theory, as a mere external addition to a nature regarded as having originally no capacity or destination for it, a donum siiperadditum. It is impossible that a being should be capable of receiving the gift of immortality, who yet in the make and constitution of his nature gives no evidence that he was destined for immortality. Otherwise immortality loses all moral significance, and sinks to the level of a mere prolongation of existence, just as the life of the 1 In his Life in Christ. 2 L^ct. III. p. 98. IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN i8i brute might be prolonged. Such evidence, if it exists, may - - not be sufficient to demonstrate man's immortality, but it will show that the make and constitution of his nature points in that direction, that immortality is the natural solution of the enigmas of his being, that without immortality he would be a riddle and contradiction to himself and an anomaly in the w^orld which he inhabits. And are there not such proofs ? 1. Our minds are arrested here, first, by the fact that i. Universal nearly every tribe and people on the face of the earth, savage P^^f^J^/^'^^ of and civilised, Aas lield in sorae form this belief in a future state futtn-e state : of existence. This suggests that the belief is one which accords ^P^^(^^'>'''^ •IIP PI 1-Ti -I- theory of this ; With the facts of human nature, and to which the mind is n^ insiM- naturally led in its inquiries. Assume the doctrine to be "^«o'- false, there is still this fact to be accounted for — that nearly all tribes and families of mankind have gone on dreaming this strange dream of a life beyond the grave.^ Mr. Spencer, of course, has a way of explaining this belief which would rob it of all its worth as evidence. The hypothesis is a very simple one. Belief in a future state, according to it, is simply a relic of superstition. It had its origin in the fancies of the savage who, from the wanderings of his mind in sleep, and supposed appearances of the dead, aided by such facts as the reflection of his image on the water and the appearance of his shadow, imagined the existence of a soul, or double, separable from the body, and capable of surviving death.2 Were I discussing this theory at length, I would like to put in a word for Mr. Spencer's savage. I would like to ask, first, Is Mr. Spencer so sure that this is the whole explanation of that singularly persistent instinct which leads even savage minds to cling so tenaciously to the idea of a future life ? May 1 Cicero urges the argument in The Tusculan Disputations, Book i. 13. For modern illustrations cf. Max Miiller's Anthropological Religion, Lecture V. ; Dawson's Fossil Men and their Modern Representatives, chap. X., etc. ^ Eccles. Institutions, chaps, i., xvi. : Strauss has a similar theory, Der alte und der neue Glaube, p. 124. . i82 THE POSTULATE OE THE CHRISTIAN VIEW it not be, though a philosopher may not care to take account of them, •* That even in savage bosoms, There are longings, yearnings, strivings, For the good they comprehend not," and that, sometimes at least, *' The feeble hands and helpless, Groping blindly in the darkness, Touch God's right hand in that darkness, And are lifted up and strengthened ? " ^ And I would like, second, to ask. Is the savage after all so illogical as Mr. Spencer would make him out to be ? Allow that he has crude notions of apparitions and dreams, this is not the essential point. The essential point is that, from the activity of his mind in thinking and dreaming, he infers the working of a power within him distinct from his body. Is he so far wrong in this ? I do not think we do justice always to the workings of the savage mind.^ The savage knows, to begin with, that there is a something written within him which thinks, feels, acts, and remembers. He does not need to wait on dreams to give him that knowledge.^ The step is natural to distinguish this thinking something from his hands and head and body, which remain after its departure.* Going further, he peoples nature with spiritual agents after the type of the mind he finds within himself. Here, there- fore, we have the clear yet not reasoned out distinction between body and spirit, and this, in connection with other hopes, instincts, and aspirations, readily gives birth to ideas ^ Longfellow's Hiawatha, Introduction. 2 Max Miiller says : ' * We cannot protest too strongly against what used to be a very general habit among anthropologists, namely, to charge primitive man with all kinds of stupidities in his early views about the soul, whether in this life or the next." — Anthropological Religion, p. 218. ^ Cf. Max Mliller's discussion of the "shadow" and "dream" theory in Anthropological Religion, pp. 218-226. "Before primitive man could bring himself to imagine that his soul was like a dream, or like an apparition, it is clear that he must already have framed to himself some name or concept of soul."— P. 221. ^ Cf. Max Muller, Anthropological Religion, pp. 195, 281, 337-338. " It was a perfectly simple process : what may almost be called ^ mere process of sub- IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN, 183 of future continued existence. But, however it may be with the savage, how absurd it is for Mr. Spencer to assume that the mature and thinking portion of mankind have no better foundation for their belief than is implied in these vulgar superstitions which he names ! You sit at the feet of a Plato, and see his keen intellect applied to this subject ; you listen to the eloquence of a Cicero discoursing on it;^ you are lifted up by the grand strains of the poets of immortality. You really thought that it was proof of the greater mental stature and calibre of these men that they speculated on such themes at all, and expressed themselves so nobly in regard to them. But it turns out you are mistaken. You and they have miserably deceived yourselves ; and what seemed to you rational and ennobling belief is but the survival of supersti- tions, born of the dreams and ghost fancies of the untutored savage ! 2. But let us leave the savage, and look at this subject in 2. Rational the light of the higher considerations which have in all f f^"^f .->^'"' ^ ^ ^ ^ this belief: ages appealed with special force to the minds of rational nature of men. I pass by here the metaphysical arguments, which at ^^^^'^^^^^• most are better fitted to remove bars to the acceptance of the doctrine than to furnish positive proofs of it. The real proofs are those which, as already said, show that the make and constitution of man's nature are not explicable on the hypothesis that he is destined only for a few short years of life on earth, but are such as point to a nobler and endur- ing state of existence. It is an interesting circumstance traction. There was man, a living body, acting, feeling, perceiving, thinking, and speaking. Suddenly, after receiving one blow with a club, that living body collapses, dies, putrefies, falls to dust. The body, therefore, is seen to be destroyed. But there is nothing to prove that the agent within that body, who felt, who perceived, who thought and spoke, had likewise been destroyed, had died, putrefied, and fallen to dust. Hence the very natural conclusion that, though that agent had separated, it continued to exist somewhere, even though there was no evidence to show how it existed and wlitre it existed." — P. 281. See also Mr. Greg, Preface to Enigmas of Life, p. 7 ; and Fairbairn's Studies in Philosophy of Religion, pp. 115 ff. 1 Plato's Phcedo, Cicero's Tmculan Disputations and Dream of Scipio, etc» Cf. Max Mliller on Anthropological Religion, Lecture XL 1 84 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW his present scene of existence. that Mr. J. S. Mill, who, in his treatment of this question, took evident delight in reducing the logical evidence to its minimum, yet practically brings all those arguments which he had thrust out by the door of the head back by the door of the heart, and uses them to found the duty of cherishing this hope of a future life> What are these indications which point to a fitness for, and are a prophecy of, immortality in man ? (I) The scale of (1) There is the fad that the scale of man's nature is too man's nature , n i • , j> • , ti i -^ ^ too zreat for ^^W^ f^'^ ^^^ present scene of existence. I have already spoken of that shadow of infinitude in man which manifests itself in all his thoughts, his imaginations, his desires, etc. Look, first, at his rational constitution. In the ascent of the mountain of knowledge is man ever satisfied ? Does not every new height he reaches but reveal a higher height ? Does not every new attainment but whet his appetite to attain more ? Is any thirst more insatiable than the thirst for knowledge ? Is it not the last confession of ripened wisdom that man as yet knows nothing as he would wish to know ? Or look at the ideas which man's mind is capable of containing. His mind spans the physical universe, and ever as the telescope expands the horizon of knowledge, it reaches out in desire for a further flight. But there are greater ideas than even those of worlds and systems. His mind can take in the thought of God, of eternity, of infinity. Is this like the endowment of a creature destined only for threescore years and ten ? The same illimitableness attaches to imagination. " The use of this feigned history," says Lord Bacon, speaking of poetry, "is to give some shadow of satisfaction to the mind of man on those points wherein the nature of things doth deny it, the world being in pro- portion inferior to the soul; by reason whereof there is, agreeable to the spirit of man, a more ample greatness, a more exact goodness, and a more absolute variety than can be found 1 In below. the Essay on " Theism," in Three Essays on Religion. See IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN. 185 in the nature of things." ^ Finally, there is desire. Give a man all of the world he asks for, and he is yet unsatisfied. " I cannot chain my soul ; it will not rest In its clay prison, this most narrow sphere. It has strange powers, and feelings, and desires Which I cannot account for nor explain, But which I stifle not, being bound to tinist All feelings equally, to hear all sides. Yet I cannot indulge them, and they live, Referring to some state of life unknown." ^ This argument is not met by saying, as Mill does, that there are many things we desire which we never get. This may be true, but the point is that even if we did get all the satisfaction which the earth could give us, our desires would still go beyond that earthly bound.^ " And thus I know the earth is not my sphere. For I cannot so narrow me, but that I still exceed it.""* The argument is further strengthened by comparing man with the other creatures that tenant the earth. Modern science justly lays stress on the constant relation subsisting between creatures and their environment. Throughout nature you find the most careful adjustment of faculty to environ- ment. If there is a fin, there is water ; if there is an eye, there is light ; if there is a wing, there is air to cleave, etc. But here is a creature whose powers, whose capabilities, whose desires, stretch far beyond the terrestrial scene that would contain him ! Must we not put him in a different category ? 1 Adv. of Learning, Book ii. 13. ^ R. Browning, Pauline. [The text is somewhat altered in 1889 edition. Works, i. p. 27.] ^ "Man," says Kant, '* is not so constituted as to rest and be satisfied in any possession or enjoyment whatsoever." — Kritik d. Urtheilskraft, p. 281 (Erd- mann's ed.). * Browning, Paidine, as revised : "How should this earth's life prove my only sphere? Can I so narrow sense but that in life Soul still exceeds it?" Works, i. p. 29. 9 1 86 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW (2) Immortal- ity involved in the view of life as moral dis- cipline. (3) Immor- tality the solution of the enigmas of life; its in completeness, inequities, etc, (2) The same inference which follows from the scale of man's endowments results if we consider life from the f)oint of view of moral discipline. Everything which strengthens our view^ of the world as a scene of moral government ; everything which leads us to put a high value on character, and to believe that the Creator's main end in His dealings with man is to purify and develop character, strengthens also our belief in immortality. The only way we can conceive of the relation of nature to man, so as to put a rational meaning into it, is, as Kant has shown, to represent it to ourselves as a means to the end of his culture and morality.^ Can we believe, then, that God will spend a lifetime in perfecting a character, developing and purifying it, as great souls always are developed, by sharp trial and discipline, till its very best has been evoked, only in the end to dash it again into nothingness ? What would we think of an earthly artist who dealt thus with his works, spending a lifetime, e.g., on a block of marble, evolving from it a statue of faultless pro- portions and classic grace, only in the end, just when his chisel was putting its last finishing touches on it, to seize his mallet and dash it again to pieces. It would stumble our faith in God — in the " Divine reasonableness " ^ — to believe that such could be his action. (3) A third consideration which points in the same direction is that frequently insisted on — the manifest incom- pleteness of the present scene of things, both as respects ' human character and work, and as respects the Divine administration. Here, again, everything that strengthens our faith in a moral government of the world, that impresses us wdth the infinite worth of human personality, that intensifies our sense of justice and injustice, forces on us the conviction ^ Cf. Kant on "The last end of nature as a teleological system," Kritik d. Urtheihhraft, pp. 280-285 ; and Caird, Philosophy of Kant, ii. p. 501. 2 **For my part," says Mr. Fiske, ** I believe in the immortality of the soul, not in the sense in which I accept the demonstrable truths of science, but as a supreme act of faith in the reasonableness of God's work." — Man's Destiny, p. 116. IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN. 187 that the present life, with its abounding anomalies, imperfec- tions, and inequities, is not God's last word to us ; ^ that there is another chapter to our existence than that which closes on earth. Here comes in the consideration which Kant urges of the need of prolonged existence to complete the fulfilment of our moral destiny ; ^ the sense of accountability which we all carry with us, instinctively anticipating a day of final reckoning ; the feeling of an unredressed balance of wrong in the arrangements of life and of society ; above all, the sense of incompleteness which so often oppresses us when we see the wise and good cut down in the midst of their labours, and their life-work left unfinished. These are the " enigmas of life " for which it is difficult to see how any solution is provided if there is not a future state in which life's mysteries shall be made clear, its unredressed wrongs rectified, the righteousness of the good vindicated, and a completion granted to noble lives, broken off prematurely here. Our faith in God leads us again to trust Him, that " He that hath begun a good work " ^ in us will not leave it unfinished. (4) Finally, there is the fact which all history verifies, (4) Only that only under the influence of this hope do tlie tiuman "'^'^'^^ *^^ influence of faculties, even here, find their largest scope and play. This this hope do was the consideration which, more than any other, weighed ^^^'^ human faculties find their highest •^ "There is no reconciling wisdom with a world distraught, scope and play Goodness with triumphant evil, power with failure in the aim, t ^ ^^7/ If — (to my own sense, remember ! though none other feel the same !) — If you bar me from assuming earth to be a pupil's place. And life, time, — with all their chances, changes, — just probation-space, Mine, for me ! " Browning, La Saisiaz, "Works, xiv. p. 178. ^ It should be noticed that as Kant grants a "doctrinal faith" in the existence of God, as distinguished from theoretical demonstration on the one hand, and the moral proof on the other (see Note F to Lecture III.), so he admits also a "doctrinal faith" in immortality. "In view of the Divine wisdom," he says, "and having respect to the splendid endowment of human nature, and to the shortness of life, so inadequate for its development, we can find an equally satisfactory ground for a doctrinal faith in the future life of the human soul."— Kriiik d. r. Vernunft, p. 661 (Eng. trans, pp. 590-591). 3 Phil. i. 6. 1 88 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW with the late J. S. Mill, in inclining him to admit the hope of immortality. " The beneficial influence of such a hope," he says, in words well worth quoting, " is far from trifling. It makes life and human nature a far greater thing to the feelings, and gives greater strength as well as greater solemnity to all the sentiments which are awakened in us by our fellow-creatures, and by mankind at large.^ It allays the sense of that irony of nature which is so painfully felt when we see the exertions and sacrifices of a life culminating in the formation of a wise and noble mind, only to disappear from the world when the time has just arrived at which the world seems about to begin reaping the benefit of it. . . . But the benefit consists less in the presence of any specific hope than in the enlargement of the general scale of the feelings ; the loftier aspirations being no longer kept down by a sense of the insignificance of human life — by the dis- astrous feeling of ' not worth while.' " ^ The evolutionist, it seems to me, should, beyond all others, respect these voices of the soul, this natural and unforced testimony of our nature to a life beyond, which does not disappear (as it would do were Mr. Spencer's hypothesis correct), but only grows clearer and more solemn, as the history of humanity advances. Conclusion. I think, then, we may conclude that reason does create a presumption, and that a very strong one, in favour of a future life. The considerations we have urged prove the ^ Cf. Uhlhorn in his Christian Charity in the Ancient Church. "There is an idea," he says, "which has been again met with in our own day, that men, when they first clearly come to believe that human life finds its end in tliis life alone, would be on that account the more ready to help one another, so that at least life here below might be made as pleasant to all as possible, and kept free from evil. But, in truth, the opposite is the case. If the individual man is only a passing shadow, without any everlasting significance, then reflection quickly makes us decide : Since it is of no importance w^hether he exist or not, why should I deprive myself of anything to give it to him ? ... It was only when through Christianity it was for the first time made known that every human soul possessed an infinite value, that each individual existence is of much more worth than the whole world, — it was only then that room was found for the growth of a genuine charity." — Pp. 33, 34 (Eng. trans.). ^ 2'hree Essays, p. 249. IN REGARD TO NATURE AND MAN 189 possibility of immortality, and show that the soul of man is naturally fitted for immortality. We need not claim that they do more, though they have proved sufficient to inspire many of the noblest minds of our race, even apart from the gospel, with a very steady persuasion that there is a life hereafter. They cannot give absolute certainty. They may not be able, apart from the light of Eevelation, to lift the mind wholly above the suspicion that the law of waste and destruction which prevails here against the body may somewhere else, and finally, prevail against the soul. But, so far as they go, they must be accepted as a powerful corro- boration and confirmation, from the side of nature, of the Christian view. LECTURE V. Eljt ^Postulate of tJ)e Cfiristian Uteto in regartr to tlje &in antr ©tsortfer of tfje aEorltr. "Therefore, as through one man sin entered into the world, and death through sin ; and so death passed unto all men, for that all have sinned." — Paul. "This is a wonder to which the worshippers of reason have not yet given a name — the story of the fall of the first man. Is it allegory ? history ? fable ? And yet there it stands, following the account of the Creation, one of the pillars of Hercules, beyond which there is nothing — the point from which all succeeding history starts. . . . And yet, ye dear, most ancient, and undying traditions of my race — ye are the very kernel and germ of its most hidden history. Without you, man- kind would be what so many other things are — a book without a title, without the first cover and introduction." — Herder. "The existence of two selves in a man, a better self which takes pleasure in the good, and a worse self which makes for the bad, is a fact too plain to be denied." — F. H. Bradley. "When we speak of primitive man, we do not mean man while lie was emerging from brutality to humanity, ' while he was losing his fur and gaining his intellect.' We leave that to the few biologists who, undeterred by the absence of facts, still profess a belief in descent of man from some known or unknown animal species." — Max Muller. " Are God and Nature then at strife, That Nature lends such evil dreams ? So careful of the type she seems, So careless of the single life ; . . . " ' So careful of the type ? ' but no. From scarped cliff" and quarried stone She cries, * A thousand types are gone, I care for nothing, all shall go. ' " Tennyson. LECTURE V. THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW IN REGAED TO THE SIN AND DISORDER OF THE WORLD. Christianity is the religion of Eedemption. As such, it has Third postu- for its third postulate the sin and disorder of the world/^f ^-(f^^^ ^ Christian The existence of natural and moral evil is one of the darkest, view— the sin deepest, and most difficult problems that can occupy human <^^f f^'O'-^^f , , of the world, thought. It is one which has exercised the hearts of men in all ages, one which is often raised in Scripture, and which The problem of should warn us off from light and superficial views of the ''''^"7^ ""!' ^ ^ i- moral evil. Divine character and purposes. Its presence is the great , difficulty in the way of a belief on natural grounds in the perfect justice and goodness of God, the obstacle we immedi- ately encounter when we try to persuade ourselves that the universe is created and ordered by a supremely good Being. So grave is this difficulty, even in respect to natural evil, that Mr. J. S. Mill declares " the problem of reconciling infinite benevolence and justice in the Creator of such a world as this " to be " impossible " ; and adds, " The attempt to do so not only involves absolute contradiction in an intellectual point of view, but exhibits in excess the revolting spectacle of a Jesuitical defence of moral enormities." ^ From the natural point of view, the assurance of God's perfect goodness must always be, to some extent, an act of faith, based on the postulate of our own moral consciousness ; and even this will often find it difficult to sustain itself, since ^ Three Essays on Religion, pp. 186-187. Cf. pp. 24-41, 112, etc. See Note A. — Defects in Creation, an Argument against Theism. 13 194 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW CJiristianity does 7iot create this problem, hut helps to solve it. Natural evil implicated with moral evil. The problem exists only for Theism. Christianity alone imparts the moral consciousness in sufficient strength to uphold the faith required. It is important to observe that though this problem meets us in connection with the Christian view of the world, it is not Christianity that makes this problem. Natural and moral evil is there as a fact in the universe, and would be there though Christianity had never been heard of. Christ- ianity intensifies the problem by the stronger light it casts on the, character of God, and the higher view it gives of man, but it does not create the problem. What it professes to do is to help us to solve it. But the problem is there all the while, and has to be taken account of by every system, whether Christian or not. It is a difficulty of philosophy, not less than of theology. While, however, in naturalistic systems moral evil is apt to fall behind natural evil, in Christianity it is the other way — the moral evil is throughout placed in the forefront, and natural evil is looked at mainly in the light of it. This is as it should be ; for while, as we shall see, natural evil presents an independent problem, there can be no doubt that its existence is deeply implicated with the existence of moral evil.i If we subtract from the sum of suffering in the world all that is directly or indirectly caused by sin — by the play and action of forces that are morally evil — we shall reduce the problem to very manageable dimensions indeed. It is the existence of moral evil which is the tremendous difficulty from a theistic point of view. I might go further, and say that it is only for a theistic system that the problem of moral evil properly exists.^ Materialism and Pantheism may acknow- ledge natural evil — misfortune, pain, sorrow, misery — but it is only by an inconsistency they can speak of sin. Both are systems of determinism, and leave no place for moral action. There is, besides, in either system, no question of a theodicy, for there is to them no God. Things are as they are by a ^ This is a point which Mr. Mill overlooks. ^ Cf. Ott's Le ProbUim du Mai, pp. 1-5, 98, 99. IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 195 necessity of nature, which we can neither account for nor get behind. If we could, indeed, really get rid of the problem of sin by adopting either of these systems, there would be some reason for accepting them. But unfortunately the problem of moral evil is one which refuses to be thus summarily got rid of. Sin is there ; the feeling of responsibility and of guilt is there; and neither the heart nor the reason of humanity will allow us to treat them as nonentities. Nor does the denial of God's existence really mitigate the difficulty. Dark as the problem of evil is, it would be immeasurably darker if we were compelled to believe that there is no infinite righteousness and love behind, through which a solution of the problem may ultimately be hoped for. I proceed to consider more narrowly what the Christian view of sin is, and how it stands related to modern theories and speculations. • I. It is in their respective relations to the sin and disorder /. Theprobhjn of the world, perhaps more than at any other point, that the ^/'^^^J^^^^^' Christian and " modern " views of the world come to a direct Christian and issue. On the one hand, there are certain respects in which ^^^^^^^^ ^^^^^ on this subject. the Christian view finds unexpected support from the modern view of the world ; on the other, there are certain respects in Respects in which it is fundamentally at variance with it. Let us briefly ^^^^"^ ^^^^. " «' modern view consider both. comes to the There are three respects in particular in which the modern ^'^PP°^\ ^f*^'-^ Christian view of the world comes to the support of the Christian view view : of sin. 1. The modern view of things is marked by a stronger i. stronger sense than in former times of the reality and universaV^f^^^^^.^'^^^ ^-^ •^ the universal 2)resence of evil — both of natural evil and of moral qyH, preseiice 0/ though moral evil, as was to be expected, is regarded more ^^^^' from its side of error, misery, and bondage, than from its side of guilt. The modern view has disposed of the superficial optimism of earlier times. The days of a flimsy ojotimism, wheu men demonstrated to their own satisfaction that this 196 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW was the best of all possible worlds, and made light of the facts which contradicted their pleasing hypothesis, are over, and everywhere there is an oppressive sense of the weight of the evils which burden humanity, and of the unsatisfactoriness of natural existence generally. The strain of modern thought is pessimistic rather than optimistic. Its high-water mark is not optimism, but what George Eliot prefers to call " meliorism." ^ Herbert Spencer, indeed, still looks for an " evanescence of evil," as the result of the working of natural and necessary laws of evolution,^ but I do not find that this represents the general temper of the age. Schopenhauer and Hartmann have at least this merit, that they raise the question of the good or evil of existence in a form which makes it impossible ever again to ignore it, or bury it out of sight. Pessimism, as Professor Flint has said, "like Macbeth, has murdered sleep." ^ All this is a gain to the Christian view. Hartmann even goes so far as to find the merit of Christianity in the fact that it is a system of Pessimism.* Both systems take for granted the facts of existence, and both look them boldly in the face. But there is this difference — Christianity looks on the world in a spirit of hope ; Pessimism looks on it in a spirit of despair. 2. Abandon- 2. It is an extension of the same remark to say that the ^^^ntofshaiiow ^^^^^^ view of the world has disposed effectually of the views of JT ./ inherent good- shallow Eousscau vicw of the inherent goodness of human ness of human ^^^^^^ ^j^j of the eighteenth century illumination dreams of a nature. ' ° •^ perfectibility of man based on education, and on altered social and political conditions.^ The optimistic and Pelagian ^ Cf. Sully's Pessimism, p. 399. He adopts the term. 2 Social Statics, p. 79. ■^ Anti-Theistic Theories, p. 294. "* Selhstzersetzung des Christenthums, p. 51. Its characteristic mark, he thinks, is "the pessimistic conviction of the unworthiness of this world to exist." Schopenhauer's language is similar. "Let no one think," he says, **that Christianity is favourable to optimism; for in the Gospels world and evil are used as almost synonymous." "The inmost kernel of Christianity is identical with that of Brahmanism and Buddhism." — Die Welt als Wille, etc., i. p. 420 ; iii. p. 420 (Eng. trans.). ^ Schopenhauer says : " Indeed the fundamental characteristic and the Tpurov ■^ivlo; of Rousseau's whole philosophy is this, that in the place of the Christian IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 197 views of human nature are as completely discredited as the optimistic view of the world generally. Kant struck this deeper key-note when, in opposition to the preceding Eationalism, he acknowledged the presence of a " radical evil " in human nature, which he could only account for by an act of the will above time.^ The modern evolutionary philosophy goes even beyond Christianity in its affirmation of the dominance of the brute element in man's being — of the ascendency of the egoistic over the social impulses in the natural man ; ^ while the moralisation of humanity which it anticipates, in the sense of a gradual subordination of the former to the latter, is admitted to be yet very imperfect. From the side of modern thought, therefore, there is no hesitation in admitting, what Christianity also affirms, that the animal in man has an undue preponderance over the intellectual and spiritual ; that the will, even in the best of men, is hampered and fettered by impulses of the lower nature to a degree which often evokes the liveliest expressions of shame and self-reproach ; that society is largely ruled by egoistic passions and aims. The law in the members warring against the law in the mind ^ — in a sense, a natural doctrine of original sin, and the original depravity of the human race, he puts an original goodness and unlimited perfectibility of it, which has only been led astray by civilisation and its consequences, and then founds upon this his optimism and humanism."— Z)ie Wdt als Wille, etc., iii. p. 398. ^ Die Religion innerhalh der Grenzen der hlossen Vernunft, Book i. — "On the Indwelling of the Evil Principle along with the Good, or on the Radical Evil in Human Nature." Cf. Caird's Philosophy of Kant, ii. pp. 566-568. 2 Mr. Fiske says: — "Thus we see what human progress means. It means throwing off the brute-inheritance,— gradually throwing it off through ages of struggle that are by-and-by to make struggle needless. . . . The ape and the tiger in human nature will become extinct. Theology has had much to say about original sin. This original sin is neither more nor less than the brute- inheritance which every man carries with him, and the process of evolution is an advance toward true salvation." — Man's Destiny, p. 103. ' ' Arise and fly The reeling Faun, the sensual feast ; Move upward, working out the beast. And let the ape and tiger die." Tennyson, In Memoriam. 3 Rom. vii. 23. 198 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW depravity and " original sin " — has its recognition in modern science and philosophy. 3. Recognition 3. In the modern view of the world we have the fullest of the organic recoofnition of the orqanic principle in human life, and of the principle zn ^ . . human life: corollary of this in heredity. This, which is the correction of heredity. ^^iQ individualistic view of human nature which prevailed in last century, I take to be one of the greatest gains of modern thought for the right understanding of the Christian doctrines both of sin and of Eedemption. The Christian view is one which gives its rightful place alike to the individual, and to the organic connection of the individual with the race ; and it is the latter side of the truth which modern thought has done so much to further. Eather, perhaps, I should say that both sides are being brought into strong prominence ; for if there never was so much stress laid on the connection of the individual with society, neither was there ever so much said about individual rights. The former idea, at all events, is now thoroughly incorporated into modern habits of think- ing, under the name of the " solidarity " of the race.^ There is an individual life, and there is a social life in which we all share. The race is an organism, and the individual, if we may so speak, is a cell in the tissue of that organism, indis- solubly connected for good or evil with the other cells in the unity of a common life.^ From this follows the conception of heredity, which plays so important a part in modern theories. Man is not simply bound up with his fellows through the external usages and institutions of society. " He has been produced by, and has become a part of them ... he is organically related to all the members of the race, not only bone of their bone and flesh of their flesh, but mind of their mind." ^ He is a bundle of inherited tendencies, and will in turn transmit his nature, with its new marks of good and evil, to those who come after ^ The word, I believe, has come from Comte. - Cf. Stephen's Science of Ethics, chap. iii. sec. 4, "Social Tissue." 2 Sorley's Ethics of Naturalism, pp. 123, 135. IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 199 him.^ It is easy to see that this conception of heredity, and of the organic unity of the race, is but the scientific expression of a doctrine which is fundamental to the Scriptures, and which underlies all its teaching about sin and salvation. In respect of the points just named, therefore, it may be Modem vieiv affirmed that the modern view of the world is largely in ^^.f ^f f. agreement with Christianity. We may not agree Yi\\h denial of Schopenhauer and Hartmann that Christianity is a system of o^^S^^^^ ^^"' Pessimism ; but we may admit that Pessimism, in so far as it recognises that the world is in an evil state, is far truer to facts and to Christianity than the superficial Optimism, the shallow perfectionism, and the Pelagian denial of original and inherited sin, which it helped to displace. In the respect last named, indeed, modern thought is nearer to Christianity than some Christian systems themselves. Eitschl, for example, teaches that sin consists only in acts, and not in states and dispositions of the heart ; that there is no such thing as original or inherited sin ; that sin is not transmissible by nature, but only through education, influence, the reciprocal action of individuals in society, etc.^ But in maintaining this, he comes into conflict, not merely with texts of Scripture, but with the whole modern conception of the organic union of the race. Universal sin, — sin which does not consist merely in acts, but springs from deep-seated causes in the heart, the effects of which, both bodily and mental, are hereditarily ^ Perhaps the most forcible illustrations of heredity are to be found in Maudsley's works. "Most certain is it," he says, " that men are not bred well or ill by accident, little as they reck of it in practice, any more than are the animals, the select breeding of which they make such a careful study ; that there are laws of hereditary action, working definitely in direct transmission of qualities, or indirectly through combinations and repulsions, neutralisations and modifications of qualities ; and that it is by virtue of these laws determin- ing the moral and physical constitution of every individual that a good result ensues in one case, a bad result in another." — Body and Will, p. 248. 2 Recht. und Ver. iii. pp. 317-332 (3rd ed.). "As a personal propensity in the life of each individual," he says, "it originates, so far as our observation reaches, out of the sinful desire and action which as such finds its adequate ground in the self-determination of the individual will." — P. 331. 200 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW transmitted, — these I take to be conceptions which neither Eitschl nor any other will now be able to overthrow.^ Fundamental When all this is said, however, it must still be granted difference ^^^ ^-j^g most fundamental difference exists between the two between Chris- tianand views — the Christian and the modern. The difference is modern views, partly one as to the nature of sin, and it runs up into a difference as to its origin. The Christian view of sin is not only infinitely deeper and more earnest than in any current conception apart from Christianity ; but it is, as I formerly remarked, profoundly modified by the difference in the views of God and of man. The first thing we have to do here is to secure clearly the Christian idea of sin ; then, when we have done this, and asked whether it is verified in conscience and experience, we are prepared to judge of theories of origin. The Christian I lay it down as a first principle that, in the Christian ^/^/ i"T~ "^^^'^j ^^^ ^^ ^^^^ which absolutely ouylit not to le} How absolutely that which absolutely ought not to be is yet permitted to ought not to be : ^^:^^^ under the government of a wise and holy God is a Its presupposi' tions. problem we may not be able to solve ; but the first thing to do is to hold firmly to the conception of sin itself. Sin, as such, is that which unconditionally ought not to be, which contradicts or infringes upon an unconditional law of right, and therefore can only be understood in the light of that which ought to be — of the moral good.^ The Christian view ^ Mr. J. J. Murphy says of Original Sin : " It is not a revealed doctrine, but an observed fact ; a fact of all human experience, and witnessed to as strongly by classical as by Biblical writers, as strongly by heathens and atheists as by Christians." — Sckntijic Basis of Faith, p. 262. Pfleiderer speaks of "the undeniable fact of experience, that, from the very dawn of moral life, we find evil present in us as a power, the origin of which accordingly must be beyond the conscious exercise of our freedom," as "a fact on which indeterminism, Pelagian or rationalistic, must ever suffer shipwreck." — Beligio7isphilosophie, iv. p. 28 (Eng. trans. ). ^ Hegel also uses this formula, but ambiguously. "What ought not to be," means with Hegel, "what ought to be done away." Cf. Julius Miiller, Chris- tian Doctrine of Sin, i. p. 322 (Eng. trans.). See on Hegel's views later. ^ "For how can anything be called evil, unless it deviate from an obligatory good, and be therefore a violation of what ought to be (seinsollendes) — of the holy law." — Dorner, System of Doctrine, ii. p. 308 (Eng. trans.). IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 201 of sin, accordingly, has for its presupposition the doctrine of - _ God as ethical Personality, previously explained. It is God's perfect nature and holy will which form the norm of character and duty for man. The law of holiness requires, not only that the human will subsist in perfect harmony with the Divine, being surrendered to it in love, trust, and obedience, but, as involved in this, that there should be a right state of the affections, a pure and harmonious inner life. The external sphere for obedience is prescribed by our position in the world, and by our relation to it, to our neighbours, and to God. As the negation of this, sin, in the Biblical view, consists Sin, as revolt in the revolt of the creature will from its rightful allegiance •^^!'f/ ° I Z' o o setting up of to the sovereign will of God, and the setting up of a idl^Q false independ- independence, the substitution of a life-for-self for life-for- ^^'^^' God.^ How such an act should ever originate may again be a problem we cannot solve ; but it is evidently included in the possibilities of human freedom. The possibility of sin arises from the fact that the creature has necessarily a relative independence; and that in man, particularly, together with the impulse towards God, there exists an impulse towards the world, which the will may be tempted to make an object on its own account.^ The false choice made, the spiritual bond between God and the soul is cut or at least infinitely weakened ; the soul enters into subjection to the world to which it has surrendered itself, and an abnormal development begins, in which the baneful and God-negating character of the egoistic principle taken into the will gradually reveals itself.^ While thus spiritual in its origin, as arising from the free Effects of in act of a will up to that time pure, sin is anything \^^^ subversion of ^ jr ' ./ o ^ ^^.^^g relation of spiritual in its effects. Its immediate result is the subversion natural and spiritual. ^ Exemplified in the Parable of the Prodigal (Luke xv. 11 ff.). 2 Cf. Martensen's Christian Ethics, i. sees. 26-28 (Eng. trans, pp. 94-102). ^ On the development and forms of sin, see Miiller, Christian Doctrine oj Sin, i. pp. 147-182 ; Dorner, System of Doctrine, ii. pp. 393-397 ; Martensen, Christian Ethics, i. pp. 102-108, etc. (Eng. trans.). 202 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW of the true relation of the natural and the spiritual in man's constitution, making that supreme which ought to be sub- ordinate, and that subordinate which ought to be supreme. The relation of the spiritual and psychical in human nature is inverted. The spiritual is reduced to subjection, can at best make only feeble and ineffectual protests ; the natural or psychical is elevated to authority and rule. Further, the spiritual bond being broken which kept the nature in harmony — reason, conscience, the God-ward affections ruling, while the lower passions and desires observed the bounds which higher law prescribed for them — not only is the psychical nature exalted to undue ascendency, but its own actings are now turbulent and irregular. It refuses to obey law ; its desires clamour importunately each for its own special gratification ; discord and division take the place of the normal unity. There is introduced into the soul a state of avo\Lia — lawlessness.^ Eeason and conscience are still there as indestructible elements of human nature, nor can the sense of its dependence on God, or obligation to Him, ever be entirely lost. Hence arise, even in the natural man, conflict, struggle, self-condemnation, painful and ineffectual attempts to break the dominion of sin, never truly successful.^ For this reason, that carnality preponderates in the nature of man as a whole, and that the most spiritual acts of the natural man betray the signs of its controlling influence, the whole man is spoken of as " in the flesh," though elsewhere Paul distinguishes the flesh from that better self — the i^ou?, or inner man — which protests against its rule.^ All this finds Verification in its verification in conscience and experience, if not in its consciousness. ^^^^^Yii^ ^^ cvcry man's consciousness, yet in the general consciousness of the race. What a man's judgment of him- self will be depends upon his standpoint, but in proportion to 1 1 John iii. 4. ^ Rq^^, yij, 13-25. ^ Rom. vii. 22, 23. On tlie various views of the Pauline use of the term ffoip^, with criticism of these, see Dr. Dickson's St. Paul's Use of the Terms Flesh and Spirit (Baird Lectures, 1883). Of. Dorner, System of Doctrine, ii. p. 319 (Eng. trans.). IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 203 the depth of his self-knowledge he will confess that his heart is not naturally possessed by love to God, and by spiritual affections ; that his inner life is not perfectly pure and harmonious ; that there are principles in his heart at war with what duty and the law of God require ; that he often transgresses the commandment which he recognises as " holy, and just, and good," ^ in thought and word and deed ; and that, in all this, he lies under his own self-condemnation. He is conscious that the sin of his heart is such that he would not willingly lay bare its secrets to his closest intimate, and he would probably confess also that this state in which he finds himself did not spring wholly, or de now, from his individual will, but that it developed from a nature in which the principle of disorder was already implanted. Gathering these observations to an issue, I conclude that sin in the the cardinal point in the Christian view of sin is, that it C^'^^^*^^^ view not some- is not something natural, normal, and necessary, but, both thing natural, as actual and as hereditary, something which must find normal, and . . n 1 IT necessary, but its explanation m a free act of the creature, annulling ^/^^ ^^^^^/^ ^y^ the original relation of the creature to God. The Christian/'^^^^^^/^^^ view, in other words, cannot be maintained on the hypo- thesis that man's existing state is his original one, — still less on the assumption that, in a moral respect, it is an advance and improvement on his original one, — but only on the supposition that man has wilfully defaced the Divine image in which he was originally made, and has voluntarily turned aside to evil. Apart from express statements on the subject, the underlying presupposition of the Christian view is that sin has a volitional cause, which, as the sin itself is universal, must be carried back to the beginning of the race — that, in other words, the development of the race has not been a natural and normal, but an abnormal and perverted one. And here it is, I admit, that the modern view of the world, with its doctrine of man's original brutishness, and his ascent by his own efforts to civilisation and moral life, 1 Eom. vii. 12. 204 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW comes into the most direct and absolute contradiction with it. Many attempts — some of them well-meant — have been made to gloze over, or get rid of, this contradiction ; but these would-be solutions all break on the fact that they make sin, or what passes for sin, a natural necessity ; whereas, on the Biblical view, it is clearly not man's misfortune only, but his fault — a deep and terrible evil for which he is responsible. Theories of sin We shall best appreciate the force of this contradiction by opposed to looking at some of the theories to which the Christian view Christian " view: is opposed. I. Theories 1. First, we havc a class of theories which seek the ground -cvhich seek the q£ ^^q -j^ creation, or in tlu original constihUion of the world ; ground of evil "^ j ' in the original but thesc I do not dwell upou. Such is the theory of constitution of Buddhism, and of all the pessimistic system.s. " The exist- the world. ence of the world," Schopenhauer holds, " is itself the greatest evil of all, and underlies all other evil, and similarly the root evil for each individual is his having come into the world " ; ^ and Hartmann speaks of the " inexpiable crime " of creation.^ Such, again, is the hypothesis of two original principles in creation, e.g. the Persian dualism, of which we see some faint attempts at a revival in modern times.^ Such were the Platonic and Gnostic theories, that evil had its origin in matter. This doctrine also has its modern revivals. Even Eothe has adopted the view which seeks the origin of evil in matter, though why matter should be supposed inimical to goodness it is not easy to see. With him, it is the non-divine, the con- tradictory counterpart to God, opposed in its essence to the Divine, a conception not Biblical, and one which cannot be maintained.* ^ Pfleiderer, Heligioiisphilosophk, ii. p. 233 (Eng. trans.). Cf. Welt als Wille, etc., i. pp. 452-461 ; iii. pp. 420-454. ^ That is, on the supposition that the Creator knew what he was about. ^ See Note B. — Dualistic Theories of the Origin of Evil. * See his theory in Theologische Ethik, 2nd ed., i. sees. 40, 104-130. Cf. his Still Hours (Eng. trans.), pp. 185, 186. He says: **The development of man passes through stages of sin. ... If sin is a necessary point in human development, it is not on that account merely negative. . . . Evil in the course of development, or sin, is not in itself a condition of the development of the IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER, 205 2. We come, second, to a class of theories which seek 2. Theories the explanation of evil in the nature of man. It is "^^^Y^ ^e.k-fhe ^ " explanation of the characteristic of all these theories that they regard evil in the sin as necessarily resulting from the constitution of human ^^^^^^^ of man. nature, in contrast with the Biblical view that it entered the world voluntarily. Of this class of theories, again, we have several kinds. (1) We have the metaphysical theories of sin — that, e.g., of (i) Metaphysi- Hegel. Sin is here regarded as a necessary stage in the '^^^ t'^^ones oj development of spirit. Hegel is fond of explicating the story of Eden in the interests of his philosophy, and this is how he does it. "Knowledge, as the disannulling of the unity of nature," he says, " is the ' Fall,' which is no casual conception, but the eternal history of spirit. For the state of innocence, the paradisaical condition, is that of the brute. Paradise is a park, where only brutes, not men, can remain. . . . The fall is, therefore, the eternal mythus of man, in fact the very transition by which he becomes man ? " ^ Sin, in brief, is the first step of man out of his naturalness, and the only way in which he could take that step. It is the negation of the immediate unity of man with nature, and of the innocence of that pristine state, but only that the negation may be in turn negated, and the true destination of spirit realised.^ (2) We have the ethical and woidd-he Christian forms of (2) Ethical these theories, in which the subject is looked at from i\^Q ^^'f '^ouid-be •^ Christian religious point of view. Such, e.g., is the theory of Schleier- theories. macher, who derives sin from a relative weakness of the good ; but it belongs to the idea of creation, as a creation out of nothing, that the created personality cannot detach itself from material nature otherwise than by being clothed upon with matter, and being in this way altered, rendered impure or sinful. This is the necessary commencement of the creation of man, but only its mere commencement, which conies to a close in the Second Adam. . . . The necessity of a transition through sin is not directly an ethical, but rather a physical necessity." The theory is criticised by Midler, pp. 146-147 (Eng. trans.); and Dorner, System of Doctrine, ii. pp. 375-380 (Eng. trans.). 1 Philosophy of History (Eng. trans.), p. 333, Cf. Beligionsphilosophie, ii. pp. 264-266. ^ See Note C. — Hegel's Doctrine of Sin. 2o6 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW spirit as compared with sense.^ Such, again, is the theory of Lipsiiis, who explains it from the fact that man is at first a naturally conditioned and self-seeking being, while his moral will is only gradually developed.^ Such is the theory of Eitschl, who connects it with man's ignorance. With him also man starts as a purely natural being, the subject of self- seeking desires, while his will for good is a " growing " quantity.^ Sin, therefore, is an inevitable stage in his development. {-^Evolution- (3) We have the evolutionary theories, in which man ary theories: ]3eorins Only a sliadc rcmovcd from the brutes, and his sub- lower aitd ° higher. sequent moralisation is the result of slow development. This theory may be held in a more naturalistic or in a more philosophical form. In the former, the genesis of our moral ideas, from which the sense of sin arises, is sought in causes outside of the moral altogether — in the possession by man of social as well as egoistic impulses, in the perception of the advantage that would accrue from the subordination of the latter to the former, in the gradual accumulation of the results of experience in the organism through heredity, in the strengthening of the bonds of society through custom, law, etc.* What this theory fails to show is how this idea of the advantageous becomes converted into the perfectly distinct conception of the morally obligatory. A clearly perceived duty lays an obligation on the will quite distinct from a perceived advantage ; and even supposing the discovery made that a larger good would accrue through every individual devotinf]j himself to the common weal, a distinct notion is 1 Der Christ. Glauhe, sees. 66-69. Cf. Miiller, i. pp. 341-359, on ''Schleier- maclier's View of the Essence and Origin of Sin," and Dorner, System of Doctrine, iii. pp. 34-38 (Eng. trans.). 2 Bogmafik, pp. 374-375. 3 Cf. liis Unterricht, 3rd ed. p. 26. This, according to him, creates only "a possibility and probability" of sin; but it is a possibility which, as shown below, in the early stages of man's history, cannot fail to be realised. ^ Cf. for different forms of the evolutionary theory, Darwin's Descent of Man, Stephen's Science of Ethics, Spencer's Data of Ethics ; and see criticism in Sorley's Ethics of Naturalism, chaps, v. to viii. m REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 207 involved when it is perceived that duty requires us to adopt this for our end.^ The higher form of the evolutionary theory, - - accordingly, makes a more promising beginning, in that it grants to man from the first his rational nature, and recog- nises that his ideas of moral truth and obligation spring directly from a rational source. It is held, however, as in the theories already considered, that at first it is the instinctive impulses, in which the self-regarding desires are necessarily preponderant, which hold the field, and that man comes to the knowledge of his true nature only gradually. Man, indeed, only begins to be a moral being, when, through the awakening of his moral consciousness, he makes the discovery that he is not what, in the true idea of his personality, he ought to be — when he forms an ideal. It is this impulse to realise his true nature, to attain to moral freedom, and brins the self-seeking impulses into harmony with moral law, which, on this theory, constitutes the mainspring of all development and progress.^ Taking this class of theories together, I contend that it is Sin in all impossible to derive out of them conceptions of sin and ^^^^"^f ^^^°^^^^ ^ made some- guilt adequate to the Christian view. In the first place, it thing neces- is evident that, in all these theories, sin is made something ^^''-^* necessary — not simply something that might be, or could be, but an absolute necessity. In every one of them, the original condition of man is supposed to be such that sin could not but result from it. This, it seems to me, is ^ Mr. Stephen substitutes the "health" for the "happiness" of society as the moral end (p. 366). But the health is in order to the liappiness, and it is presumed that the two tend to coincide (pp. 82, 83). "Morality is a statement of the conditions of social welfare," "the sum of the preservative instincts of society," "virtue is a condition of social welfare," etc. (p. 217). Strong in his criticism of the ordinary utilitarianism, Mr. Stephen is weak in his attempt to provide a substitute, or show how the moral can possibly arise out of the non- moral. See Mr. Sorley's criticism, Ethics of Naturalism, chap. viii. 2 Cf. with this general sketch Bradley's Ethical Studies (see pp. 261-265 on " The Origin of the Bad Self") ; and Green's Prolegomena to Ethics, Book iii., on "the Moral Ideal and Moral Progress." Green finds the moral end in rational "self-satisftiction," — a conception into which it is difficult to avoid importing a subtle kind of hedonism ; Bradley less objectionably finds it in " self-realisation." 2o8 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW Attempts to disclaim this conclusion : Hegel. Schleier- mcuher. Lipsitis and Ritschl. practically to empty the idea of sin of its real significance, and to throw the responsibility of it directly back on the Creator. It is probably a feeling of this kind which leads many who favour the view we are considering to disclaim the word " necessity." Hegel, even, tells us that sin is not neces- sary ; that man can will evil, but is not under compulsion to will it. But this is a mere evasion, arising from an ambiguous use of terms. In a multitude of other places Hegel tells us that sin arises from the highest logical and speculative necessity.^ Schleiermacher, in like manner, disclaims the view that sin is a necessary law of human development.^ He could not do otherwise, and hold, as he does, the sinlessness of Christ. But he holds at the same time that the develop- ment through sin — or what we subjectively regard as sin — is the form of growth ordained for us by God, with a view to the ultimate Kedemption, or perfecting, of the race in Christ.^ Lipsius will have it that sin is at once necessary and free and avoidable.* Eitschl holds, in the same way, that a necessity of sinning can be derived neither from the outfit of human nature, nor from the ends of moral life, nor from a design of God.^ Yet he grants, and starting off with man as he does as a merely natural being, he could not do otherwise, that sin is an apparently unavoidable product of the human will under the given conditions of its development.^ All these theories in fact, therefore, however they may evade the use of the name, do make sin a necessity. In the evolutionary theories this is very obvious. There is here no pretence that a sinless development is possible. How is it conceivable that a being beginning at the stage of lowest savagery should avoid sin ; and what responsibility can be supposed to attach to the acts of such a being, in whom brute passions and ^Cf. the references to Phil, des Rechts, sec. 139, in Miiller, p. 392, and see Note C. 2 Der Christ. Glauhe, sec. 68, 3. ^ Der christ. Glaube, sees. 80, 81. ^ Dogmatik, pp. 376, 377, sees. 475-477. ^ Unterricht, p. 26 ; and Becht. und Ver. iii. p. 358. ^ Hecht. und Ver. iii. 3rd ed. p. 360. IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 209 desires have full ascendency, while reason and conscience are yet a glimmer — a bare potentiality ? One immediate effect of these theories, accordingly, is to Weakening or weaken, if not entirely to destroy, the idea of guilt. How ^^iT/ 1'// can man be held responsible for acts which the constitution of his nature and his environment — without the intervention of moral causes of any kind, such as is involved in the idea of a " Fall " — make inevitable ? In all these theories I have named, accordingly, it will be found that there is a great weakening down of the idea of guilt. That man attributes his acts to himself, and feels guilty on account of them, is, of course, admitted ; but instead of guilt being regarded as something objectively real, which God as well as man is bound to take account of, it comes to be viewed as something clinging only to the subjective consciousness, — a subjective judgment which the sinner passes on himself, to which nothing actual corresponds. Redemption thus becomes, in theories that admit Redemption, not the removal of guilt, but of the consciousness of guilt ; and this, not by any real Divine pardon, but by the sinner being brought to see that his guilty fears misrepresented the actual state of God's mind towards him. Thus it is in the theories of Schleiermacher, Theories of of Lipsius, and of Ritschl — in that of Ritschl most con- Sckleier- spicuously. According to Schleiermacher, this subjective upsitis. and consciousness of guilt is a Divinely ordained thing to serve as Ki^schi. a spur to make men seek Redemption, i.e. to be taken up into the perfect life of Christ.^ Ritschl regards all sins as arising so much from ignorance as to be without real guilt in the eyes of God. God does not impute guilt on account of the ignor- ance in which we now live. The reason, therefore, why sins are pardonable is, that though the sinner imputes them to 1 Dtr Christ. Glaube, sees. 80, 81. Cf. Miiller, pp. 355-356. The views of Lipsius may be seen in his Dogmatik, sees. 768-771. "Justification," he says, "in respect of human sin, is the removal of the consciousness of guilt as a power separating from God, . . . the certainty awakened in him by tlie Spirit of God present in man of his fellowship in life and love with God, as something graciously restored in him by God Himself." — P. 690. 14 2IO THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW himself as offences, they are not properly sins at all, but acts done in ignorance. The guilt attaching to these acts is but a feeling in the sinner's own consciousness, separating him from God, which the Eevelation of God's Fatherly love in the Gospel enables him to overcome.^ But I ask, Does this harmonise with the moral experience of the race — not to say with the statements of the Bible ? Is it not the universal feeling of mankind that guilt is a terrible and stern reality, carrying with it objective and lasting effects, that it is as real as the " ought " is real, and that conscience, in passing judgment on our state, is but reflecting the judg- ment of God, to whom, ultimately, we are accountable ? This weakening down and subjectivising of the idea of guilt is to me a strong condemnation of any theory from which it springs. Differences ThcsB theories contradict the Christian view of sin, not simply in respect of its nature and of the degree of guilt attaching to it, but in the accounts they give of its origin, view depend on Xhey regard that as a normal state for man in the beginning orinn. ^^ ^^^ history, which the Christian view can only regard as an abnormal one. This is, indeed, the primary difference on Consequences which all the othcrs depend. With minor differences, these in theory of theories all agree in recjarding man's original condition as one man s original ^ m which we cannot adduce many proofs of an earlier purer faith.^ Another side from which the Christian view is contested, Relation of and the hypothesis of an orisjinally savaoje condition of man . ^^\ ^^'^ , •^ ^ o ./ o view to modern is supposed to be supported, is the evidence that has been theories of the accumulated of an extreme antiquity of the human race. \ antiquity oj , ^ . man. am not aware that the Bible is committed to any definite date for the appearance of man upon the earth ; but it will be generally felt that if the extreme views which some advocate on this subject, carrying back man's appearance some hundred thousand or two hundred thousand years, were accepted, it would, taken in connection with the comparatively recent origin of civilisation, militate against the view which we defend. I am free further to admit that, did no religious interest enter, and were the facts of science the only ones to be regarded, we would probably have been found yielding a ^ Cf. Canon Rawlinson's Origin of Nations, Part I., "On Early Civilisations ;" and the same author's "Antiquity of Man Historically Considered," in Pre>ient Day Tracts, No. 9. 2 Cf. Note A. to Lecture III. ^ See Note F.— Early Monotheistic Ideas. 2i6 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW ready assent to the hypothesis of a great antiquity. The religious interests at stake lead us, while of course acknow- ledging that whatever science really proves must be accepted as true, to be a little more careful in our examination of the proofs. And it is well we have been thus cautious ; for, if we Present state of \,^Q the latest testimony of science as to what has been usqneston. j-gally proved, wc find that the recent tendency is rather to retrench than to extend the enormous periods which were at first demanded ; and that, while some geologists tell us that one or two hundred thousand years are needed, others, equally well informed, declare that ten thousand years would cover all the facts at present in evidence.^ Professor Boyd Dawkins has said in a recent Address : — " The question of the antiquity of man is inseparably connected with the further question. Is it possible to measure the lapse of geological time in years ? Various attempts have been made, and all, as it seems to me, have ended in failure. Till we know the rate of causation in the past, and until we can be sure that it is invariable and uninterrupted, I cannot see anything but failure in the future. Neither the rate of the erosion of the land by sub-aerial agencies, nor its destruction by oceanic currents, nor the rate of the deposit of stalagmite, or of the movement of the glaciers, have as yet given us anything at all approaching to a satisfactory date. We have only a sequence of events recorded in the rocks, with intervals, the length of which we cannot measure. It is surely impossible to fix a date in terms of years, either for the first appearance of man, or for any event outside the written record." ^ Science does I claim, then, that so far as the evidence of science goes, not negative ^y^^ Bible doctrinc of a pure beginning of the race is not pure begin- Overturned. I do not enter into the question of how we are mitgofthe |.Q interpret the third chapter of Genesis, — whether as race: bibltcal account of primeval man. ^ ^®^ Note G. — The Antiquity of Man and Geological Time. 2 Report of Address to British Association, Sept. 6, 1888. Professor Dawkins is hinisflf an advocate of man's great antiquity. IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 2 1 7 history or allegory or myth, most probably of all, as old tradition clothed in oriental allegorical dress, — but the truth embodied in that narrative, viz., the fall of man from an original state of purity, I take to be vital to the Christian view. On the other hand, we must beware, even while hold- ing to the Biblical account, of putting into the original state of man more than the narrative warrants. The picture given us of the first man in the Bible is primitive in every way The Adam of the book of Genesis is not a being of advanced intellectual attainments, or endowed with an intuitive know- ledge of the various arts and sciences. If his state is far removed from that of the savage, it is equally far removed from that of the civilised m.an.^ The earliest steps in what we call civilisation are of later date, and are duly recorded, though they belong, not to the race of Seth, but to that of Cain.^ It is presumed that man had high and noble faculties, a pure and harmonious nature, rectitude of will, capability of under- standing his Creator's instructions, and power to obey them. Beyond that we need not go. The essence of the Biblical view is summed up in the words of the preacher : " God made man upright ; but they sought out many inventions." ^ II. I pass to the consideration of the connection of moral //. The pro- with natural evil, roservinoj for discussion in a succeedinf]^ emo/nama ' ^ ^ evil: coiinec' section a special aspect of that connection — the relation of Hon with sin to death. I begin by a brief consideration of the problem ^°'''^^ ^^''^' of natural evil, as such. It is not sin only, but natural evil — the existence of pain and suffering in the world — which is made the ground of an impQachment of God's justice and goodness. Everyone will remember Mr. J. S. Mill's terrible indictment of nature on this score ;* and Pessimism has given new voice to the plaints which have always been heard of 1 Cf. Dawson, Modern Science in Bible Lands, iv., "Early Man in Genesis." 2 Gen. iv. 16-22. 3 EccI. vii. 29. Cf. Delitzsch, in loc. ^ Three Essays, pp. 29-31 : " In sober truth, nearly all the things which men are hanged or imprisoned for doing to one another, are Nature's every-day performances," etc. 2i8 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRIS7IAN VIEW the misery and suffering bound up with life. On the general question, I would only like again to emphasise what I said at the outset of the extent to which this problem of natural evil is bound up with that of sin. Apart from all theological prepossessions, we have only to cast our eyes abroad to see how large a part of the total difficulty this connection with moral evil covers. Take away from the history of humanity all the evils which have come on man through his own folly, sin, and vice ; through the follies and vices of society ; through tyranny, misgovern ment, and oppression ; through the cruelty and inhumanity of man to man ; and how vast a portion of the problem of evil would already be solved ! "What myriads of lives have been sacrificed at the shrines of Bacchus and o-f lust ; what untold misery has been inflicted on the race, to gratify the unscrupulous ambitions of ruthless conquerors ; what tears and groans have sprung from the institution of slavery ; what wretchedness is hourly inflicted on human hearts by domestic tyranny, private selfishness, the preying of the strong upon the weak, dishonesty and chicanery in society ! If great civilisations have fallen, to what has the result been commonly due, if not to their own vices and corruptions, which sapped and destroyed their vigour, and made them an easy prey to ruder and stronger races ? ^ If society witnesses great volcanic eruptions like the French Eevolution, is it not when evil has reached such a height through the long- accumulating iniquities of centuries that it can no longer be borne, and the explosion effects a remedy which could not otherwise be achieved ? If all the suffering and sorrow which follow directly or indirectly from human sin could be abstracted, what a happy world, after all, this would be ! Yet there seem to be natural evils which are independent of sin, and we must endeavour to look the problem suggested by them fairly in the face. Natural evil First of all, I would say that this problem of natural evil can hardly be said to meet us in the inanimate world at all, 1 Cf. Martineau, Study of Religion, ii. pp. 131-135 (Book ii. chap. iii,). in the inani mate world. IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 219 i.e. regarding it merely as such.^ We see there what may appear to us like disharmony and disorder ; convulsion, upheaval, the letting loose of titanic forces which work havoc and destruction ; but except in relation to sentient existences, we cannot properly speak of these as evil. We may wonder why they should be, but, when we see what ends are served in the economy of nature by this apparently lawless clash and conflict of forces, we may reconcile our- selves to it as part of a system, which,, on the whole, is very good.2 Neither does this problem properly meet us in QonuQQ.t\%n Natural evil with the organic world, so far as it is not sentient, e.g. in ^^^ ^^^^ organic connection with the law of decay and death in the vegetable (i) Non- world. When it is said that, according to the Bible, there ^^'^^^^^it {vegetable). was no death before Adam, it is to be remembered that the Bible speaks of a vegetable creation, which was evidently intended to be perishable,^= — which, in fact, was given for food to animals and' men; We feel no difficulty in this. The plants are part of nature. They flower, seed, decay.. They fall under the law of all finite, merely natural existences in being subject to corruptibility and death. When we rise to animal life, the problem does appear, for (2) Sentient here we have sentiency and suffering. Yet abstracting for a (^«^^'^^^)- moment from this sentiency, the same thing applies to animals as to plants. They are finite, merely natural creatures, not ends in themselves, but subserving some general use in the economy of nature, and, by the law of their creation, exposed to corruption and death. How is this modified by the fact of sentiency ? I think we have only to look at the matter fairly to see that it is not modified in any Relation to way which is incompatible with the justice and goodness of ^''"^J^^ ^^^ the Creator. Leaving out of reckoning the pain of human Creator. life, and the sufferings inflicted on the animal world by man, 1 Cf. Ott, Le ProhUme du Mai, p. 18 ; Naville, do. p. 50 (Eng. trans.). '^ These disturbances, however, present a very different aspect when viewed in relation to man. See below. ^ Gen. i. 11, 12 (seed producing). 220 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW Is the world of we might fairly ask the pessimist to face the question, Is the 'anunhapp^^ world of Sentient beings an unhappy one ? Look at the fish one? in the stream, the bird in the air, the insect on the wing, the creatures of the forest, — is their lot one of greater pleasure or pain ? I do not think it is unhappy. We speak of " the struggle for existence," but is this necessarily pain ? The capacity for pleasure, indeed, implies as its counterpart the susceptibility of pain, but whereas the avenues for pleasure are many, the experience of pain is minimised by the sudden- ness with which death comes, the absence of the power of reflection, the paralysis of feeling through fascination or excitement, etc.^ I have been struck with observing the The Biblical predominatingly optimistic way in which the Bible, and vuw of nature especially Jesus, all throuojh regard the natural and sentient predominat- ^ J o & ^ ingly world, dwelling on its brightness, its beauty, its rejoicing, the optimistic. (,g^j.Q Q^ Providence over the creatures, their happy freedom,^ — in striking contrast with the morbid brooding over the aspects of struggle in nature which fill our modern treatises,^ The thing which strikes us most as a difficulty, perhaps, is the universal preying of species on species — " nature red in tooth and claw " * — which seems so strange a feature in a government assumed to have for its motive beneficence. But the difficulty is modified by the consideration that food in some way must be provided for the creatures ; and if sentiency is better than insentiency, greater beneficence is shown in giving the bird or insect its brief span of life than ^ We may exaggerate, too, the power of sensibility in the lower species of animals. See on this, Mivart, Lessonfi from Nature, pp. 368, 369. "Though, of course, animals feel, they do not know that they feel, nor reflect upon the sufferings they have had, or will have to endure. ... If a wasp, while enjoying a meal of honey, has its slender waist suddenly snipped through and its whole abdomen cut away, it does not allow such a trifle for a moment to interrupt its pleasurable repast, but it continues to rapidly devour the savoury food, which escapes as rapidly from its mutilated thorax." — P. 369. 2 E.g. the Sermon on the Mount, Matt. vi. 26. Another note as respects creation as a whole is struck by Paul in Rom. viii. 19-22. ^ Cf. for an example of this a passage quoted from De Maistre by Naville, p. 54. "In the vast domain of living Nature open violence reigns, a kind of fury which arms all creatures in midua fiinera,^'' etc. * Tennyson, In Memoriam, Iv. IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 2 2 1 in withholding existence from it altogether. The present plan provides for the multiplication of sentient creatures to an extent which would not be possible on any other system ; it provides, too, since death must rule over such organisms, for their removal from nature in the way which least pollutes nature with corruption.^ The real question which underlies the problem in relation Real question to the natural world is, — Is there to be room in the universe ~" ^^^^'^ ^^ ^^ room for for any grades of existence short of the highest ? In nature, gradation of as the evolutionist is fond of showing, we find every blank ^-^"^^'^^^-^ -^ space filled — every corner and niche that would be otherwise empty occupied by some form of life. Why should it not be so ? If, in addition to the higher orders of being, lower grades of sentient existence are possible, enhancing the total sum of life and happiness, why should they not also be created ? Why — to give our thoughts for a moment the widest possible range — if there is in the universe, as Dorner supposes, " a world standing in the light of eternity, a world of pure spirits, withdrawn from all relation to succession " ^ (the angelic world), should there not be also a material and time-developing world ? Why, in this temporal world, should there be only the highest creature, man, and not also an infinity of creatures under him, stocking the seas, rivers, plains, forests, and taking possession of every vacant opening and nook which present themselves ? Or, in a developing world, could the highest be reached except through the lower — the spiritual except through the natural ? Is not ^ Martineau says : "I will be content with a single question, How would you dispose of the dead animals ? . . . If no creature would touch muscular fibre, or adipose tissue, or blood, and all animated nature had to be provided with cemeteries like ours, we should be baffled by an unmanageable problem ; the streams would be poisoned, and the forests and the plains would be as noisome as the recent battlefield. Nature, in her predatory tribes, has appointed a sanitary commission, and in her carrion- feeders a burial board, far more effective than tliose which watch over our villages and cities." — Study of Beligion, ii. p. 95. See his whole treatment of this problem, '^ System, of Doctrine, ii. pp. 33, 99 (Eng. trans.). Dorner mentions the idea of Aquinas of "a complete world, exhibiting without a break a^l possible forms of life."— P. 99. 2 22 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW The questioji altered when we rise to rational self- conscious man — a being who is end to him- self. The disciplin- ary benefits of suffering, etc., inadequate as a complete solution : discussion of this theory. this the law of Scripture, as well as of nature — " that was not first which is spiritual, but that which is natural, and afterwards that which is spiritual." ^ The mere fact that in a world of this kind the denizens would be finite and perish- able — exposed to incidental pains, as well as constituted for pleasures — would not be a reason for not creating it, unless the pains were a predominant feature, and constituted a surplusage over the pleasures. But this we do not acknow- ledge to be the case. The pleasures of the animal world we take to be the rule ; the pains are the exception.^ It is when we rise from the animal world to the considera- tion of natural evil in relation to man that we first meet with the problem in a form which constitutes it a formidable difficulty. For man, unlike the animals, is an end to him- self; pain means more to him than it does to them; death, in particular, seems a contradiction of his destiny ; and it is not easy to understand why he should be placed in a world in which he is naturally, nay necessarily, exposed to these evils. The natural disturbances which we formerly noticed — floods, hurricanes, earthquakes, volcanoes, and the like — now assume a new aspect as elements in a world of which man is to be the inhabitant, and where he may be called upon to suffer through their agency.'"^ This is really a serious problem, and we have to ask whether the Biblical view affords any clue to the solution of it, and whether that solution will sustain the test of reason and of fact ? ^ It is scarcely an adequate solution of this problem of natural evil and death as it affects man, though, no doubt, a 1 1 Cor. XV. i^. 2 The difficulty is " modified, " as said, but not altogether removed by these considerations, especially when the world is viewed in its teleological relations to man, and when stress is laid, not only on the mere fact of the preying of one creature on another, but on some of the hinds of creatures with which the earth is stocked, and on the manner of their warfare ; on their hideousness, repulsiveness, fierceness, unnecessary cruelty, etc. See a powerful statement in Martensen's Jacob Bohme, pp. 217-222 (Eng. trans.). ^ To a certain extent these disturbances atfect animals also, but in these cases the question is subordinate. IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 223 profound element in the solution, to point to the disciplinary and other wholesome uses which misfortune and suffering are fitted to subserve in the moral education of man. This is the line followed by most earnest thinkers in trying to explain the mystery of suffering in the world, and it rests on the true thought that there is a Divinely ordained connection between the pains we are called upon to suffer and the ends of our highest life.^ Without trials and difficulties, it is urged, where were progress ; without checks to self-will, where were the lessons of submission to a higher will ; with- out experience of resistance, where were the stimulus to effort ; without danger and misfortune, where were courage, manhood, and endurance ; without pain, where were sym- pathy ; 2 without sorrow and distress, where would the oppor- tunity for self-sacrifice be ? This is quite true, but does it go to the root of the matter ? Does it explain all ? Because suffering and death, as existing in the world, have an educat- ing and purifying effect ; because, as may be freely granted, they have a power of developing a type of character greater and nobler than could have been developed without them (a glimpse of a theodicy in the permission of evil at all) ; because they serve for purposes of test and trial where character is already formed, and aid its yet ampler growth^ — does it follow that a world such as this, with its manifold disorders, would have been a suitable abode for an unfallen race ; or that it would have been righteous to expose such a race to these calamities ; or that, in the case of pure beings, less violent and painful methods of education would not have sufficed? * Of course, if this method of arguing were admitted, I Thus Rothe, PfleiJerer, Martineau, Ott, etc. ^ Cf. Browning, Ferishtah's Fayicies — **Mihrab Shah." ^ The theodicy in. Job takes this form. ■* Cf. Lotze, Outlines of Philosophy of Religion (Eng. trans.), pp. 124, 125 ; and Browning, La Saisiaz, Works, xiv. p. 181 : — " What, no way but this that man may learn and lay to heart how rife Life were with delights would only death allow their taste to life ? Must the rose sigh * Pluck— I perish ! ' must the eve weep ' Gaze— I fade ! ' — Every sweet warn ' 'Ware my bitter ! ' every shine bid ' Wait my shade ' ? 224 THE POSTULATE OE THE CHRISTIAN VIEW the existence of moral evils would have to be justified on the same ground, for in conflict with these, even more than with outward misfortune, is the highest type of character developed. It will be observed, also, that the argument rests largely, though not wholly, on the assumption of fault in human nature to be corrected (self-will, selfishness, etc.), and thus already presupposes sin ; it does not, for instance, tell what a world would have been into which no sin had entered. But do even the advocates of this explanation of natural evil abide by their own thesis ? Pain, it is said, begets tenderness and sympathy ; suffering engenders philanthropy ; the presence of evils in the world awakens noble self-sacrificing efforts for their removal — summons man, as Pfleiderer puts it, to fellow- ship with " the aim of God Himself, viz. to advance goodness, and to overcome evil in the world." ^ Then these are evils, and notwithstanding their advantages, we are to treat them as things which would be better absent, and do our utmost to remove them. A concrete case in this connection is worth a good deal of argument, and I take it from Naville. He tells of a letter he received, written from Zurich, at a time when the cholera was ravaging the city. "My correspondent," he says, " told me that he had seen sad things — the results of selfishness and fear ; but he also told me that so much courage, devotedness, and regard for the good of others had been brought out under the pressure of the malady, that different ranks of society had been so drawn together by the inspiration of generous sentiments, that he would not for the world have been absent from his native place, and so have missed witnessing such a spectacle." ^ Shall we then, because of these salutary effects, wish for the prevalence of cholera ? Or because wars bring out noble examples of Can we love but on condition that the thing we love must die ? Needs there groan a world in anguish just to teach us sympathy — Multitudinously wretched that we, wretched too, may guess What a preferable state were universal happiness ? " ^ Religiomphilosophie, iv. p. 63 (Eng. trans.). 2 Problem of Evil, p. 65 (Eng. trans.). IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 225 heroism, shall we desire to see wars prevail ? The question has only to be asked to be answered, and it shows that ~^ ~ this mode of justifying natural evil leaves much yet to be accounted for. It has just been seen that even this mode of explaining The connection the existence of natural evil, and the use made of it in the ^/'^f^^'f^ ^^^ ^ with sin : moral government of God, presupposes, to some extent, the nature and existence of sin. This yields a point of transition to the ^^^"^^^^^I'^^^^y of this con- Biblical view, in which this solidarity of man with his out- nection, ward world, and the consequent connection of rational with moral evil, is a central and undeniable feature. We are not, indeed, at liberty to trace a strict relation between the sins of individuals and the outward calamities that befall them ; but Christ's warning on this subject by no means contradicts the view that there is an intimate connection between natural and moral evils, and that the former are often used by God as the punishment of the latter. It is one of the most deeply ingrained ideas in the Bible that physical evils are often used by God for the punishment of individual and national wickedness, and Christ Himself expressly endorses this view in His own predictions of the approaching judg- ments on Jerusalem.^ He warns us only that the proposition — sin is often punished with physical evils — is by no means convertible with the other, — all physical evils are the punish- ment of individual sins. Nor is this teaching of Scripture to be explained away, as it is by Lipsius, Pfleiderer, and Eitschl, as meaning merely that the evil conscience subjectively regards these visitations as retributive, though objectively they have no such character, but simply flow from the natural course of events.^ Similarly, the expression, "All things work together for good to them that love God," ^ is explained as meaning that things work together for good ^ Matt, xxiii. 35 ; cf. John v. 14 : "Sin no more, lest a worse thing come unto thee." ^ Cf., e.i/., Ritschl, Rtcld. und Ver. iii. p. 334; Pfleiderer, Bcligionsphilo- .sophie, iv. jip. 42-44. ■^ Kom. viii. 28. 15 226 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW to the believer because, whatever the course of events, he is sure to profit by them. This is not the Biblical view, and it is not a reasonable one for those to take who, like the above- named writers, admit a government of the world for moral ends. Once allow a relation between the natural and the moral in the government of God, and it is difficult to avoid the conclusion that the course of outward events is directed with a regard to the good and evil conduct of the subjects of that government. The deeper A deeper qucstioH, however, which lies behind this imme- question—h ^^^^^ qj^q^ ^f ^^ placc of natural evils in the moral govern- nature itself in a normal mcut of God is, Is nature itself in a normal condition ? The condition? Bible, again, undeniably answers this question in the negative, 7^he Biblical . answer ^.ud it is important for us to ascertain in what sense pre- negative. cisely it docs SO. The most explicit passage in the New Testament is perhaps that in Eom. viii. 19-23, where the The Pauline Apostlc Paul cxprcssly declares, " For the earnest expectation view: what it q£ ^j^q creation waiteth for the revealing of the sons of God. For the creation was subjected to vanity, not of its own will, but by reason of Him who subjected it, in hope that the creation itself also shall be delivered from the bondage of corruption into the liberty of the glory of the children of God. For we know that the whole creation groaneth and travaileth in pain together until now." The plain implica- tion of this passage is that nature is a sufferer with man on account of sin ; that, as I expressed it above, there is a solidarity between man and the outward world, both in his Fall and his Eedemption. So far the passage is an echo of the statement in Genesis that the earth lies under a curse on account of human sin. Is this view scientifically tenable, or is it not a baseless dream, directly contradicted by the facts already conceded of physical disturbance, decay, and death in the world, long ere man appeared in it ? I do not think it is. This implication of creation in the effects of human sin, though science certainly cannot prove it, is an idea by no means inadmissible, or in contradiction with known facts. itnplies. IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 227 1. The view has often been suggested — is maintained, e.g., i. Theory that by Dorner and Delitzsch^ — that the constitution of nature had '^^^^''^ ^-^ from the first a from the first a teleological relation to sin ; that sin did not teleologkal enter the world as an unforeseen accident, but, as foreseen, ^^^^fion to . PI human sin. was provided tor m the arrangements of the world; that creation, in other words, had from the beginning an anticipa- tive reference to sin. This view would explain many things that seem mysterious in the earlier stages of creation, and falls in with other truths of Scripture, to which attention will subsequently be directed.^ 2. I do not feel, however, that I need to avail myself of 2. The this hypothesis. All that is essential in the Apostle's state- ^^^f ^^^^^^^' ment can be conserved without going back to pre-Adamic subjection of ages, or to vegetable decay, and animal suffering and death, ^f ^ <^^^(^i^on to We gain the best key to the passage if we keep to the mean- ing of his own word " vanity " (/iaratoT?;?) — profitlessness — as expressive of that to which creation was subjected. " It is not said," remarks Bishop Ellicott, " that the creation was subject to death or corruption, though both lie involved in the expression, but to something more frightfully generic, to something almost worse than non-existence, — to purposeless- ness, to an inability to realise its natural tendencies, and the ends for which it was called into being, to baffled endeavour and mocked expectations, to a blossoming and not bearing fruit, a pursuing and not attaining, yea, and as the analogies of the language of the original significantly imply, ^ Dorner, System of Doctrine, ii. p. 67 (Eng. trans. ) ; Delitzsch, New Com- mentary on Genesis, i. p. 103 (Eng. trans.). "The whole of the six days' creation," says the latter, "is, so to speak, supralapsarian, i.e. so constituted that the consequences of this foreseen fall of man were taken into account." ^ This theory is ingeniously argued out in an interesting chapter in Bush- naW^ Nature and the Supernatural, chap, vii., " Anticipative Consequences." Of. also Hugh Miller's Footprints of the Creator, pp. 268 ff . ; "Final Causes ; their Bearing on Geologic History ; " and Hitchcock, Religion of Geology, Lecture III. I have not touched on another theory, beginning with Bohme, which connects the present state of creation with yet earlier, i.e. daemonic evil. The most striking statement of this theory is perhaps in Marten sen, Jacob Bohme (Eng. trans,), pp. 217-222 — a passage already referred to. See the theory criticised in Reusch's Nature and the Bible, Book i. chap. xvii. (Eng. trans.). 228 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW to a searching and never finding."^ Thus interpreted, the apostle's words convey the idea that nature is in a state of arrested development through sin, is frustrated of its true end, and has a destiny before it which sin does not permit it to attain. There is an arrest, delay, or back-putting through sin, which begets in the creature a sense of bondage, and an earnest longing for deliverance.^ This certainly harmonises sufficiently well with the general impression nature makes upon us, which has found expression in the poetry and literature of all ages. 3. The earth 3. The earth is under " bondage to corruption " in another on age ^ — .^ ^j^^ ^ presence of man and his sin upon it ; cormption *' ' j r r » through the in being the abode of a sinful race ; in being compelled, very presence .(^j^rough its laws and a^encics, to subserve the purposes of of man and MS ° o ' jt x sin upon it. man's sin ; in being perverted from its true uses in the service of his lusts and vices ; in the suffering of the animal creation through his cruelty ; in the blight, famine, earth- quake, etc., to which it is subjected in consequence of his sin, and as the means of punishment of it. For it by no means follows that because these things were found in the world in the making, they were intended to be, or continue, in the world as made, or would have been found had sin not entered it. Science may affirm, it can certainly never prove, that the world is in a normal state in these respects, or that even under existing laws, a better balance of harmony could not be maintained, had the Creator so willed it. ///. Cuimina- III. This wholc discussion of the connection of natural tionoftiis ^-^j^ moral evil sums itself up in the consideration of one problem m the ^ question of the Special problem, in which the contending views may be said relation of sin ^^ |^g brought to a distinct and decisive issue — I mean to death. ° the relation of sin to death. Is human death — that crown- ^ Destiny of the Creature, p. 7. ^ Thus also Dorner : "So far, then, as sin retards this perfection, it may certainly be said that Nature is detained by sin in a state of corruption against its will, as well as that it has been placed in a long-enduring state of corrupt- ibleness, which, apart from sin, was unnecessary, if the assimilation of Nature by spirit could have been accomplished forthwith." — Synt. of Doct., ii. p. QQ. IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 229 ing evil, which carries so many other sorrows in its train — the result of sin, or is it not ? Here, again, it is hardly necessary for me to say, there is a direct contradiction between the Biblical and the " modern " view, and it is for us very carefully to inquire whether the Pauline statement, " Through one man sin entered into the world, and death through sin ; and so death passed unto all men, for that all have sinned," ^ enters into the essence of the Christian view, or whether, as some seem to think, it is an excrescence which may be stripped off. Now, so far from regarding this relation of human death to This relation sin as a mere accident of the Christian view, which may be '^'^^.^^f'^t,, ' '' accident of the dropped without detriment to its substance, I am disposed to Christian look on it as a truth most fundamental and vital — orejanicallv ^^^^' '^"^ . ° '' enters into its connected with the entire Christian system. Its importance essence. comes out most clearly when we consider it in the light of the Christian doctrine of Eedemption. The Bible, as we shall immediately see, knows nothing of an abstract immor- tality of the soul, as the schools speak of it; nor is its Eedemption a Eedemption of the soul only, but of the body as well. It is a Eedemption of man in his whole complex personality — body and soul together. It was in the body that Christ rose from the dead; in the body that He has ascended to heaven ; in the body that He lives and reigns there for evermore. It is His promise that, if He lives, we shall live also ; ^ and this promise includes a pledge of the resurrection of the body. The truth which underlies this is, that death for man is an effect of sin. It did not lie in the Creator's original design for man that he should die, — that these two component parts of his nature, body and soul, should ever be violently disrupted and severed, as death now severs them. Death is an abnormal fact in the history of the race ; and Eedemption is, among other things, the undoing of this evil, and the restoration of man to his normal complete- ness as a personal being. 1 Rom. V. 12 (R.y.). 2 Jolm xiv. 19. 230 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW its present tiniversality. iiie original That man was originally a mortal being neither follows vwi a I y of from the fact of death as a law of the animal creation, nor via7t proved ' neither by the from its present Universality. It is, no doubt, an essential law of death ^^^ ^^ ^^^ modem anti-Christian view, that man is a dying in the animal ' j o creation, nor creature, and always has been. This goes with the view that man is simply an evolution from the animal, and falls under the same law of death as the rest of the animal creation. But I have shown some reasons for not admitting the premiss,^ and therefore I cannot assent to the conclusion. There is not a word in the Bible to indicate that in its Distinction of vicw death entered the animal world as a consequence of the man from the gi^^ ^f ^^^^ g^^^ ^-^j^ ^j^^ advent of man upon the scene, animals. ^ there was, as remarked in an earlier part of the Lecture, the introduction of something new. There now appeared at the head of creation a moral and spiritual being — a being made in God's image — a rational and accountable being — a being for the first time capable of moral life, and bearing within him infinite possibilities of progress and happiness; and it does not follow that because mere animals are subject to a law of death, a being of this kind must be. More than this, it is the distinction of man from the animals that he is immortal, and they are not. He bears in his nature the various evidences that he has a destiny stretching out far into the future — into eternity; and many even, who hold that death is not a consequence of sin, do not dispute that his soul is immortal. But here is the difficulty in which such a view is involved. The soul is not the whole of the man. It is a false view of the constitution of human mg of essential nature to regard the body as a mere appendaore to the soul, parts of his i. x o being: there- ^r to supposc that the humau being can be equally com- fore abjiormai. piete whether he has his body, or is deprived of it. This is not the Biblical view, nor, I venture to say, is it the view to which the facts of modern psychology and physiology point. If anything is evident, it is that soul and body are made for each other, that the perfect life for man is a 1 Cf. last Lecture. Created for immortality. Death a con- tradiction of man's nature — the sunder- IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 231 corporeal one; that he is not pure spirit, but incorporated spirit. The soul is capable of separation from the body ; but ~ - in that state it is in an imperfect and mutilated condition. Thus it is always represented in the Bible, and heathen feeling coincides with this view in its representations of the cheerless, sunless, joyless, ghost-like, state of Hades. If then, it is held that man was naturally constituted for immortality, how can it be maintained, with any show of consistency, that he stood originally under a law of death ? That the animal should die is natural. But for the rational, moral agent, death is something -imnatural — abnormal ; the violent rupture, or separation, or tearing apart, so to speak, of two parts of his nature which, in the Creator's design, were never intended to be sundered. There is, therefore, profound truth in the Biblical representation, " In the day that thou eatest thereof thou shalt surely die " — " Dust thou art, and unto dust thou shalt return." ^ Some other way of leaving the world, no doubt, there would have been — some Enoch or Elijah - like translation, or gradual transformation of a lower corporeity into a higher, but not death as we know it.2 The true Biblical doctrine of immortality then, I think, The Biblical includes the following points :— ^"'^''''^f f 1. It rests on the Biblical doctrine of human nature, j. j^^sts on According to the Bible, and according to fact, man is a Biblical , . . Ti ^ 1 1 1 1 • •. doctrine of the compound bemg — not, like God and the angels a pure spirit, ^^^^^^ ^^ ^^^,^ but an embodied spirit, a being made up of body and oi ^s a comj>otmd soul. The soul, it is true, is the higher part of human ^* nature, the seat of personality, and of mental, moral, and spiritual life. Yet it is intended and adapted for life in the body, and body and soul together make the man — the complete human being. 1 Gen. ii. 16, iii. 19. 2 See furtlier on this subject, Note H. — The Connection of Sin and Death. 232 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW 2. No part of 2. It was no part of the Creator's design for man in the Creator's j^-g \^q^ constitution that body and soul should ever be design that , " body and soul Separated. The immortality man was to enjoy was an should be immortality in which the body was to have its share. This separated. is the profound truth in the teaching of the Bible when it says that, as respects man, death is the result of sin. Had sin not entered we must suppose that man — the complete man — would have enjoyed immortality ; even his body, its energies replenished from vital forces from within, being exempt from decay, or at least not decaying till a new and more spiritual tenement for the soul had been prepared. With the entrance of sin, and departure of holiness from the soul, this condition ceased, and the body sank, as part of general nature, under the law of death. 3. Thesouiin 3. The soul in separation from the body is in a state of separation imperfection and mutilation. When a human being loses from the body c> • ^' ^ • is in a state of One of his limbs, we regard him as a mutilated being. Were imperfection \^q ^q losc all his limbs, we would regard him as worse tion: inter- mutilated Still. So when the soul is entirely denuded of its mediate state, body, though consciousucss and memory yet remain, it must still be regarded — and in the Bible is regarded — as subsist- ing in an imperfect condition, a condition of enfeebled life, diminished powers, restricted capacities of action — a state, in short, of deprivation. The man whose life is hid with Christ in God will no doubt with that life retain the blessed- ness that belongs to it even in the state of separation from the body — he will be with Christ, which is far better ; ^ but it is still true that so long as he remains in that disembodied state, he wants part of himself, and cannot be perfectly blessed, as he will be after his body, in renewed and glorified form, is restored to him. 4. The true 4. The last point, therefore, in the Biblical doctrine is immortality is |.j^^|. ^^^^ immortality is throui^h Eedemption, and that this through Re- ^ o r » demption, and Redemption embraces the resurrection of the body.^ It is a embraces the resurrection of ^2 Cor. v. 8 ; Phil. i. 23 ; Rev. xiv. 13, etc. the body. " Rom. v. 11, viii. 23. IN REGARD TO SIN AND DISORDER. 233 complete Eedemption, a Eedemption of man in his whole personality, and not simply of a part of man. This is a subject which will be considered afterwards. It is enough for the present to have shown that the Biblical doctrines of man's nature, of the connection of sin and death, of Eedemption, and of the true immortality, cohere together and form a unity — are of a piece. APPENDIX TO LECTUEE V. THE OLD TESTAMENT DOCTRINE OF IMMORTALITY. Bearing oj The views advanced in the Lecture have an important bearing previous dis-^^ the niuch discussed question of the Old Testament cussion on Old ^ Testament doctrine of immortality. The statement is often made that doctrine of ^j^^ q^j Testament, especially in the older books, has no ijnmortahty. distinct doctrine of immortality. Many explanations have been offered of this difficulty, but I would humbly suggest that the real explanation may be that we have been looking This doctrine for evidence of that doctrine in a wrong direction. We have has been ^^^^^ lookin^? for a doctrine of " the immortality of the soul " sought for in a ° wrong direc- in the scnsc of the schools, whereas the real hope of ^^''"* patriarchs and saints, so far as they had one, was, in accord- ance with the Biblical doctrine already explained, that of restored life in the body.^ The Hebrew The early Hebrews had no manner of doubt, any more viewofSheol. ^^^ ^^ \\.-dNQ, that the soul, or spiritual part of man, survived the body.^ It would be strange if they had, for every other ancient people is known to have had this belief. Egyptians, The Egyptians, e.g.y taught that the dead descended to Babylonians, ^^ under world, where they were judged in presence of Osiris and his forty-two assessors.^ The Babylonians and Assyrians 1 The view defended in this Appendix will be found indicated in Hofmann's Schriftheweis, iii. pp. 461-477 ; and Dr. P. Fairbairn's Typology of Scripture, 3rd ed. i. pp. 343-359. ■^ Cf. Max Miiller, Anthropoloqical Religion, on "Belief on Immortality in the Old Testament," pp. 367, 377. '^ Cf. Renouf, Hibbert Lectures, pp. 195, 196 ; Budge, Dwellers on the Nile ("Bye-Paths of Bible Knowledge" Series), chap. ix. ; Vigouroux's La Bible et les Decouvertes modernes, iii. pp. 133-141. LD TESTAMENT DOCTRINE OF IMMORTALITY. 235 conceived of the abode of the dead as a great city having seven encircling walls, and a river flowing round or through ~ it.^ A name they gave to this city is believed by some to have been " Sualu," ^ the same word as the Hebrew Sheol, which is the name in the Old Testament for the place of departed spirits. It is one of the merits of the Eevised Version that it has in many places (why not in all ?) printed this word in the text, and tells the reader in the preface that " Sheol," sometimes in the Old Version trans- lated "grave," sometimes "pit," sometimes "hell," means definitely " the abode of departed spirits, and corresponds to the Greek ' Hades,' or the under world," and does not signify " the place of burial." But the thought of going to " Sheol " was no comfort to the good man. The gloomy associations Gloomy of death hung over this abode ; it was figured as a land of «-^^^«'^^^^'" ^« ^ ^ ' ° Old Testa- silence and forgetfulness ; the warm and rich light of the menu upper world was excluded from it ; ^ no ray of gospel light had as yet been given to chase away its gloom. The idea of " Sheol " was thus not one which attracted, but one which repelled, the mind. Men shrank from it as we do from the breath and cold shades of the charnel-house. The saint, strong in his hope in God, might believe that God would not desert him even in "Sheol"; that His presence and fellow- ship would be given him even there ; but it would only be in moments of strong faith he could thus triumph, and in hours of despondency the gloomiest thoughts were apt to come back on him. His real trust, so far as he was able to cherish one, was that God would not leave his soul in " Sheol," ' Cf. W\Q Descent of Ishtar, in Sayce's Hibbert Lectures, Lecture IV.; Budge's Babylonian Life and History ("Bye-Paths of Bible Knowledge "Series), pp. 140-142 ; Vigouroux, La Bible et les Decouvertes modernes, iii. pp. 123-132. 2 Thus F. Delitzsch, and Boscawen in British Museum Lecture, on Sheol, Death, the Grave, and Immortality. But the identification is held by others to be conjectural (Schrader, Keilimchriften, ii. p. 80 (Eng. trans.); Budge, Babylonian Life and History, p. 140, etc. ; Vigouroux, iii. p. 125). The Assyrian gives the name as Aralu. 2 Thus also in the Babylonian and Greek conceptions. Cf. Sayce, Hibbert Lectures, p. 364; Fairbairn, Studies, *'The Belief in Immortality," pp. 190, 191. 236 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. Passages in illustration : Genesis, etc. Job. The Psalms. Hezekiah. Not in this direction we are to look for doctrine of immortality : embraces idea of relation to God and resurrection. but would redeem him from that state, and restore him to life in the body.^ His hope was for resurrection. To illustrate this state of feeling and belief, in regard to the state of the separate existence of the soul, it may be well to cite one or two passages bearing on the subject. An indication of a belief in a future state of the soul is found in an expression several times met with in Genesis — " gathered to his people " ^ — where, in every instance, the gathering to the people (in " Sheol ") is definitely distinguished from the act of burial. Other evidences are afforded by the belief in necromancy, the narratives of resurrection, etc. "What kind of place " Sheol " was to the popular imagination is well represented in the words of Job — " I go whence I shall not return, Even to the land of darkness and the shadow of death, A land of thick darkness, as darkness itself, A land of the shadow of death, without any order, And where light is as darkness." ^ There was not much cheer in looking forward to an abode like this, and it is therefore not surprising that even good men, in moments of despondency, when it seemed as if God's presence and favour were taken from them, should moan as David did — ■ *' Return, Lord, deliver my soul ; Save me for Thy loving kindness' sake. For in death there is no remembrance of Thee, In Sheol who shall give Thee thanks ? " •* or with Hezekiah — ** Sheol cannot praise Thee, death cannot celebrate Thee : They that go down into the pit cannot hope for Thy truth. The living, the living, he shall praise Thee as I do this day." ^ It is not, therefore, in this direction that we are to look for the positive and cheering side of the Old Testament hope of immortality, but in quite another. It is said we have no doctrine of immortality in the Old Testament. But I reply, ^ See passages discussed below. ^ Gen. xxv. 8, 9, xxxv. 29, xlix. 29, 33. ^ Job X. 21, 22. Cf. description in Descent of Ishtar, Hibbert Lectures. 4 Ps. vi. 4, 5. ^ Isa. xxxviii. 18, 19. OLD TESTAMENT DOCTRINE OF IMMORTALITY. 237 we 1mm immortality at the very commencement — for man, as he came from the hands of his Creator was made for - _ immortal life. Man in Eden was immortal. He was intended to live, not to die. Then came sin, and with it death. Adam called his son Seth, and Seth called his son immortality Enoch, which means " frail, mortal man." Seth himself died, "' ^^^' his son died, his son's son died, and so the line of death goes on. Then comes an interruption, the intervention, as it were, of a higher law, a new inbreaking of immortality into a line New inbreak- of death. "Enoch walked with God; and he was not; io^il^sofalawoj immortality m God took him." ^ Enoch did not die. Every other life in that Enoch. record ends with the statement, " and he died " ; but Enoch's is given as an exception. He did not die, but God " took " him, i.e. without death. He simply " was not " on earth, but he " was " with God in another and invisible state of exist- ence.2 His case is thus in some respects the true type of all This the type immortality, for it is an immortality of the true personality, ^/^^^^^^^^ •^ '' ^ ''' immortality : in which the body has as real a share as the soul. It agrees embraces the with what I have advanced in the Lecture, that it is not an -^^oie person- immortality of the soul only that the Bible speaks of — that is left for the philosophers — but an immortality of the whole person, body and soul together. Such is the Christian hope, and such, as I shall now try to show, was the Hebrew hope also. It is a current view that the doctrine of the resurrection of Examination the dead was a very late doctrine among the Hebrews, ^^^^^.'^^ borrowed, as many think, from the Persians during, or sub- resurrection a sequent to, the Babylonian exile. Dr. Cheyne sees in it ^-^i'^;^ one among ^ ' "^ -^ the Hebrews: effect of Zoroastrian influence on the religion of Israel.^ My derived from opinion, on the contrary, is that it is one of the very oldest ^^^^^^"^^ ^^<^' doctrines in the Bible, the form, in fact, in which the hope Counter- of immortality was held, so far as it was held, from the days ^]^f^\- , J ' 'J this doctrine of the patriarchs downward.* In any case, it was a doctrine runs all through Old ^ Gen. V. 24. 2 So, later, Elijah. Testament. •^ Origin of Psalter, Lecture VIII. ; and papers in The Expository Times (July and August, 1891) on " Possible Zoroastrian Influences on the Religion of Israel." "* Thus also Hofmann : — "Nothing can be more erroneous than the opinion that the resurrection from the dead is a late idea, first entering through human 238 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. Beliefs of Egyptians ^ The Baby- lonians and Assyrians ; The Persians, Doubtful if this doctrine is found in older jiarts of the Zend-Avesta. Few and am- biguous refer- ences in Zoroastrian ■writings do not explain the prominence of the doctrine in the Old Testament. of very remote antiquity. We find traces of it in many ancient religions outside the Hebrew, an instructive testimony to the truth of the idea on which it rested. The Egyptians believed, e.g., that the reaniraation of the body was essential to perfected existence ; and this, according to some, was the thought that underlay the practice of embalming.^ The ancient Babylonians and Assyrians also had the idea of resurrection. One of their hymns to Merodach celebrates him as the "Merciful one among the gods, Merciful one, who restores the dead to life. " ^ The belief was probably also held by the Persians, though it it is still a disputed question whether it is found in the older portions of the Zend-Avesta. That question is not so easily settled as Dr. Cheyne thinks ; ^ but in any case the older references are few and ambiguous, and are totally inadequate to explain the remarkable prominence which this doctrine assumed in the Old Testament.* The Bible has a coherent reflection, the earliest traces of which, if not first given by the Parsees to the Jews, are to be met with in Isaiah and Ezekiel." — Schriftheweis, iii. p. 461. Cf. on this theory of Parsic influence, Pusey's Daniel, pp. 512-517. ^ "There is a chapter, with a vignette, representing the soul uniting itself to the body, and the text promises that they shall never again be separated." — Renouf, Hibbert Lectures, p. 188. "They believed," says Budge, "that the soul would revisit the body after a number of years, and therefore it was absolutely necessary that the body should be preserved, if its owner wished to live for ever with the gods." — Dwellers on the Nile, p. 156. - Cf. Boscawen, British Museum Lecture, pp. 23, 24 ; Sayce, pp. 98-100 ; Cheyne, Origin of Psalter, p, 392. There is no evidence, however, of a general hope of resurrection. ^ Cf. Pusey, pp. 512-517 ; and Cheyne's own citations from recent scholars, Origin of Psalter, pp. 425, 451. M. Montet formerly held that the germs of the doctrine came from Zoroastrianism, but "in 1890, in deference, it would seem, to M. de Harlez, and in opposition not less to Spiegel than to Gelder, he pronounces the antiquity of the resurrection doctrine in Zoroastrianism as yet unproven." — Cheyne, p. 451. Cf. Schultz, Alttest. Theol. p. 762. * Anyone can satisfy himself on this head by consulting the passages for himself in the Zend-Avesta, in Sacred Books of the East. The indices to the three volumes give only one reference to the subject, and that to one of a few undated "Miscellaneous Fragments " at the end. Professor Cheyne himself can say no more than that "Mills even thinks that there is a trace of the doctrine of the Kcsurrection in the Gathas. ... He (Zoroaster) may have had a vague conception of the revival of bodies, but not a theory." — Origin of Psalter, p. 438. OLD TESTAMENT DOCTRINE OF IMMORTALITY. 239 and consistent doctrine of its own upon the subject, and is not dependent on doubtful allusions in Zoroastrian texts for its clear and bold statements of the final swallowing up of death in victory. Let me briefly review some of the lines of evidence. I have referred already to the case of Enoch in the begin- Revieiv of ninff of the history, as illustrative of the Biblical idea of ''"'^'!'''' f ^ ^ '' earlier books. immortality. As respects the patriarchs, the references to their beliefs and hopes are necessarily few and inferential, — a fact which speaks strongly for the early date and genuine- ness of the tradition. The New Testament signalises them as men of " faith," and certainly their conduct is that of men who, accounting themselves " strangers and pilgrims " on the earth, look for a future fulfilment of the promises as of something in which they have a personal interest.^ Not improbably it was some hope of resurrection which inspired (as with the Egyptians) their great care for their dead, and prompted the injunctions left by Jacob and Joseph regarding the interment of their " bones " in the land of promise.^ It is significant that the Epistle to the Hebrews connects Abraham's Abraham. sacrifice of Isaac with his faith in a resurrection. " By faith Abraham, being tried, offered up Isaac . . . accounting that God is able to raise up, even from the dead ; from whence also he did in a parable receive him back."^ The Eabbis drew a curious inference from God's word to Abraham, " I will give to thee, and to thy seed after thee, the land wherein thou art a stranger." * " But it appears," they argued, " that Abraham and the other patriarchs did not possess that land ; therefore it is of necessity that they should be raised up to enjoy the good promises, else the promises of God should be vain and false. So that here we have a proof, not only of the immortality of the soul, but also of the foundation of the law — namely, the resurrection of the dead." ^ If \ 1 Heb. xi. 13. 2 Qen. 1. 5, 25 ; Ex. xiii. 19 ; Heb. xi. 22. •^ Heb. xi. 17-19 ; cf. Hofmann, pp. 461-462. •* Gen. xvii. 8. ^ Quoted in Fairbairn, i. p. 353. Moses—'^Iajn the God" etc. 240 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. this be thought fanciful, I would refer to the teaching of a greater than the Eabbis. Reasoning with the Saddu- The words to cecs, Jesus quotcs that saying of God to Moses, " I am the God of Abraham, and the God of Isaac, and the God of Jacob," adding, " God is not the God of the dead, but of the living." ^ The point to be observed is that Jesus quotes this passage, not simply in proof of the continued subsistence of the patriarchs in some state of being, but in proof of the resurrection of the dead. And how does it prove that ? Only on the ground, which Jesus assumes, that the relation of the believer to God carries with it a whole immortality, and this, as we have seen, implies life in the body. If God is the God of Abraham and Isaac and Jacob, this covenant relation pledges to these patriarchs not only continuance of existence, but Eedemption from the power of death, i.e. resurrection. It is, however, when we come to the later books — the Book of Job, the Psalms, the Prophets — that we get clearer light on the form which the hope of immortality assumed in the minds of Old Testament believers ; and it may be affirmed with considerable confidence that this light is all, or nearly all, in favour of the identification of this hope with the hope of resurrection. I take first the Book of Job, because, whenever written, it relates to patriarchal times, or at least moves in patriarchal conditions. The first rem^ark- able passage in this book is in chapter xiv. This chapter raises the very question we are now dealing with, and it is noteworthy that the form in which it does so is the possibility anticipation 0/ ^^ bodily revival. First, Job enumerates the appearances resurrection. , t • . / h. which seem hostile to mans livmg again (vers. 7-12). Then faith, rising in her very extremity, reasserts herself against doubt and fear — " Oh that Thou wouldest hide me in Sheol, That Thou wouldest keep me secret, till Thy wrath be past, That Thou wouldest appoint me a set time, and remember me ! The later books : Joby Psalms, Prophets. Book of Job pictU7'e of patriarchal conditions. /ob xiv. .* 1 Matt. xxii. 23. OLD TESTAMENT DOCTRINE OE IMMORTALITY. 241 If a man die, shall he live again ? All the days of my warfare would I wait, Till my release should come. Thou shouldest call, and I would answer Thee, Thou wouldest have a desire to the work of Thy hands." ^ There seems no reasonable room for question that what is Dr. DavU- before Job's mind here is the thought of resurrection. Dr. -^^'^'-^ ^^'^^^ A. B. Davidson explains : " On this side death he has no hope of a return to God's favour. Hence, contemplating that he shall die under God's anger, his thought is that he might remain in Sheol till God's wrath be past, for He keepeth not His anger for ever ; that God would appoint him a period to remain in death, and then remember him with returning mercy, and call him back again to His fellowship. But to his mind this involves a complete return to life again of the whole man (ver. 14), for in death there is no fellowship with God (Ps. vi. 5). Thus his solution, though it appears to his mind only as a momentary gleam of light, is broader than that of the Psalmist, and corresponds to that made known in subsequent Revelation." ^ The second passage in Job is the well-known one in /^^xix. 25-27: chapter xix., translated in the Eevised Version thus — resurrection again implied. "But I know that my Redeemer liveth. And that He shall stand up at the last upon the earth [Heb. dufit\ And after my skin hath been thus destroyed, Yet from my flesh shall I see God : Whom I shall see for myself, And mine eyes shall behold, and not another."^ I do not enter into the many difficulties of this passage, but refer only to the crucial line, " Yet from my flesh shall I see God." The margin gives as another rendering, "without ^' in'' or my flesh," but this is arrived at only as an interpretation ''^^J'''^"^ 1 Job xiv. 13-15 (R. v.). The margin translates as in A.V., '*Thou shalt call," etc. As remarked, the form in which the question is put in this passage is as significant as the answer to it. It implies that revived existence in the body is the only form in which the patriarch contemplated immortality. Life and even sensation in Sheol are presupposed in ver. 22. 2 Com. on Job, in loc. (Cambridge Series). I can scarcely agree that Job's solution is broader than that of the psalmist's. See below. 3 Job xix. 25-27. 16 242 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW, of the word " from," which is literally the one used. The natural meaning would therefore seem to be, " Yet from (or out of) my flesh shall I see God," which implies that he will be clothed with flesh.^ Dr. Davidson allows the admissibility of this rendering, and says : " If therefore we understand the words ' from my flesh ' in the sense of in my flesh, we must suppose that Job anticipated being clothed in a new body after death. Something may be said for this view. Un- doubtedly, in chapter xiv. 13 sec^., Job clearly conceived the idea of being delivered from Sheol and living again, and fervently prayed that such a thing might be. And what he there ventured to long for, he might here speak of as a thing of which he was assured. No violence would be done to the line of thought in the book by this supposition." Yet he thinks " it is highly improbable that the great thought of the resurrection of the body could be referred to in a way so brief," and so prefers the rendering " without." ^ I think, however, this is hardly a sufficient reason to outweigh the tremendously strong fact that we have already this thought of resurrection conceded in chapter xiv., and, further, that the thought of living again in the body seemed the only way in which Job there could conceive the idea of immortahty. If that is so, it may explain why more stress is not laid upon resurrection here. The hope which absorbs all Job's thought is that of " seeing God," and the fact that, if he does so at all, he must do it " in " or " from " the flesh, is taken for granted as a thing of course.^ The Psalms : The question of the testimony of the Psalms is greatly Dr, Cieynes ^y^-^\]^Q^ y^j \\^q large concessions which writers like Dr. Cheyne are now ready to make, in the belief that by admitting references to resurrection doctrine they prepare the The passages way for the proof of " Zoroastrian influences." The passages, that teach immortality ^ Cf. Pusey, p. 508, and Vigouroux, iii. pp. 172-180. imply resur- ^ Commentary on Job, Appendix on chap. xix. 23-27, p. 292. rection, ^ Dr. Davidson's remark, "On Old Testament ground, and in the situation of Job, such a matter-of-course kind of reference is almost inconceivable" (p. 292), involves the very point at issue. OLD TESTAMENT DOCTRINE OF IMMORTALITY. 243 however, are happily of an order that speak for themselves, and need no forcing to yield us their meaning. A con- spicuous example is Ps. xvi. 8-11, cited in the New Testa- /v. xvi. 8-ir. ment as a prophecy of the resurrection of Christ — " I have set the Lord always before me : Because He is at my right hand, I shall not be moved. Therefore my heart is glad, and my glory rejoiceth ; My flesh also shall dwell in safety (or confidently)^ For Thou wilt not leave my soul to Sheol ; Neither wilt Thou suffer Thine Holy One to see corruption (or the pit). Thou wilt show me the path of life : In Thy presence is fulness of joy ; In Thy right hand there are pleasures for evermore." ^ Another passage is in Psalm xvii. 15, where, after describ- /v. xvii. 15. ing the apparent prosperity of the wicked, the Psalmist says — "As for me, I shall behold Thy face in righteousness : I shall be satisfied, when I awake, with Thy likeness." The " awakening " here, as Delitzsch says, can only be that from the sleep of death.^ Yet more distinct is Ps. xlix. Ps. xiix. 14, 14, 15— '5. "They (the wicked) are appointed as a fleck for Slaeol; Death shall be their shepherd : And the upright shall have dominion over them in the morning ; And their beauty shall be for Sheol to consume, that there be no habitation for it. But God will redeem my soul from the power (hand) of Sheol : For He shall receive me." There is here again, it is believed, clear reference to the " morning " of the resurrection. The passage is the more significant that in the last words, as well as in Ps. Ixxiii. 24, there is direct allusion to the case of Enoch. " * God,' says References to the Psalmist, ' shall redeem my soul from the hand of Hades, ^''''^' '^'''^'' 1 See Acts ii. 24-31. Cf. Delitzsch, in loc. ; and Cheyne, Origin of the Psalter, p. 431. '^ Com., in loc. Thus also Pusey, Perowne, Cheyne, Hofmann, etc. "The awakening," says Cheyne, "probably means the i)assing of the soul into a resurrection body." — Orhjin of Psalter, p. 407. 244 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. for He shall take me/ as He took Enoch, and as He took Fs. Ixxiii. 24. Elijah, to Hhnself."^ Ps. Ixxiii. 24 reads thus — ** Nevertheless I am continually with Thee : Thou hast holden my right hand. Thou shalt guide me with Thy counsel, And afterward receive me to glory. Whom have I in heaven but Thee ? And there is none on the earth that I desire beside Thee. My flesh and my heart faileth : But God is the strength of my heart and my portion for ever. " These, and a few others, are the passages usually cited in favour of the doctrine of immortality in the Book of Psalms, and it will be seen that in all of them this hope is clothed in a form which implies a resurrection.^ The prophetic I need not delay on the passages in the prophetic books. the idea ^^^ j^^^.^ -^^ -g ^g^ja^jiy rrranted that the idea of resurrection is of resurrection '' ^ familiar. familiar. Not only is the restoration of the Jewish people frequently presented under this figure, but a time is coming when, for the Church as a whole, including the individuals in it, death shall be swallowed up in victory. We have a Hosea vi. 2, passage already in Hosea, which is beyond suspicion of xiu. 14. Zoroastrian influence — ' ' After two days will He revive us : On the third day, He will raise us up, and we shall live before Him." And again^ I will ransom them from the power of Sheol I will redeem them from death : ^ Perowne, in loc. Thus also Pusey, Delitzsch, Cheyne, etc. "The 'dawn,'" says Cheyne, "is that of the resurrection day." — Expositoi-y Times, ii. p. 249 ; cf. Origin of Psalter, pp. 382, 406, 407. Delitzsch, in note on Ps. xvi. 8-11, says : "Nor is the awakening in xlix:. 15 some morning or other that will very soon follow upon the night, but the final morning, which brings deliverance to the upright, and enables them to obtain dominion." 2 Or if not resurrection, then immortality in the body without tasting of death, as Enoch. But this is a hope the Old Testament believer could hardly have cherished for himself. The view of delivei-ance from death seems there- fore the more probable in Ps. xlix. 15, etc. A very different view is taken by Schultz in his Alttestamentliche Theologie, pp. 753-758. Schult^ not only sees no proof of the resurrection in the passages we have quoted, but will not even allow that they have any reference to a future life. So extreme a view surely refutes itself. It is at least certain that if these passages teach a future life, it is a life in connection with the body. OLD TESTAMENT DOCTRINE OF IMMORTALITY. 245 _____ death, where are thy plagues ? grave, where is thy destruction ? " ^ The climax of this class of passages is reached in Isa. xxv. Isa. xxv. 6-8, ^-^, xxvi. 19. Cf. also Ezek. xxxvii. 1-10, the vision of ''^^^- '9, ^^^. the dry bones.^ The last Old Testament passage I will quote is an undis- puted one, and has the special feature of interest that in it for the first time mention is made of the resurrection of the wicked as well as of the just It is that in Dan. xii. 2 — Dan. xii. 2. " And many of them that sleep in the dust of the earth shall awake, some to everlasting life, and some to shame and ever- lasting contempt." This needs no comment. From the whole survey I think it will be evident that I After all only was entitled to say that from the first the manner in which '^ ^f^^"?"'"'^ on believer s the hope of immortality was conceived by holy men in relation to God, Israel was that of a resurrection. Yet, when all is said, we cannot but feel that it was but a Iwpe — not resting on express Eevelation, but springing out of the consciousness of the in- dissoluble relation between God and the believing soul, and the conviction that God's Redemption will be a complete one. Life and immortality were not yet brought to light as they are now by Christ in His Gospel.^ The matter is unexception- ably stated by Dr. A. B. Davidson in the following words, with which I conclude : " The human spirit is conscious of Dr. Davidson fellowship with God ; and this fellowship, from the nature of ^''^^^^^• God, is a thing imperishable, and, in spite of obscurations, it must yet be fully manifested by God. This principle, 1 Hos. vi. 2, xiii. 14. Cf. Cheyne, p. 383. ^ On the passages in Isaiah, Cheyne remarks: "Instead of swallowing up, Sheol in the Messianic period shall itself be swallowed up. And this prospect concerns not merely the Church -nation, but all of its believing members, and indeed all, whether Jews or not, who submit to the true King, Jehovah." — Origin of Psalter, p. 402. Cf. Expository Times, ii. p. 226. In Ezekiel, the subject is national resurrection, but "that the power of God can, against all liuman thought and hope, reanimate the dead, is the general idea of the passage, from which consequently the hope of a literal resurrection of the dead may naturally be inferred." — Oehler, Theology of Old TestaTnent, ii. p. 395 (Eug. trans.). Oehler does more justice to these passages than Schultz.^ - 1 Tim. i. 10. 246 THE POSTULATE OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW. grasped with convulsive earnestness in the prospect of death, became the Hebrew doctrine of immortality. This doctrine was but the necessary corollary of religion. In this life the true relations of men to God were felt to be realised ; and the Hebrew faith of immortality — never a belief in the mere existence of the soul after death, for the lowest superstition assumed this — was- a faith that the dark and mysterious event of death would not interrupt the life of the person with God, enjoyed in this world. . . . The doctrine of immor- tality in the book (of Job) is the same as that of other parts of the Old Testament. Immortality is the corollary of reliorion. If there be religion — that is, if God be — there is immortality, not of the soul, but of the whole personal being of man (Ps. xvi. 9). This teaching of the whole Old Testa- ment is expressed by our Lord with a surprising incisiveness in two sentences — ' I am the God of Abraham. God is not the God of the dead but of the living! " ^ ^ Commentary on Job, Appendix, pp. 293-295. LECTURE VI. Efje Central Assertion of tlje ffl:i)rtsttan Uieto— tlje Incarnation of ffioU in fiTljrfet^ "With historical science, the life of Jesus takes its place in the great stream of the world's history ; He is a human individual, who became what He was, and was to be, through the living action of ideas and the circumstances of His time, and He, as a mighty storm-wave which has arisen through the conflict of forces, is destined to sink once more into the smooth sea in the restless whirl of earthly things, quietly subsiding from the general life of humanity, in order to make room for new and stronger throes and creations. Here, in the Church, He is the rock which rules over the flood, instead of being moved by it. . . . He, the pillar, the Son of God, will survey humanity, however far and wide it may extend, permitting it only to hold fast by Him, or to wreck itself against Him." — Keim. *' But Thee, but Thee, Sovereign Seer of time. But Thee, poet's Poet, wisdom's tongue. But Thee, man's best Man, love's best Love, perfect life in perfect labour writ, all men's Comrade, Servant, King, or Priest,— What if ov yet, wliat mole, what flaw, what lapse, What least defect or shadow of defect, What rumour, tattled by an enemy, Of inference loose, what lack of grace Even in torture's grasp, or sleep's, or death's, — Oh, what amiss may I forgive in Tliee, Jesus, good Paragon, thou crystal Christ." Sidney Lanier. LECTUKE YL THE CENTRAL ASSERTION OF THE CHRISTIAN VIEW THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST. In the second Lecture I conducted an historical argument Co77ipietion of intended to show that there is really no intermediate position ^^^'"f^^ ■*■ second in which the mind can logically rest between the admission Lectzire. of a truly Divine Christ and a purely humanitarian view. This argument I have now to complete, by showing that the necessity which history declares to exist arises from the actual state of the facts in the Christian Eevelation. We have seen what the alternative is, and we have now to ask why it is so. Why is it that we cannot rest in' a conception of Christ ^^\^hy cannot simply a prophet of a higher order ? or as a God-filled man ^^ ^^-^^ "^ ^ ^ J ^ ^ » i^^^^^ concep- in whom the Divine dwelt as it dwells in no other? or ^'& tion of Christ? the central Personage of our race, at once ideal man and the Eevelation to us of the absolute principle of religion ? These views seem plausible ; they are accepted by many ; they seem at first sight to bring Christ nearer to us than on the supposition of His true God-manhood ; why cannot the mind of the Church rest in them ? Must not the explanation be that, taking into account the sum-total of the facts of Christianity, they refuse to square with any subordinate view, but compel us to press up to the higher conception ? / This is what I affirm, and I propose in this Lecture to test the question by an examination of the facts themselves. There is, I know, in some minds, an insuperable objection, a p'iori, to the acceptance of the fact of the Incarnation, 250 CENTRAL ASSERTION OE CHRISTIAN VIEW. A priori objection to the Incarnation based on Christ's lowliness. Comparison with the assertions of liberal theologians and evolutionists. arising from the lowliness of Christ's earthly origin and condition. Can we believe, it is said, that in this historical individual, Jesus of Nazareth — this son of a carpenter — God actually became incarnate ; that in this humble man, so poor in all His earthly surroundings, there literally dwelt the fulness of the Godhead bodily ? Is the thought not on the face of it incredible ? The appeal here is to our powers of imagination — of conceiving — to our sense of the likelihood or unlikelihood of things ; and to enable us to judge fairly of that appeal, and of its nature as an objection to the In- carnation, a great many things would have to be taken into account, both before and after. I would only say that as regards a certain class who make that objection — the higher class of liberal theologians especially — the question seems only one of degree. Tf Christ is, in any case, as most of them affirm, the central, typical, religiously greatest individual of the race ; if the principle of the absolute religion is manifested in Him, as Pfleiderer allows ; ^ if He is the ideally-perfect man in whom the God-consciousness finds its fullest expression, as Schleier- macher declares f if He is alone the sinless Personality of the race, as even Lipsius will grant,^ — these are already remarkable claims, and as compared with His lowly appearance and mean historical environment create almost as great a feeling of strangeness as on the supposition of His true Divinity. Or let us suppose that the objection comes from the evolutionist. Then contrast the strangeness he speaks of with that of his own views. His objection is, that he cannot believe that in this lowly Man of Nazareth there should reside all the potentialities of Divinity. But what does he ask us to believe ? He goes back to the primitive state of things, and there, in that little speck of jelly at the first dawn of life, — in that humble drop of protoplasmic matter buried in some oozy slime, — he bids us believe that there lies wrapped up, ^ Cf. his Grundriss, sees. 128, 129. ^ Der chrisll. Qlauhe, ii. sees. 93, 94. ' Dogmatik, sec. 651. THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST. 251 ^ only waiting for development, the promise and potency of the whole subsequent evolution of life. In that first germ-cell there lies enfolded — latent — not only the whole wealth of vegetable existence, not only the long procession of future races and species of lower and higher animals, with their bodily powers and mental instincts, but, in addition, the later possibilities of humanity ; all that has now come to light in human development — the wealth of genius, the riches of civilisation, the powers of intellect, imagination, and heart, the treasures of human love and goodness, of poetry and art — the genius of Dante, of Shakespeare, of Milton — the spiritual greatness and holiness of Christ Himself; — all, in a word, that has ever come out of man is supposed by the evolutionist to have been potentially present from the first in that little primitive speck of protoplasm ! ^ I confess that, putting his assertion alongside the Christian one, I do not feel that there is much to choose between them in point of strangeness. But evolution, he would tell us, is not deprived of its truth by the strangeness at first sight of its assertion — neither is the Christian view. The question is not one to be settled a 'priori, but to be brought to the test of facts. T. Godet has said, " Christianity is entirely based upon /. Testimony Christ's consciousness of Himself, and it is the heroism of '^-\ ^f,. ' apostolic age faith to rest upon the extraordinary testimony which this as throwing Being gave to Himself." 2 This must be so, for the reason ^5^^. ''J' ^ Christ s own which Christ Himself gives, that He alone has the knowledge claims. which qualifies Him to give a true estimate of Himself. " For T know," He said to the Jews, " whence I came, and whither I go ; but ye know not whence I came, or whither I ^ Tyndall carries back this promise and potency to tlie original fire-mist. "For what are the core and essence of this hypothesis? Strip it naked, and you stand face to face with the notion that not alone the more ignoble forms of aoimalcular or animal life, not alone the nobler forms of the horse and lion, not alone the exquisite and wonderful mechanism of the human body, but that the human mind itself— emotion, intellect, will, and all their phenomena— were once latent in a fiery cloud." — Fragments, ii. p. 132. 2 Commentary on John, ii. p. 315 (Eng. trans.). 252 CENTRAL ASSERTION OF CHRISTIAN VIEW. Prerogatives which the early church assigned to Christ. go." ^ I propose, however, to begin at a point further down — that to which our first written documents belong — and to ask, What was the view of Christ's Person held in the apostolic age ? The testimony of that age is clearly one of great importance, as throwing light on Christ's own claims. When men say, Buddha also was raised to the rank of Divinity by his followers, though he himself made no such claim, I answer that the cases are not parallel. It was only long centuries after his death, and within limited circles, that Buddha was regarded as Divine ; b-ut one short step takes us from the days when Christ Himself liv^d and taught on earth into the midst of a Church, founded by His apostles, which in all its branches worshipped and adored Him as the veritable Son of God made manifest on earth fe apostolic Church a practically consentient view existed of Christ's Person, this, of itself, is a strong reason for beli-eving that it rested on claims made by Christ Himself, and rose naturally out of the facts of His historical self-manifestation.^ I begin with the broad fact which none can dispute, that, in the first age of Christianity, Christ was universally regarded as one who had risen from the dead, who had ascended on high to the right hand of God, who exercised there a goverument of the world, who was to return again to judge the quick and dead, and who, on these grounds, was the object of worship and prayer in all the churches.^ This view of Christ is found in every book of the New Testament, — in the Acts, in the Pauline Epistles, in Hebrews, in Peter, in the Book of Eevelation, in the Epistles of John, and James, and Jude, — and is so generally acknowledged to be there, that I do not need to delay in quoting special texts. But even so much as this cannot be admitted, without implying that in the faith of the 1 John viii. 14. ^ A good summary of the apostolic evidence will be seen in Dr. Whitelaw's How is the Divinity of Jesus depicted in the Gospels and Epistles ? ^ Cf. Weiss's Bih. Theol. of the Neiv Testament, pp. 177-181 (Eng. trans.); Harnack's Dogmengeschichte, i. pp. 66-68. THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST. 253 _ early Church, Christ was no mere man, but a supernatural Personage, i.e. that the Ebionitic view was not the primitive one. Think only of what is implied in this one claim to be The claim to the Judge of the world — the arbiter of the everlasting -^"^^"^ ^'^^ . . world. destinies of mankind.^ There is no point on which the writers of the New Testament are more absolutely unanimous than this — that Christ shall come again to be our Judge ; and whether the early Christians analysed all that was involved in this belief or not, there can be no doubt in the mind of anyone who has analysed it that it involved the possession of attributes which can belong only to God {e.g. omniscience). Or take the other outstanding fact of worship paid to Christ — such, e.g., as we find in the Book of Eevelation. The idea of Divine honours externally conferred on one who is essentially but man is quite foreign to the lN"ew Testament ; and the only alternative is, to suppose that Christ was from the first regarded as having a supernatural and Divine side to His Person — as being essentially Divine. As regards the apostolic testimony, the ground is happily Modem cleared in modern times by the large measure of general ^s:''^^^"^^^^ as to general agreement which exists among impartial exegetes as to the teaching of nature of the doctrines taught in the several books. The old ^^"'^ TT • • 1 1 • T 1 /¥> Testament Unitarian glosses on passages which seemed to affirm the books— the Divinity of Christ are now seldom met with ; and it is freely >''^^^''"'"^ admitted that the bulk of the New Testament writings teach '"* ' a doctrine of Christ's Person practically as high as the Church has ever affirmed. For instance, it is no longer disputed by any competent authority that, in Paul and John, it is the supernatural view of Christ's Person that is given. As to John — using that name at present for the author of the Fourth Gospel and related Epistles — his doctrine of Christ is of the highest. This is admitted by the most negative critics, e.g. by Dr. Martineau, who says that the phrase " Son of God " Martineau on 1 Cf. Balden sperger, i)a.s SelbstheAcusstsein Jesu, p. 152. "How does such a '^ ivmi yof claim, fit into the frame of a human consciousness ? Such an assumption lies in j^ ^ j /^ fact beyond all our experience, also beyond the highest religious experience," ''"^ ^ ^■^■' ^ ' etc. 254 CENTRAL ASSERTION OF CHRISTIAN VIEW, The Epistles ofPmil— I. The undisputed Epistles. applied to the pre-existing Word in the Fourth Gospel, leaves all finite analogies behind. " The oneness with God which it means to mark is not such resembling reflex of the Divine thought and character as men or angels may attain, but identity of essence, constituting Him not god-like alone, but God. Others may be children of God in a moral sense ; but by this right of elemental nature, none but He ; He is, herein, the only Son ; so little separate, so close to the inner Divine life which He expresses, that He is in the bosom of the Father. This language undoubtedly describes a great deal more than such harmony of will and sympathy of affection as may subsist between finite obedience and its infinite Inspirer ; it denotes two natures homogeneous, entirely one ; and both so essential to the Godhead that neither can be omitted from any truth you speak of it. . . . It was one and the same Logos that in the beginning was with God, who in due time appeared in human form, and showed forth the Father's pure perfections in relation to mankind, who then returned to His eternal life, with the spiritual ties unbroken which He brought from His finished work." ^ In this Gospel, therefore, the question is not so much as to the doctrine taught, but as to whether the evangelist has given us an authentic record of what Christ said and did. On this question, so far as it is affected by the Christology, it will be well to reserve our judgment till we see whether the other writings of the apostolic age do not give us — or yield by implication — quite as high a view of Christ's Person as that which creates offence in John, To aid us in determining this question there lie first to hand the writings, above alluded to, of the Apostle Paul. Here, again, it is not seriously doubted that in Paul's un- disputed Epistles we have as clear and strong an assertion of Christ's Divine dignity as we could well desire. That, in ^ Stat of Authority, pp. 428-429. Biedermann, Lipsius, Pfleiderer, Reuss, R^ville, etc., all agree in their estimate of John's doctrine. Wendt {Die Lehre Jesu, ii. pp. 450-476), seems to go back, and to explain the expressions in John only of an ethical Sonship. Cf. Appendix, THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST, 255 -^ Paul's theology, Christ had a heavenly pie-existence ;^ that the title " Son of God " applies to Him in this pre-existent state ; that He was a being of Divine essence ; that He mediated the creation of the world ; that in the fulness of time He took on Him human nature ; that now, since His death and resurrection, He has been exalted again to Divine power and glory — all this the most candid exegetes now admit. A new turn, however, has been given in recent years to this theology of Paul by the fancy of some theologians that this heavenly, pre-existent essence of the earlier Pauline Epistles —the " Son of God " who became incarnate in Christ — is not a second Divine Person, as we understand that expression, but a pre-existent " heavenly man," a being apparently of subordinate rank, at once the perfect spiritual image of God and the heavenly prototype of humanity — a conception easier to state than to make intelligible. This " heavenly The man" theory, as we may call it, has been seized on with "^^f^^^^-^ •^ "^ Man" theory. avidity by many as the true key to the Pauline Christology.^ Beyschlag of Halle adopts it as the basis of his own theory, — in this, however, differing from the others, that he attributes only an ideal pre-existence to this heavenly principle,^ while the majority admit that what Paul had in view was a real and personal pre-existence. This whole hypothesis of the " heavenly man " I can only regard as a new-fangled conceit of exegesis, resting practically on one passage — that in which Paul speaks of " the second man from heaven," * — and in diametric opposition to the general teaching of the Epistles. It is an hypothesis, therefore, which finds no countenance 1 See Note A. — The Doctrine tjf Pre-Existence. 2 It goes back to Baur, and to Ritschl, Entstehung, p. 80 (1857), and has been adopted by Holsten, Hilgenfeld, Biedermann, Lipsms, Pfleiderer, etc. Bieder- mann states it succinctly thus: — "The Person, the I of Christ, has already, before His appearance in the earthly corporeity, in the flesh, pre-existed in a pre-earthly condition with God as the iIkuv &iov, as the human image of God, and consequently as the archetypal pattern of humanity ; thus is He the Son of God. . . . The appearance of Christ in the world, sent by God in love, is not a becoming man, but a coming of the heavenly, pneumatic Man in the Hesh." — Dogmatik, ii. pp. 93, 97. » Christologie, pp. 225-226, 243. * 1 Cor. xv. 47 (R.V.). 2:; 6 CENTRAL ASSERTION OF CHRISTIAN VIEW, 2. The later Epistles— Christology of Philippians, etc. Substantial unity of doctrine in later and earlier Epistles. from more sober expositors like Meyer, "Weiss, or Eeuss, all of whom recognise in Paul's " Son of God " a Being truly Divine.^ Christ indeed, in Paul's view, has humanity, but it is not a humanity which He brought with Him from heaven, but a humanity which He assumed when He came to earth. The argument for the " heavenly man " theory completely breaks down if we take into account the later Epistles — especially Philippians, Ephesians, and Colossians, the genuine- ness of which there are no good grounds for disputing.- Pfleiderer, who advocates this theory, admits the genuineness of the Epistle to the Philippians, but there we have the strongest assertion of Christ's pre-existent Divinity. The whole argument in chap. ii. 5-11, turns on Christ's original condition of Divine glory — " being in the form of God " — and His voluntary abdication of it to take upon Him " the form of a servant" — "being made in the likeness of men" — "being found in fashion as a man." ^ As to the teaching of the Epistles to the Colossians and the Ephesians, there is no dispute, even among the friends of this theory. In these Epistles, says Lipsius, " Christ, as the image of God and the first-born of the whole creation, is an essentially Divine Personality, and the Mediator of the creation of the world." ^ Pfleiderer sees, or imagines he sees, in them the same influence of the Philonic Logos doctrine as is traceable in the Gospel of John^ — an indirect witness that between the theology of Paul in these Epistles and that of the Fourth Gospel, there is no essential difference. But though the Christology of the later Epistles is admittedly more developed than that of the earlier Epistles, the doctrine of Christ in both is substantially one.^ In both, Christ was " the Son of 1 See Weiss's criticism in Biblical Theology, i. pp. 410-412, and ii. p. 100 ; Meyer on 1 Cor. xv. 47 ; Corner, System of Doctrine, iii. pp. 175-176. 2 Renan, Reuss, Sabatier, Weiss, etc., accept them all as Pauline. ^ Cf. Bruce's Humiliation of Christ (Cunningham Lectures), pp. 21-28, 403-411. ■* Dogmatik, p. 453. ^ Urchristenthnm, pp. 676, 695. « Cf. Schmid, Bib. Theol. of New Testament, pp. 469-478 (Eiig. trans.). THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST. 257 God," eternally pre-existing in a state of glory with the Father, who, in the fulness of time, moved by love, became incarnate for our salvation.^ In both — as also in John — He existed before the creation of the world, and was the agent in its creation.^ That He is the centre of the Divine purpose, and therefore the One for whom all things as well as by whom all things, are made, is a doctrine as clearly taught in the Epistles to the Eomans and the Corinthians as in those to the Colossians and the Ephesians.^ In both, the divine name Kvpio^ is freely given to Him ; passages applied in the Old Testament to Jehovah are applied to Him also ; Divine honour is paid to Him ; He is exalted to a Divine sovereignty of the world ;* His name is constantly joined with that of the Father as the source of grace and peace in the introductions to the Epistles,^ and again with those of the Father and of the Spirit in the apostolic benediction ; ^ it is declared of Him that, as Judge, He has the attribute of the Divine searcher of hearts.^ Taking all the facts into account, and remembering how inconsonant it would have been with Paul's rigorous Monotheism to attribute Divine honours to a Being not truly Divine, it seems impossible to doubt that, in the view of the Apostle, Christ was truly a Divine Person, one in essence, though distinct in Person from the Father.^ But the most remarkable circumstance of all is — and it is a 1 2 Cor. viii. 9 ; Gal. iv. 4. 2 i Qq^^ ^^ g_ ^ Cf. Kom. i. 1-4, xvi. 25-27 ; 1 Cor. viii. 6. Bishop Lightfoot says : "The absolute universal mediation of the Son is declared as unreservedly in this passage from the First Epistle to the Corinthians ( ' One Lord Jesus Christ ; through whom are all things, and we through Him '), as in any later statement of the apostle ; and, if all the doctrinal and practical inferences which it implicitly involves were not directly emphasised at this early date, it was because the circumstances did not yet require explicitness on these points." — Commentary on Colossians, pp. 188, 189. ^ Cf. on above statements, Weiss, Biblical Theology, i. pp. 390-393. ^ Rom. i. 7 ; 1 Cor. i. 3 ; 2 Cor. i. 2 ; Gal. i. 3. 6 2 Cor. xiii. 14. 7 Rom. ii. 16 ; 1 Cor. iv. 5. ^ It is a noteworthy circumstance that nearly all the modern scholars agree in that interpretation of the strongest passage of all, Eom. ix. 5, "who is over all, God blessed for ever, Amen," which makes it refer to Christ. Thus, e.g., Tiothe, Lipsius, Pfleiderer, Kitschl, Schultz, Weiss, etc. 17 258 CENTRAL ASSERTION 01^ CHRISTIAN VIEW. point which I desire specially to emphasise — that in pro^ Paul assumes pounding these high views of Christ's Person, Paul in no case LT? °^^^ speaks or argues as one teaching a new doctrine, but through- doctrine is the out takes it for granted that his reader s estimate of the same as that \jy^^^ diojnitv is the same as his own. He gives no indication of the Churches . ° . to zuhich he in thcsc letters that he preached or contended for a higher rvntes. view of Christ's Person than that which was currently received.^ He has no monopoly of this truth, but assumes it as the common possession of the Church. He argues at length for the doctrine of justification by faith, but we never find him arguing for the Divinity of Christ. Whether writing to his own converts, or to churches he had never seen, he uses the same language on this subject, and apparently anticipates no doubt or contradiction on the part of his readers. "What inference can we draw, but that the doctrine of Christ's Person in the early Church was anything but Ebionitic, — that from the first a Divine dignity was ascribed to Christ ? The Epistle Paul's Epistlcs, howcver, are not the only witnesses on le e red)s ^j^j^ point of apostolic theoloQfV. Essentially the same an independent r x: gj j 7vitness. doctrine we find in the Epistle to the Hebrews, long attributed to Paul, but now almost universally assigned to another author. It has, therefore, the value of an independent witness. The Epistle is further valuable for its early date, most critics unhesitatingly referring it to the period before the destruction of Jerusalem, probably about a.d. QQ} But here, though the writer's standpoint is somewhat different from both Paul's and John's, we find precisely the same doctrine as before, — Jesus, the Divine Son of God, the effulgence of the Father's glory and very image of His substance, the Creator, upholder, and heir of all things, who, because the children were par- takers of flesh and blood, Himself likewise partook of the ^ Cf. Eeuss, History of Christian Theology, i. p. 397 (P^ng. trans.). The passage is quoted below. 2 Cf. Weiss, Introduction to New Testament, ii, p. 31 (Eng, trans.) ; Dr. A. B. Davidson, Hebrews, etc. A few, like Pfleiderer (who, however, thinks Apollos may have been the author), date it later. — Crchristenthum, p. G29. THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST. 259 __ same, and is now again exalted to the right hand of the Majesty on high.^ Further, in teaching this high Christo- logical view, the author is not conscious any more than Paul of bringing in a new doctrine. He stands rather upon the ground of the common Christian confession, which he exhorts the Hebrews to hold fast.^ It is conceded, however, that in the main the Christology The of the Epistle to the Hebrews is of the Pauline type, and the ^^''''^yP'' . ■•' ^ as representing question arises — Have we anywhere a witness of another ajewish- type, showing how the Person of Christ was viewed in the ^^^^^^^^" . . standpoint. distinctively Jewish, as contrasted with the Gentile sections of the Church ? The answer is given in another book of the apostolic age, the early date of which is one of the articles of the modern creed, and which is supposed by some — e.g. by Volkmar — to have been written expressly with the view of opposing Paul.^ I refer to the Apocalypse. By common consent of the modern school of critics, this book was composed immediately after the death of Xero,* and its anti-- Pauline character is not only admitted, but insisted on. Here, then, we have what may be regarded as a representative early Jewish-Christian writing ; and the question is of deep interest. What kind of view of Christ's Person do we find in it ? And the answer must be given that the doctrine of The doctrine Christ in the Apocalypse is as high, or nearly as high, as it is ^J^^^/ in either Paul or John. Picuss, who is certainly an un- high as John's prejudiced witness, has some remarks here which are worth ^^ ^^^^^^~ Neuss, quoting as corroborative of the previous line of argument, pjiciderer. " We may here observe," he says, " that the writings of Paul, 1 Cf. Weiss, ii. pp. 186-190; Reuss, ii. pp. 243, 244. Eeuss says: "It is clear from the figures chosen that the intention of the theology is to establish at once the Divinity and the plurality of the Persons in the Godhead, side by side with the monotheistic principle." 2 Heb. iv. 14. ^ Pfleiderer shares this view. See it criticised by Reuss, Christian Theology, i. pp. 308-312. Pfleiderer thinks, too, that the passage in Matthew, "Whoso- ever, therefore, shall break one of these least commandments," etc. (Matt, v, 19), is a blow aimed at Paul's antinomianism ! — Hibbert Lectures, p. 178. ^ "It is pow pretty generally acknowledged that the date of this book is the year 68-69 A. d."— Pfleiderer, Hibbert Lectures, p. 153. 2 6o CENTRAL ASSERTION OF CHRISTIAN VIEW. which carry us back, so to speak, into the very cradle of the Church, contain nothing to indicate that their Christological doctrine, so different from that of common Ebionitism, was regarded as an innovation, or gave rise to any disputations at the time of its first appearance. But we have in our hands another book, essentially Judseo - Christian, which gives emphatic support to our assertion. This is the Book of Eevelation. ... It ought unhesitatingly to be acknowledged that Christ is placed in the Eevelation on a par with God. He is called the First and the Last, the Beginning and the End, and these same expressions are used to designate the Most High." 1 Professor Pfleiderer is another critic who puts this point so strongly and unambiguously, that I cannot do better than give his words. " As, according to Paul," he says, " Christ has been exalted to the regal dignity of Divine dominion over all, so, according to our author, He has taken His seat on the throne by the side of His Father, participating therefore in His Divine dominion and power — He is the Lord of the churches, holds their stars, or guardian angels, in His hand, and is also Euler of nations and King of kings, the all-wise and almighty Judge of the nations ; indeed, to Him is due a worship similar to that of God Himself. As the author of the Apocalypse, in his apotheosis of Christ as an object of worship, thus almost outstrips Paul, neither does he in his dogmatic definitions of Christ's nature at all fall behind the Apostle. Like Paul, he calls Christ the ' Son of God ' in the metaphysical sense of a godlike spiritual being, and far beyond the merely theocratic significance of the title. . . . As Paul had described the celestial Son of Man as at the same time the image of God, the agent of creation, the head of every man, and finally even God over all, so the Christ of the Apocalypse introduces himself with the predicates of Divine majesty : ' I am the Alpha and the Omega, saith the Lord God, who is, and who was, and who is to come, the All-powerful ' ; and He is accordingly called also the ' Head 1 History of Christian Theology, i. pp. 397-398 (Eng. trans.). THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST. 261 ^ _ ^ of Creation/ and ' the Word of God/ that is, the mediating instrument of all Divine Eevelation from the creation of the world to the final judgment. It appears from this that the similarity of the Christology of the Apocalypse to that of Paul is complete ; this Christ occupies the same exalted position as the Pauline Christ above the terrestrial Son of Man." 1 It is not necessary, after these examples, that I should The PetHne dwell long on the Christology of the Petrine and minor ^'^^^^'^'' Epistles. Peter is again a distinct witness, and his testimony i. peter. is in harmony with what we have already seen. Christ is, to refer only to the First Epistle, joined with the Father and the Spirit as one of the principals in the work of salvation ; ^ He is the Eedeemer, foreordained before the foundation of . the world, but manifest in these last times ; ^ His Spirit testified beforehand in the prophets ;* He is called Kvpio^, and passages used in the Old Testament of Jehovah are applied to Him — remarkably in chap. iii. 15, "Sanctify in your hearts Christ as Lord " ; ^ He has gone into heaven, and is at the right hand of God, angels and authorities and powers being made subject to Him ; ^ He is the ordained Judge of quick and dead.^ He is therefore, as Weiss says, in His exaltation a Divine Being,^ whether the Epistle directly teaches His pre-existence or not, as, however, Pfleiderer thinks it does.^ Even James, who barely touches Christology in his 2. lames. Epistle, speaks of Christ as the "Lord of Glory," and the Judge of the world, and prayer is to be made in His name.^^ Not less instructive are the references in the brief Epistle of Jude, who describes Jesus as " our only Master and Lord, 3. /tide. Jesus Christ " ; who exhorts believers to pray in the Holy Spirit, and keep themselves in the love of God, looking for the mercy of our Lord Jesus Christ ; and who concludes his 1 Hihhert Lecture!^, pp. 159-161. 2 1 pet. i. 2. 3 1 Pet. i. 20. 4 1 Pet. i. n. 6 Cf. 1 Pet. i. 5, ii. 13, iii. 12. « 1 Pet. iii. 22. 7 1 Pet. iv. 5. 8 Biblical Theology of New Testament, i. p. 238. ^ Urchristenthum, p. 659. ^^ James ii. 1, v. 7-9, 14, 15. 262 CENTRAL ASSERTION OF CHRISTIAN VIEW. Discourses in Acts. Conclusion : The super- natural view of Chris fs Person established in first ge7ieration of believers. short letter by ascribing to the only God, our Saviour, through Jesus Christ our Lord, glory, majesty, dominion, and power, before all time, and now, and for evermore.^ If to these sources of evidence we add the popular discourses in the Acts of the Apostles, we shall have a tolerably clear idea of the views of Christ held in the Church in the earliest period of Christianity. These discourses, though, as might be expected, containing little or no dogmatic teaching on the origin or constitution of Christ's Person, yet do not fail to represent Him as possessing a unique dignity ; ^ as the holy and sinless One, whom it was not possible for death to hold ; ^ as the Prince of Life, exalted to the throne of universal dominion ;* as the Lord on whose name men were to call, the One in whom alone under heaven there was salvation, and through whom was preached forgiveness of sins to men ; ^ as the Giver of the Holy Ghost ; ^ as the appointed Judge of the world, whom the heaven must retain till the time of the restitution of all things.^ These representations, though simpler, are not inconsistent with the more developed Christ- ology of the Epistles, but rather furnish the data or premises from which all the positions of that Christology can be deduced.^ The supernatural view of Christ, then, is no late develop- ment, but was in all its leading features fully established in the Church in the generation immediately succeeding Christ's death. We find it presupposed in all the apostolic writings, and assumed as well-known among the persons to whom these writings were addressed. If there were, as the 1 Jude4, 20, 21, 25 (R.V.). ^ Acts iii. 13, 25, iv. 27. "Servant," in sense of Isaiali's "Servant of Jehovah." 3 ii. 24, iii. 14. ^ ii. 36, iii. 15. ^ i. 21, 38, iii. 26, iv. 10-12, v. 30, 31. 6 ii. 33. 7 iii, 20, 21. ® Cf. Weiss, i. p. 180 : "The Messiah who is exalted to this xvpioryis must, of course, be a Divine Being, although, for the earliest proclamation, this con- clusion gave no occasion for the consideration of the question on how far such an exaltation was rooted in the original nature of His Person." THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST. 263 _ _ Tubingen school alleges, Pauline and Petrine parties in the Church, it was held by both of these ; whatever other shades of doctrinal opinion existed, this was a common element. But this, it seems to me, is only conceivable on the supposition that the view in question was one in harmony with the facts of Christ's own life on earth, with the claims He made, and with the testimony which His apostles had deposited in the various churches regarding Him. We are now to see how far this is borne out by the actual records we possess of Christ's life. II. We go back then to the Gospels, and ask what they //. The teach. Here I leave out of view the Fourth Gospel, about t^f'^'^'^y^ ^ ' the Gospels— the teaching of which there can be little possible dispute. Christ in the ISTot simply the prologue, but the acts and sayings of Christ fourth Gospel. The question recorded in that Gospel, are decisive for anyone who admits ofgemnneness; it, as I do, to be a truthful record by the beloved disciple of ^^^ation to what Christ did and said on earth.^ It would be out of place here to discuss the question of the genuineness. I would only say that, so far as the objections are drawn from the advanced Christology of the Gospel, and the alleged traces of Alexandrian influence, after what we have seen of the general state of opinion in the apostolic age, very little weight need be attached to them. The Christology of John is not a whit higher than the Christology of Paul, or that of the Epistle to the Hebrews, or even that of the Apocalypse — all lying within the apostolic age ; the alleged traces of Philonic influence are as conspicuous in the Epistle to the Hebrews as ^ It is precisely the discourses of Jesus in the Fourth Gospel which Wendt, in his recent Die Lehre Jesu, is disposed to attribute to a genuine Johannine source. On the difference of style between the Johannine and the Synoptical discourses, Godet remarks : " The discourses of the Fourth Gospel, then, do not resemble a photograph, but the extracted essence of a savoury fruit. From the change wrought in the external form of the latter, it does not follow that the slightest foreign element has been mingled with the latter." — Introduction to Commentary, p. 135 (Eng. trans.). The contrast, however, may be exaggerated, as shown by comparison of passages where the Synoptics and John cross each other. — Cf. Godet, Introduction, pp. 155-157. 264 CENTRAL ASSERTION OF CHRISTIAN VIEW. in the Fourth Gospel. It is not therefore necessary to go beyond the apostolic age to account for them. I question, indeed, very much whether, if we except the prologue — i.e., if we keep to Christ's own doings and sayings — there is much in John's Gospel at all which would directly suggest the peculiarities of Philo. There is certainly a very exalted doctrine of Christ's Person, but the doctrine is Christian, not Philonic.^ Do the It may, however, still be said that at least the Synoptics ^ Synoptics give ^^ ^ ^ different story. Here, it will be maintained, we a different J J y view? have the human, the truly historical Christ, in contrast with the idealised and untrustworthy picture of the fourth evangelist. Dr. Martineau makes this his strongest ground for the rejection of the Gospel of John. But is it really so ? Certainly it is not so, if we let these Gospels — as it is only fair that in the first instance we should do — speak fully and freely for themselves, and do not, in the interest of theory, The Christ of Curtail any part of their testimony. The picture given us in t e ynoptics ^^^ Svnoptics is not at all that of the humanitarian Christ. also a super- '' ^ natural We have a true human life, indeed, — the life of One who Being. ^gj^|. ^j^ ^^^ Q^|. among men as a friend and brother, who , " .^ grieved, who suffered, who was tempted, who was poor and humanity. o ' ' r ' r despised, — a true " Son of Man," in every sense of the word. But do we not find more ? Does this represent their whole testimony about Christ ? On the contrary, does not this Higher lowly Being move as a supernatural Personage throughout, aspects. ^^^ ^^ ^^^ jj^g character and works bear amplest witness to the justice of His claims ? Is there, according to the Synoptics, nothing extraordinary in the commencement of ^ Harnack expresses himself very decidedly on this subject. "Neither the religious philosophy of Philo," he says, "nor the manner of thought out of which it originated, has exercised a provable influence on the first generation of Christian believers. ... A Philonic element is also not provable in Paul. . . . The apprehension of the relation of God and the world in the Fourth Gospel is not the Philonic. Therefore, also, the Logos doctrine found there is essentially not that of Philo." — Dogmengeschichte, i, p. 99. See Note A. — Philo and the Fourth Gospel. ^ Matthew, Mark, and Luke. THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST. 265 ^ Christ's life, nothing extraordinary in its close, nothing in keeping with this extraordinary beginning and end in the career that lies between ? It is easy, no doubt, to get rid of Criticism all this by denying the historical character of the Gospels, or ^"'^^^^^ , J J ^ -f ' expunge the pruning them down to suit ; but after every allowance is stipematural made for possible additions to the narrative, there remains a ^^^^^^^^^' clear enough picture of Jesus to enable us to determine the great subjects of His teaching, and the general character of His claims. In fact, the further criticism goes, the super- The natural character of Jesus stands out in clearer relief. These •^^-f^^'^^^^'^^^ belongs to the are not mere embellishments, mere external additions, essence of the obscuring the picture of a Christ otherwise human. They ^^P^^^^^^io,i^on. are not things that can be stripped off, and the real image of Christ be left behind, as the writing of a palimpsest might be removed and the picture below be brought into view. The history is the picture. All fair historical criticism must see that these supernatural features belong to the very essence of the historical representation of Jesus in the Gospels, and that, if we take them away, we have no longer a historical Christ at all, but only a Christ of our own imaginings ; ^ that we must either take these features as part of our view of Christ, or say frankly with Strauss that we really know little or nothing about Him. But it is, first, the impossibility of resting in this dictum with any fair regard to the canons of historical criticism which has constantly forced even negative critics back to a fuller recognition of the historical reality of the portraiture in the Gospels, and has again placed them in the dilemma of having to reconsider these claims of the Son of Man. Let us look at these claims of Jesus in the Synoptics a i. The little more in detail. Even this title " Son of Man " — found 'I''''''' ^-^, Jesus — the only in Christ's own lips, and never given Him by 1A\^ titles '' Son of followers — has something unique and exceptional about it. ^^'^"'^^^ ^ ^ ^ ''Son of God." it wells up from the depths of the consciousness of One who ^ Cf. on this, BushneH's Nature and the Supernatural, chap, xii., ""Water- marks on the Christian Doctrine," and Row's Jems of the Evangelists. Relation to kingdom of Gody etc. His eschatological claims. 266 CENTRAL ASSERTION OF CHRISTIAN VIEW, knew Himself to stand in some peculiar and representative relation to humanity, and to bear the nature of man in some exceptional way.^ He is not simply "a Son of Man," but " the Son of Man " ; just as, in a higher relation, He is not simply " a Son of God," but " the Son of God." How high this latter relation is, is brought out in the words — " No one knoweth the Son save the Father; neither doth any know the Father, save the Son, and he to whomsoever the Son willeth to reveal Him." ^ In conformity with the uniqueness of nature implied in these titles. He claims to be the Messiah,^ the FulfiUer of law and prophets,* the Founder of the kingdom of God, the supreme Legislator and Head of that kingdom,^ He, through faith in whom salvation is to be obtained,^ the One who demands, as no other is entitled to do, the absolute and undivided surrender of the heart to Himself.'' He for- gives sins with Divine authority,^ is the giver of the Holy Ghost,^ ascribes an expiatory virtue to His death,^^ anticipates His resurrection and return in glory,^^ announces Himself as the appointed Judge of the world.^^ This claim of Christ to be the final Judge of the world, found already in the Sermon on the Mount ; ^^ His repeated declarations of His future return in the glory of His Father, and His own glory, and the glory of the holy angels ; ^* the eschatological parables, in which he makes the ultimate destinies of men depend on relation to Himself,^^ are among the most remarkable features in His teaching, and are not to be explained away as mere figurative assurances of the ultimate triumph of His 1 Cf. Dorner, Person of Christ, i. p. 55 (Eng. trans.), and System of Doctrine, iii. p. 170 ; Gess, Christi Person und Werk, i. p. 212. On the various views as to the meaning of the title, see Bruce, Humiliation of Christ, pp. 474-487 (Cunningham Lecture). 2 Matt. xi. 27 (R.V.). ^ Matt. xi. 1-6 ; Luke iv. 17-21, etc. 4 Matt. V. 17. ^ Matt. xiii. (Parables of Kingdom) 6 Matt. xi. 28 ; Luke vii. 50. 8 Matt. ix. 2, 6. 1^ Matt. XX. 28, xxvi. 26-28, etc. 12 Matt. XX V. 31-46, etc. 1-* Mark viii. 38, etc. Matt. v. -vii. (Sermon on Mount). 7 Matt. x. 37-39. 9 Matt. iii. 11, etc. " Matt. xvi. 21, 27, xvii. 23, xx. 19, etc. ^3 Matt. vii. 21-23. 15 Matt. XXV. ; Luke xii. 11-27. s etc. THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST 267 __ cause. They constitute a claim which must either be conceded, or Christ be pronounced the victim of an extrava- gant hallucination ! We have to add to these claims of Christ, His endorsement of Peter's confession of the unique dignity of His Person — " Thou art the Christ, the Son of Peter\ the living God " ; 1 His solemn words, so fraught with self- ''""f'''^''' consciousness, in answer to the High Priest's adjuration — " Henceforth ye shall see the Son of Man sitting at the right hand of power, and coming in the clouds of heaven " ; ^ and such sublime declarations, implying an omnipresent and omniscient relation to His Church, as " Where two or three are gathered together in My name, there am I in the midst of them." ^ These are stupendous claims of Christ, but we have next 2. Re- to observe that the whole representation of Christ in the ^f ''f ^^''"'^ ^-^ ^ the character Synoptic Gospels is worthy of them. I do not dwell here on of Christ— the holy majesty with which Christ bears himself throughout ^^^ sinlessness, the Gospels in all circumstances, on the tone of authority with which he speaks, on the grace and tenderness which marked His whole relations to men, — I would concentrate attention on the one point that Christ, according to the picture given of Him in the Gospels, is a sinless Being — in this respect also standing quite apart from other men. It is Attested by the the uniform testimony of the apostles and other writers of ^^^'^^^^^ witnesses, tlie New Testament, — of Paul, of Peter, of John, of the Epistle to the Hebrews, of the Apocalypse,* — that Christ was without sin ; and the Synoptic narratives, in the picture they Bome out by give us of a character entirely God-centred, dominated by the ^^^A^^^''^ ^/ ^ J J ./ ^/^g Synoptics, passion of love to men, embracing the widest contrasts, maintaining itself in absolute spiritual freedom in relation to the world, to men and to events, uniformly victorious in temptation, untouched by the faintest stain of base, paltry, or selfish motive, completely bear out this description. So strong is the evidence on this point that we find the sinless- 1 Matt. xvi. 16, 17. 2 j^att. xxv. 64. ^ jy^att. xviii. 20. ^ E.g.,2 Cor. v. 21 ; 1 Pet. ii. 22 ; 1 John iii. 5 ; Heb. iv. 15 ; Rev. iii. 14, etc. Cf. on this subject UUmann's Sinles-viess of Jesus, and Bushnell's Nature and the Supernatural, x. 268 CENTRAL ASSERTION OF CHRISTIAN VIEW. Admitted by ness of Christ widely admitted, even by the representatives theoioptatts — ^^ schools whose general principles, one would imagine, would Vatke, lead them to deny it — by adherents of the Hegelian school c^ leier- j-j^^ Daub, Marheineke, Eosenkrantz, Vatke ; ^ by mediating Ijpsius, etc. theologians of all types, like Schleiermacher,^ Beyschlag,^ Eothe,* and Eitschl ; ^ by liberal theologians, like Hase ^ and Schenkel,^ and so decided an opponent of the miraculous even as Lipsius.^ We must contend, however, that if Christ was really the sinless Being which the Gospels represent Him, and His followers believed Him to be, we have a phenomenon in history which is not to be explained out of mere natural grounds, or on any principle of development, but a literal new creation, a true moral miracle, involving further con- sequences as to the origin and nature of the exceptional Personality to whom these predicates of sinlessness belong.^ 3. The In keeping with the character and with the claims of Ivor s of Jesus j^g^g ^^^ ^^ works ascribed to Him in the Gospels. It is, in keeping ^ ' with His as the merest glance will show, a supernatural history claims. ^ Cf. Dorner's Person of Christ, v. pp. 121-131 ; System of Doctrine, iii. p. 261 (Eng. trans.). - Der christl. Glauhe, sec. 98 (ii. pp. 78, 83). ^ Leben Jesu, i. pp. 181-191. ^ Dogmatik, ii. pp. 83, 108. ^ Unterricht, p. 19. ^ Geschichte Jesu, p. 248. Hase, however, only recognises the sinlessness of Jesus from His entrance on His public work. It was a sinlessness won by struggle. '' In his DogmatiJc, see sketch in Pfleiderer's Dev. of Theol. pp. 177-182. Pfleiderer himself doubts the "psychological possibility" of sinless perfection, and does not ascribe it to Christ. — Ihid. pp. 117, 118. In his Heligionsphilo- Sophie, i. p. 339 (Eng. trans.), he blames Schleiermacher for identifying "this personality so entirely with the ideal principle, that it is exalted to an absolute ideal, and indeed to a miraculous appearance." This affords a good standard for the measurement of Pfleiderer's general Christian position. 8 Dogmatik, sec, 651, p. 569. ^ Strauss acknowledges this when he says : "A sinless, archetypal Christ is not a hair's-breadth less unthinkable than one supernaturally born, with a Divine and human nature." — Der Christus des Glaubens und der Jesus der Geschichte, p. 63. But Strauss himself bears high tribute to the perfection of Jesus. "In the attainment of this serene inward disposition, in unity with God, and comprehending all men as brethren, Jesus had realised in Himself the prophetic ideal of the New Covenant with the Law written in the heart ; He had — to speak with the poet — taken the Godhead into His will. ... In Him man made the transition from bondage to freedom." — Leben Jesu, p. 207 (1864). THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST. 269 throughout. The miracles attributed to Jesus are not mere wonders, but deeds of mercy and love — the outflow of just such Divinity as we claim for Him. They are, accordingly, wrought by Jesus in His own name, in the exercise of His own authority,^ and are suitably spoken of as simply His " works " ^ — i.e. standing in the same relation of naturalness to Him, and to His position in the world, as our ordinary works do to us, and to our position in the world. So far from being isolated from the rest of His manifestation, Christ's miracles are entirely of one piece with it, — are Eevelations of the powers and spirit of His kingdom,^ — are the works of the kingdom, or as they are called in John, " signs." * The most skilful criticism, therefore, has never been able to excise them from the narrative. Their roots intertwine inseparably with the most characteristic elements of the gospel tradition, — with sayings of Christ, for example, of unimpeachable freshness, originality, and beauty ; and, as part of the history, they produce upon us precisely the same impression of dignity, wisdom, and beneficence, as the rest of the narrative. They are, in short, integral parts of that total presentation of Jesus which produces on us so marked and irresistible an impression of Divinity.^ Even this is not the highest point in the Synoptic 4. The testimony about Christ. If Christ died. He rose again on ^/^"^'''f^^^'^f '^ of Christ, the the third day. Meeting with His disciples, He declares to Trinitarian them, " All authority hath been given unto Me in heaven and A''''''^^» ^^^• on earth " ; He commissions them to preach repentance and remission of sins in His name to all the nations ; He bids them " make disciples of all the nations, baptizing them into the name of the Father and of the Son and of the Holy 1 E.g., Matt. viii. 3, 7-10, 26. 2 Matt. xi. 2. "Mighty works," in vers. 20, 21, 23, is literally "powers." *' Works " is tlie favourite term in John. 3 Matt. xi. 4, 5 ; Luke xi. 20. ^ j^i^n ii. 11, etc. 5 Cf. Godet's Lectures in Defence of the Christian Faith, iii., "The Miracles of Jesus Christ," p. 124 (Eng. trans.) ; and Pressense, Vie de Jesus, p. 373 (Eng. trans, p. 277). 2 70 CENTRAL ASSERTION OF CHRISTIAN VIEW. Ghost " (one name) ; He utters for their encouragement this sublime promise, " Lo, I am with you always, even unto the end of the world." ^ There can be no mistake as to the meaning of this Trinitarian formula, which, as Dorner says, does not express a relation to men, but " requires us to regard the Father as the Father of the Son, and the Son as the Son of the Father, and therefore does not signify a paternal relation to the world in general, but to the Son, who, standing between the Father and the Spirit, must be somehow thought as pertaining to the sphere of the Divine, and therefore denotes a distinction in the Divine itself." ^ Attempts are made to challenge the authenticity of these sayings. But they are at least part of the Synoptic representation of Christ, and must be taken into account when the comparison is between the Synoptic representation and that found in John, and in other parts of the Xew Testament. When, however, Christ's whole claim is considered, no valid objection can be taken to these sayings, except on principles which imply that the resurrection never took place at all, — a position which works round to the subversion of the claim itself.^ The Synoptic Such then, is the view of Christ in the Synoptic Gospels ; representahon ^^^^ ^^^ conclusion I draw is, that it is in keeping with the of Christ in ^ ^ keeping with estimate formed of Christ's Person in the apostolic age. the apostohc n^j^g ^^^ thinejs are in harmony. Given such a life as we estimate of ^ '' His Person, havc in the Gospels, this explains the phenomena of the The latter apostolic age. On the other hand, given the estimate of needs the ^ . , ^ t -, - ^ former as its Christ s Pcrson and work m the apostolic age, this supports basis. the reliableness of the picture of Christ in the Gospels, for only from such a life could the faith of the Church have originated. We have, in this Synoptic picture, the very Being whom the writings of Paul and John present to us ; and the forms they use are the only forms which can adequately interpret Him to us. In other words, given the ' Matt, xxviii. 18-20. ^ System of Doctrine, i. p. 351 (Eng. trans.). •* See Note B. — The Resurrection of Christ and the Reality of His Divine Claim. THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST. 271 Christ of the Synoptic Gospels, the doctrine of Paul and John is felt to be the only adequate explanation of His character and claims. I agree, therefore, entirely with Dorner when he says, " It may be boldly affirmed that the entire representation of Christ given by the Synoptics may be placed by the side of the Johannine as perfectly identical, inasmuch as faith, moulded by means of the Synoptic tradition, must have essentially the same features in its concept of Christ as John has " ; and adds, " Those who reject the Gospel of John on account of its glorifying of Christ, can hardly have set themselves in clear relations with the Synoptic Christology." ^ I claim, then, to have shown that if we are to do justice Conclusion: to the facts of Christianity, we must accept the supernatural ^^^f^^^f ^f view of Christ's Person, and recognise in Him the appearance revelation of a Divine Being in humanity. The argument I have ^^'/^^'^^ ^^^^ 1 T .(. . 1 PIT 1 supernattiral conducted — it it be correct — goes further than to show that ^^^^ 0/^7^ this doctrine is an integral part of Christianity. If this ^-^^'-^^'^ •' were all, it might still be said, Eather than that this ^oTevadin^or ^ doctrine be accepted, let Christianity go 1 But if my con- ^" claims. tention is right, we are not at liberty to let Christianity go. The reason why Christianity cannot be waived out of the world at the bidding of sceptics simply is, that the facts are too strong for the attempt. The theories which would explain Christianity away make shipwreck on the facts. But, if Christianity is not to be parted with, its full testimony to itself must be maintained ; and we have now seen what this means. Formerly it was shown that the attempts to maintain Christianity, while rejecting the truth of the Incarnation, have uniformly failed. Now we have seen wliy it is so. It was shown also whither the rejection of Christianity led us, and how the painful steps of return conducted us back throuoh Theism to Eevelation, and through Eevelation to belief in Christ as the supreme Eevealer. But this faith leads us again to His testimony about Himself, ^ Person of Christ, i. pp. 60, 61. 272 CENTRAL ASSERTION OF CHRISTIAN VIEW. and so once more to the Incarnation. Thus it is that the Lord stands constantly challenging the ages to give their answer to His question, " What think ye of Christ ? whose Son is He ? " 1 and increasingly it is shown that it is not in the world's power to put this question aside. However silenced for the moment, it soon again asserts its rights, and will not cease to be heard till humanity, from one end of the earth to the other, has joined in the devout acknowledgment — " My Lord and my God ! " 2 ///. Doctrinal III. This fact of the Incarnation being given, how are aspects of the ^^ ^^ interpret it ? The full discussion of what, doctrinally, Incarfiation : ^ . proposed is involved in the Incarnation, belongs rather to dogmatics reco7istruction. ^j^^^^ ^^ ^^ present inquiry ; but certain limiting positions may at least be laid down, which may help to keep our thoughts in harmony with the facts we have had before us, and may serve as a check on modern theories which, pro- fessing to give us a re-reading of this all-important doctrine more in agreement with the Christian verity than the old Christological decisions, fall short of, or go beyond these facts. The early decisions of the Church on Christ's Person are not, indeed, to be regarded as beyond criticism. It may very well be that reconstruction is needed in this doctrine as in many others. Only, we should be careful not to part with the old formulas till something better — something at least equally true to the facts of Christianity — is put in their place ; and I confess that most of the modern attempts at a revised Christology do not seem to me to fulfil this condition. In what sense Constrained by the evidence of Scripture, many theologians ^aeoHes ascribe^"^^^ in ascribing "Godhead" to Christ, whose views of the '' Godhead'' to Person of Christ yet fall short of what the complete testimony Kothc~ ^^ Scripture seems to require. Schleiermacher may be Ritschi, included in this class, though he avoids the term ; ^ of more Upsius, etc. , ^j^^^^ ^^.. ^2, , j^j^^^ ^^^ 2g_ ^ See Schleiermacher's views in Be?- christl. Glaube, ii. pp. 56, 57, 93. He says : " Inasmucli as all the human activity of Christ in its whole connection depends on this being of God in Him, and represents it, the expression is THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST. 273 recent theologians, Eothe, Beyschlag, Eitschl, Lipsius, etc., who speak freely of the " Godhead " (Gottheit), " God-manhood " (Gottmenschheit), of Christ, and of the " Incarnation " (Menschwerdung) of God in Him.^ But what do these ex- pressions mean ? In all, or most, of these theories, Christ has a high and unique position assigned to Him. He is the second Adam, or new Head of the race. Son of God in a sense that no other is, archetypal Man, sinless Mediator and Eedeemer of mankind.^ This is a great deal, and must be recognised in any theory of the Incarnation. All these theories acknowledge, further, a peculiar being or Revelation of God in Christ, on the ground of which these predicates " Godhead " and " God- manhood " are ascribed to Him. But what is its nature ? In Schleiermacher, as already seen in the second Lecture, it is the constant and energetic activity of that God-conscious- ness which is potentially present in every man — which constitutes, therefore, an original element in human nature.^ In Eothe, it is an ethical union of God with humanity, gradually brought about in the course of the sinless develop- ment of Christ, and constituting, when complete, a perfect indwelling of God in man^ — a perfect unity of the Divine and human.* In Beyschlag, it is the consciousness of a perfect and original relation of Sonship to God, which has its transcendental ground in an impersonal (Divine -human) principle eternally pre-existent in the Godhead.^ In Eitschl, justified that in the Redeemer God became man, in a sense trae of Him exclusively ; as also each moment of His existence, so far as one can isolate it, represents a new and similar incarnation of God and state of being incarnate ; since always and everywhere, all that is human in Him proceeds out of that which is i)ivine."— Pp. 56, 57. He objects to the term "God-Man" as too definite.— P. 93. 1 Rothe, Dogmatik, ii. pp. 88, 107, etc.; Beyschlag, Lehen Jem, p. 191, etc.; Ritschl, Eecht. und Ver. iii. pp. 364-393 ; Unterricht, p. 22 ; Lipsius, Dog- matik, p. 457. Cf. also Schultz, Lehre von der Gottheit Christi, pp. 536, 537 ; Hermann, Verkehr des Christen mlt Gott, pp. 42-62 ; Nitzsch, Evangelische Dogmatik, ii. p. 514, etc. 2 Schleiermacher, ii. p. 91 ; Lipsius, sec. 638. 3 Der christi. Glauhe, ii. pp. 40, 56. Cf. Lipsius, p. 492. * Dogmatik, ii. pp. 88-97, 165-182. ^ Lehen Jesu, i. p. 191 ; Chrlstologie, pp. 58, 84, etc. 18 2 74 CENTRAL ASSERTION OF CHRISTIAN VIEW. the "Godhead" of Christ has a purely moral and religious sense, expressing the fact that in Christ, as the supreme Eevealer of God, and Founder of the kingdom of God, there is perfect oneness of will with God in this world-purpose, and a perfect manifestation of the Divine attributes of grace and truth, and of dominion over the world.^ In Lipsius, again, and those who think with him, " Incarnation " and " Godhead " denote the realisation in Christ of that perfect relation of sonship to God (Gottessohnschaft) which lies in the original idea of humanity, and the perfect Eevelation of the Divine will of love (Liebewillen) in that Eevelation.^ !N"ow I do not deny that in these theories we have a certain union of the Divine and human, just as believers in Christ, through union with Him and participation in His Spirit, become "sons of God," and "partakers of the Divine nature."^ 1 do not deny, further, that these theories secure for Christ a certain distinction from every other, in that they make Him the original type of that relation of Divine Sonship into which others can only enter through Him. It is a thought also which not unnaturally occurs, whether on this idea of a God-filled humanity — a humanity of which it may be truly said that in an ethical respect the fulness of the Godhead dwells in it bodily — we have not all that is of practical value in any doctrine of Incarnation. We must beware, however, of imposing on ourselves with words, and I believe that, if we do not rise to a higher view, it will be difficult, as the second Lecture showed, to prevent ourselves drifting to pure humanitarianism. 1 Unterricht, p. 22. It will be seen that this is a tolerably complex idea of " Godhead." " DogmatiJc, pp. 574, 575. Lipsius distinguishes between the " principle " of the Christian religion— Avhich is that of religion absolutely— and the historical revelation of that principle in the Person and Work of Christ.— Pp. 535-536. Yet this principle is not accidentally or externally bound up with Christ, as if He were only casually the first representative of it, or His work only the external occasion for the symbolical representation of the general activity of this principle in humanity.— Pp. 537, 538. ^ John i. 12 : 2 Pet. i. 4. THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST 275 Two things are to be considered here— First, ^^^qWi^x Two questions these theories are tenable on their own merits ? and, second, ^^ ^"^^^'^ ^^ . , . . these theories. whether they do justice to the facts of Christ's Eevelation, and to the data of the New Testament generally ? I shall offer a few remarks on these points, then add a brief notice of the theories known as Kenotic. 1. There are two classes of these theories — those which i. First do not, and those which do, presuppose a transcendental or question— ^r^ these theoHes metaphysical ground for the predicate " Godhead " applied to tenable on Christ, and as important differences exist between them, it is ^^^^^ '^^^ . . T . -IT merits? desirable to distinguish them. Two classes (1) Of the former class are those of Schleiermacher, ^''/^ Eitschl, Lipsius, with many others that might be named. I /j) ^^rhose abstract from other features in these theories, and look only -^^^ich do not at the grounds on which " Godhead " is ascribed to ^^'^^^'^ \ transcendental and I do not find any which transcend the limits of humanity, ground for the Christ is archetypal man, ideal man, sinless man, the Perfect ff^J^^^'^^^,, Eevelation of grace and truth, the central individual of \h^ applied to race, the bearer of the principle of true religion, the Founder ^.r/!~ of the kingdom of God in humanity, the pre-eminent object macher, of the Father's love, — but He is not more than man. His ^^^^^'^^' LtpstuSf etc. humanity may be a " God-filled " humanity ; still a God-filled man is one thing, and God become man is another. There may be participation in the Divine life — even in the Divine nature — on the part of the ordinary believer ; but the man in whom God thus dwells does not on this account regard himself as Divine, does not speak of himself as a Divine person, does not think himself entitled to Divine honours, would deem it blasphemy to have the term "Godhead" applied to him. If, therefore, this is the only account we can give of Christ's Person, it is clear that this predicate "Godhead" can never properly be applied to Him. We might speak of the Divine in Christ, but we could not say that Christ himself was Divine. We might see in Him the highest organ of Divine Eevelation, but we would require to distinguish between the God revealing Himself, and the 2 76 CENTRAL ASSERTION OF CHRISTIAN VIEW. humanity through which He is manifested. It would be blasphemy here also to speak of Christ Himself as God. It would be idolatry to give Him Divine honours. We find, therefore, that Eitschl has to admit that it is only in a figurative and improper sense that the Church can attribute " Godhead " to Christ.^ This predicate, he says, is not a theoretic truth, but only a judgment of value— an expression of the worth which Christ has for the religious consciousness of the believer. In further carrying out the same idea, both Schleiermacher and Eitschl strip away, as formerly shown, all the eschatological attributes from Christ, and resolve His sitting at the right hand of God, His return to judge the world, etc., into metaphors. The only real sense in which Christ is spiritually present in His Church is through the perpetuation of His image, of His teaching, and of His influence in the community of believers.^ This is the legitimate consequence of a theory which does not go beyond the bounds of the human in its estimate of Christ ; for if the eschatological teaching of Jesus is admitted, it seems impossible to stop short of a much higher view of His Person. This method, however, of simply sweeping aside what is distasteful is too violent to be long endured; there are besides those utterances of Jesus which bespeak the con- sciousness of a relation different in kind, and not merely in degree, from that sustained by others to the Father. This class of theories, therefore, naturally passes over to another — that which seeks to do justice to the facts by admitting a deeper ground for Christ's Personality than the earthly one. (2) ^J'hose (2) Of this second class of theories, I may take those of ^presuppose a ^'^'^^ ^^^ Beyschlag as examples. Eothe thinks he effectu- transiendental /ir^'^"^'''' ' ^'*''^^' ^''''^- ''''^ ^'''- '"• p- ^' ^• ^ [^ .. _ ^ Ritschl, Recht. mid Ver. pp. 383, 384, 407, 408. "In any otlier sense," he aC/i7 ^ ^l^inks, ''the formula of the exaltation of Christ to the right hand of God is £e 'schlacr ®^^^^®^ without content for us, because Christ as exalted is directly hidden for eysciag. ^^g . ^^ becomes the occasion of all possible extravagance (Sehwarmerei)."— P. 407. Schleiermacher, Der christl. Glaube, pp. 84-88, 290-292; Lipsius, Dogmatik, pp. 494, 587. THE INCARNA TION OF GOD IN CHRIST. 2 7 7 ally secures the idea of Christ's Godhead by assuming that, in the course of Christ's sinless development, God constantly unites Himself with Him in closer and closer relations, till at length a perfect union both of person and of nature is effected.^ Beyschlag thinks to do the same by supposing that a Divine impersonal principle — a pre-existent ideal humanity — is somehow incarnated in Christ.^ But not to speak of the absence of scriptural proof for both of these theories, see the difficulties under which they labour. Can it be seriously said that, if a transcendental ground of Christ's Person is to be admitted, these theories have any advantage in simplicity or intelligibility over the old view ? Take Eothe's theory, imonsistendes What are we to make of the supposition of a personality '^^^ which begins as human, and ultimately and gradually is changed into Divine ? Then what is meant by two persons merging into one, and this by moral process ? For God is one Person to begin with, and Christ is another, and at length a perfect union is effected of both. Do we really in this theory get beyond the idea of an ethical union, or perfect moral fellowship, in which, after all, the two Persons remain distinct, though united in will and love ? If this is the character of the union, it is only by a misuse of terms that we can speak of Christ becoming really God. Yet Eothe is perfectly in earnest with this conception of the deification of Christ, so we ask finally — How is this newly constituted Person related to God the Father. For Eothe acknowledges no immanent distinction of Persons in the Godhead, and it is the Father Himself who thus unites Himself with Christ, and confers Godhead upon His Person. Eothe says expressly, " The Incarnation of God in the Second Adam is essentially an incarnation of both in Him— of the Divine personality, and of the Divine nature." ^ But if it is the One absolute Personality whom we call God, who enters into the union with the humanity of Jesus, how can the resultant relation 1 Dogmatih, pp. 165-182. 2 Christologie, p. 84, etc. ^ Dogmatik, ii. p. 172. 2 78 CENTRAL ASSERTION OE CHRISTIAN VIEW. Adds a new Person to the Godhead. Difficulties of Beyschlag's theory of a heavenly humanity. 2. Second question — Do these theories do justice to the facts of Christ's Revelation ? be described as that of Father and Son ? Or if a new Divine Person really is constituted, does not Eothe's theory amount to this, that, since the Incarnation, a new Person has been added to the Godhead ? But what does the constitution of a new Divine Person mean ? Is it not, if the expression is to be taken literally, very like a contradiction in terms ? I need not wait long on Beyschlag's rival theory of a pre- existent impersonal humanity, which solves no difficulties, and is loaded with inconceivabilities of its own. For in what sense can this idea of humanity be spoken of as Divine, any more than any other idea of the Divine mind which is realised in time ? — the idea, e.g., of the world, or of the believer, or of the Church. What, besides, is meant by a heavenly, ideal humanity ? Does it include only the single Person of Christ, or not also all the members of the human race ? ^ How, further, is this ideal humanity, which forms the super- natural principle in Christ, related to His actual humanity of flesh and blood, which came to Him "of the seed of David ? " 2 Finally, if Christ's Person was thus peculiarly constituted, even in respect of its humanity, how can it be said of Him that He was made in all things like unto His brethren ? ^ It may seem a waste of time to discuss such questions ; yet theories like Eothe's and Beyschlag's have their uses; for they aid us, by a process of exclusion, in seeing what the true theory must be, and where we are to look for it. 2. The second question I proposed to ask is already in large measure answered in the course of the above discussion, Do these theories do justice to the facts of Christ's Eevelation, and to the data of the New Testament generally ? ^ Cf. his Christologie, p. 58 ; and Leben Jesu, p. 46. ^ Rom. i. 4. ^ Heb. ii. 17. Beyschlag would avoid some of these difficulties, if he kept consistently by the position that Christ is but the perfect realisation of the "Ebenbild" of humanity, which is fragmentarily realised in all men, — is, in fact, simply the ideal Man ; but he seeks to establish a metaphysical distinction between Christ's humanity and ours, in virtue of which His personality is "originally and essentially" Divine, while ours is not— Christologie, p. 58. See further on Beyschlag's views in Appendix. THE INCARNATION OF GOD IN CHRIST 279 They clearly do not, either in a negative or a positive re- spect. There is no hint in the Scriptures of either Eothe's gradual incarnation, or of Beyschlag's pre-existent principle of humanity ; but there are many passages which directly, or by implication, claim for Christ personal pre-existence, and attribute to Him Divine acts and functions in that state of pre-existence. But, apart from this, all those passages which claim for Christ a unique relation of Sonship to the Father, taken with the sayings which imply His consciousness of the possession of attributes and functions raised above those of humanity, point to a super-earthly and pre-incarnate state of existence. And this brings us back to the fundamental^ distinction between a true and a false or inadequate What is mt, doctrine of Incarnation. Incarnation is not simply the '^'^^ '^'^^^ ^•^' endowing of human nature with the highest conceivable /«<:a^«rt//er8ouality." Schultz remarks, in speaking of Creation :— "The Spirit of God and His Word appear as powers enclosed in God. The Spirit apiK^ara as very independent, in the manner of a hypostasis."— ^/««^<. Tlifol. p. 569. On the doctrine of tlie Spirit in the Old Testament, see Schultz, Oehler, and Kleiuert in Jahrhucher fur deuUche TIi£ologit for 1667 (referred to by Cheyne). * Cf. Hegel, lieHf/hnsphilowphu:, ii. pp. 237 239. / IN VOL VED IN T//E INCARNATION. 307 tiiC present — but ftirriply on the formal contradiction of " one ind three." But what \% there to which the sanuj objection would not apply ? What i« there which i« not at the ftaxne time one and manifold ? Take any ob)V;t — it can only be f/niiy and wnceived of a» unity of »u)>»tancrdingly, must have in it a plu- rality of powers, must be thought of as capable of expressing, unfolding, or differentiating itself into a manifold, Thii ?is true on the pintheistic hypothesis, or on Mr. Spencer's LiHiory of an Unknowable Power, which manifests itself in matter and mind, or on any of the monistic systems, — Ifa^jckel'fi or I lartm an n *s, ^>i* example, — a« in the ClimiiAn TAe £lMtie dfxjtrine. It will be remembered how this question was one LX/j^>i ^7nd of the difficulties discussed in the early Greek schools, and /// remits. what came of the attempts of the Eleatics and others to hold fast the unity of the Absolute in contrast to all distinctions, om the idea of one absolute distinctionless unity, ex- cluding all plurality, all change, all mobility, all decay, came the relegation of the world of perception to the cate- gory of mere seeming, show, unreality, non-being — in brief, the denial of the reality of the existing world, or Acosmism.' It was in the atterr/pt to overry^me this difficulty ihai /tttempts t » r ° on this side. ^ Augustine is constantly acknowledging the imperfection of finite analogies to express the ineffable reality of the Godhead. See specially Book xv. The following are some of the headings of chapters : "That it is not easy to discover the Trinity that is God from the trinities we have spoken of" "There is the greatest possible unlikeness between our word and knowledge and the Divine Word and knowledge." "Still further of the difference between the knowledge and word of our mind, and the knowledge and Word of God. " How great is the unlikeness between our word and the Divine Word ! Our word cannot be, or be called, eternal," etc. "We know but in an enigma," and "Who can explain how great is the unlikeness also, in this glass, in this enigma, in this likeness, such as it is?"— De Trimtate, i). 402 (Eng. trats.)- 314 THE HIGHER CONCEPT OF GOD see the positive philosophical and theological value of this concept of God. There are several points of view from which its advantage over the Unitarian view of God becomes apparent. I. Thededuc' 1. First of all, there is the bearing of this doctrine on Hon from ^^.^ Divine self-consciousness — on knowledge and Personality knowledge. ^ . in God. The relation of knowledge seems necessarily to imply a distinction of subject and object. Philosophers have spoken of a transcendental kind of knowledge which is above this distinction, — in which subject and object melt into one. But their words convey no idea to the mind. ^ The only kind of knowledge we are capable of conceiving is one in which the subject distinguishes himself from some object which is not himself, and through this distinction returns to knowledge of himself and of his own states. In our own case, this knowledge of self is mediated through knowledge of the outward world, and in the highest degree through intercourse with our fellow human beings. Seizing on this analogy, Supposition some have thought that the Divine consciousness might be that the diviiu^^^^^^^^^ of as mediated by the idea of the world.^ The consciousness ^ '' is mediated by idea of the world in this view takes the place of the Son the idea of the -^^ ^|^q orthodox theologv. The obiections to this are — world. ^-^ *^ Objections to (1) It makes God dependent on the world, the idea of this: which is necessary for the realisation of His self - con- {!) Makes God . '^ dependent on SClOUSnCSS. the world; (2) The objcct in this case is an ideal one, and this seems (2) The object . \ , / ^. ^ -. ,. . -r-r , • only ideal. inadequate to mediate a real self-consciousness. Hegel is consistent, accordingly, if this theory is to be adopted, in making not the idea of the world, but the world itself, the object through which the Divine Spirit attains to self-con- sciousness. (3) The ob- (3) The world is a finite object, and cannot be an adequate jec a Jim e means for the mediation of an infinite self-consciousness.^ one 1 Thus, e.g., Weisse. ' It is besides only progressively realised, and thus would involve a groicing self-consciousness. IN VOL VED IN THE INCARNA TION. 3 1 5 (4) Finally, the world is not a personal object. But (4) The object the true depths of personality are only sounded when ^^^^P^^^^nai. the " I " knows itself in contradistinction from and in reciprocal relations with a " Thou " — a counter-self to its own.^ The result we reach by this line of thought is that we The Christian can only secure the reality of the Divine self-consciousness '^^^"~^^^ Divine con- by regarding it as complete in itself — apart from the \^^?^ sdousness selj- of the world : and this can only be done by positinoj an ^^^^^^^^ . '. ^ J f o through the immanent distinction in the Godhead, through which the son and Divine consciousness carries its object within itself ; and ^P^^'it- this neither an ideal, nor finite, nor impersonal object, but One in whom God sees His own personal image perfectly expressed, — who, in Scripture language, is " the effulgence of His glory, and the very image of His sub- stance " (hiTOGTadm)?' The value of the doctrine of the Trinity from this point of view is very evident. The third moment — that which corresponds to the Holy Spirit — is more difficult to arrive at a priori, but one feels the need of it to complete the circle of the Divine life in bringing to light the unity which underlies the previous distinction.^ 2. A more familiar deduction is that from Divine love. 2. The dcduc- Here, in realising what is involved in Divine love, we feel, *^°*^p'°^^^ ' ^ ' ' love. quite as strongly as in the case of the Divine Personality, the need of self-distinction. The proof of the Trinity from love — if proof it can be called — is a favourite one with ^ This objection is not obviated by assuming a world of finite personalities. 2 Heb. i. 3. Pfleiderer supposes that the Divine self-consciousness is mediated by God's own thoughts ("His changing activities and states") — but thoughts of what? — Relicjionsphilosophie, iii. p. 282 (Eug. trans.). 3 Cf. on this argument Dorner, System of Doctrine, pp. 422-426 ; Christlieb, Moderne Zweifel, pp. 271, 272 (Eng. trans.), etc. Hegel makes it the starting-point of his deduction. "Knowing implies that there is another which is known ; and in the act of knowing, the other is appropriated. Herein it is contained that God, the eternally in -and -for -Himself exist- ing One, eternally begets Himself as His Son, distinguishes Himself from Himself — the absolute act of judgment." — ReligionsphiloHophie, ii. p. 228. 3i6 THE HIGHER CONCEPT OF GOD A theologians.^ " God is love." ^ But love is self-commuiiica- I tion to another. There cannot be love without an object to /be loved. If, therefore, God is essentially love, this is in other words to say that He has from eternity an object of His love. This object cannot be the world — ideally or really — for the reason already given, that this would be to make God dependent on the world, — to make the world, ) indeed, an essential moment in God's life, — whereas the true doctrine is that God has love in its fulness in Himself, and out of that fulness of love, loves the world.^ The world, besides, is a finite object, and could not be an adequate object for the infinite love of God. If, therefore, God is love in Himself — in His own eternal and transcendent being — He must have in some way within Himself the perfect and eternal object of His love — which is just the Scripture doctrine of the Son. This view of God is completed in the • perfect communion the Divine Persons have with each other through the Holy Spirit — the bond and medium of their \ love. The opposite To See the importance of this view, we have but to hypothesis— / contrast it with its opposite, and to ask, What can love in love m a son- rc^ iary God. God mean on the supposition of His absolute solitariness ? What can be the object of God's love throughout eternity, if there is no triune distinction in God ? What can it be but Himself ? Instead of love, therefore, as we understand it, — affection going out to another, — what we have in the ^ It is developed specially by Sartorius in his Doctrine of Divine Love (traDslated). See also Martensen's Christian Ethics, i. p. 73 ; Christlieb's Moderne Zweifel, pp. 272, 273 (Eng. trans.) ; Laidlaw's Bible Doctrine of MaVy pp. 126, 127 ; Murphy's Scientific Basis of Faith, p. 377; Lux Mundi, p. 92, etc. 2 1 John iv. 16. ^ This is an important point in the doctrine of Divine Love. The thought is already met with in Irenseus. Cf. Dorner, Person of Christ, i. p. 306. Marten- sen says: "God's love to the world is only then pure and unmixed holy affection when God, whilst He is sufficient to Himself and iu need of nothing, out of infinite grace and mercy calls forth life and liberty beyond His own Being. . . . But this free power of love in the relations of God to the world presupposes the existence of perfect love realised within itself, the love of the Father and the Son in the unity of the Holy ^\m\V —Christian Ethics, i. p. 74. Similarly Dorner in his Christian Ethics, p. 94 (Eng. trans.). IN VOL VED IN THE INCARNA TION, 3 1 7 universe is an infinite solitary Ego ; a Being who loves Himself only, as, indeed, there is no other to love. Either, therefore, vi^e must come back to seek an object for God's love in the finite, created world, or recognise that God has an infinitely blessed life of love within Himself, and this brings us to the doctrine of an immanent Trinity. The value of the doctrine in an ethical aspect is seen when we recognise that only through the Trinitarian distinction are we brought into com- munion with a Being who has within Himself a life of y communion. 3. Connected with this as a third point of view — though 3. Deduction it is really only an extension of the foresfoino; — is a deduction -^^'^''^ ^^^ ^ ^ ^ . . Divine from the Divine Fatherhood. God is Father. This is Fatherhood— Christ's own new name for Him, and expresses His relation to God eternally ^ . Father. those who stand in moral dependence on Him, and who bear His image. But Father and Son are terms of relation.^ If, then, God be Father, where shall we find the Son who corresponds with this relation ? If we say, men, created angels, creatures of any kind, we are led to this, that Fatherhood in God depended on there being a creation. God is not Father simply as God. Fatherhood is not of His very essence. This could not easily be better put than it has been by Mr. E. H. Hutton, in a well-known essay on the r. h. Ilntton Incarnation in his volume of Theological Essays. " If Christ ^" ^^'' ^'''^• is the eternal Son of God," he says, " God is indeed and in essence a Father ; the social nature, the spring of love, is of the very essence of the Eternal Being ; the communication of His life, the reciprocation of His affection dates from beyond time — belongs, in other words, to the very being of God. . . . The Unitarian conviction that God is — as God and in His eternal essence — a single, solitary Personality . . . thoroughly realised, renders it impossible to identify any of the social attributes with His real essence — renders it difficult 1 This is the mistake of those who, in a Sahellian way, take Father as the name for God as the Creator, etc. The Christian idea of the Father comes 10 birth only in the Revelation of the Son. The terms are reciprocal. See Note A. 3i8 THE HIGHER CONCEPT OF GOD not to regard power as the true root of all other Divine life. ' If we are to believe that the Father was from all time, we must believe that He was as a Father, — that is, that love was actual in Him as well as potential, that the communica- tion of life and thought and fulness of joy was of the inmost nature of God, and never began to be, if God never began to be." 1 4. Bearing of 4. Finally, this doctrine of the Trinity has a profound ^he Trinity on ^^^^' ^^ the relation of God to the world. Not without God s relation ^ to the world, reason does Scripture connect the Son with the creation, and give His person and His work a cosmical significance. We may conceive of God in two relations to the world — either in His absolute transcendence over it, which is the deistic conception, or as immanently identified with it, which is the pantheistic conception. Or we may conceive of Him as at the same time exalted above the world — transcending it, and yet present in it as its immanent sustaining ground, whicli is the Christian conception. It was to maintain this double relation to the world that, as we have seen, Philo conceived of the Logos as a middle term between God and the creation, and the ISTeo-Platonists distinguished between God, the vov<^, The safeguard aud the soul of the WO rid. When a middle term is wanting, we have either, as in the later Judaism and Mohammedanism, an abstract and immobile Monotheism ; or, in recoil from this, a losing of God in the world in Pantheism. In the Christian doctrine of the triune God we have the necessary safeguards against both of these errors, and at the same time the link between God and the world supplied which specula- tion vainly strove to fiud.^ The Christian view is, therefore, the true protection of a living Theism, which otherwise ^ Theological Essays, Srd ed. p. 257. '■^ This important aspect of the Trinity, as safeguarding the true idea of God in relation to the world (His immanence and transcendence) against the opposite errors of Deism and Pantheism, is brought out with special fulness by Doruer in his discussion of Sabellianisra and Arianism, Person of Christ, i. and ii., and his System of Doctrine, i. pp. 365-378. Cf. also Martensen's Do'jmatics, pp. 103-106 ; Christlieb's Modeme Zweifel, pp. 263-265 ; Lux Mundi, pp. 92-102, etc. against Deism and Panthe- ism. IN VOL VED IN THE INCARNA TION 3 1 9 oscillates uncertainly between these two extremes of Deism and Pantheism, either of which is fatal to it.^ II. It is a special service of the doctrine of the Trinity, //. The Scrip- from the point of view we have now reached, that it brin^^s ^^''^ ^^^^ 1 -T^ 1 . . ,. , . brings Crea- creation and Eedemption into Ime, teaching us to look on Hon and Re- creation and Eedemption as parts of one grand whole, and ^^^'^A^'^« "^^'^ on Christ, now exalted to supreme dominion in the universe, ^^^^„^^j.^y-^;j^>. as at once the first-born of creation and the first-born from the dead.2 This thought of the Son as the link between God and the creation — which is so prominent a thought in the New Testament — forms the transition to the other subject on which I propose to speak in this Lecture — the relation of Relation of the the Incarnation to the plan of the world. The Eevelation of ^^^«^««^^'^« *° the plan of the the Trinity is given in the work of Eedemption, but once world. given we can see that it has its bearings also on the work of creation. This is the view of all the leading writers in the New Testament, — of Paul, of John, of the author of the Epistle to the Hebrews, — who go back, or reason back, to an original agency of the Son in the creation of the world.^ Even the Apocalypse speaks of Christ as " the beginning (apx^, or principle) of the creation of God." ^ But once started on this line, it is impossible to shut one's eyes to the question which inevitably arises, and which has so frequently been discussed in the history of theology — more keenly than ever in modern theology, Did an Incarnation lie in the original plan of the world ? Would there have been an Incarnation had man never Would there fallen? Has the Incarnation any relation to the ^^^{ovc^^l^^'^' ^'''' !'''' Incarnation ends for which the world was made ? Or is the Incarna- had man not siftftcd ^ 1 A remarkable illustration of Low the deeper tlionglit on God runs almost necessarily into a Trinitarian mould is furnished by an essay of Dr. Martineau's on *'A Way out of the Trinitarian Controversy," in his recently published volume of Essays, Ecclesiastical and Historical. See Note B. — Dr. Martineau as a Trinitarian. 2 Col. i. 15-18. 3 John i. 3 ; 1 Cor. viii. 6 ; Eph. iii. 9-11 ; Col. i. 15-18 ; Heb. i. 2. * Rev. iii. 14. 320 THE HIGHER CONCEPT OF GOD tion connected solely with the entrance of sin and the need of Eedemption ? This question To raisc a question of this kind at all may be thought by apt to be nega- ^^^^ ^q savour of idle and presumptuous speculation. It tivedaspre- '' . sumptuous. may be thought that it is one which the Scripture directly and expressly settles in the negative, in connecting the In- carnation so immediately as it does with God's great purpose of salvation to our race — making it, indeed, the crowning proof of His love to sinners that He has sent His only- begotten Son into the world, that the world might live through Him.^ There are, however, certain considerations which should give us pause before coming too hastily to this conclusion. But \. It rises 1. The first is that this is a question which does rise 7iatura yfrom naturally out of SO transcendent a fact as the Incarnation. the subject ; '' 2. Has often 2. It is a qucstion which has forced itself on the pressed Itself jj^j^^j of \]^q Church, and has been deeply and reverently on the mind of ^ , , -^ "^ "^ the Church, discusscd by its ablest thinkers for centuries. It is a view which the late Principal Fairbairn, who reasons against it, admits undoubtedly to include among its defenders "some of the most learned theologians of the present day." 2 3. Not unsug- 3. But, mainly, the theory referred to is one not unsuggested failo/the^' ^^' certain of the teachings of Scripture. The same objection teachings of which is taken to this — that it lies outside the field of Scripture. ^-^^ ^^ Eedemption — may be made against the Scripture statements as to the relation of the Son to creation ; but it is the grandeur of the Christian view that, starting with our primary necessities as sinners, it opens up principles and views fertile and far-reaching vastly beyond their original application. The history It is Unnecessary for my purpose to enter at any length eques ion. -^^^ ^^ history of the question. A sketch of it may be seen in Dorner's History of the Doctrine of the Person of Jesus 1 1 John \v. 9. 2 Typology of Scripture, 4th ed. i. p, 118, IN VOL VED IN THE INCARNA TION 3 2 1 Christ} or in the finely-toned essay on the subject, entitled " The Gospel of Creation," appended to Bishop Westcott's Commentary on the Epistles of St. John. These writers, with Archbishop Trench in his Cambridge University Sermons, take the view that the Incarnation was not conditioned by human sin ; and the same view is held by Eothe, Lange, Oosterzee, Martensen, Ebrard, and a large number of other theologians. The opposite view is stated with great temperateness and force by Principal Fairbairn in the fourth edition of his valuable work on the Typology of Scripture.'^ It may perhaps be found as the result of a brief consideration of the sub- ject that the truth does not lie exclusively on either side in this profound and difficult controversy, but that a higher point of view is possible from which the opposition dis- appears. The strong point in favour of the view that the Incarna- strong pomt tion is conditioned solely by human sin is the fact that in ^^"^^^^/^^ Scripture it is represented invariably in this connection, constant con- I need not quote many passacres in illustration of this state- 'f ^^^^" ^f^^^'^ ^ ./ i o Incarnation ment. " The Son of Man came to seek and to save that with Redemp- which was lost." ^ " God so loved the world that He gave ^^°^^- His only-begotten Son, that whosoever believeth in Him should not perish, but have eternal life." * " God sent forth His Son, born of a woman, born under the law, that He might redeem them which were under the law, that we might receive the adoption of sons." ^ " To this end was the Son of God manifested, that He might destroy the works of the devil." ^ These and numerous other Scriptures explicitly associate Christ's coming with man's Eedemption. Christ is the unspeakable gift of God's love to men for their salvation. On the other hand, it is argued that, while the Scripture Passages which stiggest ^ Person of Christ, iii. pp. 361-369. This view was already involved in the a wider view. theology of Irenceus. See Dorner, i. p. 316; and Article, "Irenseus," in Dictionary of Christian Biopraphy. 2 Vol. i. pp. 117-135. =^ Luke xix. 10. '* John iii. 16. 5 Gal. iv. 4 (R.V.). ^ 1 John iii. 8. 21 32 2 THE HIGHER CONCEPT OF GOD thus directly connects the Incarnation with the work of Eedemption, it leaves room for, and contains passages which necessarily suggest, a wider view. Such are the passages already referred to, which throw light on the original rela- tion of the Son to creation — which declare that all things were made by Him, that all things consist or hold together in Him, that He is the first-born of all creation — above all, that all things were created for Him — that, in the language of Dr. Lightfoot, " the Word is the final cause as well as the creative agent of the universe " — " not only the a/3%»7 but also the Te\o9 of creation, not only the first but also the last in the history of the universe." ^ These passages I shall advert to again. It is further argued — and this is a point on which great stress is laid — that an event of such tremendous magnitude as the Incarnation cannot be regarded as a mere contingency in the universe ; that if it was in view at all, it must have governed the whole plan of creation ; and that, in point of fact, it is through it that, according to Scripture, the creation docs reach its end — not only redeemed humanity, but all things, both in heaven and in earth, being ultimately gathered up into Christ as Head.^ A plan of such vast ex- tent cannot, it is held, be conceived of as an afterthought, — as something grafted on creation outside its original design, — it must have lain in the original design itself. Difficulty It seems to me that the real source of difiBculty in ^toTab^straaa ^^i^^^iug ou this subjcct Hcs in not grasping with sufficient viexvofthe firmucss the fact that, however we may distinguish from Divine plan. ^^^ human point of view between parts and aspects of the Divine plan, God's plan is in reality one, and it is but an abstract way of thinking which leads us to suppose other- wise. In our human way of apprehension, we speak as if God had first one plan of creation — complete and rounded of in itself — in which sin was to have no place ; then, when it was foreseen that sin would enter, another plan was in- troduced, which vitally altered and enlarged the former. But 1 On Col. i. 16, 2 Eph. i. 10. IN VOL VED IN THE INCARNA TION 3 23 if we take a sufficiently high point of view, we shall be compelled to conclude, I think, that the plan of the universe God'spk an IS is one, and that, however harsh the expression may sound, ""^^ ^'^^'^ff^- the foresight and permission of sin was from the first in- dudes fore- eluded in it. An ultra- Calvinist would speak of the fore- •''^'^^ ""''"^ . p . T 1 permission ordmation of sm ; I take lower ground, and speak only of of sin. the foresight and permission of sin. Dealing with the question on the largest scale, I do not see how either Calvinist qx Relation of Arminian can get away from this. It is not a question qI ^f^^^^^/ ^^^^ . Armiman to how sin historically or empirically eventuated, — that we this question. agree it must have done through human freedom, — but it is the question of fact, that sin is here, and that in the Divine plan it has been permitted to exist — that it has been taken up by God into His plan of the world. His plan included the permission of sin, and the treatment of it by Eedemption. In a previous Lecture, I referred to the view held by some that nature even before the Fall had a prophetic reference to man's sin, and that in this way is to be explained much that is other- wise mysterious and perplexing in its arrangements. We have only to enlarge our range of vision to see that this way of looking at the subject applies to the whole plan of God. Ic is idle to speculate whether, had there been no sin, the plan of the universe would have included an Incarnation or not. Had this been different everything else would have been different also. What we do know is that in the infinite possibilities of things, God has chosen to create a universe into which it was foreseen that sin would enter ; and the Incarnation is Creation huHt a part of the plan of such a creation. This being so, it J!^^^^ ^^f^ption may very well be conceived that the Incarnation was the pivot on which everything else in this plan of creation was made to turn. To state my view in a sentence — God's plan is one ; Christ was the Lamb slain from the foundation of the world ;^ and even creation itself is built up on Eedemption lines. 1 Rev. xiii. 8. Cf. the interesting remarks in Hugh Miller's Footprints of the Creator, 23rd ed. p. 289 (1887). 324 THE HIGHER CONCEPT OF GOD Great weight We must, I think, on this question allow great weight to on this qties- ^j^g consideration of the revealed end. The Scriptures speak tion to be at- , . c- ^^ ,^ - - tachedtothe of an ultimate gathering together m one of all things in revealed end— Qhrist — of a Summing up of them in Him as Head.^ It is upifjr^^^ then to be asked, Is this only the external unification of a things in universe not originally intended to be so unified, but in ^^ ' regard to which God's original plan was something entirely different ? Or did it not lie in its original destination ? The end of a thing, we are to remember, is that which in This end not the Diviiic plan determines the beginning of it. What a arbitrary but ^^-^^ -^ ^^ |^g -^ -^ ^^^^^ ^^^ ^^' ^ -^.g original make. To one for which ^ >=> J & the universe turn it from that end, and superinduce another upon it, must already ^quM be to some extent to contradict its true nature. If have been , . . . . • -i t • i fitted. this IS SO in general, must it not be so in the highest degree when the end we speak of is the end of the universe, and the plan in question is that of gathering together in one all things in the Incarnate Son. If such a destination did not lie in the original plan of creation, was it in the nature of things possible that it could afterwards be externally superinduced upon it ? Then what, in this view, becomes of the statement that all things were made for Christ, as well as by Him ? ^ Can it be received at all, for such words go deeper than a mere economical adaptation ? The longer these questions are pondered, the clearer will it appear that Christ's relation to the universe cannot be thought of as something ad- ventitious and contingent; it is vital and organic. This means that His Incarnation had a relation to the whole plan of the world, and not simply to sin. Dr. Fairbairn Dr. Pairbairn himself really admits all that is here agrees^wth contended for, when he says, " The argument derived from this view. the wonderful relationship, the personal and everlasting union into which humanity has been brought with the Godhead, as if the purpose concerning it should be turned into a kind of afterthought, and it should sink, in a manner derogatory to its high and unspeakably important 1 Eph. i. 10. 2 Col. i. 16. IN VOL VED IN THE INCARNA TION 3 2 5 nature, into something arbitrary and contingent, if placed in connection merely with the Fall ; — such an argument derives all its plausibility from the limitations and defects inseparable from a human mode of contemplation. To the eye of Him who sees the end from the beginning, — whose purpose, embracing the whole compass of the provi- dential plan, was formed before even the beginning was effected, — there could be nothing really contingent or un- certain in any part of the process." ^ That is to say, the Incarnation is not to be placed in connection merely with the Fall ; but the plan even of creation had from the first a reference to an Incarnation for the sake of Eedemption from sin, and the perfecting of humanity. When, from this point of view, we look back to the Harmony of Scriptures, we find them in full harmony with the ideas now ^"'^P^^^^ '^^^^ ^ ' *' Mts View. indicated. 1. The Scriptures know of only one undivided purpose i. The Scrip- of God, — that eternal purpose which He purposed in Christ ^^7"^ ^^^°'^ ^'^ Jesus, and which embraces, apparently, both creation and divided pur- Eedemption.2 pose of God. 2. We have the clearest acknowledgment, as has already 2. Assert a been shown, of a direct relation of the Son to the work ^1^^^'^^ ^ejation oj the Cion as creation.^ It does not detract from the suggestiveness of to creation. the passages which declare this relation, but immensely adds to it, that, as Dr. Fairbairn says, the subject of the assertions is the historical Christ, He by whom believers have obtained Eedemption, and in whom they have forgiveness of sins. For the drift of the passages is evidently to bring these two things more completely into line — the work of creation and 1 Typology of Scripture, 4tli ed. i. p. 133. 2 Cf. Weiss, Biblical Theology of New Testament, ii. pp. 97-100 (Eng. trans.). On Eph. iii. 9 he says : *' If it is said that the mystery of salvation was hid from eternity in God, who created the universe, it is indicated by this character- istic of God, that the purpose of salvation is connected in the closest way with the plan of the world, which began to be realised in creation ; and that purpose having been formed by the Creator before the creation of the world, was regula- tive even in its creation." 3 John i. 3 ; 1 Cor. viii. 6 ; Col. i. 15-18 ; Heb. i. 3. 326 THE HIGHER CONCEPT OF GOD the work of Eedemption, and to show them to be parts of one Divine plan. 3. Represent 3. Still more significant is the fact already insisted on, Christ as the i\^q^^^ j^ somc of the abovo passages, Christ is not only repre- Jinal cause of • i i n 1 p Creation. scntcd as the agent in creation, but as the final cause or creation. " All things have been created through Him, and unto Him." ^ He is the Alpha and Omega, the First and the Last.^ Indirectly suggestive of the same idea are the passages which speak of " the kingdom prepared for (believers) from the foundation of the world " ; ^ of " the Lamb slain from the foundation of the world," ^ of Christ as "foreknown indeed before the foundation of the world," etc.^ 4. God's pur- 4. There are the express statements, also already quoted, pose actually ^j ^^^ g^^j ^^ ^j^-^j^ g^^.g purposc actually tends. I may tmification of here again avail myself of the words of Bishop Lightfoot, all things in commenting on the words "unto Him."^ "All things," he Christ. ° ^ Bishop Light' says, " must find their meeting-point, their reconciliation, at foot on this, length in Him from whom they took their rise — in the Word as mediatorial agent, and through the Word in the Father as the primary source. . . . This ultimate goal of the present dispensation in time is similarly stated in several passages. Sometimes it is represented as the birth-throe and deliverance of all creation through Christ — as Eom. viii. 19, sq. Some- times it is the absolute and final subjection of universal nature to Him — as 1 Cor. xv. 28. Sometimes it is the reconciliation of all things through Him — as below, ver. 20. Sometimes it is the recapitulation, the gathering up in one head, of the universe in Him — as Eph. i. 10. The image involved in this last passage best illustrates the particular expression in the text ; but all alike enunciate the same truth in different terms. The Eternal Word is the goal of the universe, as He was the starting-point. It must end in unity, as it proceeded from unity; and the centre of this unity is Christ." 1 Col. i. 16. 2 Rev. i. 8, 17. ' Matt. xxv. 34. * Rev. xiii. 8. « 1 Pet. i. 20 (R.V.). 6 Col. i. 16. IN VOL VED IN THE INCARNA TION. 3 2 7 The conclusion I reach is that this question, Would there Summary and have been an Incarnation but for sin ? is one which rests <^<^^^'^^^^^^*^- upon a false abstraction. There is but one plan of God from the creation of the world, and it includes at once the permission of sin and the purpose of Eedemption from it. It includes, therefore, the Incarnation as an integral and essential part of that purpose. The Incarnation has, indeed, immediate reference to Eedemption ; but it has at the same time a wider scope. It aims at carrying through the plan of creation, and conducts, not the redeemed portion of humanity alone, but the universe at large to its goal. Thisvieiv There is, however, another inference which we are entitled ''^^^f f^^ ^ on Christ s to draw — one which remarkably illustrates the unity of the Person. Christian view. If we rightly interpret that view as im- plying that the Divine plan of the world contemplates an ultimate gathering up of all things into one in Christ, it will readily be seen that this, in turn, reflects back light on the doctrine of Christ's Person. It shows that we are right in ascribing to Him full and proper Divinity, not less than true humanity. For it is manifest that no other than a truly Divine Being is fitted to occupy this position which Scrip- ture, with consentient voice, assigns to Christ. From the is in harmony new height we have reached, light falls back also on Christ's '^ll^J^^^^^^"^ place in the universe, in remarkable agreement with our previous postulates as to the nature of man, his place in creation, and the law of ascent and development to which God's natural works so strikingly testify. As the inferior stages of existence are summed up in man, who stands at the head of the earthly creation, and forms a first link between the natural and the spiritual, so are all stages of humanity summed up in Christ, who in His Person as God-man links the creation absolutely with God. LECTURE VIII. SCfje Incarnation anti Eetremptton from &in. " In whom we have our Eedemption through His blood, the forgiveness of our trespasses, according to the riches of His grace." — Paul. "The faith of the Atonement presupposes the faith of the Incarnation. It may be also said historically that the faith of the Incarnation has usually had conjoined with it the faith of the Atonement. The great question which has divided men as to these fundamental doctrines of the faith has been the relation in which they stand to each other — which was to be regarded as primary, which secondary? Was an Atonement the great necessity in reference to man's salvation, out of which the necessity for an Incarnation arose, because a Divine Saviour alone could make an adequate Atonement for sin? — or, is the Incarnation to be regarded as the primary and highest fact in the history of God's relation to man, in the light of which God's interest in man and purpose for man can alone be truly seen ? — and is the Atonement to be contemplated as taking place in order to the fulfilment of the Divine purpose for man which the In- carnation reveals?" — J. M'Leod Campbell. "Fourier's void. And Comte absurd, and Cabet puerile. Subsist no rules of life outside of life. No perfect manners without Christian souls ; The Christ Himself had been no Lawgiver Unless He had given the Life, too, with the Law." Mrs. Browning. LECTUEE VIII. THE INCARNATION AND REDEMPTION FROM SIN. Whatever we may think of the Incarnation in its wider Christianity a relations to the plan of the world and the ends of creation as ^^J'^f'^'^ ^f ^ Redemption, a whole, it remains the fact that in Scripture it is always brought into immediate connection with sin, and with the purpose of God in Eedemption. " He was manifested to take away sins," says John, " and in Him was no sin " ; ^ and so say all the writers in the New Testament. Christianity is thus distinctively a religion of Redemption, — a great Divine economy for the recovery of men from the guilt and power of sin — from a state of estrangement and hostility to God — to a state of holiness and blessedness in the favour of God, and of fitness for the attainment of their true destination. It is in this light we are to consider it in the present Lecture. We may, therefore, set aside at once as alien to the true Vieivs which Christian view, or at least as indequate and defective, all such ^'^"•^ ^^^^ '^•^^'^^• representations of Christianity as see in its Founder only a great religious teacher and preacher of righteousness ; or a great religious and social reformer, such as has often appeared in the history of the world; or a great philan- thropist, caring for the bodies and souls of men ; or one whose main business it was to inoculate men with a new " enthusiasm for humanity " ; ^ or a teacher with a new ethical secret to impart to mankind; or even such representations as see in Him only a new spiritual Head of humanity, whose work it is to complete the old creation, and lift the race to a J 1 John iii. 5 (R.V.). 2 ^^^e Homo, chap. 17. ?>?>2 THE INCARNATION AND Comparison and contrast ivith Buddhism. Special Quest- ion — the con- nection of Redemption with the sufferings and death of Christ, higher platform of spiritual attainment, or help it a stage further onwards to the goal of its perfection. Christ is all this, but He is infinitely more. God's end in His creation indeed stands, as also His purpose to realise it ; but, under the conditions in which humanity exists, that end can only be realised through a Eedemption, and it is this Eedemption which Christ pre-eminently came into the world to effect. A comparison has sometimes been instituted in this respect between Christianity and Buddhism, which also is in some sort a religion of Eedemption. But the comparison only brings out the more conspicuously the unique and original character of the Christian system. For whereas Buddhism starts from the conception of the inherent evil and misery of existence, and the Eedemption which it promises as the result of indefinitely prolonged striving through many suc- cessive lives, is the eternal rest and peace of non-being ; the Christian view, on the other hand, starts from the conception that everything in its original nature and in the intent of its Creator is good, and that the evil of the world is the result of wrong and perverted development ; holds, therefore, that Eedemption from it is possible by the use of appropriate means. And Eedemption here includes, not merely deliver- ance from existing evils, but restoration of the Divine like- ness which has been lost by man, and the ultimate blessedness of the life everlasting.^ The chief point on which the discussion in this subject turns is the connection of Eedemption with the Person and work of Christ. Here at the outset it is necessary to guard against too narrow an idea of Eedemption, as if the saving work of Christ were limited to that doing and suffering which we call the Atonement. The ends of Christ's coming into the world include much more than the making Atonement for sin. This is recognised when the Church names three offices ^ "In Buddhism Redemption comes from below; in Christianity it is from above ; in Buddhism it comes from man ; in Christianity it comes from God." — Carpenter, Permanent Elements of Religion, Introduction, p. 34. REDEMPTION FROM SIN. 333 which Christ executes as our Eedeemer — a prophetic and a kingly as well as a priestly office. Yet it is principally on the question of Atonement, or the manner of the connection of Eedemption with the doing and suffering of Christ, that discussion has been directed, and it is to this subject I shall specially address myself.^ I. It needs no proof that all the New Testament writers /. Scripture who refer to the subject regard the forgiveness of sins and *^^^f^^^°^^y ^^ . this subject — the salvation of men as connected in quite a peculiar way the apostolic with the death of Christ ; and it is not less evident that they w^'^«^-^^- do this because they ascribe to Christ's death a sacrificial and expiatory value. They do this further, as every one must feel, not in a mere poetic and figurative way, but with the most intense conviction thab they have really been redeemed and reconciled to God by the death of Christ upon the cross. The how of this redemptive transaction most of them may not enter into, but Paul, at least, has a theology on this subject, with the main outlines of which the others, judging from tlie expressions they use, and the propitiatory virtue they ascribe to the shedding of Christ's blood, must be held to agree.^ Happily we are freed from the necessity of dwelling long on the 1 To prevent ambiguity, it is desirable that I should refer here for a moment to the meaning of this word "atonement." It is the eq[uivalent of the New Testament word xtt.rcx.xxa.yvi, which is always translated in the Revised Version "reconciliation," and of the German words "Versohnung" and "Siihnung." It is therefore capable of a wider and of a more special sense. In both cases it refers to the "reconciliation" or " making-at-one " of mankind and God, and in New Testament usage imjjlies that this reconciliation is effected through ex- piation or propitiation. But in the one case it denotes the actual state of recon- ciliation with God into which believers are introduced through Christ, whose work is then regarded as the means to this end ; whereas in the other it denotes the reconciling act itself — mankind being viewed as objectively reconciled to God in the work or death of His Son, which is the sense the term ^rdinarily bears when we speak of the Atonement. Dr. Hodge would discard this term altogether because of its ambiguity, and substitute for the latter meaning of it the term "satisfaction." — Systematic Theology, ii. p. 469. But "satisfac- tion " is too narrow and exclusively forensic a term to express all that is implied in the reconciling act. 2 The passages may be seen classified in Dale on The Atonement, or in Pro- fessor Crawford's Doctrine of Holy Scripture respecting the Atonement. 334 THE INCARNA TION AND apostolic testimony on this subject, for the same reason which I gave when speaking of the Person of Christ — namely, that impartial exegesis and Biblical theology practically grant to us all that we assert. Apart from such occasional specula- tions as, e.g., Holsten's, that, in Paul's view, sin is identical with the body or " flesh " of Christ, and that the slaying of Christ's body or flesh denotes the slaying of sin,^ it will be found that the descriptions given of the teaching of the Epistles as to the work of Eedemption do not differ much from those met with in our ordinary books of theology. The accounts given us, e.g., by Baur or Eeuss or Pfleiderer, or even by Martineau^ — not to speak of an exegete like Meyer, or a Biblical theologian like Weiss — of the doctrine of Paul on Eedemption, is what, with very slight exception, any of us could accept. The same is true of the other New Testa- ment witnesses — of the Epistle to the Hebrews, of Peter, of Eevelation, of the Epistles of John. With differences of stand- point and strong individual characteristics, it is acknowledged that they teach a fundamentally identical doctrine of Eedemp- tion from the guilt and power of sin through Christ, and particularly that they ascribe to His death a sacrificial or propitiatory virtue. To get rid of the attribution of this view to the author of the Fourth Gospel, Dr. Martineau has to assume, in face of all probability and evidence, that the Eirst Epistle of John is not by the same author as the Gospel.^ Does Christ's Morc important is the question which the newer forms of ^withthafT controversy press upon us — whether Christ's doctrine on this the apostles ? subjcct is the samc as that of His apostles ? We have a ^whkhthuis *^®ology 0^ propitiation in the Epistles — that is admitted ; contested. but havc WO anything of the same kind in Christ's own 1 Cf. Weiss, Biblical Theology of Neio Testament, i. p. 422 (Eng. trans.). - Cf. Seat of Authority, pp. 478, 479. Baur's views may be seen in his Pavlus, pp. 537-547 ; those of Reuss in his Hist, of Christ. Theol. in the Apost. Age, ii. pp. 68-74 (Eng. trans.) ; those of Lipsius in his Dogmatik, p. 498 ; those of Pfleiderer in his Urchristenthum, pp. 222-242. ^ Seat of Authority, p. 509. REDEMPTION FROM SIN. 335 words? Was not the gospel preached in Galilee a much simpler thing than the theological gospel preached by Paul, or contained in the Epistle to the Hebrews, and is it not free from every trace of this cumbrous machinery of Atonement, or of pardon on the ground of the suffering and death of another? Where, it is asked, is there any vestige of this doctrine in the Sermon on the Mount, or in the parable of the Prodigal Son ? Is this doctrine not an aftergrowth, the result of the running of the Divine thoughts of the Master, and of the impression produced by His life and death, into the moulds of Jewish sacrificial conceptions which had no real affinity with them, and have indeed served to overlay and obscure them to the apprehension of all subsequent generations ? If the case were as this objection represents it, I grant that insufficiency it would have very serious consequences for our faith. If the ^•'^ ^^t •^ ■'■ grounds. apostles of Christ — the very persons chosen by Him to com- municate His doctrine to the world, and to whom He promised the illumination of His Spirit for this very end — could so seriously misunderstand and pervert His doctrine on this essential point, I do not know what credit we should be able to attach to them on any point on which they profess to represent the mind of Christ. Dr. Dale has argued this point so strongly in his book on the Atonement ^ that I do not need to do more than refer to it. It is not for us, it is for the objector to explain, how the guides and leaders of the apos- tolic Church should come with this singular unanimity to shift the centre of gravity in Christ's gospel from where He Himself had placed it, and so to mislead the world as to the essentials of their Master's teaching. But the question remains — Have they done so? And this is certainly not proved from the circumstance that, in Christ's own teaching, the doctrine of Atonement is not brought forward with the same explicitness as it is in the apostolic writings. That Christ took up a central position in relation to the truths which He proclaimed, that He invited men to faith in Himself as the ^ Lecture IV. 336 THE INCARNATION AND Proof that Christ attached a redemptive significance to His death. condition of their participation in the blessings of the king- dom, that He promised the fullest satisfaction in the approach- ing kingdom to the hunger and thirst of the spiritually needy, that He declared that it was by their relation to Him that men would be ultimately judged, — this lies upon the surface of the Gospels. But that He should have preached to the Galilean multitudes truths which, on any hypothesis, could only be intelligible after His death and resurrection had taken place, — that He should have done this before He had even publicly proclaimed Himself to be the Messiah, — this is to ask what in reason we are not entitled to expect. Before there could be any preaching of an Atonement, there must be an Atonement to preach. I grant, however, that if the apostolic gospel really represents the truth about Christ's work, the facts of His early manifestation ought to bear this out. They must be such, at least, that the apostolic gospel is felt to be the natural key to them. In reality they are much more ; for, taken in their entirety, they point unmistak- ably to just such a view as the apostolic doctrine gives, and explain to us, what else would be a complete enigma, how such a doctrine could arise. It is significant that the most unbiassed modern inquiry into Christ's teaching recognises that He attributed a redemp- tive virtue to His death, and connected it directly with the forgiveness of sins.^ Eitschl also acknowledges that Christ first, and after Him the oldest witnesses, connect Eedemption or forgiveness, not with His prophetic office, but much more with the fact of His death.^ Taking the testimony of the Gospels as a whole, I think it is exceedingly strong. It is remarkable that in the Gospel of John, the most spiritual of the four, we have both the earliest and the clearest state- ments of the fact that Christ's death stood in direct relation to the salvation of the world. I refer to such passages as ^ Cf. Baldensperger's Selbstbewiisstsein Jesu, 2nd ed. pp. 153-155 ; Wendt's Lehre Jesu, ii. pp. 526-530 ; Schmoller's Die Lehre vom Beiche Gottes, pp. 144, 145, etc. 2 Unterricht, p. 36. REDEMPTION EROM SIN, 337 the Baptist's utterance, "Behold the Lamb of God, which taketh away the sin of the world" ;i Christ's words to Mcodemus, "As Moses lifted up the serpent in the wilder- ness, even so must the Son of Man be lifted up," 2 etc. ; and the sayings in chap. vi. about giving His flesh for the life of the world.3 In the Synoptic Gospels, while in one saying at least of the earlier ministry there is a premonition of the cross,* it was not till after Peter's great confession that Jesus began to speak explicitly to the disciples of His approaching sufferings and death.^ Then we have many utterances declaring the neces- sity of His death, and such a saying throwing light upon its character, as, " For verily the Son of Man came not to be ministered unto, but to minister and to give His life a ransom for many." 6 On the Mount of Transfiguration it was the decease which He should accomplish at Jerusalem which was the subject of discourse.^ But the clearest expression of all prior to His death is His solemn utterance at the institution of the Supper, when, taking the sacramental bread and wine, He said, " This is My body ; this is My blood of the Cove- nant, which is shed for many, unto remission of sins." ^ To this must be added the instruction which the disciples are recorded to have received after the resurrection. On one remarkable occasion we read that Christ said to them, " foolish men, and slow of heart to believe in all that the prophets have spoken ! Behoved it not the Christ to suffer these things, and to enter into His glory. And beginning from Moses and from all the prophets, He interpreted to them in all the Scriptures the things concerning Himself." ^ And at a later meeting with the eleven, " These are My words which I spake unto you, while I was yet with you, how that all things must needs be fulfilled, which are written in the law 1 John i. 29. Marg. in R.V., "beareth the sin." Cf. Dorner, System of Doctrine, iii. p. 415. 2 John ill. 15. 3 Vers. 51-56. 4 Matt. ix. 15. 5 Mark viii. 31, ix. 12, 31, x. 33, 34. « Mark x. 45 (R. V. ). 7 Luke ix. 31. 8 Matt. xxvi. 26, 28 (R.V.). ^ Luke xxiv. 25-27 (R.V.). 22 338 THE INCARNATION AND Grounds on which the apostolic Church pro- ceeded. I. The object- ive facts of ChHsfs death, resur- rection, etc. These needed an explanu" Hon, 2. Christ's sayings on the meaning and necessity of His death. of Moses, and the prophets, and the psalms concerning Me. Then opened He their mind, that they might understand the Scriptures ; and He said unto them. Thus it is written, that the Christ should suffer and rise again from the dead on the third day, and that repentance and remission of sins should be preached in His name unto all the nations, beginning from Jerusalem." ^ These passages are invaluable as giving us a clue to the clearness and decision of the subsequent apostolic doctrine. What these lengthened interpretations of Jesus included we cannot of course tell, but they must have embraced much light on the significance of His death ; and for the nature of that light we are entitled to look to the Spirit-guided utterances of the apostles who received it. The apostolic Church, therefore, was not left without guid- ance in its construction of the doctrine of Eedemption, any more than in its construction of the doctrine of Christ's Person. It had various groups of facts to lead it to a conclusion. 1. It had the objective facts themselves of Christ's death, resurrection, and subsequent exaltation to heaven. Holding fast as it did to the Messiahship and Divine Sonship of Jesus, it could not but find the death of Christ a dark and per- plexing-problem, till it grasped the solution in the thought of a Divine necessity for that death for the accomplishment of the Messianic salvation. With this had to be taken the fact of Christ's own command that repentance and remission of sins should be preached in His name to all nations. Behind this again were all the facts of His earthly life, with its Kevelations of Messianic power and grace, and its not less wonderful self-abasement and sorrow. 2. There were the sayings of Christ, above referred to, which threw light upon the meaning and necessity of His sufferings and death. These, in the new illumination of the Spirit, would be earnestly pondered, and are sufficient to explain all the forms in which Christ's death came to be regarded by them. ^ Luke xxiv. 44-47. REDEMPTION FROM SIN. 339 3. There was an earlier Eevelation with which the new 3. The teach- economy stood in the closest relations, and to which Christ ^^'^^-^^'^' ^'''^ Covenant as Himself had directed His disciples for instruction regarding thriving light Himself. In many ways also this old covenant aided them ^'^ ^^^^^^'^ auork. to a fuller comprehension of the meaning of the sufferings and death of Christ. (1) There were the prophecies of the Old Testament, — (i) its pro- foremost among them that wonderful prophecy of the Servant ^^.f^^"^""'^"^^' of Jehovah in Isaiah liii., to whose undeserved sufferings, lovingly and submissively borne, an expiatory virtue is expressly ascribed. " There is no exegete," says Pro- fessor G. A. Smith, " but agrees to this ... all agree to the fact that by Himself, or by God, the Servant's life is offered an expiation for sin — a satisfaction to the law of God." 1 (2) There was the work of the law in men's hearts, be- (2) The Law netting in them the sense of sin, and, in virtue of its ^^ ^^^^^^^^ « *='*=' sense o/stn, propaedeutic character, creating the deep feeling of the need and feeling 0/ of Eedemption. It is with this consciousness of the want oi^^J^^^^^f Atonement, righteousness wrought by the law, and the consequent feeling of the need of Eedemption, that Paul's doctrine specially connects itself. (3) There was the sacrificial system of the Old Testament. (3) The This was the remaining key in the hands of the early Church ^^^^^^^^^ ° •' *' economy. to unlock the significance of Christ's death. If the law created the sense of sin, it was the sacrificial system which created the idea of Atonement. This, in turn, is the thought to which the Epistle to the Hebrews specially attaches itself. When, therefore, exception is taken to the apostles casting their ideas into the moulds of Jewish sacrificial conceptions, we have rather to ask whether the economy of sacrifice was not Divinely prepared for this very end, that it might fore- shadow the one and true Sacrifice by which the sin of the world is taken away, and whether this is not in accordance with all the data at our disposal ? 1 TAe Booh of Isaidhy ii. p. 364. 340 THE INCARNA TION AND II. Expiana- 11. Assuming, however, that all this is granted, — that it is Hon of the conceded that the apostles teach Eedemption through the redemptive . , . significance death of Christ, and that there is no discrepancy in this of Christ's respect between their teaching and that of Christ Himself — sufferings and i . p -i • i • -i death— we are still far from a solution or the many questions which Theories of jjj^y be raised in regard to this great cardinal doctrine. Indeed our real task is only commencing. Those who think that, on the basis of Scripture passages, a ready-made theory of Atonement lies to our hand, have only to consider the slow and gradual process by which the doctrine of the Church has been built up to its present form, to become convinced of the contrary. Christ's death is a sacrifice, but in what sense is it a sacrifice ? It is a propitiation for our sins ; but what are the elements in it which give it value as a propitiation ? It is connected with the remission of sins ; but what is the nature of this connection? These are questions as keenly discussed to-day as ever, and we cannot avoid considering them in connection with the deep and difficult problems which they raise. Legitimacy of Now I for One do not think it is the duty of the Church ^th'^^^\^^t ^^ ^^^^ content — as some express it — with the fact of the Atonement, without further inquiring as deeply as we can into its nature. I cannot believe that any doctrine of Scripture — least of all the doctrine of Atonement, which is represented in Scripture as the Eevelation of the innermost heart of God to man, the central and supreme manifestation of His love to the world — was ever meant to lie like a dead- weight on our understanding, incapable of being in any degree assimilated by our thought. Certain it is that any doctrine which is treated in this way will not long retain its hold on men's convictions, but will sooner or later be swept out of the way as a piece of useless theological lumber. The Atonement, as Dr. John M'Leod Campbell was fond of putting it, must be capable of being seen in its own light. I grant, indeed, that the fact of the Atonement is greater than all our apprehensions of it. We are here in the very holy of holies of the Christian REDEMPTION FROM SIN. 341 faith, and our treatment of the subject cannot be too reveren- tial. The one thing a 'priori certain about the Atonement is that it has heights and depths, lengths and breadths, greater than any line of ours can fathom or span. It is this which Elements of should make us patient of what are called theories of the ^7'^''^/'^ ^^^ theories. Atonement. I do not know any one of these theories of which it can justly be said that it is unmixed error, — which has not rather in the heart of it a portion of the truth, — which does not apprehend some side or aspect of the Atone- ment which other theories neglect, or have thrust into the background. Instead, therefore, of being too keen to scent error in these theories, our wiser plan will be to be ever on the outlook for an enlargement of our knowledge of the truth through them. If I might indicate in a word what I take to be the Tendency of tendency of the modern treatment of the Atonement, I would ^^^ ^!^^ ^^' '' ctisstons on say that it consists in the endeavour to give a spiritual inter- this subject— pretation to the great fact which lies at the heart of our ^^^^^^f^ ^^«- . . . nect the Atone- Eedemption, — not necessarily to deny its judicial aspect, for mettt with that, I take it, will be found impossible, — but to remove from ^P^^^^^^^ laws. it the hard, legal aspect it is apt to assume when treated as a purely external fact, without regard to its inner spiritual content; and, further, to bring it into harmony with the spiritual laws and analogies which obtain in other spheres. There is the attempt (1) to find spiritual laws which will make the Atonement itself intelligible ; and (2) to find spiritual laws which connect the Atonement with the new life which springs from it. I may add that this is a depart- ment of the truth in which I think that the theology of our own country has rendered better service to the Christian view than the theology of the continent. In accordance with my plan, I am led to study this subject The Atone- of Atonement through Christ especially from the point of view ^^l^2red7rom of the Incarnation. There is an advantage in this method, the point of for as, on the one hand, we see how the Atonement rises ^^^^ '^^^^f * ' Incarnation. naturally out of the Incarnation, so that the Son of God could 342 THE INCARNATION AND not appear in our nature without undertaking such a work as this term denotes; so, on the other, we see that the Incarnation is itself a pledge and anticipation of reconcilia- tion. It is evident that such an event could never have taken place had there been no purpose or possibility of salvation; had humanity been a hopelessly ruined and re- jected race. In principle, therefore, the Incarnation is the declaration of a purpose to save the world. It is more : it is itself a certain stage in that reconciliation, and the point of departure for every other. In the Incarnation, God and man are already in a sense one. In Christ a pure point of union is established with our fallen and sin-laden humanity, and this carries with it the assurance that everything else that is necessary for the complete recovery of the world to God Theorieswhich will not be lacking. Theories, therefore, have never been emphasise this ^^nting in the Church which, in one form or another, lay the point of view. ^ " stress in Eedemption on the simple fact of the Incarnation. As Dr. Hodge has expressed it, " The Incarnation itself, the union of the Divine and human natures, was the great saving act. Christ redeems us by what He is, not by what He does." ^ Germs of such theories appear in some of the early Church fathers, e.g. in Irenseus.^ They reappeared in the middle ages, and at the Eeformation.^ They have a modern analogue in the theories of the Hegelian school, which in the realised unity of God and humanity in Christ, see the prototype of that unity of God and man which is to be accomplished in the race in general. The thought of the identity of Incar- nation and Eedemption colours modern theology in many other ways.* These theories are obviously defective, if meant ^ System. Theology, ii. p. 585. 2 ^.g., " To this end the Word of God was made Man, and He who was the Son of God became the Son of Man, that man, having been taken into the Word, and receiving the adoption, might become the Son of God."— Iren. iii. 19. Harnack finds a germ of this doctrine in Justin Martyr. — Dogmenge- schickie, i. p. 459. There are, however, other elements in the teaching on Redemption of all these Fathers. ^ E.g. Osiander, Schwenkfeld. * E.g., in the school of Erskine of Linlathen. Cf. Murphy, Scientifc Basis REDEMPTION FROM SIN, 343 to exhaust the whole Scripture doctrine on the subject ; but they have their point of truth in this, that the perfect union of the Word with humanity is already a reconciliation of the race with God in principle, and is, besides, the medium by which a new Divine life is introduced into humanity — a view with which the theology of John specially connects itself. In further considering the theories on this subject, it will Three points be convenient to observe that all theories of Eedemption ^^^^^f^J^ ^ granted m all within Christian limits agree in taking for granted three Christian things as included under this term : — theories of , Redemption — 1. There is the removal of guilt, or of the consciousness of i. Removal of guilt, which carries with it the sense of the Divine forgiveness, g^i^^— forgive- ness, 2. There is the breaking down of the actual enmity of the 2. Breaking heart and will to God, and the turning of the sinner from ^f^^ ^f dead works to serve the living and true God. enmity. 3. There is the taking up of the believer into the positive 3. Fellowship fellowship of eternal life with Christ, and into the conscious- '^V^f^^^^^ ness of a Divine Sonship. These are the immediate effects, from which others follow in a changed relation to the world, gradual progress in holiness, and deliverance at death and in eternity from all natural and spiritual evils. Accordingly now as theories relate themselves predomin- Theories differ antly to one or other of these points of view, they present a ^^J;^/^^'^^^ different aspect. one or other of 1. Theories which attach themselves by preference to the ^'^.^'^^^''''^^^-^ •^ ^ view — last point of view — that of fellowship — are apt to regard i. Redemption Christ chiefly as the type of the normal relation of God to ^f reception J J ^ . . into Christ s humanity, and to subordinate the other aspects of His life andy^//^^^/^^^. work to this. of Faith (a disciple of this school) : " I do not speak of the Incarnation as one act and the Atonement as another — they are one and the same Divine act, which in itself is called the Incarnation, and in its results is called the Atone- ment. The act of the Son of God in becoming a partaker of our nature is the Incarnation ; the result of this act, in making us partakers of the Divine nature, is the Atonement or Reconciliation ; though these latter two words are both of them inadequate." — P. 384. 344 THE INCARNATION AND 2. Christ's work as the supreme moral dynamic. 3. Christ's ivork as expiation. More detailed examinatiott of theories — 2. Theories which attach themselves to the second point of view — the breaking down of the sinner's enmity — regard Christ's work as a great moral dynamic — " the power of God unto salvation,"^ the effect of which is to break down the natural distrust of the heart towards God, and to melt the sinner into penitence, — " to bring men," as Bushnell expresses it, " out of their sins, and so out of their penalties." ^ 3. Theories which attach themselves to the first point of view — the removal of guilt — lay special stress on the relation of Christ's work to the Divine righteousness, and view it specially as an expiation. A perfect theory, if we could obtain it, would be one which did justice to all these standpoints, and presented them in their scriptural relations to each other and to the Person and work of the Eedeemer. Without adhering rigidly to the scheme here indicated, which would be indeed impossible, seeing that the different theories cross each other at innumerable points, I shall now glance at the chief standpoints represented in these theories, and try to show that they gradually lead us up to a view which embraces them all, and is in harmony with the full Scripture testimony. 1. We have a class of theories which start from the idea of fellowship, based on the unique relation which Christ sustains to the race as perfect, archetypal Man — a relation expressed in the title — " Son of Man." The point on which stress is laid here is the solidarity between Christ and the race which He came to save ; a true thought in itself, and one which takes the place in modern theology of the older way of looking at Christ's relation to the race as purely federal or official. The typical example of this class of Representative i\iQoxiQ^ is Schlcicrmacher's. With the idea of fellow- Christ. ^^^P Schleiermacher combines that of representation. The essence of Eedemption, in his view, consists in deliver- ance from the miserable contradiction of flesh and spirit, ■^ Rom. i, 16. 2 YicaiHous Sacrijice, p. 7. I. Theories of fellowship — Schleier- macher, etc. REDEMPTION FR OM SIN. 345 through being taken up into the fellowship of Christ's life of holiness and blessedness.^ As standing in this fellowship with Christ, believers are the objects of the love of God, who looks upon them in Him. " Christ," he says, " purely represents us before God in virtue of His own perfect fulfilment of the Divine will, to which, through His life in us, the impulse is active in us also, so that in this connection with Him we also are objects of the Divine good-pleasure." ^ In thus speaking of Christ in His sinless perfection as representing believers before God, it might appear as if Schleiermacher held a doctrine of imputation, — indeed, he says this is the true meaning of that much misunderstood phrase, the imputation of the righteous- ness of Christ.^ When, however, we probe the matter a little further, his meaning is found to be nothing more than this — that God already sees in the initial stage of the believer's holiness the germ of his subsequent full perfection, — of that perfection of which Christ is the pattern or type, — and views him in the light of that ideal.* This thought of a justification through germinal holiness, is a favourite one with writers of a mystical and speculative tendency ; but it manifestly shifts the ground of acceptance from Christ for us to Christ in us, and treats objective reconciliation as unnecessary.^ In Schleiermacher's theory, accordingly, as in those of a kindred Schhier- type, Christ's sufferings and death have only a very ^^"^- "^^fclns/s'^ ordinate place. These sufferings arose from His being in a sufferings, etc. world where evils are a necessary result of sin, and from His fellow-feeling with us in our sins. They may therefore be called substitutionary, as endured by a sinless Being for the sake of others, but they are in no sense satisfactory or expiatory. They are connected with our Kedemption as teaching us to feel that outward evils are not necessarily penal, but chiefly through the Revelation they give us of Christ's ^ "The Redeemer takes believers up into the fellowship of His un- troubled blessedness, and this is His atoning activity." — Dtr clir'istl. GlauhCy sec. 101. 2 Ihid. ii. p. 133. 3 /j^-^^ ^i p_ 133, 4 m^^ ji, pp. 133^ 134. ^ See Note A. — The Germ Theory of Justification. 346 THE INCARNA TION AND constancy and love, and through the moral impression they are fitted to make upon us.^ Schleiermacher's theory in the end thus passes over into one of moral influence ; indeed, it is through the powerful working of Christ's Personality upon us that we are moved to enter into fellowship with Him at all. He is our Eedeemer through the exceptional strength of His God-consciousness, by which our own is invigorated to overcome sin. If, then, we ask how, on this theory, the sense of guilt is removed, the answer we get is very curious. In fellowship with Christ, Schleiermacher says, the believer is a new man, and in the new man sin is no longer active. Sin in the believer is but the after-workiug and back-working of the old man, and as such the believer does not identify himself with it.^ He is relieved, therefore, from the conscious- ness of guilt. Something like this is Kant's theory,^ and in our own days it is the theory of a section of the Plymouth Brethren — so do extremes meet. But it is evident that, on this hypothesis, the doctrine of forgiveness is retained only in name. The old man is not forgiven, and the new man does not need forgiveness. Between the two, forgiveness falls to the ground.* 2. Theories 2. Schleicrmacher, in his treatment of Christ's sufferings, based omdea jj^^g special stress on His sympathy or fellow-feeling with us, Bushneii. as a causc of 'these sufferings. This gives us a point of transition to a second class of theories, the keynote of which may be said to be sympathy. The starting-point here is not the thought of Christ's archetypal perfection, but the ^ Cf. on these views, Der christl. Glauhe, ii. pp. 136-147. ^ Der christl. Glaiibe, ii. p. 194. What Schleiermacher means by forgiveness of sins is indicated in the following sentence : ' ' The beginning here is the vanishing of the old man, consequently also of the old manner of referring all evil to sin, therefore the vanishing of the consciousness of desert of punishment, consequently the tirst thing in the moment of reconciliation is the forgiveness of sin. "—P. 105. ^ Religion innerhalh der Grenzen der bloss. Vernunft, Book ii. sec. 3. ^ Ritschl rightly remarks that what Schleiermacher calls reconciliation with God is really reconciliation with evil, — "the reconciliation of man with suifer- iilg, with his position in the world, which as sinner he had traced to his guilt." — Recht. und Ver. i. p. 470 (Eng. trans.). REDEMPTION FROM SIN. 347 fitness of Christianity in a dynamical relation to break down the enmity of the sinner's heart to God. The best-known type of this class of theory is Dr. Bushnell's, in his original and freshest presentation of it in his work on Vicarious Sacrifice. The strong and true point in Dr. Bushnell's theory Real substitu- is in its insistence on the vicarious element involved in the *^°^ involves sympathetic very nature of sympathetic love. We speak of Christ's sub- identification stitutionary work,^ — of His standing, suffering, dying io^ ~^^^^^^^^- 1 i i n, 1 1 -1 -1 . . , tionary forces Sinners, — but how often do we apprehend this in a purely in u^^^ external and official way ! It is the merit of Dr. Bushnell's book that, with a wealth of illustration drawn from every sphere of life in which a like law of substitution prevails, he makes us feel that it is something real and vital. When we speak of sympathy, we are already in a region in which substitutionary forces are at work. " None of us liveth to himself, and none dieth to himself." ^ We benefit and suffer involuntarily through each other, but we have it also in our power to enter voluntarily into the partnership of the world's joys and sorrows, and by bearing the burdens of others to help to relieve them of their load. From His unique relation to our race, this law applied in the highest degree to Christ. In the whole domain of love. Divine and human, we find substitutionary forces acting ; but in Christ's life we find them acting at a maximum. Christ not only wears our nature, but in the exercise of a perfect sympathy He truly identifies Himself with us in our lot, bears our sins and sorrows on His soul, and represents us to the Father, not as an external legal surety, but with a throbbing heart of love. This of itself may not be Atonement — we shall see immediately it is not — but whatever else there is in Atonement, Scripture warrants us in saying that at least there is this. " Himself took our infirmities, and bare our diseases," says Matthew,^ in a passage which Dr. Bushnell 1 Cf. Dorner, System of Doctrine, iv. pp. 89-98 : "There are substitutionary forces, and a receptiveness for them in humanity." 2 Rom. xiv. 8 (R.V.). '^ Matt. viii. 17. 348 THE INCARNATION AND Points in which this theory comes short. adopts as the key to his theory. " It behoved Him in all things to be made like unto His brethren, that He might be a merciful and faithful High Priest in things pertaining to God, to make propitiation for the sins of the people." ^ This, then, is the key which Dr. Bushnell gives us to the vicarious sufferings of Christ — that of sympathetic love ; and so far as the book in question goes, it is the whole key. If I were disposed to criticise the theory minutely, I might remark that, on Dr. Bushnell's own principles, it is too narrow to cover all the facts. To get an adequate explanation of Christ's undeserved sufferings, alike as regards their nature, their motive, and their end, we need a wider view of them than is covered by this single word — sympathy. Sympathy, in a pure and holy nature like Christ's, was necessarily one cause of His sufferings, but it was not the only cause. He suffered from natural causes — as hunger and thirst, from the unbelief of the world, from the persecutions and malice of His enemies, from temptations of the devil, from the faith- lessness and desertion of disciples, etc. Deeper and more mysterious causes of suffering are not obscurely intimated in the Gospel narratives. Sympathy was only indirectly con- cerned with all these. If it be said that it was the sym- pathetic entrance into and endurance of these sufferings, which gave them their vicarious character, I would remark that we need here a wider word than sympathy. Christ voluntarily took upon Him abasement, suffering, and death for the salvation of men ; but He did so, not simply from sympathy, but — as Dr. Bushnell also often recognises, though still generally emphasising the sympathetic aspect — in a spirit of large, self-sacrificing love. Love includes sympathy, but is not necessarily exhausted by it. "We take also too narrow a view when we seek in the moral influence of sympathy or love the sole key to the peculiar fruitfulness of self-sacrifice. That self-sacrifice acts as a potent inspiration to like deeds in others — that it has power to soften and iHeb. ii. 17(R.V.); cf. v. 12. REDEMPTION FROM SIN. 349 subdue the obdurate heart — is a great truth. But it should not be overlooked that a main part of the secret of the fruit- fulness of self-sacrifice lies in the way in which one life is linked with another, and society is bound together as a whole ; so that through the labours and sacrifices of one, or of a handful — martyrs or patriots — benefits accrue to multitudes who never come within the range of its moral influence.^ This leads directly to another remark — namely, that Dr. Sympathy Bushnell does not give any clear answer to the question, ^^^'^^—^^^ ° " u > doing what ? What was the distinctive life-task, or vocation, in the fulfil- ment of which these great and heavy sorrows came upon Christ ? This is a point of very great importance. Sym- pathy, or disinterested love, will lead one person to undertake labours and undergo sacrifices for another, but the sacrifice is undergone, not for the mere sake of displaying sympathy, but always in the prosecution of some independent end. The mother wears out her strength for her sick child, but it is in the hope that by her nursing she will aid in its recovery. The philanthropist will devote life and fortune for the cause in which he is interested, but it is in carrying out plans and projects which he thinks will contribute to the success of his object. If we ask, then, what was the work which Christ came into the world to do, in the accomplishment of which He endured such sufferings ? it will not do to reply simply — to manifest sympathy, for the sake of the moral impression to be produced by it. We must still ask, What was the work which made submission to this suffering necessary ? To this question Dr. Bushnell gives us no very definite answer, none which carries us beyond Christ's immediate ministries to soul and body, or His witness-bearing in word or deed for the Father. But even this must have for its content some special declaration of God's character and will, if it is not simply to point us back to the exhibition of love in the vicarious suffering. It is on the latter really that Dr. Bushnell lays all 1 This is admirably worked out in tlie section on the fruitfulness of sacrifice in Bishop Westcott's The Victorij of the Cross, ii. 23-35. 350 THE INCARNATION AND the stress ; the suffering in his view is not simply a necessary incident in the prosecution of some independent task of love, but is the main, substantial reason of Christ's appearance in the world.^ If, on the other hand, we lay the chief weight on the witness of Christ, and view His sufferings in subordina- tion to this as furnishing occasions for the manifestation of His patience, steadfastness, and love to men — then is His work purely declarative. His sufferings add nothing to its content, and owe their value for redemptive purposes solely to their power of moral enforcement. Removes It is obvious that, if Dr. Bushnell's theory be true, vicari- Christ's work ^^g goffering which has redemptive efficacy, is not confined to uniqtie post- Christ, but runs through the whole spiritual universe. This, tion—non- indeed, is what he asserts.^ It points, however, to a clear recognition of ,..,.. . , ., ,, t p /^^ • its expiatory ^^i^ct in his vicw, luasmuch as it removes the work of Christ character. from that unique and exceptional position which the Scrip- tures constantly ascribe to it. Even were this difficulty surmounted, there remains the crowning objection, which is the really fatal one — namely, that in resolving the redeeming ef&cacy of the sufferings of Christ solely into their moral influence, the theory runs directly counter to the explicit and uniform declarations of the New Testament, which put in the foreground their expiatory and propitiatory character. It is the less necessary to ask whether Dr. Bushnell's theory in this respect is adequate, since he himself at a subsequent period was compelled to modify it in favour of the recogni- zor. BushneWs tion of an objective element in the Atonement. In his later later modifica- ^^^^^ ^^ Forqiveness and Law, he tells us that he had formerly tton of his . view. conceived the whole import and effect of Christ's work to lie in its reconciling power on others ; now he has been brought ^ The work of Christ he conceives of "as beginning at the point of sacrifice, vicarious sacrifice, ending at the same, and being just this all through." — Vicarious Sacrijice, Introduction, p. 35 (1886). On the sense in which he does regard Christ's work as declarative, i.e. as a Revelation of the eternal vicarious sufferings of the Godhead, see below. . ^ VicxLrious Sacrifice, pp. 17, 18. "The suffering of Christ," he says, "was vicarious suffering in no way peculiar to Him, save in degree." — P. 68. REDEMPTION FROM SIN. 35 1 to see that it has a propitiatory effect on God also. The peculiar view which underlies this second work — namely, that God must overcome His repugnance to the sinner by making cost or sacrifice for him, need not detain us here, especially as I do not know of anyone who has ever adopted it.^ But I cannot refrain from adverting, as most of Dr. Bushnell's critics have done, to the striking evidence which Striking ad- even the earlier volume affords of the necessity of recognising ^"-^^f^"^ ^« ;^" •z 00 earlier work. an objective propitiation. There is, perhaps, nothing more curious in literature than the way in which, in the closing chapter of his Vicarious Sacrifice, after exhausting all his powers to convince us that the efficacy of Christ's sufferings lies solely in their moral efficacy. Dr. Bushnell practically throws the whole theory he has been inculcating to the winds as inadequate for the moral and spiritual needs of men. " In the facts of our Lord's passion," he says, " out- wardly regarded, there is no sacrifice, or oblation, or atone- ment, or propitiation, but simply a living and dying thus and thus ... If, then, the question arises. How are we to use such a history so as to be reconciled by it ? we hardly know in what way to begin. How shall we come to God by the help of this martyrdom ? How shall we turn it, or turn ourselves under it, so as to be justified and set in peace with God ? Plainly there is a want here, and this want is met by giving a thought-form to the facts which is not in the facts them- selves. They are put directly into the moulds of the altar, and we are called to accept the crucified God-Man as our 1 In this work Dr. Bushnell develops the idea already suggested in his earlier book (pp. 18, 35, 37), that Christ's sacrifice has its chief significance as a revelation of the eternal sacrifice in God's own nature. "The transactional matter of Christ's life and death," he says, " is a si)ecimen chapter, so to speak, of the infinite book that records the eternal going on of God's blessed nature within. ... All God's forgiving dispositions are dateless, and are east in this mould. The Lambhood nature is in Him, and the cross set up, before the Incarnate Son arrives. ... I have already said that the propitiation, so called, is not a fact accomplished in time, but an historic matter represented in that way, to exhibit the interior, ante-mundane, eternally proceeding sacrifice of the Lamb that was slain before the foundation of the world."— Pp. 60, 61, 74. This, surely, is to give Christ's work something of a docetic character. 352 THE INCARNATION AND 3. Theories based on idea of vocation — Ritschl. sacrifice, an offering or oblation for us, our propitiation, so as to be sprinkled from our evil conscience — washed, purged, and cleansed from our sin. ... So much is there in this, that without these forms of the altar we should be utterly at a loss in making any use of the Christian facts that would set us in a condition of practical reconciliation with God. Christ is good, beautiful, wonderful ; His disinterested love is a picture by itself; His forgiving patience melts into my feel- ing ; His passion rends my heart. But what is He for ? And how shall He be made to me the salvation that I want ? One word — He is my Sacrifice — opens all to me ; and behold- ing Him, with all my sin upon Him, I count Him my offering ; I come unto God by Him, and enter into the holiest by His blood." 1 Not a word needs to be added to this self-drawn picture by Dr. Bushnell of the inadequacy of a mere moral influence theory of the Atonement. If the soul, in order to find peace with God, must explicitly renounce that theory, how can it be put forward as in any sense a theory of recon- ciliation ? It fails to satisfy the wants of the awakened conscience ; and it fails to satisfy Scripture, which, as we have seen, demands an objective connection between Christ's work and our forgiveness. 3. Before dealing with theories which recognise an object- ive element in the Atonement, it may be useful to glance at a theory which really belongs to the subjective class, though its author has done his best to give it an objective form — I mean the theory of Eitschl. As Bushnell's theory turns on the idea of sympathy, so that of Eitschl may be said to turn on the idea of Vocation. Eitschl's strong point lies precisely in the answer which he gives to the question which Bushnell failed to meet — namely, what was the work which Christ came into the world to do, which entailed on Him suffering and rejection ? What was His vocation, His life-work, His peculiar moral task? It is this thought of Christ's fulfil- ment of His vocation (Beruf) which is the central thing in ^ Vicarious Sacrifice, pp. 460, 461. REDEMPTION FROM SIN. 353 Ptitschl. He speaks of the solidaric unity of Christ with God.i By this he means that Christ adopted God's end in the creation and government of the world (Weltzweck) as His own end, and lived and died to fulfil it. This end is summed up in the establishing of the kingdom of God — that is, of a religious and moral community, in which the members are bound together by love to God and love to man, and act solely from the motive of love ; and in which they attain the end aimed at in all religions, namely, moral supremacy over the world, which is Eitschl's synonym for eternal life.^ This, it will be allowed, is a somewhat bald scheme, and it does not become richer as we proceed. In what sense, we ask, is Christ a Eedeemer ? The essential part of the answer seems to be that through His Eevelation of God's grace and truth, through His preaching of the kingdom of God, and through His personal devotion to God's world-aim. He influences and enables men to turn from their sins, and leads them to appro- priate God's end as their own. The uniqueness of Christ's Person is supposed to be secured by the fact that in Him first the final end of the kingdom of God is realised in a personal life, so that everyone who would undertake the same life-task must do it in dependence on Him.^ Ritschl, there- fore, is able, like Schleiermacher, to speak of Christ as the " Urbild " of humanity in its relation to the kingdom of God, and as such the original object of the love of God, in whom God beholds and loves those who are embraced in His fellow- ship.* But fellowship here means simply unity of moral aim. What significance, on this theory, have the sufferings of Christ? Only this significance, that they are the highest proof of Christ's fidelity in His vocation — the guarantee of the reality of that new relation to God which is exhibited in 1 Unterricht, pp. 20, 21 ; cf. Recht. und Ver. 3rd ed. iii. p. 428. 2 Ihid. pp. 7, 12 ; cf. Recht. und Ver. iii. p. 497 : "Therefore is the direct content of eternal life or of blessedness to be recognised in the religious functions ruling the world."— P. 497 ("Eternal Life or Freedom over the World," title of sec. 54). 3 Ihid. p. 20. * Ihid. p. 20. 23 354 THE INCARNA TION AND His Person.^ Here, as in Schleiermacher, we are plainly back to the theory of a mere moral influence. Eitschl, like Dr. Bushnell, would cast his idea of Christ's death in the moulds of the altar ; but this must be connected with his theory of the Old Testament sacrifices, which, he holds, had no reference to Atonement for sin, but only served to dispel the creature's distrust in drawing near to a great and holy God. Christ, in like manner, by His death, brings us near to God by dispel- ling distrust of God, and inspiring confidence in His grace.^ What, finally, on this theory, becomes of the idea of guilt ? Strictly speaking, guilt is not removed, but God admits us to fellowship with Himself, and to co-operation with Him in work for His kingdom, without our guilt, or feeling of guilt, forming any hindrance thereto.^ This is what Eitschl under- stands by justification. It is the easier for him to take this view that, as we saw before, guilt with him has little objective significance, and exists more for our own feeling than for God.* In proportion as this view is adopted, however, the experience of forgiveness becomes subjective also, and there remains nothing objective but the actual change of mind and feeling.^ It is plain that we have here quite changed the centre of gravity in the Christian view of Eedemption ; and the only remedy is to restore the idea of guilt to its scriptural importance, which, again, necessitates a changed idea of its treatment.^ 1 Cf. Unterricht, pp. 36, 37, 38. 2 Cf. iUd. p. 40. Cf. Dorner's criticism of Ritschl on this point, System of Doctrine, iii. 405, 406. 3 Ihid. p. 32. ^ Eitschl's view of Christ's sufferings and their relation to forgiveness is expounded at length in his Becht. und Vers. 3rd ed. iii. 417-428, 505-533. Cf. specially pp. 422, 511, 512, 513, 524, 574. "Christ's death, in the view of the apostles, is the compendious expression for the fact that Christ has iuAvardly maintained His unity with God and His revelation-position in the whole course of His life. "—P. 511. ^ It is not remarkable, therefore, that Hermann, as quoted by Lipsius, should speak of the forgiveness of sins as "nothing at all particular" {ganz nichts hesonderes"). — Die RitschVsche Theologie, p. 12. Hermann certainly expresses himself very differently in his Verkehr, pp. 39, 40 (2nd ed. p. 103). ^ A kindred view of atonement to Ritschl's is that of F. A. B. Nitzsch in his REDEMPTION FROM SIN. 3^5 f- The theories we are now to consider differ from those we Theories have just had under review in that they recognise an objective "^^^"^^ ^^""T . ./ o ^ ^^^^ ^^ object- element m the Atonement, and in this way come nearer to ive eie^nent in the manifest teaching of Scripture. They recognise \)^^\,t^e Atonement. ^ . , 1 /¥• In what does Chnsts work not only affects us subjectively in the way oi a consist? moral influence, but is an objective work, on the ground of which God forgives sin, and receives us into fellowship with Himself. And the question they raise is, What is the nature of this objective element ? 4. The first answer which is given to this question is by 4. Theories that erroup of theories which find the essential feature in the '^'^"^^'^ '^'^ ^^'^'^ ^ ^ . ofself-sur- Atonement in the surrender of the holy will of Christ to render of holy God. The idea of Atonement here, then, is the self-surrender "^^^^ ^° , God- Maurice^ etc. of the human will to the Divine. This is Maurice's theory, but essentially also that of Kothe^ Pressense, Bahr, Oehler, and many others.^ Here, as in previous theories, Christ is regarded as the Head of the race, and as representing in Him- self all humanity. In this humanity He offers up to God the perfect sacrifice of a will entirely surrendered to His service. As Maurice puts it, " Supposing the Father's will to be a will to all good ; supposing the Son of God, being one with Him and Lord of man, to obey and fulfil in our flesh that will by entering into the lowest condition into which men had fallen through their sin ; supposing this Man to be, for this reason, an object of continual complacency to His Father, and that complacency to be fully drawn out by the death of the Lehrhuch der Evang. Dogmatik, ii. (1892). "God," he holds, "could only forgive the sin of humanity if the representative of humanity was able to afford him the security of a moral renewal of the same, the security of a new humanity. But this Christ did as the Beginner of the new humanity, and as Founder of a community on which He could take over His own fellowship with God. We • cannot, therefore, say that the doing of Christ first made it possible for God the Father to be gi-aciously disposed to men, but rather that He made it possible for God to reveal His grace."— P. 508. Christ is therefore a guarantee to God for our future sanctification. This is not a thought which we find prominent in Scripture, while the scriptural idea that Christ reconciles us to God by removal of our guilt is overlooked. 1 Cf. Rothe's Dogmatik, ii. pp. 265-269 ; Pressens^, Apostolic Age, p. 274 (Eng. trans. 4th ed. ) ; Biihr, Symbolik, etc. 356 THE INCARNATION AND cross ; supposing His death to be a sacrifice, the only com- plete sacrifice ever offered, the entire surrender of the whole spirit and body to God, is not this, in the highest sense, the Atonement ? Is not the true, sinless root of humanity revealed ; is not God in Him reconciled to man ? Is not the cross the meeting-point between man and man, between man and God ? " ^ That which, on this view, gives the sacrifice of Christ its value, is not the suffering, but the perfect ^will of obedience expressed in the suffering. When, according to the Epistle to the Hebrews, sacrifices and offerings, and whole burnt-offerings and sacrifices for sin, God would not, neither had pleasure therein, " then hath He said, Lo, I am come to do Thy will. He taketh away the first, that He may estab- lish the second. By which will we have been sanctified, through the offering of the body of Jesus Christ once for all." ^ This surrender of the will is the only kind of sacrifice God delights in, and it is the perfect Atonement.^ The sin of humanity is its negation of the will of God, and the cross takes back that negation on behalf of humanity. This is brought into harmony with the Old Testament sacrifices by the theory that in these sacrifices it is not the death of the victim that is the essential thing, but the presentation of the blood. The death is only the means of obtaining the blood, which, as the vehicle of the pure life, the offerer presents to God as a covering for his own sin.* True elements Again, there Can be no doubt of the deep spiritual truth m this involved in this theory of the sacrifice which Christ offered for theory ; its defects. our Ecdcmption. We may again say that, whatever else there is in the Atonement, there is this in it. Viewing Christ's death as a sacrifice, we cannot question that the nerve and 1 Theological Essays, p. 147. 2 jjeb. x. 5-10 (R.V.). ^ Erskine of Linlatlien's theory was akin to this: "The true and proper sacrifice for owr sin" is "the shedding out of the blood of owr will — of that will which had offended." — Doctrine of Election, 2nd ed. p. 156. ^ Cf., e.gr., Oehler, Theology of Old Testament, i. p. 411 (Eng. trans.) ; Bahr, Symbolik (see his view criticised by Dorner, System of Doctrine, iii. pp. 407, 408 ; and Fairbairn, Typology, 3rd ed. ii. pp. 290-297). Thus also Eothe, Rielim, Nitzsch, Schultz, etc. REDEMPTION FROM SIN. 357 core of the sacrifice was the holy will, in which, through the Eternal Spirit, He offered Himself without spot or blemish to God.i It was not the mere fact of the sufferings, but that which was the soul of the sufferings, — the holy, loving will in which they were borne, and the self-surrender to the will of the Father in them, which gave them their spiritual value.^ The only question is, Is this the whole of the explanation ? Does this exhaust the meaning of Christ's sacrifice ? Does this fill up the whole of the scriptural testimony regarding it ? And, however fascinated one may be for a time with this theory, it seems impossible permanently to rest in it as adequate. I do not go back on the inadequacy of a theory which lays the whole stress of Atonement on self-sacrifice, without saying sacrifice for what, or in what, but come at once to the point in which it seems peculiarly to fail. That point is, that the Scriptures appear to assert a direct relation of the sacrifice of Christ to the sin and guilt of men, — a direct expiatory power to remove that guilt, — a relation, not only to God's commanding will, but to His condemning will. Not only the Old and New Testament doctrine of the right- eousness and holiness of God, and of His judicial attitude towards sin, — not only the extreme gravity of the scriptural doctrine of guilt, but the deepest feeling of the awakened conscience itself, demands that guilt shall not be simply over- ^ Heb. ix. 14, x. 4-10. ^ This is the point of view emphasised in Bishop Westcott's Tlie Victory of the Gross, which may be classed with this group of theories. The key -words of the book are Fatherhood, Incarnation, Sacrifice. Sufferings in general are viewed in the light of discipline — "a revelation of the Fatherhood of God, who brings back His children to Himself in righteousness and love." — P. 82. Christ bore these sufferings according to the mind of God as " entering into the Divine law of purifying chastisement," ''realising in every pain the healing power of a Father's wisdom."— Pp. 69, 82. But in what sense can we speak of ** purifying chastisement" and "healing power" in the case of the Sinless One ? Bishop Westcott himself has expressions which recognise a deeper relation of sufferings to sin, as where, e.g., Christ is spoken of as gathering "into one supreme sacrifice the bitterness of death, the last penalty of sin, knowing all it means, and bearing it as He knows;" and His sufferings are held as showing "His complete acceptance of the just, the inevitable sentence of God, on the sin of humanity."— Pp. 68, 81. The thoughts of the book are not worked out into perfect clearness. 358 THE INCARNA TION AND looked, but that it shall be dealt with also in the transacting of Christ with God for man, and that the forgiveness which is sealed in His death shall have placed on it the holy sanc- tion of justice as well as that of love. I go on, therefore — 5. Theories 5. To look at theories which not only affirm the offering which recog- q£ ^ j^^iy ^'^ ^f obedience in Christ's sacrifice, but nise a relation ^ . rNii--iTi! togiiiit— recognise its relation to guilt. Such theories include, alter Dorner, etc. ^^ among their representatives, the great bulk of the ablest and most scriptural theologians — as Dorner, Luthardt, Marten - sen, Oosterzee, Godet, etc.; and an undesigned testimony is borne to their substantial truth by the approximations often made to them in theories of a different tendency, and by the difficulty felt in avoiding language which would imply the expiatory view, as well as by the studied accommodation of all parties, as far as possible, to the recognised language of the Church. Yet the dislike of many, and these often men of the most spiritual mind, to the forms of the imputation theology, their inability to rest in anything which seems to them to wear an air of legal fiction, suggests to us the necessity of seeking to approach even this side of the subject from within, and of trying to connect it with spiritual laws which will commend it to the conscience and the heart. Campbeits I may begin here with a theory which, though it opposes theory of itsclf dircctlv to the idea of penal sufferings, yet deals with vicarious •' ^ o ' j repentance and this question of the relation of Atonement to guilt, and has, confession. j tj^ij^j^^ valuable light to throw upon the subject, — more, perhaps, than is sometimes admitted, — I refer to the theory of Dr. John M'Leod Campbell. Dr. Campbell starts with the Incarnation, and his idea is to see the Atonement developing itself naturally and necessarily out of Christ's relation to men as the Incarnate Son — which is, I think, a sound point of view. Next, he distinguishes in Christ's work two sides — (1) a dealing with men on the part of God, and (2) a dealing with God on the part of men ; which, again, I think, is a true distinction. The peculiarity of his theory, and here un- doubtedly it becomes artificial and indefensible, lies in the REDEMPTION FROM SIN, 359 proposal to substitute a vicarious repentance for sins, and confession of sins, for the vicarious endurance of the penalties of transgression.! There is here, first, a confusion between repentance for sins and confession of them. The idea that Christ could in any sense repent of the sins of the humanity which He represented, could bring to God '' a perfect repent- ance " for them, is one totally inadmissible, even though his premiss were granted, which it cannot be, that a perfect repentance would of itself constitute Atonement. That Christ should confess our sins in His high-priestly intercession for us with God is, on the other hand, not inadmissible, but is rightly classed as a part of His substitutionary activity for us. It has its analogies in the intercessory confessions of Moses, Daniel, and Nehemiah, and may very well be regarded by us as an element in the Atonement. When we get behind Dr. Campbell's words, and look at Deeper eie- the kernel of his theory, and even at what he means to '!!'^^^^"^ ^" Campbell's convey by these unfortunate expressions about a perfect view— the repentance, we obtain light on the Atonement which is, i"^f"en"in , . , 111 rrn • response to thmk, valuable. The point of this theory, as I understand God's judg- it — that on which Dr. Campbell himself constantly insists '^^^'^^ ^" ^"'• through all his volume — is, that with the most perfect apprehension of what the sin of man was, on the one hand, and of what the mind of God towards sin, and sin's due at the hands of God, was, on the other, there went up from the depths of Christ's sinless humanity a perfect " Amen " to the righteous judgment of God against sin. There must, there- fore, be recognised, even on Dr. M'Leod Campbell's theory, a certain dealing of Christ with God's wrath — with His judicial condemnation upon sin. "Christ, in dealing with God on behalf of men," he says, " must be conceived of as dealing with the righteous wrath of God against sin, and as according to it that which was due." ^ "Let us consider," he says again, " this ' Amen ' from the depths of the humanity of Christ to the Divine condemnation of sin. What is it in relation ^ Tha Nature of the Atonement, cliap. vii. ^ Ibid. 4th ed. p. 117. 36o THE INCARNA TION AND to God's wrath against sin ? What place has it in Christ's dealing with that wrath ? I answer, He who so responds to the Divine wrath against sin, saying, ' Thou art righteous, Lord, who judgest so,' is necessarily receiving the full apprehension and realisation of that wrath, as well as of that sin against which it comes forth, into his soul' and spirit, into the bosom of the Divine humanity, and so receiving it. He responds to it with a perfect response — a response from the depths of that Divine humanity — and in that perfect re- sponse He absorbs it." ^ If, however, this were all that was in Dr. Campbell's theory, we should still have to say that, valuable as the suggestion is which it contains, it is only a half-truth. It will be observed that, so far as these quota- tions go, it is only a vivid mental realisation of God's wrath against sin to which we are to conceive Christ as responding. He has the perfect realisation of what sin is in man ; He has the perfect realisation of God's mind towards sin ; but He is Himself in no sense brought under the experience of that v/rath, or of its penal effects : it may be thought by many He could not be. And this might seem to detract from the value of that " Amen " from the depths of Christ's humanity on which all the stress is laid. To take an analogous case, it is one thing to be patient and resigned under a vivid mental realisation of possible trials, another thing to be resigned under actual experience of sorrow. Yet the only resignation which has worth is that which has been actually tested in the fires of trial. In order, therefore, that Christ's " Amen " to the judgment of God against sin might have its fullest con- tent, it would appear to be necessary that it should be uttered, not under a mere ideal realisation of what God's wrath against sin is, but under the actual pressure of the judgment which . This response that wrath inflicts. Is this possible ? Strange to say, with "^^atZ'txpeti- ^^^ ^^^ protests against Christ being thought of as enduring ence of the penal evils, it is precisely this view to which Dr. Campbell penal conse.^ in the end comes. He is quite awake to the fact of the ijiiences oj sm. ^ ^ The Nature of the Atonement, p. 118. REDEMPTION FROM SIN. 361 unique character of Christ's sufferings; quite aware that they involved elements found in no ordinary martyr's death ; quite conscious that an " Amen " uttered, as he calls it, " in naked existence," ^ would have little value. It must be uttered under actual experience of the evils which this judgment of God lays on humanity, especially under the experience of death. The closing period of Christ's life, he says, was one of which the distinctive character was suffering in connection with a permitted hour and power of darkness ;2 while his remarks on our Lord's tasting death are so important and apposite that I cannot forbear quoting one or two of them. " When I think of our Lord as tasting death," he says, " it seems to me as if He alone ever truly tasted death. . . . Further, as our Lord alone truly tasted death, so to Him alone had death its perfect meaning as the wages of sin. . . . For thus, in Christ's honouring of the righteous law of God, tlu sentence of the laio was included, as well as the mind of God which that sentence expressed. . . . Had sin existed in men as mere spirits, death could not have been the wages of sin, and any response to the Divine mind concerning sin, which would have been an Atonement for their sin, could only have had spiritual elements; but man being by the constitution of humanity capable of death, and death having come as the wages of sin, it was not simply sin that had to be dealt with, but an existing law with its penalty of death, and that death as already incurred. So that it was not only the Divine mind that had to be responded to, but also that expression of the Divine mind which was contained in God's making death the wages of sin." ^ It is evident how nearly in such passages Dr. Campbell comes to a theory of the Atonement which holds that Christ, as a member of humanity and the new Head of the race, really bore 1 TJie Nature of the Atonement, p. 259. ^ Ibid. p. 224. ^ Ibid. pp. 259-262. He even says: ''The peace maJcing between God and man, which was perfected by our Lord on the Cross, required to its reality the presence to the spirit of Christ of the elements of the alienation as well as the possession by Him of that eternal righteousness in which was the virtue to make peace."— P. 250. The italics in the extracts are Dr. Campbell's own. 362 THE INCARNATION AND in His own Person the penal evils which are the expression of the wrath of God against the sin of the world. He main- tains, indeed, that for Christ these were not really penal evils ; but, in the light of the explanations just given, the difference seems to resolve itself mainly into one of nomenclature. Whatever sense we may give to that expression, " Christ bore the wrath of God for us," it is held by no one to mean that Christ was personally the object of His Father's anger. All that is meant is that by Divine ordainment He passed under the experience of evils which are the expression of God's wrath against sin, or a judgment laid on humanity on account of that sin. The peculiarly valuable idea, as I take it, which Dr. Campbell brings to the elucidation of Christ's sufferings as atoning is — that it was not simply the patience and resignation with which He bore them, not simply the surrender of His will to God in them, but the perfect acknow- ledgment, which accompanied His endurance of theni, of the righteousness of God in their ordainment, which made them a satisfaction for sin, " By that perfect response in Amen to the mind of God, in relation to sin," as he himself expresses it, " is the wrath of God rightly met, and that is accorded to Divine justice which is its due, and could alone satisfy it." ^ Christ's suffer- It is, I own, difficult to frame a theory to which no excep- zngs viewed as ^-^^ ^^^ ^^ taken, which shall show how the sufferinojs of expiatory. " Christ, which were in large part sufferings endured for right- eousness' sake, had at the same time an expiatory value ; yet it is the clear teaching of Scripture that they possess this character. As aids to the apprehension of the subject, the facts remain that these sufferings of the sinless Son of God were voluntarily undertaken, and (what can be said of no other of the race) wholly undeserved ; that Christ did enter, as far as a sinless Being could, into the penal evils of our state, and finally submitted to death — the doom which sin has brought on our humanity ; that He did this with a perfect consciousness and realisation of the relation of these evils to ^ ThE Nature of the Atonement, p. 119. REDEMPTION FROM SIN. 363 sin ; that He experienced the full bitterness of these evils, and, especially in His last hours, was permitted to endure them without even the alleviations and spiritual comforts which many of His own people enjoy; that there were mysterious elements in His sufferings, which outward causes do not seem adequate to explain {e.g. the agony in Geth- semane, the awful darkness of His soul on Calvary), which appear related to His position as our Sin-bearer ; — finally, that in this mortal sorrow, He still retains unbroken His relation to the Father, overcomes our spiritual enemies, so transacts with God for men, so offers Himself to God in substitutionary love on our behalf, so recognises and honours the justice of God in His condemnation of sin, and in the evils that were befalling Himself in consequence of that sin, that His death may fitly be regarded as a satisfaction to righteousness for us — the Eedemption of the world, not, indeed, ijpso facto, but for those who through faith appropriate His sacrifice, die in spirit with Him in His death, and make His righteousness the ground of their hope. Is exception taken — as it was by the Socinians — to \h.^ Objections to idea of the innocent satisfying for the guilty ? Is it asked, ^^'^ '"i^w-the How should the righteous suffer for the guilty ? Is it just suffering for that they should do so? Or, how can the sufferings of the ^^'^ *"^"''^-^* righteous atone for the unrighteous ? I would point out in answer that there are two questions here. The first relates to a matter of fact — the suffering of the righteous for the guilty. We know that they do so. It is the commonest This, in itself fact in our experience. In the or(:janic relation in which we ^-^^^ ^^ ^ o common ex- stand to each other it could not be otherwise. The penalties /^/-zVw^*?, of evil-doing are probably never confined to the actual wrong- ^Pp^'g'I^om ^ r J u ^/^g organic doer, but overflow upon others, and sometimes involve them connection of in untold misery. To impeach the justice of this is to ^^^*^"""^^y' impeach the justice of an organic constitution of the race. Thus far, then, we can say that Christ is no exception to this universal law ; nay. He is the highest exemplification of it. Christ could not enter the world without receiving upon Him 364 THE INCARNA TION AND the brunt of its evils. Just because He was the infinitely- pure and holy One, they fell on Him with greater severity. A writer like Bushnell here often uses the strongest language. He speaks of Christ as incarnated into the curse of the world. " It is," he says, " as if the condemnations of God were upon Him, as they are on all the solidarities of the race into which He is come." ^ " It means," he says again, " that He is incarnated into common condition with us, under what is called the curse ... He must become a habitant with us, a fellow-nature, a brother ; and that He could not be without The real being entered into what is our principal distinction as being question— -LiiKjer the curse ... He has it upon Him, consciously, as the Hoio should ^ stick sufferings cursc or penal shame and disaster of our transgression." ^ The become expta- question is not, therefore, how should Christ, the sinless One, tory for others? The answer Suffer for the guilty ? but, how can sufferings thus endured suggested. bccomc cxpiatory or atoning ? And this I have tried to answer by pointing out the unique relation which Christ sustains to our race, in virtue of which He could become its Eepresentative and Sin-bearer; and, secondly, by indicating how in our humanity He must, as Dr. M'Leod Campbell says, have related Himself to our sins — not only patiently and lovingly enduring sufferings, not only yielding up to His Father a will of obedience in them, but viewing them in the light of their causes, entering fully into God's judgment on the sin of which they were the consequences, and rendering to God in our nature a full and perfect and glorifying response to His justice in them. In this way His sufferings might well become, like those of the Servant of the Lord in Isaiah liii., expiatory. Recapitulation Gathering together, in closing, the various aspects of Christ's andconciu- ^q^.]^ which have been brought before us, we see, I think, the truth of a previous remark that the true or full view of ^ Forgiveness and Law, p. 155. ^ Ibid. pp. 150, 158. Bushnell will have it that his "penal sanctions " are "never punitive, but only coercive and corrective." — P. 132. But what does " penal" mean, if not " punitive ? " And can penalties not be "judicial," and yet up to a certain point "corrective ? " sion. REDEMPTION FROM SIN, 365 Christ's work in Eedemption is wide enough to include them all — takes up the elements of truth in every one of them. A complete view of Christ's work will include the fact that in the Incarnation a new Divine life has entered humanity; will include the fact that Christ is our perfect Representative before God as the new Head of the race, and the wearer of our humanity in its pure and perfect form ; will include the fact of an organic relation of Christ with all the members of the race, in virtue of which He entered, not merely outwardly, but in the most real and vital way, into the fellowship of our sin and suffering, and truly bore us on His heart before God as a merciful and faithful High Priest ; will include the idea of a vocation which Christ had as Founder of the kingdom of God on earth, though this vocation will embrace, not only the Eevelation of the Father's character and doing His will among men, but also the making reconciliation for the sins of the people ; will include the fact of a holy and perfect and continuous surrender of Christ's will to God, as an offering, through the Eternal Spirit, in humanity, of that which man ought to render, but is unable in his own strength to give — the presentation to God in humanity, there- fore, of a perfect righteousness, on the ground of which humanity stands in a new relation to God, and is accepted in the Beloved ; — will include, finally, a dealing with God in reference to the guilt of sin, which is not simply a sympa- thetic realisation of the burden of that guilt as it rests on us, nor yet simply a confession of sins in our name, nor yet simply an acknowledgment in humanity of the righteousness of God in visiting our sins with wrath and judgment, but is a positive entrance into the penal evils of our condition, and, above all, into death as the last and most terrible of these evils, in order that in these also He might become one with us, and under that experience might render to God what was due to His judicial righteousness, — an Atonement which, as Dr. M'Leod Campbell says, has in it an " Amen " from the depths of our humanity towards the righteous judgment of 366 THE INCARNA TION AND REDEMPTION. God on our sins. So far from this latter aspect of Christ's work — the judicial — being to be thrown into the background, it is, I think, the one which the apostolic theology specially fastens upon as the ground of the remission of sins, and the means by which the sinner is brought into a relation of peace with God — the ground, as Bunyan phrases it, on which God "justly justifies the sinner." The Incarnate Christ, as the Son of God, incarnate in our nature, is the Son alone ^^ ^^^ qualified to undertake this work ; and as Son of cotdd achieve Redemption. God and Son of Man He did it. He alone could enter, on the one hand, into the meaning of the sin of the world ; on the other, into a realisation of all that was due to that sin from God, not minimising either the sin or the righteousness, but doing justice to both, upholding righteousness, yet opening to the world the gates of a forgiving mercy. In Him we see that done which we could not do ; we see that brought which we could not bring ; we see that reparation made to a broken law which we could not make ; we see, at the same time, a righteousness consummated we long to make our own, a victory over the world we long to share, a will of love we long to have reproduced in ourselves, a grandeur of self- sacrifice we long to imitate. And, appropriating that sacrifice, not only in its atoning merit, but in its inward spirit, we know ourselves redeemed and reconciled. LECTURE IX. V^t Incarnation antr ©uman iBesting. "This earth too small For Love Divine ? Is God not Infinite ? If so, His Love is Infinite. Too small ! One famished babe meets pity oft from man More than an army slain ! Too small for Love ! Was earth too small to be of God created ? Why then too small to be redeemed ? " Aubrey De Verb. "And so beside the silent sea I wait the muffled oar, No harm from Him can come to me On ocean or on shore. " I know not where His islands lift Their fronded palms in air, I only know I cannot drift Beyond His love and care." Whittier. "The last enemy that shall be abolished is death." — Paul. LECTUKE IX. THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY. Every view of the world has its eschatology. It cannot help Necessity of an raising the question of the whither, as well as of the what ^^''^^^^^^^'^ and the whence ? " my Lord," said Daniel to the angel, " what shall be the end of these things ? " ^ What is the end, the final destiny, of the individual ? Does he perish at death, or does he enter into another state of being ; and under what conditions of happiness or woe does he exist there ? What is the end, the final aim, of the great whole ; that far-off Divine event, to which the whole creation moves ? It is vain to tell man not to ask these questions. He will ask them, and must ask them. He will pore over every scrap of fact, or trace of law, which seems to give any indication of an answer. He will try from the experience of the past, and the knowledge of the present, to deduce what the future shall be. He will peer as far as he can into the unseen ; and, where knowledge fails, will weave from his hopes and trusts pictures and conjectures. It is not religions only, but philosophy and science also, Eschatology in which have their eschatologies. The Stoics had their concep- ^'^.'*^'''''-^'^->' ^'^'^ ° ^ ^ science. tions of world-cycles, when everything, reabsorbed in the primal fire, was produced anew exactly as before. The Buddhists had their kalpas, or world-ages, periods of destruc- tion and restoration, " during which (as in Brahmanism) constant universes are supposed to appear, disappear, and reappear " ; ^ new worlds, phoenix-like, incessantly rising out ^ Dan. xii. 8. 2 Buddhism, by Trofessor Monier- Williams, p. 120. Cf. p. 118. 24 370 THE INCARNA TION AND HUMAN DESTINY, of the ruins of the old. The pessimist, Hart maun, has his eschatology as truly as the New Testament has its.^ Kant speculated, in his Theory of the Heavens, on the birth and death of worlds ; and Strauss compares the cosmos to one of those tropical trees on which, simultaneously, here a blossom bursts into flower, there a ripe fruit drops from the bough.^ How is the science of to-day seen peering on into the future, trying to make out what shall be the end of these things ; whither the changes, and transformations, and integrations, and dissolutions of the physical universe all tend ; and what fate is in store for the earth, and for the physical system as a whole ! Mr. Spencer has his eschatology, and speculates on a boundless space, holding here and there extinct suns, fated to remain thus for ever ; though he clings to the hope that in some way he knows not, out of the ashes of this old universe, a new universe wall arise.^ The authors of The Unseen Universe say, "What happens to our system will happen likewise to the whole visible universe, which will, if finite, become in time a lifeless mass, if indeed it be not doomed to utter desolation. In fine, it will become old and efifete, no less truly than the individual, — it is a glorious garment this visible universe, but not an immortal one — we must look elsewhere, if we are to be clothed with immortality as with a garment." ^ The Christian The Christian view of the world, also, has its eschatology view esc ato- — ^^^ ^^^ -^^ -^^ physical issucs, not very different from that logical because > r j » j teieological. just described. The Christian view, however, is positive, where that of science is negative ; ethical, where it is material ; human, where it is cosmogonic ; ending in personal immortality, where this ends in extinction and death. The eschatology of Christianity springs from its character as a teieological religion. The highest type of " Weltanschauung " is that which seeks to grasp the unity of the world through ^ On Hartmann's "Cosmic Suicide," see Caro's Lt Pesnmisme, chap. viii. 2 Der alte und der neue Glauhe, p. 152. 3 First Principles, p. 529, 537. * Unseen Universe, 5tli ed. p. 196. Cf. pp. 165, 166. THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY. 371 the conception of an end or aim. It is only through a con- ception of the world that is itself unified that man can give a true unity to his life — only in reference to an aim or end that he can organise his life to a consistent whole. On the cycle hypothesis, no satisfactory view of life is possible. All is vanity and vexation of spirit. A truly purposeful view of life is only possible on the basis of a world -view which gathers itself up to a highest definite aim. As giving this, Christianity is the teleological religion 'par excellence. It is, says Dorner, the only absolute teleological religion.^ In one other respect Christianity agrees with the higher speculation — scientific and other — and that is in its breadth and scope, extending in its issues far beyond this little spot called earth, and touching in its influence the remotest regions of creation. I. Before entering directly on eschatological questions, it /. The astro- niay be worth our while, in connection with the fact j^st ''.^''"'"''^ ''^-^'^'" •^ ^ ' "^ tion to mentioned, to glance at the objection sometimes raised to Christianity. Christianity from the enlargement of our knowledge of the physical universe through modern discoveries — chiefly through astronomy. The enormous expansion of our ideas in regard to the extent of the physical universe brought about through the telescope, and the corresponding sense of the insignifi- cance of our planet, awakened by comparison with the gigantic whole, is supposed by many to be fatal to belief in Christ- ianity. Strauss boldly affirms that the Copernican system gave the death-blow to the Christian view of the world.^ So long as the earth was believed to be the centre of the universe, and the only inhabited spot in it, so long was it possible to maintain that God had a peculiar love to the inhabitants of our world, and had sent His Son for their Itedemption. But when the true relation of the earth to the sun, and to the other planets of the system, was discovered ^ System of Doctrine, iv. p. 376 (Eng. trans.)- Of. Martensen, DogmaticSy pp. 465, 466 (Eng. trans.). - Is fatal even to belief in a personal God. Cf. Ins Der alte und der neue. Glaube, pp. 108-110. 3 7 2 THE INCARNA TION AND HUMAN DESTINY. — when, beyond this, the infinite depths of the heavens were laid bare, with their innumerable suns, galaxies, and con- stellations, to which our own sun, with its attendant planets, is but as a drop in the immeasurable ocean — then the idea that this little globe of ours — this insignificant speck — should become the scene of so stupendous a Divine drama as the Christian religion represents ; should be the peculiar object of God's favours, and the recipient of His Revelations ; that, above all, the Son of God should become incarnate on its surface, seemed nothing less than incredible. In a universe teeming with worlds, presumably inhabited by intelligences of every order and degree, it is thought preposterous to connect the Deity in this peculiar and transcendent way with one of the very smallest of them. Reply: Are Here, first, since the objection is made in the name of ^^^h"b-t% science, it might fairly be asked how far the premiss on which it rests — the assumption of innumerable spheres peopled with such intelligences as we have in man (I do not refer to angelic intelligences, for the Christian view has always admitted these, without our thoughts of the greatness of the Christian Redemption being thereby lessened, but corporeal inhabitants of other planets and worlds) — how far this assumption is scientifically established, or is even matter of plausible conjecture. Kant declared that he would not hesitate to stake his all on the truth of the proposition — if there were any way of bringing it to the test of experience — that at least some one of the planets which we see is inhabited ; ^ but others may not be prepared to share his confidence. Of direct scientific evidence, of course, there is none, and the argument from analogy is weakened rather than strengthened by the progress of modern discovery. If astronomy has been extending our views of the universe in space, geology has been extending our views of our own world backwards in time, and it has been pointed out that though preparation was being made through the millions of years of ^ Krililc d. r. Ver. p. 561, Erdmann's ed. (Eng. trans, p. 500). THE INCARNA TION AND HUMAN DESTINY, 3 7 3 that long past, it is only in quite recent times that man appeared upon its surface, and then under conditions which we have no reason to suppose exist in any other planet of our system.1 Are there not worlds in the making, as well as worlds already made ? 2 Certain it is, that of the seven hundred and fifty-one parts, or thereabouts, into which our solar system can be divided, life, such as we know it, or can conceive of it, is not found in seven hundred and fifty of them, for the sun monopolises that enormous proportion of the whole for himself ; and of the remaining one part, it is only an insignificant fraction in which the physical conditions exist which render any of the higher conditions of life possible.^ If the same proportion prevails through the universe, the area reserved for rational life will be corre- spondingly restricted. But, in truth, we know nothing of planets in other parts of the heavens at all, or even whether — except in one or two problematical instances — such bodies exist.* What if, after all, our little planet should be the Eden of the planetary system — the only spot on which a place has been prepared for rational life, or in which the conditions favourable to its blossoming forth have been found ? ^ It is a singular circumstance that the objection here urged against Christianity is not exclusively applicable to it, but bears as strongly against all those speculative systems — Hegelianism, Schopenhauerism, Hartmannism, etc. — which have been hatched in the full light of the nineteenth century. Here, too, it is assumed that our planet stands alone as the ^ This is the point specially made in Whewell's The Plurality of Worlds. 2 Sun and planets. ^ In Mars, and even here Professor Ball doubts the possibility. — Story of the Heavens, p. 190. 4 Professor Ball says : " It may be that, as the other stars are suns, so they too may have other planets circulating round them ; but of this we know nothing. Of the stars we can only say that they are points of light, and if they had hosts of planets these planets must for ever remain invisible to us, even if they were many times as large as Jupiter." — Story of the Heavens, p. 95. '^ " The earth is perhaps at this hour the only inhabited globe in the midst of almost boundless space." — Eenan, Dialogues, p. 61. 374 THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY, place in which the absolute has come to consciousness of himself (or itself), and where the great drama of his historical evolution is unfolded — where, in Hegelian phrase, God is incarnate in man ! ^ The objection Apart from such considerations, however, the real reply to a quantitative ^j^-^ objection to the Christian view of the world is that it one, • 1 • J £ is a merely quantitative one. Be the physical magnitude or the universe what it may, it remains the fact that, on this little planet, life hm effloresced into reason ; that we have here a race of rational beings who bear God's image, and are capable of knowing, loving, and obeying Him. This is a fact against which it is absurd to put into comparison any mere quantities of inanimate matter — any number of suns, nebulae, and planets. Even suppose that there were other inhabited worlds, or any number of them, this does not detract from the soul's value in this world. Mind, if it has the powers we know it has, is not less great because other minds may exist elsewhere. Man is not less great, because he is not alone great. If he is a spiritual being, — if he has a soul of infinite worth, which is the Christian assumption, — that fact is not affected though there were a whole universe- full of other spiritual beings, as indeed the Christian Church has always believed there is. The truth is, what we have underlying this objection is that very anthropomorphism in thinking about God against which the objection is directed. It is thought that while it might be worthy of God to care for man if he existed alone, it is derogatory to God's greatness to think of him when there are so many other objects in the universe. Or it is thought that God is a Being so exalted that He will lose sight of the individual in the crowd. Those who think thus must have very unworthy ideas of the Being whom they wish to exalt ; must forget, too, that the ^ Cf. Renan: "For my part I think that there is not in the universe any intelligence superior to that of man, so that the greatest genius of our I)lanet is truly the priest of the world, since he is the highest reflection of it." — Dialogues, p. 283. See on Kenan's extraordinary eschatology — Note A. THE INCARNA TION AND HUMAN DESTINY. 375 universe caa only exist on the condition that God is present in the little as in the great ; that His knowledge, power, and care extend, not to things in the mass, but to each atom of matter separately, to each tiniest blade of grass, to each insect on the wing, and animalcule in the drop of water. It is the Bible which gives the true philosophy, when it teaches that the same God who cares for stars cares also for souls; that the very hairs of our head are all numbered ; that not even a sparrow falls to the ground without our heavenly Father.i But the question still remains, even if all these bright The bearing worlds were inhabited — which they are not, — inhabited by ^/"•^^^/^^ ^'^^ '' '' question. rational beings like to man himself, — are they sinful ? Sin retains its awful significance in the universe, no matter how many worlds there may be. If this world alone is sinful, then it is worthy of God to redeem it. Have men's hearts not recognised the Divineness of that parable of Christ about the lost sheep ? Is it not the Divinest thing that God can do to seek and to save the lost ? Suppose that this universe were as full of intelligent life as the objection represents, but that this world is the one lost sheep of the Divine flock, would it not be worthy of the Good Shepherd to seek it out and save it ? Shall its size prevent ? Then is the worth of the soul a thing to be weighed in scales ? Mr. Spencer, in one passage of his writings, thinks he has Mr. Spencer's destroyed the case for Eevelation, when he asks us if we can ^J^*^^^'* believe that " the Cause to which we can put no limits in space or time, and of which our entire solar system is a relatively infinitesimal product, took the disguise of a man for the purpose of covenanting with a shepherd - chief in Syria." 2 He first defines God in terms which put Him infinitely far away from us, and then asks us to combine with this a conception which seems to contradict it. But what if God is not only the "Cause" of all things — the infinitely great Creator of stars and systems — but, as Mr. 1 Ps. cxlvii. 3, 4 ; Matt. x. 29-31. ^ Ecchs. Institidions, p. 704. The issues of Redemption not confined to this planet. 376 THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY. Spencer's own principles might lead him to hold, One also infinitely near to us, — "Speak to Him, thou, for He hears, and spirit with spirit can meet; Closer is He than breathing, and nearer than hands or feet," ^ — and, beyond this, infinite goodness and love as well, — is it then so strange that He should draw a Syrian shepherd to His side, and should establish a covenant with him which had for its ultimate aim, not that shepherd's personal aggrandise- ment, but the blessing, through him, of all mankind ? But finally, and this is the complete answer to the objec- tion, if the Christian view is true, the scope of God's purpose is not confined to this little planet, but embraces all the realms of creation.^ The Incarnation is not a fact the signi- I ficance of which is confined to earth. The Scriptures do not so represent it, but seek rather to impress us with the thought of how wide this purpose of God is ; how extensive in its sweep ; how far-reaching in its issues. The objection to the Christian scheme with many, I fancy, will rather be, that with its base on earth it rises too high ; that when it speaks to us of the bearing of the gospel on distant parts of creation, of angels desiring to look into it, of principalities and powers in the heavenly places being instructed by it in the many- sided wisdom of God, — above all, of all things in heaven and in earth being gathered up in Christ,^ — it presents us with a plan the magnitude of which soars beyond our powers of belief. But if the Divine plan is on a scale of this grandeur, why complain because its starting-point is this physically small globe ? The answer to this objection, as to the similar one drawn from the earthly lowliness of Christ, must be, ^ resjpice finem — look to the end ! //. Principles H. In proceeding now to deal directly with the eschato- tion ofischa'to- ^^S^^^^ relations of the Christian view, it is to be remembered logical 1 Tennyson's Higher Pantheism. prophecy. 2 This is the argument developed in Chalmers' celebrated Astronomical Discourses. 3 I pyj._ I 12 ; Eph. ii. 10, i. 10, etc. THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY. 377 that it stands differently with lines of prophecy projected into the future, from what it does with facts already past. In dealing with the history of God's past Eevelations — with the ages before the advent, with the earthly life and Eevela- tion of Jesus Christ, with the subsequent course of God's Providence in His Church — we are dealing with that which has already been. It stands in concrete reality before us, and we can reason from it as a thing known in its totality and its details. But when the subject of Eevelation is that which is yet to be, especially that which is yet to be under forms and conditions of which we have no direct experience, the case is widely altered. Here it is at most outlines we can look for ; and even these outlines will be largely clothed in figure and symbol; the spiritual kernel will seek • material investiture to body itself forth ; the conditions of the future will require to be presented largely in forms borrowed from known relations.^ The outstanding thoughts will be sufficiently apparent, but the forms in which these thoughts are cast will partake of metaphor and image. Examples of undue literalism in the interpretation of RitschVs prophetic language will occur to everyone ; as an example on ^^J^^^^°^ ^f the other side, I may instance Eitschl, who, because of the figurative character of the language employed, sweeps the whole of the New Testament eschatology on one side, and simply takes no account of it. This is a drastic method, which makes us wonder why, if these representations convey no intelligible representations to the mind, use was made of them at all. With Eitschl, the sole thing of value is the Ritschi and idea of the kingdom of God, for the realisation of which we ^f°!' '''j^' o ' kingdom cj. are to labour in this world. The form which the kingdom of God- God will assume beyond this life we cannot know, and need not concern ourselves about. The recoil from this one-sided position of Eitschl is seen in the further development of his school, particularly in Kaftan, who precisely reverses Eitschl's standpoint, and transports the good of the kingdom of God ^ Cf. Fairbairn on Prophecy, chap. iv. sec. 4. 378 THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY. entirely into the life beyond. " The certainty of an eternal life in a kingdom of God," he says, " which is above the world, which lies to us as yet in the beyond, is the very The nearer nerve of our Christian piety." ^ This is an exaggeration on aim of Christ- ^^ other side, in opposition to which the truth of Kitschl's ianity — the , , . , coming of the vicw has to be Contended for, that there is a kingdom of kingdom of Qq^j ^^ \^^ striven for even in this world. What did Christ God on earth. „•« . i-r. i • t«t come for, if not to impart a new life to humanity, which, working from within outwards, is destined to transform all human relations — all family and social life, all industry and commerce, all art and literature, all government and relations among peoples — till the kingdoms of this world are become the kingdoms of our Lord and of His Christ ? ^ Whether more slowly or more rapidly, whether peacefully or, as Scrip- ture seems to indicate, by a succession of crises, surely this grand result of a kingdom of God will be brought about ; and it is our duty and privilege to pray and labour for it. Relation of What is the reproach which is sometimes brought against this to modern Christianity by its enemies, but that of " other- worldliness " social move- " " vients. — of exclusive devotion to a good beyond this life, to the neglect of interests lying immediately to hand ? And what is the remedy for this reproach, but to show that Christianity is a power also for temporal and social salvation, a leaven which is to permeate the whole lump of humanity ? It is on this side that a great and fruitful field opens itself up for Christian effort in the present day ; on this side that Christ- ianity finds itself in touch with some of the most character- istic movements of the time. The ideals of the day are pre-eminently social ; the key- word of Positivism is " Altruism " — the organisation of humanity for social efforts ; the call is to a " service of humanity " ; ^ the air is full of ideas, schemes, ^ The sentence is quoted from Pfleiderer, Beligioiisphilosophle, ii. p. 206 (Eng. trans.). Cf. Kaftan, Wesen, pp. 67, 71, 171, 173, 214, 213, etc.; Wahr- heit, p. 547, etc. 2 Rev. xi. 15. ^ Cf. Cotter Morisou's The Service of Man. "The worship of deities has passed into 'the Service of Man.' Instead of Theolatry, we have Anthropo- THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY. 379 Utopias, theories of social reform ; and we who believe that Christianity is the motive power which alone can effectually attain what these systems of men are striving after, are surely bound to put our faith to the proof, and show to men that in deed and in truth, and not in word only, the kingdom of God has come nigh to them. We know something of what Christianity did in the Koman Empire as a power of social purification and reform ; ^ of what it did in the middle ages in the Christianising and disciplining of barbarous nations ; of the power it has been in modern times as the inspiration of the great moral and philanthropic movements of the century ;2 and this power of Christianity is likely to be yet greater in the future than in the past. Tliere is yet vast work to be accomplished ere the kingdom of God is fully come.^ This, therefore, may be said to be the nearer aim of Christ- History has ianity — the coming of the kingdom of God on earth; but^^"^^'^." , •/ o o ^ traitsthon to beyond this there is, as certainly, another end. Even on eschatology earth the kingdom of God does not consist supremely, ox^^^^^^' even peculiarly, in the possession of outward good, but in the inward life of the Spirit, in righteousness and peace and joy in the Holy Ghost.* History, too, moves onward to its goal, which is not simply a transformed society, but a winding up of all terrestrial affairs, and the transition from a world of time to a new order of things in eternity, in which the good of the kingdom of God will be perfectly realised. In dealing with the eschatology proper of the Christian The positive view, it will be of advantage to turn our attention first to JJ^^ ^^^^^^ those aspects of it which stand out distinct and clear. I Christian latry ; the divine service has become human service." — P. 265. As if the truest service of God did not carry in it the service of humanity. 1 Cf. Loring Brace's Gesta Chrisii ; Schmidt's Social Results of Early Christianity (Eng. trans.) ; Uhlhorn's Christian Charity in tJie Early Church; Lecky's History of European Morals, etc. 2 Mr. Stead, himself an enthusiast in social work, says : "Most good work is done by Christians. Mrs. Besant herself expressed to me that they did very little indeed, and those who did were only those who like herself had been brought up Christians." — Church of the Future, p. 9. 3 See Appendix on **The Idea of the Kingdom of God." * Rom. xiv. 17. view. 38o THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY, Three things clear : — I. The end as respects the believer is conformity to the image of the Son. 2. This in- cludes likeness to His glorious body ; the Resurrection. (I) The Re- demption of the body not an accident^ but an essen- tial part of the Christian vieiv. have said that a truly purposeful life is only possible on the basis of a world-view which has a definite aim. What that aim is in the Christian view,, as respects its positive and bright side, is seen in the light of the Incarnation. There are three points here which seem to stand out free from all uncertainty. 1. The aim of God as regards believers is summed up in the simple phrase — conformity to the image of the Son. " Whom He foreknew, He also foreordained to be conformed to the image of His Son, that He might be the First-born among many brethren." ^ This is the one absolute light-point in the eternal future. The mists and shadows which rest on other parts of the eschatological problem do not affect us here. We see not yet all things put under humanity, " but we behold Him who hath been made a little lower than the angels, even Jesus, because of the suffering of death crowned with glory and honour," ^ and we know that our destiny is to be made like Him. This is conformity to type in the highest degree. By what processes the result is to be brought about we may not know, but the end itself is clear — the assimilation begun on earth shall be perfected above. 2. This conformity to Christ includes not only moral and spiritual likeness to Christ, but likeness to Him also in His glorious body ; that is, the Eedemption of the body, life in a glorified corporeity. Difficulties rise here of course in great numbers, and the question will be put, " How are the dead raised, and with what manner of body do they come ? " ^ But, first, I would say that there are certain thiugs here also which stand out clear. (1) First of all, this doctrine of the Eedemption of the body is needful for the completion of the Christian view. It is not an accident, but an essential and integral part of it. It is essential to a complete Eedemption, as we saw in speaking of immortality, that not the soul only, but man in his whole complex personality, body and soul together, should be 1 Rom. viii. 29 (R.V.). ^ Heb. ii. 8, 9 (R.V.). ^ i Cor. xv. 35 (R.V.). THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY. 381 redeemed. In the disembodied state, the believer indeed is with Christ, rests in the blessedness of unbroken fellowship with Him, but it is the resurrection which is the perfection of his life.^ (2) I say, next, that this doctrine of the resurrection of (2) This the body is not exposed to some of the objections often made ^^^^^^^^ ^°^ to it. How, it is asked, can the same body be raised, when so7ne of the it is utterly decayed, and the particles of which it ^^^^ objections made against it. composed are scattered to the winds of heaven, or perhaps taken up into other bodies ? But the doctrine of the True doctrine resurrection does not involve any such belief. The solution ^-v ^ ^^^^^^^' '' tion — bodily lies, I think, in a right conception of what it is which con- identity, stitutes identity. Wherein, let us ask, does the identity even '^^^^^ of our present bodies consist ? Not, certainly, in the mere identity of the particles of matter of which our bodies are composed, for this is continually changing, is *in constant process of flux. The principle of identity lies rather in that which holds the particles together, which vitally organises and constructs them, which impresses on them their form and shape,. and maintains them in unity with the soul to serve as its instrument and medium of expression. It lies, if we may so say, in the organic, constructive principle, which in its own nature is spiritual and immaterial, and adheres to the side of the soul. At death, the body perishes. It is resolved into its elements ; but this vital, immaterial principle endures, prepared, when God wills, to give form to a new and grander, ^ because more spiritual, corporeity. The existence of mystery here I "rant ; we cannot understand the resurrection from natural causes, but only, as Christ teaches us, from the power • of God.2 It is a miracle, and the crowning act of an economy of miracles. But we need not make the mystery greater 1 The idealistic school, on the other hand, speak slightingly of life in the body. "A renewed 'embodiment,'" says Mr. Green, "if it means anything, would be but a return to that condition in which we are but parts of nature, a condition from which the moral life is already a partial deliverance."— Works, iii. p. 206. Was Plotinus then right wdien he blushed that he had a body ? 2 Matt. xxii. 29. 382 THE INCARNA TION AND HUMAN DESTIN Y, than it is by insisting on a material identity between the new body and the old, which is no part of the doctrine of Scripture — indeed, is expressly contradicted by the words of PauVs the apostle, touching on this very point. " Thou foolish one," analogy. ^^^^ Paul, " that which thou thyself sowest is not quickened except it die ; and that which thou sowest, ihoii sowest not the hody which shall he, but a bare grain, it may chance of wheat, or of some other kind, but God giveth it a body even as it pleaseth Him, and to each seed a body of its own." ^ In the case supposed, we see very clearly, first, that the identity consists only in a very minute degree, if at all — and then only accidentally — in identity of material particles ; and, second, that the real bond lies in the active, vital principle which connects the two bodies. {Z)Nota (3) A third point is, that the resurrection contemplated is resurrection at ^^^^ ^ rcsurrcction at death, but a future event connected with death, but a future event, the Consummation of all things. The opposite view is one which has had many modern advocates, — among them the authors of The Unseen Universe ; ^ but, though it professes to stay itself on the expressions, " a house not made with hands, eternal in the heavens," " clothed upon with our habitation which is from heaven," ^ I do not think that this view accords with the general representations of Scripture, which always contemplate the resurrection as future, and regard the 1 1 Cor. XV. 36-38 (R. V.). Cf. Origen, De Principiis, ii. 6 : "For him the re- surrection is not the reproduction of any particular organism, but the preservation of complete identity of person, an identity maintained under new conditions, which he presents under the apostolic figure of the growth of the plant from the seed ; the seed is committed to the earth, perishes, and yet the vital power which it contains gathers a new frame answering to its proper nature." — West- cott in Dictionary of Christian Biography, iv. p. 121. '^ Unseen Universe, pp. 200-211 ; and on Swedenborg's views, pp. 63, 64. Thus also Hunger in his Freedom of Faith: "This change necessarily takes place at death, A disembodied state, or state of torpid existence between death and some far-off day of resurrection, an under-world where the soul waits for the reanimation of its body : these are old-world notions that survive only through chance contact with the Christian system." — P. 309. Then, were Hymenseus and Philetus not right who said that "the resurrection is past already," and in Paul's view overthrew the faith of some ? (2 Tim. ii. 18.) Cf. Newman Smyth's Old Faiths in New Lights, chap. viii. 3 2Cor. V. 1, 2(R.V.). THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY. 383 believer's state as, till that time, one of being " unclothed." What Scripture does seem to teach is, that meanwhile a preparation for this spiritual body is going on, a spiritual basis for it is being laid, through the possession and working of Christ's Spirit.^ 3. The doctrine of the Christian consummation carries 3. The per- with it, further, the idea that, together with the perfectincr ^ififi^gofthe ° X o Church carries the believer, or of the sons of God, there will be a perfecting with it the or glorification even of outward nature. This is implied in ^^'^^^^^'^•^ ^^ nature. the possession of a corporeity of any kind, for that stands in relation to an environment, to a general system of things. A new heavens and earth there must be, if there is to be glorified corporeity. Scripture, accordingly, makes clear that nature also, the creation also, will be delivered from the bondage of vanity and corruption under which it is at present held.2 It is needless for us to attempt to anticipate what changes this may imply ; how it is to be brought about, or how it stands related to the changes in the material universe predicted by science. The day alone will declare it. Connected with these views and anticipations of \}i\Q o^oiw- Pictorial and summation, are certain pictorial and scenic elements in the ^'^^^^^ ^ ^' ^ ments : Christian eschatology, to which attention must now be given, i. The Per- Such are the descriptions of the second Advent and of the ■^^'^^^ ^^^^"^ •* hcTM to be general Judgment. Here belong the eschatological discourses interpreted! and sayings of Christ and His apostles, in regard to which, again, the question is, How are they to be interpreted ? Taking, first, those which relate to Christ's personal return to Beyschlag's the world, I might quote Beyschlag as a typical example of ^^^^* how these pictorial and scenic elements are treated by many who are indisposed to take a literal view of their import. '' Jesus," he says, " grasps up together in the sensible image of His coming again on the clouds of heaven, all that which 1 The Scriptures mention also a resurrection of the wicked (John v. 29 ; Acts xxiv. 15 ; Rev. xx. 12), likewise, we cannot doubt, connected with Christ's appearance in our nature, but, beyond describing it as a resurrection of con- demnation, they throw little light upon its nature. 2 Rom. viii. 21 ; 2 Pet. iii. 13. 384 THE INCARNA TION AND HUMAN DESTINY. lay beyond His death — the whole glarious reversal of His earthly life and the death on the cross, from His resurrection on till the perfecting of His kingdom at the last day ; and the more we keep in view the genuinely prophetic nature of this comprehensive sense-image, and how it shares the essential limits of all prophecy, the more is a solution found of the at first apparently insoluble difficulty of this prophetic part of The Coming, a His doctrine." ^ Now, I think a careful study of the passages process in ^-^^ compel US to apfree with this writer on one main point, which many x <=> i. ' elements flow namely, that Jesus does not always speak of His coming in together. ^^ same scusc ; that it is to Him rather a process in which many elements flow together in a single image, than a single definite event, always looked at in the same light.^ Thus, He says to the high priest, with obvious reference to the prophecy in Daniel, " Henceforth," that is, from this time on, " ye shall see the Son of Man sitting at the right hand of power, and coming on the clouds of heaven."^ He came again to His disciples after the resurrection ; He came in the mission of the Comforter ; He came in the power and spread of His king- dom, especially after the removal of the limitations created by the existing Jewish polity, which seems to be the meaning in the passage, " There be some of them that stand here which shall in no wise taste of death, till they see the Son of Man coming in His kingdom";* He has come in every great day of the Lord in the history of His Church ; He will come yet more con- Stiil, a Per- spicuously in the events of the future. Yet I cannot agree ^h\tFT^^ ^^'^^ Beyschlag when, on these grounds, he would exclude ^ Leben Jesu, i. p. 356. 2 That Jesus did not anticipate His immediate return, but contemplated a slow and progressive development of His kingdom, is shown by many indica- tions in the Gospels. Cf. on this subject, Beyschlag, Lehen Jcsu, i. pp. 354-356; Reuss, Hist, of Christ. Theol., i. pp. 217-218 ; Bruee's Kingdom of God, chap. xii. 3 Matt. xxvi. 64 (R.V.). Cf. Dan. viii. 13, 14. In Daniel's vision the "one like unto a Son of Man " comes on the clouds of heaven to receive a kingdom from the Ancient of Days, not to judge the world. * Matt. xvi. 28 (R.V.). Mark has "till they see the kingdom of God come with power" (ix. 1); Luke simply, ''till they see the kingdom of God" (ix. 27). THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY. 385 altogether a final, personal advent of Jesus, a visible return in power and glory to the world. It seems to me that Christ's words on this subject, repeated by His apostles, are altogether too explicit and of too solemn an import to be explained away into mere metaphor. I would agree, there- fore, with the Church catholic in its confession, " From thence He shall come to judge the quick and the dead." In Bey- schlag's case it seems the more arbitrary to deny this, as he fully admits the reality of Christ's resurrection, and, if not of His visible ascent, at least of His actual bodily reception into heaven. His words are, " What then was the original thought of the ascension ? What else can it have been than that of the elevation of Jesus above the limits of the earthly life, of His translation into another, supra-mundane, Divine form of existence — in a word, of His exaltation or glorifica- tion ? " ^ If this be so, there is surely no incongruity in the thought that He who thus went away shall again appear in manifested glory. It is not otherwise with the pictures we have of a final 2. The General act of Judgment as the accompaniment of this reappearance-^^ ^"^^^ ' of the Lord. Here, also, it is correct to speak of a continuous judgment of the world. The history of the world, as we often hear, is the judgment of the world. Yet the represen- its certainty. tations which Christ Himself gives us of a gradual ripening of both good and evil to the harvest, then of a final and decisive separation ^ — ^joined with the similar representations of the apostles^ — compel us, it seems to me, to speak of a day of reckoning, when God shall judge the secrets of men by Christ Jesus ; which shall be at once a vindication of God's action in the government of the world, and a decision upon the issues of the individual life. From a teleological view of the world, also, as well as from a survey of its existing imper- fections, it is felt that there is an inherent fitness, if not a moral necessity, in the supposition of such a last judgment ^ Lehen Jesu, i. p. 448. ^ Matt. xiii. 30, 49, etc. '^ Acts xvii. 31 ; Rom. ii. 16 ; 2 Cor. v. 10, etc. 25 386 THE INCARNA TION AND HUMAN DESTINY. which shall form, as it were, the dAnouement of the great Parabolic drama of universal history.^ It is manifest, on the other character of ^^^^A ^\^^^ ^y^ ^jjg descriptions and pictures which we have of descriptions. ^ ^ this dread event are so charged with figurative and parabolic elements, that we can infer nothing from them beyond the great principles on which the judgment will proceed. ///. The dark III. By these steps we are led up, in the consideration of side oft IS ^^^ j^g^ thino^s, to that which is for us the question of supreme question — the ° ^ ^ destiny of the conccrn on this subject — the question of individual destiny. -cozcked. J Y^Q^^jQ spoken of this already as regards the believer. But what of the shadow alongside of the light ? What of the judgment of condemnation alongside of the judgment of life ? What of the wrath of God abiding on the unbeliever, along- side of the blessedness of those who are saved ? These ques- tions are not arbitrarily raised, but are forced upon us by the plain statements of Scripture, by the fears and forebodings of the guilty conscience, and by the anxiety and perplexity they Three theories are Causing to many hearts. To the questions thus raised, on this subject ;, , . i i ♦ i • three mam answers have been given, and are given. 1. The first is that of dogmatic Universalism. This was I. Dogmatic the view of Origen in the early Church,^ and is the view of mversa ism. gchleiermacher, expressed in the words, " that through the power of Eedemption there will result in the future a general restoration of all human souls" ;^ the view expressed yet more dogmatically by Dr. Samuel Cox, " While our brethren hold the Eedemption of Christ to extend only to the life that now is, and to take effect only on some men, we maintain, on the contrary, that it extends to the life to come, and must take effect on all men at the last " ; * the view breathed as a wish by Tennyson^ — "The wish that of the living whole No life may fail beyond the grave. "^ ^ Cf. Martensen, Dorner, Van Oosterzee, Luthardt, for illustrations of this thought. 2 De Pri7idpii.8, i. 6. 3 j)^^ christl Glauhe, ii. p. 505. * Salvator Mundi, 11th ed. p. 225. ^ /^^ Meynoriam. THE INCARNA TION AND HUMAN DESTINY, 387 It is a view which, I am sure, we would all be glad to hold, if the Scriptures gave us light enough to assure us that it was true. 2. The second answer is that of the theory of Annihilation, 2. The doc- or, as it is sometimes called. Conditional Immortality. This ^''"^^ °f Annihilation. is the direct opposite of the universalistic view, inasmuch as Conditional it assumes that the wicked will be absolutely destroyed, or ^"""ortaiity. put out of existence. Eothe and others have held this view among continental theologians ; ^ in this country it is best known through the writings of Mr. Edward White. A kindred view is that of Bushnell, who, reasoning " from the known effects of wicked feeling and practice in the reprobate characters," expects " that the staple of being and capacity in such will be gradually diminished, and the possibility is thus suggested that, at some remote period, they may be quite wasted away, or extirpated." ^ The service which this theory has rendered is as a corrective to Universalism, in laying stress on those passages in Scripture which appear to teach a final ruin of the wicked. 3. The third answer is that which has been the prevailing 3. The doc- one in the Protestant Church, the theory of an eternal punish- J^J^^^ mcnt of the wicked in a state of conscious suffering ; a theory. Punishment. also, with which, in the form in which it has been commonly presented, a strong feeling of dissatisfaction at present exists. A modification of this theory is that which supposes the ultimate fate of the wicked — or of those who are the wicked here — to consist in the punishment of loss, rather than in that of eternal suffering. Such are the views that are held ; what attitude are we Fundamental to take up towards them? I shall best consult my own ^^'^'^^■^'" ^^^'^ ^ ^ down : feelings and sense of duty by speaking frankly what I think upon the subject. Here, in the first place, I would like to 1 Dogmatih, iii. p. 108. Ritsclil, too, teaches that if there are any who oppose themselves absolutely to the realisation of the Divine plan, their fate would be annihilation.— i?ec/i^. und Ver. ii. pp. 129, 140-142. But the case is purely hypothetical, iii. p. 363. 2 Forgiveness and Law, p. 147. 388 THE INCARNA TION AND HUMAN DESTINY. lay down one or two fundamental positions which seem to me of the nature of certainties. 1. Theprin- 1. I would lay down, as the first and great fundamental ciple of certain certitude, the truth enunciated by the prophet, " Say ye of retribution for sin. the rightcous, that it shall be well with him ; for they shall eat the fruit of their doings. Woe unto the wicked ! it shall be ill with him ; for the reward of his hands shall be given him " ; ^ in other words, the great and fundamental principle of certain retribution for sin. This is a principle we cannot hold too clearly or too strongly. Whatever tends to tamper with this principle, or to weaken its hold upon the conscience, is alien to the true Christian view. By unalterable laws impressed upon the nature of man and on the universe, righteousness is life, and sin is inevitable misery and death.^ Omnipotence itself could not reverse this law, that so long as the sinner continues in his sin he must suffer. On the other hand, where this principle is firmly grasped, there ought, I think, to be much room left for difference of views on points which, from the nature of the case, are obscure and tentative. 2. Need of 2. I think, in the next place, a strong distinction ought to distinguishing ^^^ drawn between those thinojs which Scripture expressly between what ^ r r j Scripture tcaches, and those things on which it simply gives no light ; in regard to which it neither affirms nor denies, but is simply silent. Here our wisdom is to imitate its caution, and refrain simply silent, from dogmatism. I confess I marvel sometimes at the con- fidence with which people pronounce on that which must and shall be through the eternities and eternities — the ages and ages — of God's unending life, during which also the soul of 1 Isa. iii. 10, 11 (R.V.). 2 Mr. Greg also has his doctrine of future retribution. " Must not a future world in itself— the condition of 'spiritual corporeity' alone— bring with it dreadful retribution to the wicked, the selfish, and the weak ? In the mere fact of their cleared perceptions, in the realisation of their low position, in seeing themselves at length as they really are, in feeling that all their work is yet to do, in beholding all those they loved and venerated far before them, away from them, fading in the bright distance, may lie, must lie, a torture, a purifying fire, in comparison with which the representations of Dante and Milton shrivel into baseness and inadequacy."— Creerf of Christendom, p. 280. teaches and subjects on which it is THE INCARNA TION AND HUMAN DESTINY. 389 man is to exist ; and this in respect of so appalling a subject as the future fate of the lost. There is room here for a wise i^gnosticism. I prefer to say that, so far as my light goes, I see no end, and there to stop. 3. I hold it for a certainty, that to deal with all the sides 3. A larger cai- and relations of this difficult subject we would require a much 'f ""' '''^'^''^ ^ than we at larger calculus than with our present light we possess. ^\i2X present possess. chiefly weighs with many in creating dissatisfaction with the ^^^^^^^M « , r^^ ^ ' ' large view of current Church view is not so much special texts of Scripture the issues of as rather the general impression produced upon the mind by ^^^ Christian the whole spirit and scope of the gospel Eevelation. Starting with the character of God as Christ reveals it ; with the fact of the Incarnation ; with the reality and breadth of the Atonement ; with the glimpses given into the issues of Christ's work, the feeling is produced in every thoughtful mind, that the sweep of this great scheme of Incarnation and Eedemption cannot be exhausted in the comparatively meagre results which we see springing from it here, — meagre, I mean, in comparison with the whole compass of the race or even of those who are brought outwardly within the range of its influence. What, men are asking with a constantly The question heavier sense of the burden of the difficulty, of the untold ^-^^'^^'^^''^'^^''• millions who have never heard of Christ at all, of the millions and millions who have never even had the chance of hearing of Him ? What, even within the limits of Christendom, of the multitudes, as they must be reckoned, in comparison with the really Christ-like in our midst, who give no evidence of true regeneration, vast numbers of whom are living openly worldly and godless lives ? We feel instinctively that the last word has not been — cannot be — spoken by us here. It may be said, and with much truth, that for those who Degrees of have the light, there is no excuse. Salvation has been put '•^•^/^«-^^'^/^^' the data of one of "judgment."* In every description of the judgment, or this life. allusion to it, it is constantly what a man has been, or has done, in this life, which is represented as the basis on which the determination of his final state depends. There is not a word, or hint, to indicate that a man who would be found on the left hand of the King, or who would pass under con- demnation, on the basis of his earthly record, may possibly be found on the other side, and be accepted, on the ground of some transaction in the state between death and judgment. 1 1 Pet. iii. 18-20, iv. 6. 2 2 Cor. vi. 2 (R.V.). 3 E.g., Matt. xxv. 31-46 ; 2 Cor. v. 10 ; Rev. xx. 12. ^ Heb. ix. 27. 396 THE INCARNA TION AND HUMAN DESTINY, Surely this does not agree well with a " future probation " theory, but would rather require us to suppose that, in principle at least, man is presumed to decide his destiny here. (3) The silence (3) There is, as the converse of these facts, the silence of ofScripttire gc^ipture on the subject of probation beyond ; for the passages Probation— in 1 Peter, even accepting the interpretation which makes limits of the \^^yq. refer to a work of Christ in the state of the dead, form application of , i • i i -i i I Pet. iii. 19, surely a slender foundation on which to build so vast a 20, iv. 6. structure. The suggestions they offer are not to be neglected. But neither do they speak of general probation, if of proba- tion at all ; nor give information as to the special character of this preaching to the dead, or its results in conversion ; least of all, do they show that what may apply to the heathen, or others similarly situated, applies to those whose opportunities have been ample. I have spoken of the influences of heredity, etc., as an element to be taken account of in judgment ; but we must beware, even here, of forgetting how much responsibility remains. Will is at work here also ; personal volition is interweaving itself with the warp of natural circumstance and of hereditary predisposition. In the sphere of heathenism itself — even apart from the direct preaching of the gospel — there is room for moral decision wider than is sometimes apprehended, and a type of will is being formed on which eternal issues may depend. Yet the issites I rccognise, howcvcr, in the light of what I have stated of life must ^j^q^j^ ^]^e VLQ.^ii of a larger calculus, that the issues of this somehow be ° brought to a life must prolong themselves into the unseen, and, in some bearing m the ^^^ unknown to US, be brought to a bearing there. All I plead for is, that we should not set up a definite theory where, in the nature of things, we have not the light to enable us to do so. This again is a reason for refusing to acquiesce in many of the dogmatic affirmations which are advanced in the name of a doctrine of eternal punishment. Suffering and loss beyond expression I cannot but conceive of as following from definite rejection of Christ; nor do I see anything in Scrip- ture to lead me to believe that this loss can ever be repaired. THE INCARNATION AND HUMAN DESTINY. 397 How this will relate itself to conditions of existence in eternity I do not know, and beyond this I decline to speculate. The conclusion I arrive at is, that we have not the Result— we elements of a complete solution, and we ought not to attempt ^^'"^ ""^^ ^^^ it. What visions beyond there may be, what larger hopes, complete what ultimate harmonies, if such there are in store, will come ^°^"^^^^^' in God's good time ; it is not ours to anticipate them, or lift the veil where God has left it drawn! What Scripture wishes us to realise is the fact of probation now, of responsibility here. We should keep this in view, and, concentrating all our exhor- tations and entreaty into the present, should refuse to sanction hopes which Scripture does not support ; striving, rather, to bring men to live under the impression, " How shall we escape, if we neglect so great salvation ! " (Heb. ii. 3). Here I bring these Lectures to a conclusion. No one is Comiusion of more conscious than myself of the imperfection of the out- ^^^^^*^'^^' lines I have sought to trace ; of the thoughts I have brought before you in the wide and important field over which we have had to travel. Only, in a closing word, would I state the deepened, strengthened conviction which has come to myself out of the study, often prolonged and anxious enough, which the duties of this Lectureship have entailed on me : the deepened and strengthened conviction of the reality and certainty of God's supernatural Eevelation to the world, — of His great purpose of love and grace, centring in the manifestation of His Son, but stretching out in its issues through all worlds, and into all eternities, — of a Eedemption adequate to human sin and need, the blessings of which it is our highest privilege to share, and to make known to others. With this has gone the feeling — one of thankfulness and hope — of the breadth of the range of the influence of this new power which has gone out from Christ : not confined, as we might be apt to think, to those who make the full con- fession of His name, but touching society, and the world of modern thought and action, on all its sides — influencing its life 398 THE INCARNA TION AND HUMAN DESTINY. and moulding its ideals ; and in circles where the truth, as we conceive it, is mutilated, and even in important parts eclipsed, begetting a personal devotion to Christ, a recognition of His unique and peerless position in history, and a faith in the spread and ultimate triumph of His kingdom, which is full of significance and comfort. I hail these omens ; this widespread influence of the name of Jesus. It tells us that, despite of appearances which seem adverse, there is a true kingdom of God on earth, and that a day of gathering up in Christ Jesus is yet to come. I do not believe that the modern world has ceased to need the Christian view, or that in spirit its back is turned against it. The "isms" of the day are numerous, and the denials from many quarters are fierce and vehement. But in the very unbelief of the time there is a serious feeling such as never existed before ; and there is not one of these systems but, with all its negations, has its side of light turned towards Christ and His religion. Christ is the centre towards which their broken lights converge, and, as lifted up, He will yet draw them unto Him. I do not, therefore, believe that the Christian view is obsolete ; that it is doomed to go down like a faded constellation in the west of the sky of humanity. I do not believe that, in order to preserve it, one single truth we have been accustomed to see shining in that constellation will require to be withdrawn, or that the world at heart desires it to be withdrawn. The world needs them all, and will one day acknowledge it. It is not with a sense of failure, therefore, but with a sense of triumph, that I see the progress of the battle between faith and unbelief. I have no fear that the conflict will issue in defeat. Like the ark above the waters, Christ's religion will ride in safety the waves of present-day unbelief, as it has ridden the waves of unbelief in days gone by, bearing in it the hopes of the future of humanity. I thank the Principal and Professors, I thank the students, for their unfailing courtesy, and for their generous reception of myself and of my Lectures. APPENDIX. W^t EDea of t{)e i%instrom of ©otJ. APPENDIX. THE IDEA OF THE KINGDOM OF GOD. In the original plan of these Lectures it was my intention to Relation of include a Lecture on " The Incarnation and the New Life of ^f ^-^^^^A^ ^' the Course. Humanity; the Kingdom of God," which would have found its fitting place between the eighth and what is now the ninth. Such a Lecture is obviously needed to complete the course. After resurrection came exaltation. After Calvary came Pentecost. After the ministry of the Son came the dispensation of the Spirit. The new life proceeding from Christ, entering first as a regenerating principle into the individual soul, was gradually to permeate and transform society. The doctrine of Eedemption passes over into that of the kingdom of God. This design has reluctantly had to be abandoned, and all I can here attempt, in addition to the brief allusions in Lecture Ninth, is to give a few notes on the general idea of the kingdom of God. I. I shall refer first to the place of this idea in recent/. The place theology. of the idea in °'' theology — This idea has had a prominence accorded to it in recent recent views, theology it never possessed before, and the most thorough- going attempts are made to give it application in both dogmatics and ethics. By making it the head - notion in theology, and endeavouring to deduce all particular concep- tions from it, it is thought that we place ourselves most in Christ's own point of view, and keep most nearly to His own lines of teaching. Kant here, as in so many other depart- ments, may be named as the forerunner ; and fruitful 26 402 APPENDIX, suggestions may be gleaned from writers like Schleiermacher, Schmid, and Beck. It is the school of Eitschl, however, which has done most to carry out consistently this all-ruling notion of the kingdom of God, making it the determinative conception even in our ideas of sin, of the Person of Christ, etc. Through their influence it has penetrated widely and deeply into current theological thought, and is creating for itself quite an extensive literature.^ Reasons for This being the prevailing tendency, I may not un- not treating n^turallv be blamed for not making more use of this idea the kingdom of . God as the than I liavc done in these Lectures. " If this is the chief and all-embracing all- embracing, the all-comprehensive and all-inclusive notion conception. r^-t • > of the pure Christian view, it may be felt that the attempt to develop the Christian " Weltanschauung," without explicit reference to it, is bound to be a failure. I may reply that I have not altogether left it out ; it is, indeed, the conception I should have wished to develop further, as best fitted to convey my idea of the goal of the Christian Redemption, and ' of the great purpose of God, of which that is the expression. J But I have another reason. It is, that I gravely doubt the possibility or desirability of making this the all-embracing, all-dominating conception of Christian theology, except, of course, as the conception of an end affects and determines all that leads up to it. And even here the idea of the kingdom of God is not the only or perfectly exhaustive conception. The following reasons may be given for this opinion : — 1. The kingdom of God is not so presented in the New Testament. In the preaching of Christ in the Synoptic Testament. gospels, this idea has indeed a large place. Christ attaches Himself in this way to the hopes of His nation, and to the ^ Recent works in our own country are Professor Candlisli's The Kingdom of God (Cunningham Lectures, 1884), and Professor A. B. Bruce's The Kingdom of God (1889). A good discussion of the subject is contained in an article by D. J. Kostlin, in the Sfudien und KrUlken for 1892 (3rd part). I may mention also Schm oiler's recent work. Die Lehre vom Eeiche Gottes in den SchHften des neuen Testaments (1891) ; another by E. Issel on the same subject (1891) ; and a revolutionary essay by J. Weiss, entitled Die Prediyt Jesii vom Reiche Gottes (1892). I. It is not so presented in the New THE IDEA OF THE KINGDOM OF GOD, 403 doctrine of the prophets. Yet the very variety of the aspects of His doctrine of the kingdom shows how difficult it must be to sum them all up permanently under this single formula. In the Gospel of John, the idea is not so prominent, but recedes behind that of " life." In the Epistles, it goes still more decidedly into the background. Instead of the kingdom, it is Christ Himself who is now made prominent, and becomes the centre of interest. Harnack notices this in his Dogmen- geschichte. " It is not wonderful," he says, " that in the oldest Christian preaching 'Jesus Christ' meets us as frequently as in the preaching of Jesus the kingdom of God itself." ^ 1 Peter does not use the expression ; James only once. The Pauline theology is developed from its own basis, without any attempt to make it fit into this conception. In the Epistle to the Hebrews, it is other ideas that rule. Where this idea is used in the Epistles, it is generally with an eschatological reference.^ The Apocalypse is the book of the New Testa- ment which gives it most prominence. ^ 2. The kingdom of God is not a notion which can helz^M^ an idea treated as a fixed quantity. The greatest possible diversity ^^^'^^ ^'^^ ^^ prevails among the interpreters as to what ideas are to be fixed qnantity, attached to this expression. Whether the kingdom of God is something set up in this life (Eitschl, Wendt, etc.), or is something which has reference only to the future (Kaftan, SchmoUer, J. Weiss, etc.) ; whether it is to be taken in a purely ethical and religious sense (Eitschl, etc.), or is to be extended to embrace all the relations of existence — the family, state, art, culture, etc. (Schleiermacher, Beck, etc.) ; what is the nature of the good which it promises — these and ^ I. p. 70. Kaftan similarly remarks: "In Paul also the doctrine of the highest good is determined through faith in the risen and exalted Christ who had appeared to him before the gates of Damascus. It can indeed be said that the glorified Christ here fills the place taken in the preaching of Jesus by the super-terrestrial kingdom of God, which has appeared in His Person, and through Him is made accessible as a possession to His disciples." — Das Wesen, p. 229. " Not always, however, e.g. Eom. xiv. 17. Besides, wlmt Christ meant by the present being of His kingdom is always recognised by these writers. 3- Found difficuli in practice to bring all 404 APPENDIX, numberless other points are still keenly under discussion. This is not a reason for saying that on Christ's lips the term had no definite signification, but it shows that the time is not yet ripe for making it the one and all-inclusive notion in theology. 3. Even when we have reached what seems a satisfactory conception of the kingdom, it will be found difficult in practice to bring all the parts and subjects of theology under theology unde^^^^ j^ p^^^f ^f ^j^jg^ appeal might be made to the work of those who have adopted this as their principle of treatment.^ The older Nitzsch, in his System of Doctrine, says of a writer (Theremin) who maintained the possibility of such a deduc- tion, that if he had really applied his general notion of the kingdom of God to a partition and articulation of the Christian doctrinal system, it would have become manifest of itself that this was not the right middle notion to bind the parts together. Schleiermacher, and Beck, and Lipsius, — aUke fail to carry through this idea in their systems. Dither the doctrines are viewed only in this relation, in which case many aspects are overlooked which belong to a full system of theology ; or o, mass of material is taken in which is only connected with this idea in the loosest way. The idea of the kingdom of God becomes in this way little more than a formal scheme or groundwork into which the ordinary — material of theology is fitted. Ritschl, indeed, renounces the idea of a perfect unity, when he says that Christianity is an ellipse with two foci — one the idea of the kingdom of God, \ the other the idea of Eedemption.^ 4. The trne /. 4. The true place of the idea of the kingdom of God in ideaisas^l fftheology is as a teleological conception. It defines the aim teieoiogicai ! and purpose of God in creation and Eedemption. It is the ^ '^' I highest aim, but everything else in the plan and purpose of / God cannot be deduced from it. Even as end, we must distinguish between the aim of God to establish a kingdom of ^ Cf. article by Kostlin above referred to. 2 Hecht. und Ver. iii. p. 11. THE IDEA OE THE KINGDOM OF GOD. 405 God on earth and the ultimate end— the unity of all things natural and spiritual in Christ. The fulness of this last conception is not exhausted in the one idea of " kingdom," though this certainly touches the central and essential fact, that God is " all in all." ^ / II. Let us next consider the teaching of Jesus on the//. The teach- kingdom of God. Here, ing of Jesus on the kingdom of God. The king- 1. I cannot but agree with those who think that the kingdom of God, in Christ's view, is a present, developing reality .2 This is implied in the parables of growth (mustard seed, leaven, seed growing secretly) ; in the representations ^^^^^^y of it, in its earthly form, as a mixture of good and bad (wheat and tares, the net of fishes) ; in the description of the righteousness of the kingdom (Sermon on the Mount), which is to be realised in the ordinary human relations ; as well as in many special sayings. I do not see how anyone can read these passages and doubt that in Christ's view the kingdom was a presently-existing, slowly- developing reality,^ originating in His word, containing mixed elements, and bound in its development to a definite law of rhythm (" first the blade, then the ear," etc.).* On the other hand, the idea has an eschatological reference. The kingdom is not something which humanity produces by its own efforts, but something I 1 1 Cor. XV. 28. 2 E.g. Wendt. » Cf. as in earlier note (p. 384), Reuss, Hist, of GhHst. Theol, i. pp. 217, 218 (Eng. trans.) ; Bruce, Kingdom of God, chap. xii. * The kingdom of God, in its simplest definition, is the reign of God in human hearts and in society ; and as such it may be viewed under two aspects : (1) the reign or dominion of God Himself ; (2) the sphere of this dominion. This sphere, again, may be (1) the individual soul ; (2) the totality of such souls (the Church invisible) ; (3) the visible society of believers (the Church) ; (4) humanity in the whole complex of its relations, so far as this is brought under the influence of Christ's Spirit and of the principles of His religion. It is obvious — and this is one source of the difficulty in coming to a common understanding — that Christ does not always use this expression in the same sense, or with the same breadth of signification. Sometimes one aspect, some- times another, of His rich complex idea is intended by this term. Sometimes the kingdom of God is a power within the soul of the individual ; sometimes it Ls a leaven in the world, working for its spiritual transformation ; sometimes dom a present t developutg 4o6 APPENDIX. which comes to it from above. It is the entrance into humanity of a new life from heaven. In its origin, its powers, its blessings, its aims, its end, it is supernatural and heavenly. Hence it is the kingdom of heaven, and two stadia are dis- tinguished in its existence — an earthly and an eternal ; the "^ latter being the aspect that chiefly prevails in the Epistles.^ 2. The naiure/ 2. What is the nature of this kingdom of God on earth ? of this king- dom of God on earth. (I) The religious and ethical side of this kingdom alone is made prominent. In the Lecture, I have spoken of it as a new principle introduced into society which is fitted and destined to trans- form it in all its relations. This is the view of Schleier- macher, Neander,^ Beck, of Dorner, Martensen, Harless, in their works on " Christian Ethics," and of most Protestant writers. This view, however, is contested, and has to be considered. (1) Now, first, it is to be acknowledged, that in Christ's teaching it is the spiritual, or directly religious and ethical, side of the kingdom which alone is made prominent. Those who would identify the kingdom off-hand with social aims and endeavours, such as we know them in the nineteenth century, look in vain in Christ's teaching for their warrant. There the whole weight is rested on the inward disposition, on the new relation to God, on the new life of the Spirit, on the new righteousness proceeding from that life, on the new hopes and privileges of the sons of God. Everything is looked at in it is the mixed visible society ; sometimes it is that society under its ideal aspect ; sometimes it is the totality of its blessings and powers (the chief good) ; sometimes it is the future kingdom of God in its heavenly glory and perfection. The view that Christ looked for a long and slow process of development and ripening in His kingdom may seem to be opposed by the eschatological predic- tions in Matt. xxiv. Even here, however, it is possible to distinguish a nearer and a remoter horizon — the one, referring to the destruction of Jerusalem and the dissolution of the Jewish state, and denoted by the expression, " these things" ("this generation shall not pass away, till all these things be accom- plished," ver. 34) ; and the other, denoted by the words, "that day and hour" (ver. 36), regarding which Christ says, "Of that day and hour knoweth no one, not even the angels of heaven, neither the Son, but the Father only." ^ The eschatological view alone is that taken by Kaftan, Schmoller, J. "Weiss, etc. ^ See History of the Church, opening paragraphs. THE IDEA OF THE KINGDOM OF GOD, 407 the light of the spiritual, the eternal. We read nothing in Christ of the effects of His religion on art, on culture, on philosophy, on politics, on commerce, on education, on science, on literature, on economical or social reform. It is the same with the apostles. Absorbed in the immediate work of men's salvation, they do not look at, or speak of, its remoter social effects. How far this is due in their case to the absence of-^ apprehension of a long period of development of Christ's religion, and to a belief on the impending dissolution of the world, I need not here discuss.^ The fact remains that, as already stated, while regarding the believer as already in God's kingdom and partaker of its blessings, their conceptions of the kingdom, in its actual manifestation, are mainly eschatological. (2) But, second, as it is certain that a principle of this kind could not enter into society without profoundly affecting it in all its relations, so we may be sure that Christ did not leave this aspect of it out of account. And when we look a little deeper, we see that Christ, though He does not lay stress on this side, yet by no means excludes it, but, on the contrary, presupposes and assumes it, in His teaching. It is to be observed — {a) Christ, in His teaching, presupposes the truth of the Old Testament, and moves in the circle of its conceptions. The Old Testament moves predominatingly in the religious {a) The view and ethical sphere too, but there is a large material back- ^^^^^J^'^^^ ground or framework. We have accounts of the creation, oi presupposed— the early history of man, of his vocation to replenish the Christ's reia- . r, ' c X. tiontothe earth and subdue it, of the first institutions of society, of the world and to beginnings of civilisation, of the divisions of nations, etc. •^^"'^i'- Christ never leaves this Old Testament ground. The world to Him is God's world, and not the devil's. He has the 1 Paul's large view of the philosophy of history in Rom. xi., of a future "fulness of the Gentiles," etc., is against this supposition. It is too hastily assumed that the Apostle looked for the Lord's return in his own lifetime.— See note by Professor Marcus Dods on 1 Thess. iv. 15 in Schaff's Pojndar Com- raentary on the New Testament, (2) Yet a prin- ciple which affects society in all its relations^ The recogni- tion of this by Christ : {b) The world in its existing form hostile^ iut capable of 408 APPENDIX. deepest feeling for its beauty, its sacredness, the interest of God in the humblest of His creatures; His parables are drawn from its laws ; He recognises that its institutions are the expression of a Divine order. The worlds of nature and of society, therefore, in all the wealth and fulness of their relations, are always the background of His picture. We see this in His parables, which have nothing narrow and ascetic about them, but mirror the life of humanity in its amplest breadth — the sower, shepherd, merchant, handicraftsman, the servants with their talents (and proving faithful and unfaithful in the use of them), the builder, the vineyard-keeper, weddings, royal feasts, etc. {h) The world, indeed, in its existing form, Christ cannot recognise as belonging to His kingdom. Eather, it is a hostile power — " the world," in the bad sense. His disciples are to Redemption expcct hatred and persecution in it. It is under the dominion and renewal. of Satan, " the prince of this world." ^ His kingdom will only come through a long succession of wars, crises, sorrows, and terrible tribulations. Yet there is nothing Manichaan, or dualistic, in Christ's way of conceiving of this presence of evil in the world. If man is evil, he is still capable of Eedemption ; and what is true of the individual is true of society. His kingdom is a new power entering into it for the purpose of its transformation, and is regarded as a growing power in it. (f) Christ's I (c) Christ, accordingly, gives us many indications of His ^^.';^'^^r,^<^" true view of the relation of His kingdom to society. The nition of the \ ° •' Divine order world is His Father's, and human paternity is but a lower of society, and reflection of the Divine Fatherhood. Marriage is a divine the duty of ... . . His disciples institution, to be jealously guarded, and Christ consecrated it to 7vork in it, i3y jj^g special presence and blessing. The State also is a and save it. -n^- • Divme ordinance, and tribute is due to its authorities.^ The principles He lays down in regard to the use and perils of ^ John xii. 31, xvi. 11, etc. ^ On above see Matt. vii. 11, xix. 3-9 ; John ii. 1-11 (cf. Matt. ix. 15) ; Matt. xxii. 21. etc. THE IDEA OF THE KINGDOM OF GOD, 409 wealth ; love to our neighbour in his helplessness and misery ; the care of the poor; the infinite value of the soul, etc., introduce new ideals, and involve principles fitted to trans- form the whole social system. His miracles of heahng show His care for the body. With this correspond His injunc- tions to His disciples. He does not pray that they may be taken out of the world, but only that they may be kept from its evil.^ They are rather to live in the world, showing by their good works that they are the sons of their Father in heaven ; are to be the light of the world, and the salt of the earth.2 Out of this life in the world will spring a new type of marriage relation, of family life, of relation between masters and servants, of social existence generally. It cannot be otherwise, if Christ's kingdom is to be the leaven He says it shall be. The apostles, in their views on all these subjects, ~~ are in entire accord with Christ.^ (3) We may glance at a remaining point, the relation of the idea of the kingdom of God to that of the Church. If our previous exposition is correct, these ideas are not quite identical, as they have frequently been taken to be. The kingdom of God is a wider conception than that of the Church. On the other hand, these ideas do not stand so far apart as they are sometimes represented. In some cases, as, e.g, in Matt, xviii. 18, 19, the phrase "kingdom of heaven" is practically synonymous with the Church. The Church is, as a society, the visible expression of this kingdom in the world ; is, indeed, the only society which does formally profess (very imperfectly often) to represent it. Yet the Church is not the outward embodiment of this kingdom in all its aspects, but only in its directly religious and ethical, i.e, in its purely spiritual aspect. It is not the direct business of the Church, e.g., to take to do with art, science, politics, general literature, etc., but to bear witness for God and His truth to men, to preach and spread the gospel of the kingdom. (3) The rela- tion of the idea of the kingdom of God to that of the Church. 1 John xvii. 15. 2 Matt. v. 13-16. 3 E.g. Rom. xiii.; 1 Tim. ii. 1, 2 ; Heb. xiii. 4; 1 Pet. ii. 13-15. 410 APPENDIX, to maintain God's worship, to administer the sacraments, to provide for the self-edification and religious fellowship of be- lievers. Yet the Church has a side turned towards all these other matters, especially to all efforts for the social good and bettering of mankind, and cannot but interest herself in these efforts, and lend what aid to them she can. She has her protest to utter against social injustice and immorality ; her witness to bear to the principles of conduct which ought to guide individuals and nations in the various departments of their existence ; her help to bring to the solution of the questions which spring up in connection with capital and labour, rich and poor, rulers and subjects ; her influence to throw into the scale on behalf of " whatsoever things are true, whatsoever things are honourable, whatsoever things are just, whatsoever things are pure, whatsoever things are lovely, whatsoever things are of good report" (Phil. iv. 8). A wholesome tone in literature, a Christian spirit in art and science, a healthy temper in amusements, wise and beneficent legislation on Christian principles in the councils of the nation, the spirit of long-suffering, peace, forbearance, and generosity, brought into the relations of men with one another in society, Christian ideals in the relations of nations to one another, self-sacrificing labours for the amelioration and elevation of the condition of the masses of the people, — these are matters -, in which the Church can never but be interested. Else she foregoes her calling, and may speedily expect to be removed \ out of her place. ///. The / kingdom of God and the new life of III. Historically, we might have looked, had space per- mitted, at this kingdom of God as the principle of a new life to humanity. I do not enter into this extensive field, humanity. but Only remark : I. Theprin- I 1. The principle of this new life is Christ risen and '^ifchriltrisei^^^^^^^' ^^ ^^^^ ^'^^ ^7 ^^^ preaching merely that Christ and exalted, \came to Set up the kingdom of God. The foundation of it Iwas laid, not only in His Word, but in His redeeming acts — , . THE IDEA OF THE KINGDOM OF GOD. 411 in His death, His resurrection, His exaltation to heaven. His [ sending of the Spirit. The new kingdom may be said to ( have begun its formal existence on the day of Pentecost. This is the mistake of those who would have us confine our ideas of the kingdom solely to what is given in the records of Christ's earthly life. They would have us go behind Pentecost, and remain there. But Christ's teaching on earth could not anticipate, much less realise, what His death, and the gift of His Spirit, have given us. It is not Christ's I earthly life, but His risen life, which is the principle of I quickening to His Church.^ He himself bade His disciples | wait for the coming of the Spirit ; and told them that it was through His being "lifted up" that the world would be brought to Him. The Spirit would complete His mission ; supply what was lacking in His teaching; bring to remembrance what He had said to them ; and would work as a power con- vincing of sin, of righteousness, and of judgment in the world.^ 2. This new life in humanity is (1) a new life in the 12. This individual, a regeneration of the individual soul, a power of/^^^^ ^^~ sanctification and transformation in the nature. But (2) it is further, as we have seen, a principle of new life in society exercising there a transforming influence. What society owes to the religion of Christ, even in a temporal and social respect, it is beyond the power of man to tell. It is this that enables us, from the Christian standpoint, to take an interest in all labours for the social good of men, whether they directly bear the Christian name or not. The influence of Christ and His ideals is more apparent in them than their promoters sometimes think. They are not without relation to the progress of the kingdom. 3. The kingdom of God being the end, is also the centre,j3. The king- i.e., it is with ultimate reference to it that we are to ^^^Adom of God as ' 1 the centre oj and are best able to appreciate, the great movements o^Cod'sprovid- 1 "In truth the life of the soul hidden with Christ in God is the keraelj^''^'^* of the Christian religion."— Kaftan, Da8 Wesen^ p. 76. Kaftan has here the' advantage over Ritschl, Schleiermacher, etc. 2 John xii. 32, xiv. 26, xv. 7-15. (1) a life in the individual soul; (2) in society. 412 APPENDIX, I Providence. We can already see how the progress of inven- tion and discovery, of learning and science, of facilities of communication and interconnection of nations, has aided in manifold ways the advance of the kingdom of God. It has often heen remarked how the early spread of Christianity was facilitated by the political unity of the Eoman Empire, and the prevalence of the Greek tongue ; and how much the revival of learning, the invention of printing, and the enlarge- ment of men's ideas by discovery, did to prepare the way for the sixteenth-century Eeformation. In our own century the world is opened up as never before, and the means of a rapid spread of the gospel are put within our power, if the Church has only faithfulness to use them. It is difficult to avoid the belief that the singular development of conditions in this century, its unexampled progress in discovery and in the practical mastery of nature, the marvellous opening up of the world which has been the result, and the extraordinary multiplication of the means and agencies of rapid communi- cation, together portend some striking development of the kingdom of God which shall cast all others into the shade, — a crisis, perhaps, which shall have the most profound effect upon the future of humanity.^ The call is going forth again, " Prepare ye in the wilderness the way of the Lord, make straight in the desert a highway for our God. Every valley shall be exalted, and every mountain and hill shall be made low ; and the crooked shall be made straight, and the rough places plain ; and the glory of the Lord shall be revealed, and all flesh shall see it together, for the mouth of the Lord hath V spoken it." ^ ^ It is curious how this feeling of an impending crisis sometimes finds expres- sion in minds not given to apocalyptic reveries. Lord Beaconsfield said in 1874 : *' The great crisis of the world is nearer than some suppose." In a recent number of the Forum, Professor Goldwin Smith remarks : "There is a general ieeling abroad that the stream of history is drawing near a climax now ; and there are apparent grounds for the surmise. There is everywhere in the social frame an untoward unrest, which is usually a sign of fundamental change within." 2 Isa. xl. 3, 4 (R.V.). NOTES TO LECTURES. NOTES TO LECTUEE I. NOTE A. ILLUSTRATIONS OF THE WORD "WELTANSCHAUUNG" AND RELATED TERMS. I DO not know that Kant uses this term, or the equivalent term " Welt- ansicht," at all — it is at least not common with him. The same is true of Fichte, Schelling, and generally of writers till after the middle of this century.^ Yet Kant above all gave the impulse to its use, both by his theoretic "Idea" of the world, and by his practical philosophy, which results in a "Weltanschauung" under the idea of the moral. Hegel, however, has the word, e.g.^ "As man, religion is essential to him, and not a strange experience. Still the question arises as to the relation of religion to the rest of his * Weltanschauung,' and philosophical knowledge relates itself to this subject, and has to do essentially with it." — Eeligionsphilosophie, i. p. 7. Within the last two or three decades the word has become exceedingly common in all kinds of books dealing with the higher questions of religion and philosophy — so much so as to have become in a manner indispensable. The following extracts will illustrate its use, as well as throw light on some of the ideas connected with it. It will be observed that most of the passages have reference to the widespread conflict of old and new views. Strauss says, in his Der alte und der neue Glauhe (1873) : " The ground on which I take my stand can be no other than what we name the modern 'Weltanschauung,' the laboriously won result of continuous natural and historical investigation, in opposition to that of the Christian church."— P. 7. He speaks of the contradiction into which many are forced by the knowledge, the view of life and the world (der Welt- und Lebens- anschauung), of the present age.— P. 5. He proposes to inquire first, " Wherein this ' Weltanschauung ' consists, and on what proof it supports itself in contrast with the old church view" (Ansicht) ; then to ask, " Whether this modern view of the world (Weltansicht) does for us the 1 But Fichte has the equivalent "Ansicht der Welt," and occasionally "Weltan- sicht." See especially his Die Anweisung zum seligen Leben (1806), Lect. V. "Weltansicht" is Schopenhauer's word. 4i6 NOTES TO LECTURE I. like service to that, and whether it does it better or worse than the Christian view did for the old believers." — Pp. 11, 12. Luthardt, in like manner, begins his Apologetic Lectures on Bit Grundwahrheiten des Christenthums (1864\ vfith. one on "The Opposition of Views of the World in its Historical Development" (Der Gegensatz der Weltanschauungen in seiner geschichtlichen Entwicklung). He says : " Over against the Christian ' Weltanschauung ' stands a non- Christian ; and there increasingly threatens us the accomplishment of a division in the whole direction of thought in the modern world, which would mean a break with history, and would on that account be full of peril." — Grundwahrheiten^ p. 1. Luthardt's latest apologetic course (1880) has for its title Die modernen Weltanschauungen und ihre praJdischen Konsequenzen. A recent metaphysical writer, Th. Weber, says in his Preface, quoting from a previous work : " It is a fact which lies patent before the eyes of all, that the science of the newer time, under the banner of free inquiry, has brought to light a quite inexhaustible number of views of the world and of life (Welt- und Lebens-ansichten) which already for long have proclaimed a war of life and death against positive Christianity. ... In place of the latter is brought forward, as something once for all estab- lished by science, what is wont to be designated by the expression — though in its applications an exceedingly indefinite one — * modern view of the world ' (moderne Weltanschauung)." But, adds this writer, " Science has yet by no means overthrown the old Christian ' Weltansicht.' " — Metaphysik. Eine vnssenschaftliche Begriindung der Ontologie des positiven Ghristenthums, vol. i. (1888). Preface. The titles and contents of recent books show very manifestly the influence of this term ; e.g.y Dr. Gass entitles a valuable work (1876), Optimismus und Pessimismus ; Der Gang der christlichen Welt- und Lebens- ansicht. In the Preface to this book he writes : " Welt- und Lebens- ansicht sind Lieblingsworte unserer Zeit " (are darling words of our time). Hartmann designates his work on the Philosophy of the Unconscious, Versuch nach einer Weltanschauung. An able work by Fr. Rieff has the title. Die christliche Glaubenslehre als Grundlage der christlichen Weltanschauung (1876). Pfleiderer has a work on Lotze's Philosophische Weltanschauung nach ihren Grundziigen (1882). A well- written brochure, which has had a remarkable run of popularity in Germany, is entitled, Im Kampf um die Weltanschauung ; BeJcentnisse eines Theologen (1889). Reference may be made to an able article by Hermann Schmidt in the Studien und KritiJcen (1876), which bears the title, "Die ethischen Gegen- satze in dem gegenwartigen Kampfe der biblischen und der modern- theologischen Weltanschauung " (" The Ethical Oppositions in the present Conflict of the Biblical and the Modern- Theological View of the World "). Another able recent production is Die christliche Weltanschauung und Kant's sittlicher Glauhe, by Chr. Schrempf (1891). The word is common in Lipsius, Pfleiderer, Ritschl, Hermann, Schultz, etc. The last-named, in his Alttestamentliche Theologie, discusses the NOTES TO LECTURE I. 417 content of the religion of Israel nnder the heading, "Die religiose Weltansch auung." — Pp. 493-8 1 5. Karl Peters (pessimistic school), in his work, Willenswelt und Weltwille, has an abundance of phrases which show the wide range of the applica- tion of this term. Thus we read of the "Theistic," "Atheistic," " Pantheistic," " Realistic," " Materialistic," " Mechanistic," " Buddhistic," " Kantian," Weltanschauung, and a multitude of similar phrases might be cited. This writer remarks : " It is often said that each ' Weltanschauung ' can be proved in relation to the problem here touched on (nature of the ground-principle of the universe), thus : Does it recognise an intentional finality in nature, or not ?— that is the deciding question which makes a sharp distinction between a mechanical and a teleological 'Weltan- schauung.'" — P. 140. For other examples, see Appendix II. to Lecture, and subsequent notes. NOTE B. CLASSIFICATION OF " WELTANSCHAUUNGEN." It is not easy to find a principle of division which will yield a perfectly satisfactory classification of systems which we yet readily recognise as presenting distinct types of world- view. The deepest ground of division, undoubtedly, is that which divides systems according as they do or do not recognise a spiritual principle at the basis of the universe. But when, by the aid of this principle, we have put certain systems on the one side, and certain systems on the other, it does not carry us much further. We must, therefore, either content ourselves with a simple catalogue, or try some other method. In the earliest attempts at a world- view many elements are mixed up together — religious, rational, and ethical impulses, poetic personification of nature, the mythological tendency, etc., and classification is imj)ossible. The " Weltanschauung " at this stage is rude, tentative, imperfect, and goes little further than seeking an origin of some kind for the existing state of things, and connecting the difi'erent parts of nature and of human life in some definite way with particular gods. The interest felt in the soul and its fates enlarge this " Weltanschauung " to embrace a world of the unseen (Sheol, Amenti, etc.). Of reflective " Weltanschauungen," as these appear in history, we may roughly distinguish — I. The Phenomenalistic and Agnostic — which refuse all inquiry into causes, and would confine themselves strictly to the laws of phenomena. The only pure type of this class which I know is the Comtist or Positivist, which contents itself with a subjective synthesis.^ (Mr. Spencer's system, though called Agnostic, is really a system of Monism, and falls into the third class. See Lecture III.) 1 A more extreme type of view still is the denial of the reality of the world altogether — Acosmism. 27 4i8 NOTES TO LECTURE I. II. The Atomistic and Materialistic (Atheistic). The systems of Democritus, Epicurus, Lucretius, and materialistic systems generally, are of this class. As no spiritual principle is recognised, the unity can only be sought in a highest law of the elements — in the order of the universe — in the way in which things cohere. (But many modern systems of Materialism, again, are really Monisms, e.^r., Haeckel, Strauss.) III. Pantheistic systems — and these constitute a vast family with a great variety of forms. Here the universe is conceived as dependent on a first principle or power, but one within itself, of which it is simply the necessary unfolding, and with which, in essence, it is identicah The systems differ according to the view taken of the nature of this principle, and of the law of its evolution. The principle may be con- ceived of : 1. Predominatingly as physical — in which case the system is allied to Materialism (Materialistic Pantheism). 2. As the vital principle of an organism (Hylozoistic). 3. As an intelligent world-soul (Stoicism — analogous to fire). 4. Metaphysically — as Being (Eleatics), Substance (Spinoza), etc. 5. Spiritually — as impersonal Reason, or Spirit (Hegel), or Will (Schopenhauer, etc.). Thus, while on its lower side Pantheism is indistinguishable from Materialism and Atheism, on its higher side it approaches, and often nearly merges into. Theism (as with the Neo-Hegelians). IV. Systems which recognise a spiritual, self-conscious Cause of the universe. Here belong : 1. Deism — which views God predominatingly as Creator, but denies present communication and Revelation, and practically separates God from the world. ^ 2. Theism — which views God as the Living Creator, Immanent Cause, and Moral Ruler of the world and of man. 3. Christian Trinitarianism — a higher form of Theism. [The division of systems as Optimistic and Pessimistic has reference to another standpoint — not to the first principle of the system, but to its ethical character and end. As combined with the others, it would form a cross-division.] There is yet another division of types of world- view (equally important for our subject), based, not on their objective character, but on the mental attitude of the observer, and on the activities employed in their forma- tion. Three main types of world - view may be here distinguished, answering to three distinct standpoints of the human spirit, from each of which a " Weltanschauung" necessarily results. These are : 1. The "Scientific" — in which the standpoint of the observer is in the objective world, and things are viewed, as it were, wholly from without. Abstraction is made from the thinking mind, and only external relations (co-existence, succession, cause and eff'ect, resemblance, etc.) are regarded. The means employed are observation and induction, and the end is the 1 On the definition of terms cf. Lipsius' Dogmatik, pp. 88, 89 ; and Flint's Anti- Theistic Theories, pp. 339, 441-445. NOTES TO LECTURE I. 419 discovery of laws, and ultimately of a highest law, under which all particular phenomena may be subsumed.^ 2. The " Philosophical " — which precisely inverts this relation. The standpoint here is the thinking Ego, and things are regarded from within in their relations to thought and knowledge. It starts from the side of the thinking mind, as science from the side of the world as known, in abstraction from the mind knowing it. From the philosophical stand- point the world assumes a very different aspect from that which it presents to empirical science, or to the ordinary irrefiective observer. All higher philosophy may be described as an attempt to conclude in some way from the unity of reason to the unity of things. The resultant world- view will assume two forms, according as the point of departure is from the theoretical or the practical reason : (1) a theoretical (as in the Absolutist attempts to deduce all things from a principle given through pure thought) ; (2) a moral {e.g., the Kantian). 3. The "Eeligious" — which views everything from the standpoint of the consciousness of dependence upon God, and refers all back to God. It starts from the practical relation in which man stands to God as dependent on Him, and desiring His help, support, and furtherance in the aims of his life (natural, moral, distinctively religious aims). The nature of the religious " Weltanschauung " and its relation to theoretic knowledge is discussed later. At no time, however, can these points of view be kept perfectly distinct, and the claim of either science or philosophy- to produce a self- sufficing world-view must be pronounced untenable. In all scientific theories, as remarked in the text (p. 7), there is a large admixture of unconscious metaphysics. It is easy to say, Let us keep only to what we see and know and can verify, and have nothing to do with either meta- physics or religion. But the thing cannot be done. Science has only to inquire a little into the meaning of its own terms, to go back a little on its own presuppositions, to ask what it means by space, time, power, cause, etc., to find itself plunged into the region of metaphysics. Science, besides, has its own way of teaching the lesson that things are not altogether what they seem ; and the student of nature, as his studies advance, has his confidence in the first rude appearances of nature considerably shaken. It is not merely that he is compelled to correct his first sense-imptessions 1 I use the term "scientific" in its current acceptation as applicable to the sciences which rest on an inductive basis, without prejudice to the question as to whether there are not other methods of knowledge, and whether we may not speak also of philosophical and theological sciences. That the inductive method is not the only one is evident from the two examples of mathematics, which is a purely deductive science, and logic, which also is not inductive, and ranks as one of the philosophical sciences. Whether or not pure philosophy in its two branches of metaphysics and morals is to be admitted among the sciences, will depend on the view we take of the legitimacy of its methods of rational analysis and synthesis— a subject I do not here discuss. But if these methods are valid, and many think they are, we can hardly refuse them the name " scientific," seeing that they represent the purest theoretic activities of which the mind is capable. The sense in which we can speak of theology as a science would demand a discussion for itself. 420 NOTES TO LECTURE I, by maturer knowledge of the real relations of things, but the very nature of things seems changing under his view. The tones, colours, smells, tastes, g.gf., with which his unsophisticated mind was wont to clothe the universe, are now discovered to belong to a world within himself, while in the dark, silent universe there are only different kinds of vibratory and undulatory motions. This but leads to the further discovery— at least so his most trusted guides will inform him— that he knows nothing of the real universe at all ; that all he does know are the phenomena or appearances it presents to him ; and that these in their last analysis are but sensations and impressions produced within himself by unknown causes which science must postulate, but can do nothing to explain (thus Huxley, Tyndall, Spencer, Helmholtz, etc.). The universe seems on the point of disappearing into a subjective idealism ; and if this is to be avoided, it can only be by going back on the real nature of knowledge, and on the manner in which our experience of the world is built up. And this is philosophy. Finally, besides the world of matter, there is the world of mind — of thought and feeling and will — to be reckoned with ; and if science persists in resolving these also into matter, it has to show how moral life is to be rescued from the ruin, or face the descent into Zolaism, or worse — something entirely " earthly, sensual, devilish." Such a " Weltanschauung," if it is constructed, is already condemned, for human life will revolt against it, and claim a place for those ideals and aspirations it so ruthlessly sacrificed. Insensibly, therefore, even in the pursuit of science, the standpoint changes from science to philosophy ; but this, in turn, cannot dispense with the material which the sciences and the history of religions furnish to it ; and is equally unable, out of its own resources, to produce an adequate and satisfying world-view. It cannot do this, if it attempts to explain the universe as a necessary evolution of "Being" or "Thought" ; ^ while if it does not do this, it must forego the pretension to explain the world or history by rational deduction, except in the most general and formal way. It cannot therefore take the place of religion, or furnish a "Weltanschauung" satisfying to the religious consciousness. It is a well-recognised truth that philosophy has founded systems and schools but never religions. ^ The religious world-view is better capable of independent existence than the others, for here at least the mind is in union with the deepest principle of all. But that principle needs to develop itself, and in practice it is found that religion also is largely influenced in the con- struction of its world-views by the state of scientific knowledge and the philosophy of the time. The Indian religious systems are metaphysical throughout. The early Greek fathers of the Church were largely influenced by Platonism ; the mediaeval schoolmen by Aristotelianism ; modern theologians by Kant, Hegel, etc. The type of world-view freest 1 See Lectiire III. 2 "A religion," says Reville, "may become historical, but no philosophy has ever founded a religion possessing true historical ^oyf&c"— History of Religions, p. 22 (Eng. trans.) ; cf. Strauss, Der alte und cler neue Glauhe, p. 103 ; Hartmann, Religionsphilosophie, p. 23 ; A. Dorner, Das menschl. Erkennen, p. 239. NOTES TO LECTURE L 421 from all trace of foreign influence is that found in tlie Old Testament, and comjDleted in the New. This unique character belongs to it as the religion of Eevelation. NOTE C. UNCONSCIOUS METAPHYSIC. Schopenhauer has remarked that each man has his metaphysic. " The man," says Zeller, " who is without any philosophic standpoint is not on that account without any standpoint whatever ; he who has formed no scientific opinion on philosophical questions has an unscientific opinion about them." — Pre-Soc. Phil. p. 23. This fact is not always remembered by our modern thinkers. Prin- cipal Fairbairn observes : " Professor Tyndall's presidential address is memorable enough, were it only as an instance of sweet simplicity in things historical, and the most high-flying metaphysics disguised in scientific terms." — Studies, p. 65. Regarding Mr. Spencer: "Just as the term force revolutionises the conception of the Unknowable, so it, in turn, transmuted into forces, beguiles the physicist into the fancy that he is walking in the, to him, sober and certain paths of observation and experiment, while in truth he is soaring in the heaven of metaphysics." — Ibid. p. 97. Professor Caird remarks of Conite : " Hence, while he pretends to renounce metaphysics, he has committed himself to one of the most in- defensible of all metaphysical positions. ... It is a residuum of bad metaphysics, which, by a natural Nemesis, seems almost invariably to haunt the minds of those writers who think they have renounced meta- physics altogether." — Soc. Phil, of Comte, p. 121. NOTE D. SCOPE OF THE MODERN SCIENTIFIC CLAIM. The following extracts will illustrate the statements in the text : — "Unification," says Mr. Spencer, "being thus the characteristic of developing thought of all kinds, and eventual arrival at unity being fairly inferable, there arises a yet further support to our conclusion."— First Principles, p. 553. " If," he says again, " the entire visible universe has been evolved— if the solar system as a whole, the earth as a part of it, the life in general which the earth bears, as well as that of each individual organism ; if the mental phenomena displayed by all creatures, up to the highest, in common with the phenomena presented by aggregates of these highest ; if one and all conform to the laws of evolution, — then the necessary 422 NOTES TO LECTURE L implication is that those phenomena of conduct in these highest creatures with which morality is concerned, also conform." — Data of Ethics^ p. 63. Speaking of Darwin's theory, Mr. Clodd says : " But that theory deals only with organic evolution, i.e. with the origin of the myriad species of plants and animals ; and the prominence given to it in virtue of its more immediate interest makes us apt to overlook the fact that it is only a small part of an all-embracing cosmic philosophy. For whatever lies within the phenomenal — the seen or felt — and therefore within the sphere of observation, experiment, and comparison, whether galaxy which only the telescojDe makes known, or monad whose existence only the microscope reveals, is subject-matter of inquiry, both as to its becoming and as to its relation to the totality of things. It is this more general conspectus of evolution as a working hypothesis which, if it does not explain every fact, is inconsistent with none, that the following pages are designed to give." — Story of Creation, p. 3. " No one can enter on a consideration of the subject of Evolution with the expectation of attaining to clear ideas and relatively correct conclusions unless he first of all thinks of it as cosmic, i.e. comprehensive, in its operation, of the entire universe of matter and mind, and throughout all time." — Chapman, Pre-organic Evolution, etc., p. 3. NOTE E. ANTAGONISM OF CHRISTIAN AND " MODERN " VIEWS OF THE WORLD — ANTISUPERNATURALISM OF THE LATTER. See passages already quoted on this subject in Note A. I here add some further illustrations. Principal Fairbairn puts the matter thus : " The scientific and religious conceptions of the world seem to stand at this moment in the sharpest possible antagonism. . . . There is one fact we cannot well overrate, — the state of conflict or mental schism in which every devout man, who is also a man of culture, feels himself compelled more or less consciously to live. His mind is an arena in which two conceptions struggle for the mastery, and the struggle seems so deadly as to demand the death of the one for the life of the other, faith sacrificed to knowledge or knowledge to faith." — Studies in the Philosophy of Religion and History, pp. 61, 62. The uncompromising character of the conflict and the nature of the issues involved are well brought out in the following extracts from Mr. Wicksteed's pamphlet on The Ecclesiastical Institutions of Holland. "The religious movement," he says, "known in Holland as that of the ' Modern School,' or ' New School,' or sometimes the ' School of Leiden,' is essentially a branch of that wider religious movement extending over the whole of Europe and America, which is a direct product upon the field of religion of the whole intellectual life of the nineteenth century." "This Modern School, in the larger sense, is in fact essentially the religious phase of that undefinable ' Zeit-Geist,' or spirit of the age, NOTES TO LECTURE L 423 sometimes called on the continent 'modern consciousness,' tlie most characteristic feature of which is a profound conviction of the organic unity, whether spiritual or material, of the universe. " This modern consciousness can make no permanent treaty of peace with the belief which takes both the history and the philosophic science of religion out of organic connection with history and philosophical science in general. No compromise, no mere profession of a frank acceptance of the principles of the modern view of the world, can in the long run avail. The Traditional School cannot content the claims of the ' Zeit-Geist ' by concessions. Ultimately, it must either defy it or yield to it unconditionally. . . . " The task of modern theology then is to bring all parts of the history of religion into organic connection with each other, and with the general history of man, and to find in the human faculties themselves, not in something extraneous to them, the foundations of religious faith." — Pp. 55, 56. The venerable Dr. Delitzsch, from the standpoint of faith, recognises the same irreconcilable contrast, and in The Deep Gulf between the Old and the Modern Theology; a Confession (1890), gives strong expression to his sense of the gravity of the situation. " It is plain," he says, " that the difference between old and modern theology coincides at bottom with the difference between the two conceptions of the world, which are at present more harshly opposed than ever before. The modern view of the world declares the miracle to be unthinkable, and thus excluded from the historical mode of treatment ; for there is only one world-system, that of natural law, with whose permanence the direct, extraordinary interferences of God are irreconcilable. ^ . . . When the one conception of the world is thus presented from the standpoint of the other, the mode of statement unavoidably partakes of the nature of a polemic. The special purpose, however, with which I entered on my subject was not polemical. I wished to exhibit as objectively as possible the deep gap which divides the theologians of to-day, especially the thoughtful minds who have come into contact with philosophy and science, into two camps. An accommodation of this antagonism is impossible. We must belong to the one camp or the other. We may, it is true, inside the negative camp, tone down our negation to the very border of affirmation, and inside the positive camp we may weaken our affirmation so as almost to change it to negation ; the re- presentation by individuals of the one standpoint or the other leaves room for a multitude of gradations and shades. But to the fundamental question — Is there a supernatural realm of grace, and within it a miraculous interference of God in the world of nature, an interference displaying itself most centrally and decisively in the raising of the Redeemer from the dead?— to this fundamental question, however we may seek to evade it, the answer can only be yes or no. The deep gulf 1 Similarly Max Miiller finds the kernel of the modern conception of the world in the idea "that there is law and order in everything, and that an unbroken chain of causes and effects holds the whole universe together "—a conception which reduces the miraculous to mere seeming.— Anthropological Religion, Preface, p. 10. 424 NOTES TO LECTURE I. remains. It will remain to the end of time. No effort of tliouglit can fill it lip. There is no synthesis to bridge this thesis and antithesis. Is ever shall we be able, by means of reasons, evidence, or the witness of history, to convince those who reject this truth. But this do we claim for ourselves, that prophets and apostles, and the Lord Himself, stand upon our side ; this we claim, that while the others use the treasures of God's word eclectically, we take our stand upon the whole undivided truth." — Translation in Expositor^ vol. ix. (3rd series), pp. 50, 53. See also Hartmann's Die Krisis des Ghristenthums in der modemen Theologie (1888); and his Selbstzersetzung des Ghristenthums (1888). " From whatever side," he declares, "we may consider the ground-ideas of Christianity and those of modern culture, everywhere there stands out an irreconcilable contradiction of the two, and it is therefore no wonder if this contradiction comes to light more or l«ss in all derivative questions." — Selbstzersetzung des Ghristenthums, p. 30. NOTE R INTERNAL CONFLICTS OF THE " MODERN " VIEW. An internecine warfare is waged among the representatives of the "modern" view, quite as embittered and irreconcilable as that which they unitedly wage against Christianity. A "Kampf der Welt- anschauungen " is going on here also. Deists, Pantheists, Agnostics, Pessimists, Atheists, Positivists, and liberal theologians, unceasingly refute each other ; and were their respective systems put to the vote, out of a dozen systems, each would be found in a minority of one, with the other eleven against it. If escape were sought in a theoretical scepticism, which despairs of truth altogether, this would but add another sect to the number, which would encounter the hostility of all the rest. Not without justice, therefore, does Dr. Dorner, after reviewing the systems, speak of the attempt to set up a rival view to Christianity as ending in a " screaming contradiction." — System of Ghristian Doctrine, i. pp. 121, 122 (Eng. trans.). " The atheistic systems of Germany," says Lichtenberger, " have raised the standard, or rather the 'red rag' of Kadicalism and Nihilism ; and have professed that their one and only principle was the very absence of principles. The one bond which unites them at bottom is their hatred of religion and of Christianity." — History of German Tlieology in the Nineteenth Gentury, p. 370 (Eng. trans.). "It is not here our business," says Beyschlag, "philosophically to arrange matters between the Christian- theistic ' Weltanschauung ' on the one side, and the deistic, or pantheistic, or materialistic, on the other, which latter have first to fight out their mortal conflict with one another." — Leben Jesu, i. p. 10. A few examples in concreto will point the moral better than many general statements. NOTES TO LECTURE I, 425 The columns of the Nineteenth Century for 1884 witnessed an interesting controversy between Mr. Herbert Spencer and Mr. Frederick Harrison, in which some pretty hard words were bandied to and fro between the com- batants. Mr. Spencer had written a paper (" Keligious Retrospect and Prospect," January, 1884), developing his theory of the origin of religion from ghost- worship, and expounding his own substitute for decaying religious faith. To this Mr. Harrison replied in a vigorous article (July 1884), ridiculing Mr. Spencer's proposed substitute as "The Ghost of Religion," and scoffing at his " Unknowable " as "an ever-present conundrum to be everlastingly given up." Extending his attack to certain modern Theisms, he said, " The Neo-Theisms have all the same mortal weakness that the Unknowable has. They offer no kinship, sympathy, or relation whatever between worshippers and worshipped. They, too, are logical formulas begotten in controversy, dwelling apart from men and the world." " Tacitly implying," retorts Mr. Spencer, in a later round of the controversy, " that Mr. Harrison's religion supplies this relation" (November 1884), which, as he shows at great length, it does not ("Retrogressive Religion," July 1884). Sir James Stephen also had offended Mr. Spencer by describing his "Unknowable" (June 1884) as " like a gigantic soap-bubble, not burst, but blown thinner and thinner till it has become absolutely imperceptible;" and Mr. Harrison also returns to the attack ("Agnostic Metaphysics," September 1884). In a subsequent controversy, Mr. Harrison fares as badly at the hands of Professor Huxley as he did at those of Mr. Spencer. Replying to an article of his on " The Future of Agnosticism," Professor Huxley says : "' I am afraid I can say nothing which shall manifest my personal respect for this aljle writer, and for the zeal and energy with which he ever and anon galvanises the weakly frame of Positivism, until it looks more than ever like John Bunyan's Pope and Pagan rolled into one. There is a story often repeated, and I am afraid none the less mythical on that account, of a valiant and loud-voiced corporal, in command of two full privates, who, falling in with a regiment of the enemy in the dark, orders it to surrender under pain of instant annihilation by his force ; and the enemy surrenders accordingly. I am always reminded of this tale when I read the Positivist commands to the forces of Christianity and of science ; only, the enemy shows no more signs of intending to obey now than they have done any time these forty years."--" Agnosticism," in Nineteenth Century, February 1889.^ Mr. Samuel Laing, author of Modern Science and Modern Thought, and a multitude of other works, probably regards himself as quite a typical representative of the modern spirit. The " old creeds," he informs us, " must be transformed or die." Unfortunately, not content with assailing other people's creeds, he undertook the construction of one of his own,^ 1 Mr. Harrison complains {Fortnightly Review. October 1892) that Mr. Huxley, in this article, has held him up "to public ridicule as pontiff, prophet, general humbug, and counterpart of Joe Smith the Mormon," and tries to show how much agreement, mostly in negations, underlies their differences. 2 "It appears that Mr. Gladstone, some time ago, asked Mr. Laing if he could draw up a short summary of the negative creed ; a body of negative propositions 426 NOTES TO LECTURE I. concerning which Professor Huxley writes : " I speak only for myself, and I do not dream of anathematising and excommunicating Mr. Laing. But when I consider his creed and compare it with the Athanasian, I think I have, on the whole, a clearer conception of the meaning of the latter. ' Polarity,' in Art. viii., for example, is a word about which I heard a good deal in my youth, when ' Naturphilosophie ' was in fashion, and greatly did I suffer from it. For many years past, whenever I have met with ' polarity ' anywhere but in a discussion of some purely physical topic, such as magnetism, I have shut the book. Mr. Laing must excuse me if the force of habit was too much for me when I read his eighth article." — Nineteenth Century, Ibid. Rather hard on Mr. Laing ! ^ Mr. Rathbone Greg is another writer who laboured hard to demolish " the creed of Christendom," while retaining a great personal reverence for Jesus. His concessions on this subject, however, did not meet with much favour on his own side. Mr. F. W. K ewnian, in an article on " The New Christology," in the Fortnightly Revieio (December 1873), thus speaks of his general treatment : " He has tried and proved the New Testament, and has found it wanting, not only as to historical truth, but as to moral and religious wisdom ; yet he persists in the effort of hammering out of it what shall be a ' guide of life.' In fact, he learns by studying the actual world of man ; but in his theory he is to rediscover a fountain of wisdom, by penetrating to some ' essence ' in a book which he esteems very defective and erroneous. This is ' to rebuild the things he has destroyed.' To sit in judgment on Jesus of Nazareth, and convict Him of glaring errors, as a first step, and then, as a second, set Him on a pedestal to glorify Him as the most divine of men and the sublimest of teachers, a perpetual miracle, — is a very lame and inconsequent proceeding. . . . Mr. Greg, as perhaps all our Unitarians, desires a purified gospel. Why, then, is not such a thing published ? No doubt, because it is presently found that nearly every sentence has to be either cut out or re- written." Mr. Greg and Mr. Newman are Theists. The latter even writes : " The claim of retaining a belief in God, while rejecting a Personal God, I do not know how to treat with respect." Mr. Fiske also, author of Cosmic Philosophy, is in his own way a Theist. But " Physicus," another repre- sentative of the " modern " view, in his Candid Examination of Theism, can see no evidence for the existence of a God, and speaks thus of Mr. Fiske's attempt to develop Theism out of Mr. Spencer's philosophy : " I confess that, on first seeing his work, I experienced a faint hope that, in the higher departments of the philosophy of evolution as conceived by Mr. Spencer, and elaborated by his disciple, there might be found some rational justification for an attenuated form of Theism. But on examina- tion I find that the bread which these fathers have offered us turns out which have so far been adopted on the negative side as to be what the Apostles' and other accepted creeds are on the positive ; and Mr. Laing at once kindly obliged Mr. Gladstone with the desired articles— eight of them."— Professor Huxley, as above. 1 Mr. Laing's own book, Science and Modern Thought, is a good example of how these "modern " systems eat and devour one another. See his criticisms of theories in chap, vii., etc. NOTES TO LECTURE L 427 to be a stone. ... We have but to think of the disgust with which the vast majority of living persons would regard the sense in which Mr. Fiske uses the term 'Theism,' to perceive how intimate is the association of that term with the idea of a Personal God. Such persons will feel strongly that, by this final act of purification, Mr. Fiske has simply purified the Deity altogether out of existence." — CandtcZ Examination, essay on "Cosmic Theism," pp. 131, 138, and throughout. Thus the strife goes on. Strauss, in his Old Faith and the New, refutes Pessimism ; but Hartmann, the Pessimist, retorts on Straiiss that he has " no philosophic head," and shows the ridiculousness of his demand that we^ should love the Universe. " It is a rather strong, or rather naive claim, that we should experience a sentiment of religious piety and dependence for a ' Universum ' which is only an aggregate of all material substances, and which threatens every instant to crush us between the wheels and teeth of its pitiless mechanism." — Selbstzer. des Christ. Pref. and p. 81. What these thorough-going representatives of the "modern" view think of the half-way attitude of our modern " liberal Protestant theo- logians," who vaunt so loudly their loyalty to the "modern" spirit, may be seen in a note to next Lecture. It will be apparent that all these criticisms bear in the direction of stripping off the disguises with which the nakedness of the " modern " view is wont to conceal itself, and of reducing this view to its ultimate level of Agnosticism, Atheism, or Pessimism. Hartmann may as well speak of the " Selbstzersetzung " and " Zer- spitterung" of unbelief, as of the disintegration of Christianity. NOTE G. UNIQUENESS OF THE OLD TESTAMENT VIEW. It may be confidently affirmed that the drift of modern criticism and research has not been to lower, but immensely to exalt, our concej)tious of the unique character of the Old Testament religion. The views of the critics of the earlier stages of the religion of Israel are low and poor enough, but, as if in compensation, they exalt the " Ethical Monotheism " and spiritual religion of the prophets and psalms, till one feels, in reading their works, that truly this religion of Israel is something unexampled on the face of the earth, and is not to be accounted for on purely natural principles. Schleiermacher and Hegel spoke disparagingly of the Old Testament, but this is not the more recent tendency. The following are some testimonies from various standpoints. Lotze, in his Microcosmus, bears a noble testimony to the uniqueness of the Old Testament religion, and to the sublimity and unparalleled character of its literature. "Among the theocratically governed nations of the East," he says, "the Hebrews seem to us as sober men among drunkards " (vol. ii. p. 267, Eng. trans.). See his spirited sketch of the 428 NOTES TO LECTURE L Old Testament view (pp. 466-468) ; and his eulogy of tlie literature (pp. 402-404). Dr. Hutcheson Stirling says : " The sacred writings of the Hebrews, indeed, are so immeasurably superior to those of every other name that, for the sake of the latter, to invite a comparison is to undergo instant- aneous extinction. Nay, regard these Scriptures as a literature only, the literature of the Jews— even then, in the kind of quality, is there any literature to be compared with it ? Will it not even then remain still the sacred literature? A taking simpleness, a simple takingness, that is Divine — all that can lift us out of our own week-day selves and place us, j)ure then, holy, rapt, in the joy and the peace of Sabbath feeling and Sabbath vision, is to be found in the tnere nature of these old idylls, in the full-filling sublimity of these psalms, in the inspired God-words of these intense-souled prophets." — Phil, and Theol. (Gilford Lectures), pp. 18, 19. Dr. Eobertson Smith has well brought out the singularity and elevation of the Hebrew view in contrast with that of the other Semitic and Aryan nations in his Religion of the Semites (Burnett Lectures). " The idea of absolute and ever- watchful Divine justice," he says, "as we find it in the prophets, is no more natural to the East than to the West, for even the ideal Semitic king is, as we have seen, a very imperfect earthly provid- ence ; and, moreover, he has a different standard of right for his own people and for strangers. The prophetic idea that Jehovah will vindicate the right, even in the destruction of His own people of Israel, involves an ethical standard as foreign to Semitic as to Aryan tradition " (p. 74). Again : " While in Greece the idea of the unity of God was a philo- sophical speculation, without any definite point of attachment to actual religion, the Monotheism of the Hebrew prophets kept touch with the ideas and institutions of the Semitic race by conceiving of the one true God as the King of absolute justice, the national God of Israel, who, at the same time, was, or rather was destined to become, the God of all the earth, not merely because His power was world-wide, but because, as the perfect ruler. He could not fail to draw all nations to do Him homage " (p. 75). Again : " The Hebrew ideal of a Divine Kingship that must one day draw all men to do it homage, offered better things than these, not in virtue of any feature that it possessed in common with the Semitic religions as a whole, but solely in virtue of its unique conception of Jehovah as a God whose love for His people was conditioned by a law of absolute righteousness. In other nations, individual thinkers rose to lofty conceptions of a supreme Deity, but in Israel, and in Israel alone, these conceptions were incorporated in the conception of the national God. And so, of all the gods of the nations, Jehovah alone was fitted to become the God of the whole earth" (pp. 80, 81). Kuenen writes thus of the universalism of the prophets : " What was thus revealed to the eye of their spirit was no less than the august idea of the moral government of the world — crude as yet, and with mani- fold admixture of error (?), but pure in principle. The prophets had no conception of the mutual connection of the powers or operations of NOTES TO LECTURE I, 429 nature. They never dreamed of carrying them back to a single cause, or deducing them from it. But what they did see, on the field within their view, was the realisation of a single jolan — everything, not only the tumult of the peoples, but all nature likewise, subservient to the working out of one great purpose. The name ' Ethical Monotheism ' describes better than any other the characteristics of their point of view, for it not only expresses tlie character of the one God whom they worshipped, but also indicates the fountain whence their faith in Him welled up.'"' Hibbert Lectures, pp. 124, 125. " So far," says Mr. Gladstone, " then, the office and work of the Old Testament, as presented to us by its own contents, is without a compeer among the old religions. It deals with the case of man as a whole. It covers all time. It is alike adapted to every race and region of the earth. And how, according to the purport of the Old Testament, may that case best be summed up ? In these words : it is a history first of sin, and next of Redemption." — Impregnable Rock of Holy Scripture. See the whole chapter on "The Office and Work of the Old Testament in Outline." I may add a few words of personal testimony from Professor Monier Williams, on the comparison of the Scriptures with the Sacred Books of the East. " When I began investigating Hinduism and Buddhism, I found many beautiful gems ; nay, I met with bright coruscations of true light flashing here and there amid the surrounding darkness. As I pro- secuted my researches into these non - Christian systems, I began to foster a fancy that they had been unjustly treated. I began to observe and trace out curious coincidences and comparisons with our own Sacred Book of the East. I began, in short, to be a believer in what is called the evolution and growth of religious thought. ' These imperfect systems,' 1 said to myself, ' are interesting efforts of the human mind struggling upwards towards Christianity. Nay, it is probable that they were all intended to lead up to the one true religion, and that Christianity is, after all, merely the climax, the complement, the fulfilment of them all' " Now there is unquestionably a delightful fascination about such a theory, and, what is more, there are really elements of truth in it. But I am glad of this opportunity of stating publicly that I am persuaded I was misled by its attractiveness, and that its main idea is quite erroneous. . . . We welcome these books. We ask every missionary to study their contents, and thankfully lay hold of whatsoever things are true and of good report in them. Bat we warn him that there can be no greater mis- take than to force these non-Christian bibles into conformity with some scientific theory of development, and then point to the Christian's Holy Bible as the crowning product of religious evolution. So far from this, these non-Christian bibles are all developments in the wrong direction. They all begin with some flashes of true light, and end in utter dark- ness. Pile them, if you will, on the left side of your study table, but place your own Holy Bible on the right side — all by itself, all alone — and with a wide gap between."— Quoted l^y Joseph Cook in God in the Bible (Boston Lectures), p. 16. 430 NOTES TO LECTURE L NOTE H. ORIGIN OP THE OLD TESTA.MEXT VIEW — RELATION TO CRITICAL THEORIES. Many feel that from the peculiarity of Israel's religion referred to in last note, the need will arise sooner or later for recasting the whole critical view of the development. The more rich and wonderful the religious development of the age of the prophets is shown to be, the more will it be felt necessary to postulate something in the earlier stages to account for this development — the more natural and life-like will Israel's own account of its history appear ^ — the more impossible will it be found to explain the presence of such a development or religion at all apart from the fact of supernatural Kevelation. As it is, there is a growing acknowledgment among the critics of the most advanced school that, date the books when we may, the religion can only be explained by Eevelation. I quote from three recent works. H. Schultz, in his new edition of his Alttestamentliche Theologie, 1889, thus writes : " The Old Testament religion is thus only to be explained out of Revelation ; that is to say, out of the fact that God raised up to this people men, in whose original religious and moral endowment, developed through the leadings of their inner and outer life, the recep- tivity was given for an absolutely original comprehension of the self- communicating, redeeming will of God towards men, the religious truth which makes free — not as a result of human wisdom or intellectual effort, but as an irresistible, constraining power on the soul itself. Only he who explicitly recognises this can do historical justice to the Old Testament" (p. 50). R. Kittel, in his recent valuable Geschichte der Hebriier, 1888-92, also based, though discriminatingly, on the results of the later criticism, thus sums up on the question — " Whence did Moses derive his knowledge of God 1" " The historian stands here," he says, "before a mystery, which is almost unique in history. A solution is only to be found if in that gap a factor is inserted, the legitimacy of which can no more be proved by strict historical methods. There are points in the life of humanity where history goes over into the philosophy of history, and speculation must illuminate with its retrospective and interpreting light the other- wise permanently dark course of the historical process. Such a case is here. Only an immediate contact of God Himself with man can produce the true knowledge of God, or bring man a real stage nearer to it. For in himself man finds only the world, and his own proper ego. Neither one nor the other yields more than heathenism : the former a lower, the latter a higher form of it. Does the thought flash on Moses that God is neither the world nor the idealised image of man, but that He is the Lord of Life, of moral commands, exalted above multiplicity and the world of sense, and the Creator, who does not crush man, but ennobles 1 Cf. Robertson's Early Religion of Israel (Baird Lectures). An alile criticism of some of Professor R. Smith's positions in The Religion of the Semites appeared in the Edinburgh Review, April 1892. NOTES TO LECTURE I. 431 him ; so lias lie this knowledge, not out of his time, and not out of him- self—he has it out of an immediate Revelation of this God in his heart." Geschichte, i. pp. 227, 228. Alex. Westphal, author of an able French work, Les Sources du Pentateicque, Etude de Critique et d'Histoire, 1888-92, is another writer who uncompromisingly accepts the results of the advanced critical school. But he earnestly repudiates, in the Preface to the above work, the idea that these results destroy, and do not rather confirm, faith in Revelation, and even builds on them an argument for the historic truthfulness of the early tradition. He separates himself in this respect from the unbeliev- ing position. " Truth to tell," he says, " the unanimity of scholars exists only in relation to one of the solutions demanded, that of the literary problem. . . . The position which the scholar takes up towards the Ijooks which he studies, and his personal views on the history and the religious development of Israel, always exercise, whether he wishes it or not, a considerable influence on the results of his work. However, we may be permitted to affirm, and hope one day to be able to prove, that the reply to the historic question belongs to evangelical criticism, which, illuminated by the spirit of Revelation, alone possesses all the factors for the solution of this grave problem. . . . Far from being dismayed by the fact that the plurality of sources involves profound modifications in our traditional notion of the Pentateuch written by Moses, we should rather see in it a providential intervention, at the moment when it is most necessary, a decisive argument in favour of the primitive history." ^ — Les Sources, i. Preface, p. 28. NOTE I. NATURE AND DEFINITION OF RELIGION. In strictness these Lectures ought to have included a treatment of the general question of religion as preparatory to the consideration of the specific Christian view. Christianity involves a " Weltanschauung," and it belongs to the type " religious." It ought therefore to be shown in what distinctively a religious " Weltanschauung " consists, and how the Christian view is related to the general conception. This, again, would 1 This somewhat novel position is expounded further on. "What is then the result of these bold labours at which the Church is so alarmed, and on which un- lielief congratulates itself? The putting of three books in place of one book, a series of witnesses in place of a single witness. . . . Shall we regard these as variations of one and the same popular legend ? Impossible ; their divergences are too numerous, their character too distinct. A fable become legendary, and appear- ing on the domain of history under the form of a triple tradition — that appears to us difficult to comprehend. But that an historic fact, transmitted from age to age by an oral tradition, should become little by little the epic of generations, and bear till the day of its redaction the strong impress of the genius of the tribes Avhich liave preserved it, and the stamp of the time which has fixed it in writing — nothing is more natural. Facts of this kind abound in the annals of history " (p. 29). 432 NOTES TO LECTURE L involve an inquiry into the general nature of religion ; in order, on this basis, to show how a " Weltanschauung " necessarily originates from it. A few notes are all that can be attempted here, in addition to what is said in Appendix II., and in the text of various portions of the Lectures. The main question is as to the general character, or essential nature, of religion, as a means of understanding how a " Weltanschauung " springs from it. This question is not answered — 1. By an abstract definition of religion. Much has been written on the definition of religion.^ A prior question is, in what sense do we speak of definition % Do we mean to include in our definition of religion only the common elements in all religions ; or do we propose to define by the idea of religion, as that may be deduced from the study of the laws of man's nature, seen in their manifestation on the field of history, and most conspicuously in the higher religions ? Tlie fault of most definitions is that, aiming at a generality wide enough to embrace the most diverse manifestations of the religious consciousness, — the lowest and most debased equally with the most complex and exalted, — they necessarily leave out all that is purest and most spiritual in religion — that which expresses its truest essence. They give us, in short, a logical summum genus, which may be useful enough for some purposes, but is utterly barren and unprofitable as a key to the interpretation of any spiritual fact. On the other hand, if we take as our guide the idea of religion, we may be accused of finding only one religion which corresponds to it — the Christian ; and in any case the definition will leave outside of it a vast variety of religious phenomena. What is wanted is not a logical defini- tion, which will apply to nothing from which its marks are absent, but such a comprehension of the inner principle and essential character of religion as will enable us to discern its presence under forms that very rudely and imperfectly express it.^ 2. By exclusively 'psychological or historical methods in the treatment of religion. These are the methods in vogue at the present day in what is designated " The Science of Eeligions." I call a theory psychological which seeks to account for the ideas and beliefs which men entertain regarding their deities by tracing them to psychological causes, without raising the question of how far these ideas and beliefs have any objective truth. Psychology deals with the empirical — the given. It observes the facts of the religious consciousness — groups and classifies them — seeks to resolve the complex into the simple, the compound into the elementary — notes the laws and relations which discover themselves in the different phenomena, etc. In doing this, it performs a necessary service, but its method is liable to certain obvious drawbacks. 1 For a summary view of these definitions, and examination of them, see Max Miiller's Gitford Lectures on Natural Religion (1888), and Nitzsch's Evangelische Dogmatik, i. pp. 46-109 (1889). 2 See a good treatment of this subject in Kaftan's Das Wesen der christ. Rel. (1881), pp. 1-5 ; cf. also Caird's Philosophy of Religion (pp. 314-317), and Note "On the possibility of discovering in the ' essence of religion ' a universal religion," in Conder's Basis of Faith, p. 438. NOTES TO LECTURE I. 433 (1) If religion is a necessity of human nature, springing by an inner necessity from the rational and spiritual nature of man, this method can never show it. Psychology can only show what is, not what must or should be. Its function is ended when it has described and analysed facts as they are. It does not reach inner necessity. From the per- sistency with which religion appears and maintains itself in human nature, it may infer that there is some deep and necessary ground for it in the spirit of man, but it lies beyond the scope of its methods to show what that is. Its line is too short to reach down to these depths. (2) It is a temptation in these theories to aim at an undue simplicity. This is a fault, indeed, of most theories of religion, that they do not do justice to the multiplicity of factors involved in religion, but, laying hold on one of these factors, exalt it to exclusive importance at the expense of the rest. Keligion is a highly complex thing, blending in V itself a multitude of elements readily distinguishable, — hopes and fears, belief in the invisible, the feeling of dependence, the sense of moral relation, desire for fellowship, emotions of awe, love, reverence, surrender of the will, etc., — and I suppose no definition of it has ever been con- structed which did not leave out some of its extraordinarily varied mani- ^ festations. Theories, therefore, err which attempt to deduce all religious sentiments and ideas from some one principle, e.fj.^ Hume, from man's hopes and fears ; Tylor, from the animistic tendency in human nature ; Spencer, from ghost worship ; Feuerbach, from man's egoistic wishes — " What man would have liked to be, but was not, he made his god ; what he would like to have, but could not get for himself, his god was to get for him" (Strauss); others from Totemism, etc.^ (3) It is a common error of these theories to study religion chiefly as it presents itself in the lowest, poorest, crudest manifestations of the religious consciousness ; and to suppose that if they can explain these, all the higher stages of religious development can be explained in the same way. This is much the same as if a botanist, wishing to exhibit the essential characteristics of plant life, were to confine his attention to the lowest order of plants, and even to the most dwarfed, stunted, and imf)Overislied specimens of these. (4) It is a further weakness of psychological theories that they move ^ solely in the region of the subjective. They occupy themselves with psychological causes, and with the ideas and fancies to which these give rise ; but have nothing to teach us of the object of religion — neither what the true object is, nor whether a true object is to be known at all. Their function is ended when they have described and analysed facts ; they claim no right to pass judgment. They have, in other words, no objective standard of judgment. Yet the question of the object is the one of essential importance in religion, as determining whether it has any ground in objective truth, or is only, as Feuerbach would have it, a deceptive play of the human consciousness with itself. ^ / (5) Finally, even the higher class of psychological theories form a very inadequate basis for a true conception of religion. Schleiermacher, e.gf., 1 Cf. on some of these theories Note A to Lecture III. 2 Cf. Max Miiller, Natural Religion, p. 56. 28 434 NOTES TO LECTURE I. explains religion as the immediate consciousness of the infinite in the finite, and of the eternal in the temporal ; Max Miiller as the perception of the infinite/ etc. But if we ask in Kantian fashion — How is such an immediate consciousness — feeling or perception— possible ? What view of man's nature is implied in his capacity to have a consciousness, or feeling, or perception of the infinite ? we are driven back on deeper ground, and come in view of a rational nature in man which transforms the whole problem. ^ / The same criticisms apply in part to the Mstorical treatment of religion. This, like the psychological, has its own part to play in the construction of a philosophy of religion ; its help, indeed, is of untold value. By its aid we see not only what religion is in its actual manifestations ; not only get an abundance of facts to check narrow and hasty generalisations ; but we find a grand demonstration of the universality of religion. Yet the historical treatment, again, like the psychological, does not furnish us with more than the materials from which to construct a theory of religion. If the historical student, in addition to recording and classifying his facts, and observing their laws, passes judgment on them as true or false, good or evil, his inquiry is no longer historical merely, but has become theo- ^ logical or philosophical. i3. Our question is not answered by explaining religion out of the necessity which man feels of maintaining his 2}erso7iality and spiritual independence against the limitations of nature. This, as shown in Appendix II., is the Ritschlian position, and the passages there quoted illustrate how Ritschl and his followers develop a " Weltanschauung " (from it. Its value lies in the recognition of the fact that religion contains not only a relation of dependence, but a practical impulse towards freedom ; and in this sense the Ritschlian mode of representation has extended far beyond the limits of the school. Thus Pfleiderer (otherwise a sharp critic of Ritschl) says : " There belongs to the religious consciousness some degree of will, some free self-determination. And what this aims at is simply to be made quite free from the obstructing limit and dependence which our freedom encounters in the world" {Religionsphilosophie, i. p. . 323, Eng. trans.). "In the religious 'Weltanschauung,'" says Lipsius, " there is always posited on the part of man the striving to place himself in a practical relation to this higher power on which he knows himself and his world to be dependent, in order that through this he may further his well-being against the restrictions of the outer world, and victoriously maintain his self-consciousness as a spiritual being against the finite limitations of his natural existence " {Dogmatik, p. 25). Reville says : " Religion springs from the feeling that man is in such a relation to this spirit, tliat for his well-being, and in order to gratify a spontaneous impulse of his nature, he ought to maintain with it such relations as will afford him guarantees against the unknown of destiny" {History of Religions, p. 29, Eng. trans.).^ In its Ritschlian form, this theory is open 1 Cf. Natural Religion, pp. 48, 188. 2 See Appendix to Lecture III. s Kaftan, on the other hand, finds the root-motive of religion in the infinity of the 'claim on life" inseparable from our nature, which this world is not able to satisfy. NOTES TO LECTURE I. 435 to very serious objections. Professing to account for religion, it really inverts the right relation between God and the world, making the soul's relation to the world the first thing, and the relation to God secondary and dependent ; instead of seeking in an immediate relation to God the first and unique fact which sustains all others.^ While, further, it may be conceded to Eitschl and his followers, that the primary motive in religion is practical (though not prior to the immediate impression or consciousness of the Divine in nature, in the sense of dependence, in conscience, etc.), it must be insisted on that the practical motive is such | as can originate only in beings with a rational nature,— i.e., reason under- I lies it. Had this been kept in view, it would have helped to prevent the strong division which this school makes between religious and theoretic knowledge (see later note). 4. The rational self-consciousness of man being posited as the ground- ' work,^ we may with confidence recognise the following as elements entering into the essence of religion, and connecting themselves with its development. (1) There is first the sense of al)Solute dependence, so justly emphasised \ by Sclileierraacher {Der christ. Glaube, sect. 4). But this alone is not • sufficient to constitute religion. Everything depends on the kind of power on which we feel ourselves dependent. Absolute dependence, e.g., on a blind power, or on an inevitable fate or destiny, would not produce in us the effects we commonly ascribe to religion. With the sense of dependence there goes an impulse to freedom. The aim of religion, it I has been justly said, is to transform the relation of dei:>endence into one ) of freedom. This involves, of course, the shaping of the idea of the Godhead into that of personal spirit. I (2) Equally original with the feeling of dependence, accordingly, is the \ impulse in religion to go out of oneself in surrender to a higher object — the impulse to worship. The idea of this higher object may be at first ' dim and indistinct, but the mind instinctively seeks such an object, and cannot rest till it finds one adequate to its own nature. Here, again, the rational nature of man is seen at w^ork, impelling him to seek the true infinite, and allowing him no rest till such an object is found (cf. Appendix to Lecture II I. ).^ (3) Another directly religious impulse is the desire that is early manifested to bring life, and the circle of interests connected with it, *' Generally the claim on life (Anspruch auf Leben) lies at the foundation of religion. That this claim is not satisfied in tlie world, and further through the world, is the common motive of all religions" (Das Wesen, p. 67, cf. 60). But whence this "claim on life" ? Why this striving after an infinite and "iiberweltlichen" good ? What view of man's nature is implied in the possibility of such strivings ? These are questions which Kaftan does not answer, but which a true theory of religion should answer. 1 See criticism of this theory of religion in Pfleiderer's Die RitschVsche Theologie, p. 17 fF., and in Stahlin's Kant, Lotze, und Ritschl, pp. 238-250 (Eug. trans.) ; and A. Arnold's Das menschliche Erkennen, p. 221. - See further, Appendix to Lecture III. 3 Man's actual knowledge of the Divine is drawn from, or based on, experiences of its presence and workings (Lecture III.). 436 NOTES TO LECTURE I. under the immediate care and sanction of the Divine. This, which has its origin in the sense of weakness and finitude, is apparent in all religions, and brings religion within the circle of men's hopes and fears. (4) As moral ideas advance,— and we do not here discuss how this advance is possible, — the ground is prepared for yet higher ideas of God, and of His relations to the world and man. There has now entered the idea of a moral end ; man also has become aware of the contradictions which beset his existence as a being at once free, and yet hemmed in and limited on every side in the attainment of his ends ; not to speak of the deeper contradictions (within and without) which beset his existence through sin. It is here that the idea of religion links itself with the moral " Weltanschauung " of Ritschl, Lipsius, Pfleiderer, and others, who find the solution of these antinomies in the idea of a teleological govern- ment of the world, in which natural ends are everywhere subordinated to moral ; which, again, implies the monotheistic idea of God, and faith in His moral government, and out of which springs the idea of a " kingdom of God " as the end of the Divine conduct of history. It does not follow, because this conception, or rather that of the Father-God of Christ, is the only one capable of satisfying man's religious or moral aspirations, that therefore man has been able to produce it from his own resources. Even if he were able, this alone would not satisfy the religious necessity. For religion craves not merely for the idea of God, but for personal fellowship and communion with Him, and this can only take • place on the ground that God and man are in some way brought together — in other words, on the basis of Divine Revelation or manifestation. 5. We may perhaps test the statements now made, by applying them to two cases which seem at first sight to contradict them, viz.. Buddhism, and the Comtist " Religion of Humanity " ; for in neither of these systems have we the recognition of a God. Are they, then, jDroperly to be accounted religions % (1) Buddhism is a religion, but it is not so in virtue of its negation of the Divine, but in virtue of the provision it still makes for the religious nature of man. Buddhism, as it exists to-day, is anything but a system of Atheism or Agnosticism ; it is a positive faith, with abundance of super- natural elements. It may have begun with simple reverence for Buddha, — itself a substitute for worship, — but the unstilled cravings of the heart for worship soon demanded more. Invention rushed in to fill the vacuum in the original creed, and the heavens which Buddha had left tenantless were repeopled with gods, saints, prospective Buddhas, and still higher imperishable essences, ending in the practical deification of Buddha him- self. Buddhism has all the paraphernalia of a religion, — priests, temples, images, worship, etc.^ (2) In like manner, Comte's system has a cult, in which the sentiments and affections which naturally seek their outlet in the direction of the Divine are artificially directed to a new object, collective humanity, 1 On Buddhism, see Monier Williams' "Duff Lectures" (1889); and on its relation to religion, Carpenter's Permanent Elements of Religion (1889), Lecture III. ; Gender's Basis of Faith, Note I ; Hartmaun's Religionsphilosophie, ii, p. 5 ; Kaftan's Das Wesen, p. 41, etc. NOTES TO LECTURE I. 437 which man is bid adore as the " Grand fitre," along with space as the "Grand Milieu," and the earth as the "Grand Fetiche" ! There is the smell of the lamp in all this, which betrays too obviously the character of Comtism as an artificial or " manufactured " religion ; but if it receives this name, it is because there is an application of Divine attributes to objects which, however unworthy of having Divine honours paid to them, are still worshipped as substitutes for God, and so form an inverted testimony to the need which the soul feels for God.^ NOTE J. UNDOGMATIC RELIGION. The type of view described in the text is too common to need further characterisation. I add a few illustrations of it from recent literature. " The vital essence of faith," says Mr. Picton, " though, like every mental and moral affection, impossible of realisation in abstract simplicity, lies not in any form of opinion which may clothe it, but in the energy of a voluntary devotion to the best ideal known. . . . No definition of religion can be satisfactory unless it surrenders all distinction between essential and non-essential dogmas ; unless, in fact, it is capable of embracing within its scope every conceivable opinion that can by any possibility be conscientiously held."— M^s^er?/ of Matter, pp. 159, 213. " To leave the religious idea in its more complete indeterminateness," says Kenan, " to hold at the same time to these two propositions : — (1) ' Religion will be eternal in humanity ; ' (2) ' All religious symbols are assailable and perishable ; ' such, then, will be, if the opinion of the wise could be that of the majority, the true theology of our time. All those who labour to show, beyond the symbols, the pure sentiment which constitutes the soul of them, labour for the future. To what in fact will you attach religion, if this immortal basis does not suffice you?" — Fragments philosophiques, p. 392. Eeville says : " If religions are mortal, religion never dies, or we may say, it dies under one form only to come to life again under another. There is then underneath and within this multicoloured development a permanent and substantial element, something stable and imperishable, which takes a firm hold on human nature itself." — History of Religions^ p. 3 (Eng. trans.). M. Eeville is a distinguished member of the Liberal Protestant party in France, whose programme was summed up thus in their organ, VEmanci- jjation: " A Church without a priesthood ; a religion without a catechism ; a morality without dogmatics ; a God without an obligatory system." 1 On Comtism as a religion, see Caird's Social Philosophy of Comte (pp. 47-55 ; and Chapter IV.); Carpenter's Permanent Elonents, Introduction, 25, 49 ; Conder's Basis of Faith, Lecture I.; Spencer's ''Retrogressive Religion" in Nineteenth Century, July 1884. On modern substitutes for Christianity generally, see an excellent treatment in Bruee's Miraculous Elements in the Gosjyels, Lecture X. 438 NOTES TO LECTURE L • Frequently this view is propounded in the name of science, as "by Professor Tyndall in his Belfast address :~" You, who have escaped from these religions into the high-and-dry light of the understanding may deride them ; but in so doing you deride accidents of form merely, and fail to touch the immovable basis of the religious sentiment in the emotional nature of man. To yield this sentiment reasonable satisfaction is the problem of problems at the present hour. And grotesque in relation to scientific culture as many of the religions of the world have been and are — dangerous, nay, destructive to the dearest privileges of freemen as some of them undoubtedly have been, and would, if they could, be again — it will be wise to recognise them as the forms of a force, mischievous, if permitted to intrude on the region of hiowledge^ over which it holds no command, but capable of adding, in the region of jpoetry and emotion^ inward completeness and dignity to man." — Fragments of Science, ii. 198. The theory is sometimes advocated in the ethical interest. The position of the "modern" school in the Netherlands is thus described by Professor Bavinck, of Kampen : " The God we need is not to be found outside of ourselves, but within. Religion is consecration to the moral ideal, to tlie power of the good, to the ' Thou shalt ' of conscience. Religion is not science, not a view of the world, but a specific conception of life. Pure morality, holiness is the content of religion. Some adherents of this tendency went to such an extreme in the avowal of these ideas, that with a degree of justice an ' atheistic school ' of modern theology began to be spoken of."— Art. in Fresbyt. and Bef. Eev., April 1892, See also Dr. Martineau's Ideal Substitutes for God (1879), pp. 7, 8 ; and the interesting appendix in Dr. Tulloch's Christian Doctrine of Sin, on the "Modern School of Dutch Divines — Die ethische Richtung." I need only refer to Matthew Arnold's view of religion as " morality touched by emotion." A warfare has recently been going on in Germany on this subject of a dogmatic or undogmatic Christianity, provoked by a brochure of Dreyer's entitled Undogmatisches Ohristenthum (1888). Kaftan has replied in his Glaube und Dogma, and others have taken part in the controversy. In our own country, it is difficult to distinguish the positions of writers like Dr. Hatch, in his Hil^bert Lectures on The Influence of Greek Ideas and Usages upon the Christian Church (1888), and Mr. Bartlett in his Bampton Lectures on The Letter and the Spirit, from that of the advocates of a perfectly undogmatic Christianity. NOTE K. ESTHETIC THEORIES OP RELIGION. The theories which ascribe to the ideals and beliefs of religion only an imaginative, poetic, or aesthetic value, constitute a large family. In Christian theology the tendency found a representative in the beginning of NOTES TO LECTURE L 439 the century in De Wette, whose " aesthetic rationalism " is explained and criticised by Dorner {Doctrine of the Person of Christ, v. pp. 51-58, Eng. trans.) and Pfleiderer {Develojjment of Theology, pp. 97-102). On the side of materialistic science, the best- known representative is Fr. A. Lange, author of the History of Materialism (1875), whose positions are yet more fearlessly carried out by his disciple Vaihinger : "We ought to have, and may have, a theory of the world (or religion), but we must not believe in it theoretically ; we must only allow ourselves to be practically, aesthetically, ethically influenced by it." See this theory explained and acutely criticised in Stahlin's Ka7it, Lotze, und Eitschl, pp. 92-110 (Eng. trans.) ; and in Pfleiderer's Religionsphilosophie, ii. pp. 173-175. From the idealistic side, this view, again, is represented by Vacherot in his La Metaphysique et la Science (1858) : " God is the idea of the world, and the world is the reality of God." His theory is criticised at length by Caro, in his L'Idee de Dieu, chap, v., and in Kenan's Fragments philo- sophiques, pp. 267-324. Finally, Feuerbach, from the atheistic side, regards the idea of God as a mere illusion — the projection by man of his own ego into infinity. See his JVesen des Christenthums (translated). Professor Seth has said of this class of theories as a whole : " The faith bred of ignorance is neither stable, nor is it likely to be enlightened. It will either be a completely empty acknowledgment, as we see in the belief in the Unknowable, or it will be an arbitrary play of poetic fancy, such as is proposed by Lange for our consolation. Our phenomenal world, says Lange, is a world of materialism ; but still the Beyond of the Unknowable remains to us. There we may figure to ourselves an ampler and diviner air, and may construct a more perfect justice and goodness than we find on earth. The poets, in word and music and painting, are the chief interpreters of this land of the Ideal. To them we must go if we would restore our jaded spirits. But we may not ask — or if we do, we cannot learn — whether this fairyland exists, or ■whether it has any relation to the world of fact. To all which it may be confidently replied, that such an empty play of fancy can discharge the functions neither of philosophy nor of religion. The synthesis of philosophy and the clear confidence of religion may both, in a sense, transcend the actual data before us, and may both, therefore, have a certain affinity with poetry ; but the synthesis is valueless and the confidence ill-timed if they do not express our deepest insight into facts, and our deepest belief as to the ultimate nature of things." — Scottish Philosophy, pp. 178, 179. NOTE L. SCHLEIERMACHER ON DOGMATICS. Schleiermacher's views on the nature and place of dogmatics are ex- pounded in his Der christ. Glauhe, Sects. 15-19. He says: "Sect. 15. Christian propositions of faith are apprehensions of the pious states of 440 NOTES TO LECTURE I. heart (Gemiithszustande) of the Christian exhibited in speech. Sect. 16. Dogmatic propositions are propositions of faith of the exhibitory didactic kind, in which the highest possible degree of definiteness is aimed at. Sect. 17. Dogmatic propositions have a twofold value, an ecclesiastical and a scientific ; and through both, and the relation of the two to one another, is their perfection determined. Sect. 18. The placing together of dogmatic propositions with a view to connect them with one another, and to relate them to one another, proceeds from the same need as the dogmatic formation of propositions itself, and is only a natural con- sequence of this." He says under this section — " It is not to be thought that the pious self-consciousness is living enough to be able to express and communicate itself without didactic expression. . . . And just as little in any pious community is it to be thought that the single elements of this consciousness can exist without being obliged to form themselves into the fulness of a series of thoughts, which partly aim, in accordance with their original end, at describing the states of the Christian mind (Gemiith) in a real sequence, or in their natural connection ; partly have the design of perfecting the didactic expression for its own sake to the utmost possible clearness." NOTE M. RELIGIOUS AND THEORETIC KNOWLEDGE. A. Arnold states the distinction as it appears in recent theology and philosophy thus : " It has recently been sought in manifold ways, under a stimulus derived from Kant, to find an essential distinction between theoretic knowledge, and a knowledge which does not extend our know- ledge of objects in the least, but stands solely in the service of purely subjective interests. This latter has only the significance of expressing in any given case the worth of the object for the subject ; these notions have nothing whatever to do with the knowledge of truth, but only with practical interests ; therefore our knowledge is not furthered through any of these notions, but they are only the means for the attainment of subjective ends. Shortly, knowing is placed here at the service of another mental function, and on this account produces, not objective knowledge, but only representations (Vorstellungen), which are formed in a foreign interest, but are perfectly indiff'erent whether they also extend our knowledge— help-representations, we may call them, formed in order by their means to reach other ends. Should reference be made to truth, this would still in no wise have anything to do with knowledge ; the truth of such representations would be measured solely by this, whether with their help one does or does not attain the wished-for end, irrespective of whether these representations were in themselves mere phantasies or not. Just for this reason is all metaphysical worth refused to such notions, e.gr., aesthetic or religious."— Das menschliche Erkennen, " Die auf Werthurtheile ruhenden Begriffe," pp. 170, 171. NOTES TO LECTURE I. 441 The kindredsliip of this view to the " sestlietic rationalism " referred to in last note is greater than is sometimes acknowledged — in one disciple of the school, Bender, it becomes indistinguishable from it. (See his Das Wesen der JReligion, 1886.) It should, however, be remarked, that Kaftan has severed himself from 'the extreme positions of this school, and has sought in his various works to find an adjustment between faith and theoretic knowledge which will avoid the appearance of collision between them. He expressly lays down the proposition that "there is only o??e truth, and that all truth is from God"; acknowledges that faith- propositions have their theoretic side, and that " in the treatment of the truth of the Christian religion it is the theoretic side of these which comes into consideration " ; explains that " truth " in this connection means simply what it does in other cases, not subjective truth, but "objective" — "the agreement of the proposition with the real state of the case," etc. {Die Wahrheit, pp. 1-7). Most significant of all is his statement in a recent article that he has abandoned the expression " Werthurtheile " altogether, as liable to misunderstanding. " I have," he says, " in this attempt to describe the knowledge of faith according to its kind and manner of origin, avoided the expression ' Werthurtheile,' although I have earlier so characterised the propositions of faith (in which the knowledge of faith is given). They are theoretic judgments, which are grounded upon a judgment of worth, which therefore cannot be appropriated without entering into this judgment of worth which lies at their foundation."— " Glaube und Dogmatik," in Zeitschrift fur Theol. und Kirche, i. 6, p. 501. Of. further on this distinction, Stiihlin's acute criticism in his Kant, Lotze, und Bitschl, pp. 157 ff. (Eng. trans.); Hartmann in his Beligions- philosophie, ii. pp. 1-27 ; Lipsius in his Dogmatik, pp. 16-93. Hartmann and Lipsius deal at length with the distinction and relations of the " religious '* and the " theoretic " "Weltanschauung." NOTE K RITSCHL ON RELIGION AND PHILOSOPHY. The following extracts illustrate the division which Kitschl makes between religious and philosophical knowledge, while acknowledging their application to the same object : — " The partition of the material of theology into rational propositions and propositions derived from Revelation is a method whose validity is no longer admitted. In opposition to it the contention has gradually become prevalent that religion and the theoretic knowledge of tlie world are distinct functions of the spirit, which, where they are applied to the same objects, do not even partially coincide, but go in toto asunder from each other ."—Rechtfertigung und Versohnung, iii. (3rd ed.) p. 185. " The possibility of the intermingling, and again of the collision of the two kinds of knowledge, lies in this, that they are directed on the same 442 NOTES TO LECTURE I. object, namely, the world. It is not permitted to lis to content ourselves with the peaceful decision that the Christian knowledge grasps the world as a whole, the philosophical establishes the particular and general laws of nature and of the spirit. For each philosophy combines with its task also the aim of comprehending the world-whole in a highest law ; and a highest law is also for Christian knowledge the form in which the world as a whole is comprehended under God. Also, the thought of God, which belongs to religion, is in some form or other applied in every philosophy not materialistic. Tlierefore, provisionally at least, no distinction of the two kinds of knowledge is to be reached in the object." — Ihid. pp. 193, 194. NOTE 0. THE HEGELIAN THEORY OF RELIGION. I HAVE not discussed this theory in the text, as it does not represent any immediately reigning tendency. On the crucial question of the possibility of a knowledge of the Divine, Hegel is at the very opposite pole from Schleiermacher and Ritschl. So far from the mind being incapacitated for the knowledge of God, it is its destiny as rational spirit to know God, and it cannot rest till it has attained that knowledge. But with this Hegel holds what must be regarded as essentially a false view of the relation of religion to philosophy. Religion he would have us view as but a lower stage in the progress to pure philosophical thought. The idea with him is everything. Religious truths are but rational ideas clothed in a sensuous garb. It is the part of philosophy to lift the veil, and raise the idea to the form of pure thought. Religion gives the " Vorstellung," or figurate representation ; philosophy gives the rational conception, or " Begriff." ^ The claims of philosophy are here pitched too high, as, on the other hand, the claims of religion are put too low. There is no mere "Vorstellung" in religion — at least in the highest religion, Christianity ; but mingling with the figurative element 1 The distinction is explained by Hegel in the Introduction to his Geschichte der Philosophies i. pp. 79-97. A fuller exposition is given in his ReligionsphilosopMe, i. pp. 20-25. "The object of religion," he says, "as of philosophy, is the eternal truth in its very objectivity, — God, and nothing else than Grod and the explication of God. Philosophy is not a wisdom of the world, but knowledge of the non-worldly, not knowledge of the external mass, of empirical existence and life, but knowledge of that which is eternal, what God is and what flows from His nature. For this nature must reveal and develop itself, . . . Religion and philosophy therefore coin- cide in one ; philosophy is in fact itself a service of God— is religion — for it is the same renunciation of subjective conceits and opinions in the being occupied with God. Philosophy is therefore identical with religion, but the difl'erence is that it is this in a peculiar way, distinct from the way which it is customary to name religion as such. . . . Speculative philosophy is the consciousness of the Idea, so that all is grasped as Idea ; but the Idea is the true in thought (Gedanken), not in mere sensuous view (Auschauung) or representation (Vorstellung)," pp. 21-23, On the notion of religion particularly, and the stages of the religious consciousness, see pp. 85-137. NOTES TO LECTURE I. 443 i?j)roper to all religious apprehensions there is much clear and precise statement of spiritual truth, much naked and open vision of the Divine spirituality, righteousness, and love ; the constant shining through of the spiritual reality — the " Begriff," if one wills— even in the case of the most figurative representations. And in philosophy, on the other hand, there is no absolute "Begriff"— no knowledge of the Divine which is perfectly purged from all figurative and analogical elements. It is but a vain pretension of the Hegelian or any other philosophy to claim that it knows God so absolutely — so entirely as He is in Himself — that no human or representative features still cleave to the conception ; a vain dream, for example, of Biedermann's, one of the last representatives of this mode of thought, that his spectral abstractions represent God better, or are nearer the absolute truth, than the living concrete representations of Scripture.^ The fault of the Hegelian theory is its predominatingly intellectual and abstract character. We do not indeed attribute to Hegel the absurd view that religion has only to do with intellectual appre- hension, or notions of the reason, and not also with a relation of the heart and will. For all that, the relation between God and the soul in religion is too intellectually conceived. God is lost in logical relations. It is a system of categories, practically, which is presented to us instead of the Divine. It is the logical relation, the eternal truth, which absorbs all the interest. All else is appearance, manifestation, temporary form. In such a system, Christian doctrines find, of necessity, a new significance, and the process of extracting the " Begrifl: " from them consists in finding the suitable logical idea to which they correspond. The "Begriff" of the Incarnation, e.g.^ is the idea of the essential unity of God and man, and the "Vorstellung" is the representation of this in the Christian doctrine of the God-Man, Christ Jesus. At the shrine of the idea the historical is ruthlessly sacrificed. It is not thus that Christianity conceives of the relation to the Father-God in Christ ; and the reaction was inevitable which led to the repudiation of the metaphysical in theology altogether. One of the most delicate tasks of theology is to adjust the relation between these opposite one-sidednesses. 1 Cf. Biedermann's Ch/ristlidie Dogmatik, ii. pp. 516-561 (1884-85). NOTES TO LECTUKE II. NOTE A. THE CENTRAL PLACE OF CHRIST IN HIS RELIGION. The unique and central place of Christ in His religion, different from that of other founders of religion, is attested by writers of the most varied standpoints. Hegel says : " If we regard Christ in the same light as Socrates, we regard Him as a mere man, like the Mahometans, who consider Christ to have been an ambassador from God, as all great men may generally be called ambassadors or messengers of God. If we say no more of Christ than that He was a teacher of mankind, and a martyr for truth, we express ourselves neither from the Christian point of view, nor from that of true religion." — Phil. d. Kel. ii. p. 287. Sclielling says, in his Phil. d. Offenbarung : " The principal content of Christianity is, first, Christ Himself ; not what He said, but what He is, and did. Christianity is not, in the first place, a doctrine ; it is a thing, something objective ; and the doctrine can never be anything but the expression of the thing." — Quoted by Pfleiderer, Eeligionsjjhilosophiej ii. p. 16 (Eng. trans.). Dorner bears witness to the valuable service of Schelling and Hegel in overcoming the older rationalism, and introducing a profounder treat- ment of Christological questions. — Doctrine of the Person of Christ, v. pp. 100, 138 (Eng. trans.). De Wette says: "The personality of Jesus, His life and death, and faith in Him, constitute the centre of Christianity. The spirit of religion became personal in Him, and, proceeding from Him, exerted an influence upon the world, which stood in need of a new religious life in order to regenerate it. — Vorles. ilher die Religion, p. 444 (quoted by Hagenbach), Pfleiderer thus sums up the views of Vatke, a post-Hegelian : " All the streams of the world's history issue in the kingdom of God, which is the Avill of God in its concrete development to a moral commonwealth. Providence here acts as an actual spirit through all persons and deeds, through which the idea of the good becomes more real, especially through the creative world - historical persons, among whom Christ occuj^ies a unique position as the centre point of history, as the Revealer and the NOTES TO LECTURE 11. 445 Reality of tlie archetypal idea, as the love of God grown personal."— BeligionspMlosophie, ii. p. 268 (Eng. trans.). On the views of Biedermann and Lipsius, see the Christliche Dogmatih of the former, ii. pp. 580-600 ("the central dogma of the Christian principle "), and the Lehrh. d. Dogmatik of the latter, pp. 535-538. " In its dogmatic utterances on the Person and work of Christ," Lipsius says, "the Church expresses the consciousness that its existence has its historical foundation in the Person of Jesus, not merely in the sense which would be suitable to all other religions having personal founders, but in the sense that tlie Person of Christ is the archetypal representation of the Christian idea, and therefore the authoritative pattern for all time to come ; and that His work forms the permanently sufficient, therefore the creative, basis for the constantly progressing realisation of that idea in the common and individual life of Christians." — Bog. p. 537. Ritschl says : "The Person of the Founder of Christianity is the key to the Christian ' Weltanschauung,' and the standard for the self -judg- ment and moral striving of Christians." — Eecht. u. Ver. iii. p. 193 (3rd ed.). Cf. the comparison with Moses, Zoroaster, Mahomet, and Buddha, in pp. 364, 365. Kaftan emphatically says : " In the question of the Godhead of Jesus Christ, the discussion turns, not on one proposition among others which a Christian recognises and confesses, but upon the central point of the entire Christian confession of faith." — Brauchen wir ein neues Dogma'? p. 52. Hartmann, too, in his Krisis des Christemthums, treats this doctrine as the central matter, and discusses it in his first section under the heading, "The Christian Central Dogma and its inevitable Dissolution." Cf. Preface to 3rd ed. of his Selbstzersetzung d. Christenthums. It is needless to adduce instances from writers of a more orthodox tendency. NOTE B. THE DEFEAT OF ARIANISM. " The Christian doctrine has been accused," says a writer in the Church Qimrterly Review, " of being the result of the base intrigues of imperial politics, and to one who resolutely looks only at the details of much of the controversy, such a judgment might seem natural, while a close acquaintance with the Byzantine Court will not make its odour more pleasing. But to a wider view, such a judgment is impossible. The decision of the Council of Niciea was the result of the free play of the theological ideas of the time ; for Constantine — caring little about the result, though caring very much for unity — wisely left to the Council a free hand ; but its decision may very well have been owing to the influence of a sovereign who threw his whole weight on the side which he saw was prevailing. Arius was condemned by an overwhelming majority, but the decision of the Council was not sufficient to stamp out 446 NOTES TO LECTURE II. opinions wliicli had a natural liold on a large section of tlie Cliurcli. So the reaction was obliged to spread. Arianism survived for fifty years ; with the help of imperial patronage it even obtained an unreal supremacy. But it had no basis of truth, and was naturally hostile to Christianity. As long as it was established, it continued to exist ; orthodoxy was oppressed and persecuted, but orthodoxy increased. As soon as the balance of the temporal power swung round, orthodoxy became supreme, and Arianism vanished from the Empire as if it had never existed. It had more than a fair chance, but had no basis of truth. Orthodoxy had a terrible fight with odds against it, but in the end it was completely victorious." — Church Quart , April-July, 1888, pp. 462, 463. Harnack's judgment on Arianism is equally severe. " Only as cosmo- logists," he says, " are the Arians monotheists ; as theologians and in religion they are polytheists. Finally, deep contradictions lie in the background : a Son, who is no Son ; a Logos, who is no Logos ; a Mono- theism, which does not exclude Polytheism ; two or three Ousias, who are to be worshipped, while still only one is really distinguished from the creatures, an indefinable nature, which first becomes God when it becomes man, and which still is neither God nor man. . . . The opponents were right ; this doctrine leads back into heathenism. . . . The orthodox doctrine has, on the contrary, its abiding worth in the upholding of the faith, that in Christ God Himself has redeemed men, and led them into His fellowship. . . . This conviction of faith was saved by Atlianasius against a doctrine which did not undei'stand the inner nature of religion generally, which sought in religion only teaching, and ultimately found its satisfaction in an empty dialectic." — Grundriss d. Dogmengeschichte, i. p. 141 ; cf. the Dogmengeschichte, pp. 217-224.^ On the later history of Arianism in England, and its transformation into Unitarianism, see the valuable Appendix by Dr. Fairbairn to Dorner's History of the Doctrine of the Person of Christ, vol. v. pp. 337-466. NOTE C. MODERN UNITARIANISM. The completeness with which modern Unitarianism has divested itself of every trace of the supernatural will be seen from the following extracts. Dr. Martineau, criticising Mr. Greg's Creed of Christendom, writes : "The education and habits of a refined and devout Unitarian family 1 In his recent Lectures on The Incarnation (p. 91), Mr. Gore directs attention to two striking passages from Thomas Carlyle and Tliomas Hill Green to the same effect as the above. Mr. Froude writes of Carlyle : " He made one remark which is worth recording. In earlier years he had spoken contemptuously of the Athauasiau Controversy, — of the Christian world torn to pieces over a diphthong. ... He now told me that he perceived Christianity itself to have been at stake. If the Arians had won, it would have dwindled away to a legend. "—Zi/e in London, ii. p. 4()2. See Green's view in Works, iii. p. 172. NOTES TO LECTURE IT. 447 gave him the theory of life from which his independent thought set out. Outside observers, both sceptical and mystical, have always upbraided that theory as a weak attempt to blend incompatible elements and settle the contradictions of the world by a hollow compromise, while not denying its correspondence with a certain equilibrium of understanding and character. It may be described as essentially natural religion, enlarged and completed by a supernatural appendix. The whole of its theism, and half of its ethics, were within the reach of the human reason and conscience ; but of the inner and higher range of morals, — spiritual purity, forgiveness of injuries, love to the unlovely, — the obligation was first impressed by the Christian Eevelation. And the life beyond death, vainly pursued by the dialectic of Plato, and claimed by the rhetoric of Cicero, became an assured reality with the Eesurrection of Christ. The universe was a mechanical system of delegated causality, instituted for beneficent and righteous ends, and, for their better attainment, not excluding fresh intercalary volitions at special crises. . . . The former of these conceptions it cost Mr. Greg but little to modify or even to sacrifice," etc. — Nineteenth Century^ February 1883. What even Mr. Greg desires to retain of reverence for the spiritual perfection of Jesus, Mr. F. W. Newman, in his review of the volume, regards only as an amiable weakness, in total inconsistency with Mr. Greg's own principles of treatment of the Gospels. See passage quoted in Note F to Lecture I. (from Fortnightly Review, vol. xiv.). In his Loss and Gain in Recent Theology (1881), Dr. Martineau sets himself explicitly to state the position of present-day Unitarianism ; and the two gains he principally notices are : " the total disappearance from our branch of the Keformed Churches of all external authority in matters of religion" ("the yoke of the Bible follows the yoke of the Church," p. 9) ; ^ and, second, " the disappearance of the entire Messianic theology." " As objective reality, as a faithful representation of our invisible and ideal universe, it is gone from us, gone, therefore, from our interior religion, and become an outside mythology. From the Person of Jesus, for instance, everything official, attached to Him by evangelists or divines, has fallen away ; when they put such false robes on Him, they were but leading Him to death. The pomp of royal lineage and fulfilled predic- tion, the prerogatives of King, of Priest, of Judge, the advent with retinue of angels on the clouds of heaven, are to us mere deforming 1 The late Principal Cairns observes on this: "It is important to remark how completely his admission bears out the whole contention of writers of the school opposite to his in the Socinian controversy, that the tendency of Unitarian doctrine and criticism was to abrogate the authority of Scripture, and reduce it to the level of human literature. This allegation was vehemently resisted in their day by the Polish brethren, who often put on Scripture a non-natural sense rather than seem to invade its authority ; and in more recent times, by Priestley and Belsham, and other controversialists. It will be remembered that in the earnest debate between Moses Stuart and Channing on the Trinity, the former urged tlie latter, by the example of Continental rationalism, no longer to profess unlimited submission to Scripture, but to escape insuperable critical difficulties which arose on his side, by openly denying its claims to be a judge in controversy."— Art. in Catholic Presbyterian, November 1888. 448 NOTES 70 LECTURE TT. investitures, misplaced, like court dresses, on the 'spirits of the just,' and He is simply the Divine Flower of humanity, blossoming after ages of spiritual growth — the realised possibility of life in God. . . . All that has been added to that real historic scene, — the angels that hang around His birth, and the fiend that tempts His youth ; the dignities that await His future, — the throne, the trumpet, the assize, the bar of judgment ; with all the apocalyptic splendours and terrors that ensue, — Hades and the Crystal Sea, Paradise and the Infernal Gulf, nay, the very boundary walls of the Kosmic panorama that contains these things, have for ns utterly melted away, and left us amid the infinite space and the silent stars "(pp. 14, 15). "Time was," says the Rev. J. W. Chadwick, of Brooklyn, "when Christianity was universally regarded by Unitarians as a supernatural revelation, attested by signs and wonders, promulgated by One who, even if purely human, was endowed with certain supernatural gifts, and per- petuated in a literature — the New Testament — whose writers were mira- culously restrained from all erroneous statement, whether of doctrine or fact. These views are no longer held in their entirety by Unitarians. . . . There are to-day few Unitarians, if any, who believe in any of the New Testament miracles, from the birth of Jesus to His Resurrection inclusive, in the proper sense of the word miracles — violations of natural laws." — In a recent paper, Wlwj I am a Unitarian. NOTE D. CONCESSIONS OF RITSCHLIANS ON THE PERSON OF CHRIST. In this school, as stated in the Lectures, the attribution of Divinity to Christ is regarded as a simple religious judgment — a judgment of value — with no metaphysical meaning behind it. It simply expresses the value which Christ has to the believer as the Revealer of God to him in His grace and truth, and tells us nothing of what Christ is in Himself. How Christ came to be what He was, or what lies in the constitution of His Person behind this Revelation, it is no part of the business of theology to inquire. This is the original Ritschlian position, but it is significant that Ritschl's followers are feeling the need of some modification of it, and have already made several significant concessions. " It is increasingly recognised," as I have stated elsewhere, "that we cannot stand simply dumb before the Revelation which it is acknowledged we have in Christ, and refuse to ask who this wonderful Person is that bears the Revelation, and whose personal character and relation to the kingdom of God is so unique. We cannot rest with simply formulating the value of Christ to us ; we must ask what He is in Himself. . . . The mind will not stay in the vagueness of expressions about Christ's 'Godhead,' to which the suspicion constantly attaches that they are mere metaphors. Thus, in spite of their wishes, the Ritschlians are forced to declare themselves a little further, and it is significant that, so far as their explanations go, NOTES TO LECTURE II. 449 they are in the direction of recognising that metaphysical background in Christ's Person against which at first protest was entered.^ Thus, in a remarkable passage in his Der VerJcehr des Christen mit Gottf Hermann says : " It may be unavoidable that this wonderful experience should excite in us the question, how a man can win this importance for us. And it appears to me as if, for all who wish to go back on this question, and follow out the representation of a union of the Divine and human natures in Christ, the Christological decisions of the ancient Church still always mark out the limits within which such attempts must move" (p. 46, 1st ed., 1886). In his earlier work. Die Religion im Verhdltniss zum Welterkennen und %ur Sittlichkeit, Hermann had expressed himself, if possible, still more decidedly. " I have certainly the conviction," he says, " the grounds of which I do not need to state here further, that faith in Christ was led in a natural progress to the representation of a pre- existence of Christ, and indeed of a personal, and not an ideal, pre-existence. The assumption of a so-called ideal pre-existence seems to me unjustified. It is still clearly the Person of the exalted Lord, whose worth for the Church and for the kingdom of God is expressed by saying that He did not come into being under earthly conditions as we have done, but that, independently of the world, which represents the perfectly dependent sphere of His Lordship, He is. This thought finds, in the expression of a personal pre-existence of the Lord, an expression very full of contradic- tions indeed, but still the only one which stands at our command, which, therefore, must also have its salutary truth. The contradiction will be removed, if once a solution is found of the problem of time, in which we now view our existence. . . . Faith is led to this, to regard the Redeemer, whom it knows as the Revelation of God, as pre-existent." — Die Religion, etc., pp. 438, 439 (1879). Yet more positively do Bornemann, in his Unterricht im Christenthum (1891), and Kaftan, in his various works, demand a real "Godhead" of Christ, though still with much criticism of " the old dogma," ^ and the repudiation of all speculative or metaphysical theologising. The former says : " Faith in the Godhead of Christ is in a certain sense the sum of the whole gospel ; the aim and the whole content of the Christian life. Its marks are the same as those of the Godhead of the heavenly Father." — Unterricht, p. 91. Kaftan's views are most fully exhibited in his Brauchen wir ein neues Dogma ? (1890), (" Do we need a New Dogma ?"). In a section of this pamphlet, under the heading, " What think ye of Christ?" he says: "Many will object that all has no basis and no guarantee of truth, if it is not established that Jesus has His origin and 1 Art. on "The Ritsclilian Theology," in The Thinker, August 1892. 2 The contrast between the "old" and the "new" is expressed by Kaftan thus: "The eternal relation of Jesus Christ to the Father is in the old dogma the peculiar and whole object of the doctrine ; it accords with evangelical Christianity, on the other hand, to know His Godhead in its living present relations to us and to our faith" (Brauchen wir, etc., p. 54). But this is not an absolute opposition, nor are the standpoints necessarily exclusive. 29 450 NOTES TO LECTURE 11. the beginning of His earthly life from above, and not from below. And in this lies something, the truth of which cannot be gainsaid. At least, it is in my view also a consequence we cannot refuse of faith in the Godhead of the Lord, that He, that His historical Person, stands in a connection of nature with God perfectly unique and not capable of being repeated. We know not how we can call a man ' God,' — the word is too great and too weighty, — if we do not truly mean that the eternal God Himself has come to us in Him, and in Him converses with us. ... Do we believe in the Godhead of the Lord, then we believe also in His origin from above, out of God." — Brauchen wir, etc., p. 58. Of. the statements in his original work. Das Wesen, etc., pp. 308 fF. (1st. ed.). This movement cannot fail to go further, and work itself into clearer relations with the old dogma which it condemns. ^ NOTE E. THE WEAKNESS OF DEISM. The weakness of Deism as a logical system is universally conceded. "Deism," says M. Keville, "in sound philosophy is not tenable. It establishes a dualism, a veritable opposition, between God and the world, which stand opposite to and limit each other. ... A reaction, in fact, was inevitable. It was necessary that it should be at the same time philosophical and religious, and should come to the satisfaction of the needs that had been misunderstood and suppressed. In philosophy Deism could no longer hold up its head against the objections of reason. In religion, every one was wearied of optimism and of empty declama- tions. Deism removed God so far from the world and from humanity, that piety exhausted itself in the endeavour to rejoin Him in the icy heights of heaven, and ended by renouncing the attempt." — La DiviniU de J^sus- Christ, pp. 163, 171. Again : " The eighteenth century little imagined that natural religion, the religion which humanity was bound to profess in this age of idyllic virtue, in which le contrat social had been elaborated before it was corrupted by the artifices of priests and kings, was nothing else but philosophic Deism. It did not perceive that this pretended natural religion was merely an extract subtly derived from Christian tradition, the fruit of a civilisation already old and artificial, already saturated with , criticism and rationalism, quite the opposite of a religion springing up spontaneously in the human mind still influenced by its primitive traditions." — History of Religions, p. 14 (Eng. trans.). Professor Seth has said : " Deism does not perceive that, by separating God from the world and man, it really makes Him finite, by setting up alongside of Him a sphere to which His relations are transient and accidental. The philosopher to whom the individual self and the sensible 1 Wendt, on the other hand, in his Inhalt der Lehre Jesu, refuses to see in Jesus anything but an ethical Sonship (pp. 450-476). NOTES TO LECTURE II. 451 world form the first reality, gradually comes to think of this otiose Deity as a more or less ornamental appendage in the scheme of things. In France, the century ended in atheism ; and in cosmopolitan circles in England and Germany, the belief in God had become little more than a form of words."— i^rom Kant to Hegel, p. 24. " The philosophic rationalism of the vulgar Aufklarung," says Hart- mann, "appeared with the claim to set up in place of the disesteemed historical religions a self-evident * natural religion ' or ' religion of reason ' for all men, the content of which was first a shallow Deism, with its trinity of ideas of a personal God, personal immortality, and personal freedom of will ; but already in the circles of the French Encyclopajdists this spiritless Deism had struck over into an equally spiritless materialism." — Eeligionsphilosophie, ii. p. 24. NOTE F. WEAKNESS OF MODERN LIBERAL PROTESTANTISM. The modern Liberal Protestantism in Germany, Holland, Switzerland, and France, which, while discarding the supernatural in history, still re- tains the name Christian,— nay, claims to be the true Christianity, purified and brought into harmony with the " modern " spirit,— meets with scant mercy at the hands of those who have gone further, who ruthlessly strip off the veil which disguises its essential rationalism. Pfleiderer and Reville may be named as well-known representatives. The party, while claiming the right to criticise and reject every article of the creed, would retain the traditional forms of worship, and delight, even, to clothe their conceptions in the familiar forms of the traditional dogmatics. It is thus that a service of the " moderns " is described by one of their own number. "Only put yourself," says this witness, "in the position of those who had never received any other teaching, for example, than that Jesus was born of the Virgin Mary, and suddenly heard their pastor speak on some Christmas - day of 'simple parents of the man of Nazareth,' or on Easter Sunday of ' the delusion of the early Christians that Jesus has returned to earth from his grave.' . . . Yet such preach- ing was actually heard. . . . The Church listened, thought it over, thought it over again, and finally a large number of her members accepted the new teaching " (quoted by Mr. Wicksteed, Eccl. Instit. of Holland, p. 59). It is the glaring inconsistency of this position which is remorse- lessly satirised by writers like Strauss and Hartmann, and the thing which gives their strictures sharpness is that there is so much truth in them. There was a time when Strauss also wrote : " But we have no fear that we should lose Christ by being obliged to give up a considerable part of what was hitherto called the Christian creed ! He will remain to all of us the more surely, the less anxiously we cling to doctrines and opinions that might tempt our reason to forsake Him. But if Christ remains to us, and if He remains to us as the highest we know, and are capable of 452 NOTES TO LECTURE 11. imagining witliin the spliere of religion, as the Person without whose presence in the mind no perfect piety is possible ; we may fairly say that in Him do we still possess the sum and substance of the Christian faith " (Selbstgesprdche, p. 67, Eng. trans.). But in his The Old Faith and the New, Strauss later faced the question, " Are we still Christians ? " with a bolder look, and gave it the uncompromising answer, " No." He goes over the articles of the Apostles' Creed one by one, and shows that every one of them is taken by the " modern " theologians in a non- natural sense. He invites his readers "to assist in thought at the cycle of festivals in a Protestant church, whose minister stands on the ground of present-day science, and see whether he can still be uprightly and naturally edified thereby." He pictures the statements that such a minister would be compelled to make at Christmas, at the Epiphany, at Good Friday, at Easter, and Ascension Day ; compares them with the book he reads, the prayers he uses, the sacraments he administers ; and shows how com- pletely the whole thing is a ludicrous pretence. His conclusion is : " If we do not wish to escape difficulties, if we do not wish to twist and dissemble, if we wish our yea to be yea, and our nay, nay, — in short, if we would speak as honourable, upright men, — we must confess, we are no longer Christians." — Der alte und der neue Glauhe, pp. 12-94. Hartmann is even more severe on the unchristian character of the modern Protestant Liberalism in his Selbstzersetzung des Christenthums (chaps, vi. and vii.). "We ask," he says, "what right the Protestant Liberals have to call themselves Christians beyond the fact that their parents have had them baptized and confirmed. In all ages there has been one common mark of the Christian religion — belief in Christ. . . . But we have seen that the Liberal Protestants cannot believe in Christ as either Luther, or Thomas of Aquinas, or John, or Paul, or Peter, believed in Christ, and least of all as Jesus believed in Himself, for He believed Himself to be the Christ— the Messiah" (pp. 64, 65). Apart, however, from criticisms of opponents, which may be deemed unfair, it is a fact that, through all its history, Protestant Liberalism has found it exceedingly difficult to maintain itself on the platform even of Theism, not to speak of that of Christianity. Its tendency has been Constantly "downgrade," till either it has ended in open rejection of Christianity, or has been displaced by more positive forms of belief. Strauss's case is not a solitary one. A parallel is found in the career of Edmond Scherer, the inaugurator of the modern Liberal movement in Switzerland and France, who, beginning with the most uncompromising traditional orthodoxy, went on, according to M. Gretillat, to the progressive repudiation of all the fundamentals of Christian belief, religious and even moral, up to the point of absolute scepticism. The party of Liberal Christianity initiated by him, of which Reville is a surviving representative, had, according to the same authority, " only a fleeting existence, and its name, to speak in popular language, soon dis- appeared from the handbill " ^ (article on " Theological Thought among French Protestants " in Presbyt. and Ref. Review, July 1892). In Holland, too, the "modern" school is seen running a remarkable course. Its 1 It was replaced by newer Ritschlian tendencies. NOTES TO LECTURE 11. 453 originator, Scholten, was at first, like Sclierer of Geneva, quite conserva- tive. Then he passed to a view of Eevelation and of Christianity not unlike Pfleiderer's. His " thoughts, however, were not expounded with perfect distinctness in the beginning. They were too much clothed in the old orthodox forms, and had too large an admixture of conservative elements for this. Scholten himself lived in the honest conviction of having discovered the reconciliation of faith and knowledge, of theology and philosophy, of the heart and the intellect. He was able also to impart this conviction to others. Soon the new Gospel was proclaimed with enthusiasm from many pulpits. . . . Among his followers the illusion was well-nigh imiversal, that the reasonableness of the faith and of the doc- trine of the Reformed Church had been established." This confidence received a rude shock when, in 1864, Scholten himself declared that, while formerly believing that he found in the Scriptures, rightly expounded, his view of the world, he was no longer of that opinion. " He now begins to recognise that between his ideas and those of the Bible there is no agree- ment, but a deep chasm. . . . The results soon showed themselves. The illusion had been dispelled ; faith and enthusiasm suffered shipwreck. Some ministers, like Pierson and Busken Huet, resigned the office and left the Church. Others felt dissatisfied with the monism of Scholten. . . . A whole group of modern theologians broke loose from Scholten's system, and sought a closer alliance with Hoekstra. . . . Some adherents of this tendency went to such an extreme in the avowal of these ideas that, with a degree of justice, an ' atheistic shade ' of modern theology began to be spoken of." — Professor Bavinck, of Kampen, in Preshyt. and Eef. Review^ April 1892. Professor Bavinck thus sums up on the development in Holland : " In casting a retrospective glance at the three tendencies described up to this point, we are struck with the tragic aspect of this development of dogmatic thought. It is a slow process of dissolution that meets our view. It began with setting aside the Confession. Scripture alone was to be heard. Next, Scripture also is dismissed, and the Person of Christ is fallen back on. Of this Person, however, first His Divinity, next His pre-existence, finally His sinlessness, are surrendered, and nothing remains but a pious man, a religious genius, revealing to us the love of God. But even the existence and love of God are not able to withstand criticism. Thus the moral element in man becomes the last basis from which the battle against Materialism is conducted. But this basis will appear to be as unstable and unreliable as the others." NOTE G. CHRISTIANITY AND THE IDEA OP PROGRESS. "The hopeful view of human history," says Professor J. Candlish, "according to which there is to be expected a gradual progress in an upward direction, and an ultimate state of goodness and happiness, was 454 NOTES TO LECTURE II. entirely foreign to tlie ideas of the ancient world. Its pliilosopliers and poets either regarded the course of mankind as a continual degeneracy from a golden age in the past, or as a vast cycle in which there was a continual return or reproduction of the same events and states of things. . . . The idea of the perfectibility of mankind, and of the gradual and steady improvement of the race in the course of time, which has been so largely used by those who reject Christianity, and which enables them to make light of the supernatural grounds of hope for the world that Christians cherish, was entirely strange to the pre-Christian ages ; and though it may be due in part to the progress of science, yet is much more to be ascribed to the promises and truths of Revelation. At least it may be said with truth that Christianity, and more particularly the Christian idea of the kingdom of God, furnishes the only solid ground for such hopes for mankind. ... In modern times the discoveries of science in its investigation of the works of creation have tended to awaken in men's minds a similar hopeful spirit, so that the gradual and sure advance of mankind to perfection has been accepted almost as an axiom or self- evident truth by many who do not accept the religious basis on which it rested in Israel. But it may be doubted whether, apart from a belief in God as the Creator of the universe, and at the same time the God of grace and salvation, there is any solid foundation for such a hopeful view of the world's history. The rise and prevalence of Pessimistic views in modern times serves to show this ; and some of those who are most sanguine about the prospects of mankind, apart from Eevelation and Christianity, acknowledge frankly that there can be no certainty of this on a merely natural basis, and that possibly after all we may have to fall back into Pessimism." — Tlie Kingdom of G^o^-(Cunningham Lectures, 1884), pp. 38-42. See on this subject the careful history of the idea of progress in Flint's Philosophy of History, pp. 28-42 ; and the valuable remarks in Hare's Guesses at Truth (referred to also by Dr. Candlish), pp. 305-348 (1871).' Cf. Leopardi's (and Hartmann's) three stages of human illusion, in Caro's Le Pessimisme, pp. 39-49. NOTE H. THE PREVALENCE OF PESSIMISM. " It is a singular phenomenon," says Luthardt, " that in our time, in which so much complaint is made of the decay of philosophical study and interest, a definite philosophical system has attained a popularity which is almost without precedent in earlier systems ; and a philosophical work has had a success which usually falls only to the lot of the most spirited literary works, and to romances. I refer to the philosophy of Pessimism, and to the work of E. von Hartmann, The Philosophy of the Unconscious." —Die Mod. Welt. p. 183. Caro observes : " We can now understand in what sense, and how far it NOTES TO LECTURE IL 455 is true that the disease of Pessimism is a disease 'essentially modern.' ^ . . . How strange this revival of Buddhistic Pessimism, with all the apparatus of the most learned systems, in the heart of Prussia, at Berlin ! That three hundred millions of Asiatics should drink in long draughts the opium of these fatal doctrines which enervate and act as a soporific on the will is already sufficiently strange ; but that a race, energetic, disciplined, so strongly constituted for knowledge and for action, at the same time so practical, a rigorous calculator, warlike and stern, certainly the opposite of a sentimental race, — that a nation formed of these robust and lively elements should give a triumphant welcome to these theories of despair divulged by Schopenhauer, — that its military optimism should accept with a sort of enthusiasm the apology for death and for annihilation, — it is this which at the first view seems inexplicable. And the success of the doctrine is not confined to the banks of the Spree. The whole of Germany has become attentive to this movement of ideas. Italy, with a great poet, had outstripped the current ; France, as we shall see, has followed in a certain measure ; she also, at the present hour, has her Pessimists." — Le Pessimisme, pp. 25, 26. " There can be no question," says* Karl Peters, " that Schopenhauerism is for the time the dominating tendency in our fatherland. One needs only to consult Laban's book-list to be convinced of the fact ; our whole atmosphere is, so to speak, saturated with Schopenhauer's views and ideas. . . . Hand in hand with the colossal forward development of our race in all departments, goes the fact that the sorrow of earthly existence is felt to-day more keenly than ever by the masses. A decided Pessimistic current goes through our time." — Willenswelt, pp. 109, 244. Pessimism, according to Hartmann, is the deeper mood of humanity — its permanent undertone (Selbstzer. d. Christ, p. 96). NOTE I. THE LITERATURE OF PESSIMISM. The following books are referred to in the Lectures and Notes, and may be consulted on the subject of Pessimism :— Schopenhauer's Die Welt ah Wille und Vorstellung. Translated into English. Hartmann's Philosophie des Unbewussten. Versuch einer JVeltanschauung. Translated. Hartmann's Zur Geschichte und Begriindung des Pessimismus. 1880. Hartmann's Religionsphilosophie : Die Religion des Geistes. 1882. Many excellent ideas. Hartmann's Selhstzersetzung des Christenthums und Die Religion der Zukunft. 1888. French translation under title La Religion de UAvenir. iMartenseu remarks of modern Pessimism that "a Pessimism like it, though it be far from Christian, can only be found in the Christian world, where the infinite cravingof personality has been awakened."— CAmiiaw Ethics, i. p. 178 (Eug. trans.). 456 NOTES TO LECTURE II, Koeber's Die Philosophie Arthur Schopenhauers. 1888. Karl Peters' Willenswelt und Weltwillej Studien und Ideen %u einer Welt- anschauung. 1883. Acute critique of systems, and excellent points. W. Gass's Optimismus und Pessimismus. Der Gang der christlichen Welt- und Lehens-ansicht. 1876. Caro's Le Pessimisme au xix^ siecle, 1878 ; and ProUemes de Morale Sociale. 1887. Jouvon's Le Pessimisme. 1892. Crowned by the Academy. Sully's Pessimism ; a History and a Criticism. 1877. Luthardt's Die modernen Weltanschauun^en und ihre praktischen Konse- quenzen. 1880. Wright's Ecclesiastes in relation to Modem Criticism and Pessimism. 1883. Kenan's Dialogues et Fragments philosophiques. 1876. Flint's Anti-Theistic Theories. 1885. Essays in Philosophical Criticism. 1883. Edited by Seth and Haldane. Pfleiderer's Religionsphilosophie, vol. ii. Eng. trans. Radford's Modern Pessimism^ in "Present Day Tracts" (a popular statement). Mallock's Is Life Worth Living ? 1885. See also sections in Martensen's Ethics, and similar works. NOTE J. TRANSITION FROM PESSIMISM TO THEISM — HARTMANN AND KARL PETERS. It is a remarkable circumstance that Pessimism also should end by recognising the need of religion, and in its own way should be found seek- ing to provide for that need. The new religion, Hartmann thinks, will represent the synthesis of the religious evolution of the East and of that of the West — of the pantheistic and of the monotheistic evolution : only resting on that which is the indispensable presupposition of all religion, "the Pessimism of positive Christianity." He describes it as "a Pantheism, and indeed a pantheistic Monism (with exclusion of all Polytheism) ; or impersonal immanent Monotheism, whose Godhead has the world as its objective manifestation, not outside of, but within itself " {Selhst. d. Christ. pp. 93, 97, 121). The basis of this new religious system is elaborated in the second part of his Religionsphilosophie, entitled Die Religion des Geistes. A simple reference to the table of contents in this work will show in how extraordinary a fashion it is attempted to take over the whole nomen- clature of Christianity into this new philosophical religion. First the human side of the religious relation is treated of, often very suggestively. Then it is treated of in its double-sided aspect— Divine and human — under the following headings — (1) Grace and Faith in General; (2) The Grace of Revelation and Intellectual Faith ; (3) The Grace of Redemption and Faith of the Heart ; (4) The Grace of Sanctification and Practical Faith. The object of religion in turn is considered in a three- fold aspect — (1) God as the Moment overcoming the Dependency of the World; (2) God as the Moment grounding the Dependency of the> NOTES TO LECTURE IL 457 world ; (3) God as the Moment grounding the Freedom of the world (Freedom in God, the righteousness of God, the holiness of God). Man is considered— (1) as in need of Redemption ; and (2) as capable of Redemption. The process of salvation itself is exhibited in a threefold light— (1) The Awakening of Grace ; (2) The Unfolding of Grace ; (3) The Fruits of Grace (!). Yet God, endowed with all these attributes, wise, omniscient, gracious, righteous, holy, etc., is still regarded as im- personal and unconscious. Is not Hartmann chargeable with the same fault which he seeks to fasten on the Protestant Liberals, of trying to profit by the respect which is paid to the Bible while teaching a totally different doctrine % (Selbst. d. Christ, p. 62). Karl Peters is undoubtedly right, when he says of the systems both of Frauenstadt and of Hartmann, that they represent the transition to Theism without knowing it. In Frauenstadt's system, he remarks, " the world in its totality is no more identified with the world-Ego, and we have, without being aware of it, gone over from Pantheism to Theism." Criticising Hartmann, he comments on " this absolute, unconscious, all- wise idea, an omniscient wisdom, which embraces all, and only knows not itself," and argues that in principle Theism is involved in Hartmann's doctrine. "Here," he says, "we reach the kernel of the whole criticism. I maintain, namely, positively, that the Philosophy of the Unconscious represents the transition from Pantheism to Theism. ... As in Schopen- hauer, we have the transition from an idealistic to a realistic, so in Hartmann there is executed the transition from a pantheistic to a theistic ' Weltanschauung.' The former indeed believed himself to stand on quite the other side, and no doubt the latter also thinks that he is planted on the opposite bank. But as Schopenhauer could not prevent the historical development from growing beyond his standpoint, so Hartmann will seek in vain to guard himself against such a breaking up of his system. . . . Ed. V. Hartmann's Unconscious is an almighty and all- wise Providence, raised above the world-process, which comprehends and holds within itself the whole woTld-deYelo^meTit."—Willenswelt, pp. 148, 268, 272. NOTE K. MATERIALISM IN GERMANY. The descent from an overstrained idealistic Pantheism to materialistic Atheism in Germany— through Feuerbach, Stirner, Ruge, etc.— is matter of notoriety. The following extract from an able article on "Lotze's Theistic Philosophy," in the Presbyterian Review, vol. vi. (1885), will illustrate the length to which things went in that direction :— " The one-sided opposition of Empiricism to Idealism developed into dogmatic Materialism. From the 18th September, 1854, when Rudolph Wagner delivered at Gottingen his famous address on ' The Creation of Man and the Substance of the Soul,' the Materialistic conflict raged in Germany for a couple of decades with unabated vigour. Taking up the 458 NOTES TO LECTURE II, gauntlet wliicli Wagner had tlirown down, Karl Vogt entered tlie lists with ' Kohlerglaube imd Wissenschaft,' flaunting, amidst satire and ridicule, in the face of his opponent, who had declared himself content with the simple religious faith of the collier, the now famous sentence that * thought stands in about the same relation to the brain, as gall to the liver or urine to the kidneys.' A flood of writings, more or less popular in style, followed, and a sort of religious propaganda was made of the gospel of Materialism, while a fierce crusade was waged against everything claiming to be superior to matter, or a ' function ' of matter. The hostility against religion was pronounced and bitter. The creed preached was Atheism, naked and unashamed. Matter is held to be eternal ; physical and chemical forces are the only ultimate agents ; the world exists, Vogt tells us, 'without organic substance, without a known Creator, nay, without a leading idea.' Hellwald expressly announces that the task of science is ' to destroy all ideals, to manifest their hollowness and nothing- ness, to show that belief in God and religion is deception ; ' while Biichner, who is ever, if j^ossible, a little more audacious than the rest, sums up the matter as follows : ' Theism, or belief in a personal God, leads, as all history shows, to monachism, and the rule of priests ; Pantheism, or belief in an all-pervading God, leads, where it is in the ascendency, to contempt of the senses, denial of the Ego, to absorption in God, and to a state of stagnation. Atheism, or philosophical Monism, alone leads to freedom, to intelligence, to progress, to due recognition of man — in a word, to Humanism.' . . . The progress of Materialism was rapid. Blichner's Force and Matter^ the 'Bible of German Materialism,' passed, within twenty years from its first appearance (1858), through no less than fourteen editions, and was translated into almost every language in Europe. The scientific camp was said to be materialistic almost to a man. The common people, among whom this way of thinking was frequently allied with the political tenets of social democracy, were, and are still to-day, largely leavened by the infection. The philosophical chairs in the Universities were feeble to resist it. . . . Materialism in Germany is no longer as strong as it was ; good authorities express it as their opinion that as it grew, so also it is waning ' rapidly ' " (pp. 652-655). See also the sketch of the German atheistic parties in Lichtenberger's "History of German Theology in the Nineteenth Century" (Histoire des Id^es religieuses en Allemagne), pp. 360-70 (Eng. trans.) ; and Christlieb's "Modern Doubt and Christian Belief" {Moderne Zweifel am christliche Glauhe), j^p. 138-40 (Eng. trans.). NOTE L. fichte's later philosophy. EiCHTE himself always maintained that his philosophy was a unity throughout, and Professor Adamson, in his book onFichte in the " Philosophical Classics," supports this contention. Passages are quoted NOTES TO LECTURE II. 459 also in the "Memoir" of Ficlite prefixed to the English translation of his popular works, to show that from the first Fichte distinguished between the individual Ego and the absolute Ego, from which the individual Ego is deduced. It would be difficult, however, to make this out from his earliest work — the JVissenschaftslehre. Our starting-point in thinking through the process there described must always be the concrete Ego — for that alone is given in consciousness, or "intellectual intuition." Indeed, Fichte's view strictly pressed yields no other self, — or conscious Ego, — for to arrive at self-consciousness we must posit the negation or limit ; and the absolute Ego, if such it can be called, which antecedes or stands behiiid this primary act, is not conscious — is something outside of tliought or conception altogether, an Unknowable, and is taken no account of — if indeed it is assumed — in Fichte's earlier dialectic. The only Ego we know in self-consciousness is an Ego limited by the Non-ego, which appears to it as foreign. It is a further stage when Fichte, analysing the conditions of self-consciousness, gets behind it (in spite of protests that this is impossible) to a " pure " Ego, which is not the Ego of the intuitive consciousness at all, but only an abstraction of the " form " of self-consciousness from the concrete Egos in which alone it has reality. To get out of the difficulty now arising from positing an absolute Ego behind consciousness, from which the latter is supposed to be derived, Fichte falls on the expedient of asserting that all exists at once and eternally — " at a stroke " — that there is no temporal derivation in the case. Apart, however, from the difficulties about time which this suggests, it has the effect of making the sole reality of the Absolute to consist in the individual Egos, which are its concrete embodiments. Apart from these, the pure Ego is, on the one hand, only an ideal pre-supposition or logical condition, — on the other, a goal or ideal to which self-consciousness tends without ever realising it — the ideal self-consciousness — God. From this position Fichte comes more and more to recognise the Absolute as something real, from which the individual Egos and the world arise ; but he does this again through several stages of development. The Absolute is first conceived of in Schelling's sense as the " Neutrum " or indifference-point between subject and object ; then as "Life," finally as "Will," — or God in the sense described in the quotation in the text. The higher Pantheism here closely verges on, if it does not merge into, Theism.^ Fichte's Christology turns on the distinction of that which is absolutely and eternally true, and that which is true only from the temporary point of view of Jesus and His Apostles. He starts from the Johannine description in the Prologue of the Fourth Gospel, and explains thus :— From the first or metaphysical standpoint, the eternal Knowledge or Word becomes flesh, assumes a personal, sensible, and human existence, in every individual man who has a living insight into this unity with God, and who actually gives up his personal life to the Divine life within him,— precisely in the same way as it became incarnate in Jesus Christ. From the historical point of view, Jesus of Nazareth, absolutely by and through 1 On Fichte's philosophy, cf. Professor Adamsoii's Fichte, in "Philosophical Classics," and Professor Seth's Hegelianism and Personality, Lecture II. 46o NOTES TO LECTURE IL Himself, is the perfect sensible manifestation of the eternal Word, as no one whatever has been before Him ; while those who are His disciples are as yet not so, but must first become so through Him. He thus secures a certain uniqueness in the Person of Jesus — " thus it is confirmed in every- way, that, even to the end of time, all wise and intelligent men must bow themselves reverently before this Jesus of Nazareth ; and that the more wise, intelligent, and noble they themselves are, the more humbly will they recognise the exceeding nobleness of this great and glorious manifestation of the Divine Life." Yet he holds, in entire antithesis to the newer Ritschlians, that " the metaphysical only, and not the historical, can give us blessedness ; " and thinks it a secondary matter, if a man is actually living this life in God, to ask how he attained it. — In " Tlie Way to the Blessed Life " (Anweisung zum seligen Lehen), pp. 471-473 (translated "Works"). This view of Fichte's, of the distinction of the metaphysical and the historical in Christ, is that which runs through all the speculative Christ- ologies, — those of Schelling, Hegel, Green, etc., — and may be said to be their characteristic feature. In Schelling's later philosophy, however, he seems to teach the incarnation of a real potence of the Godhead in Christ, in a way in which it can be affirmed of no other. See sketch in Pfleiderer's ReligiGnsphilosophiey ii. pp. 15-30 (Eng. trans.). NOTE M. MODERN THEORY OF REVELATION. The following extracts will illustrate the statements in the text : — Biedermann says : " The division of Revelation into natural and su2oer- natural is ambiguous and uncertain in expression, and abstract and figurate as respects the fact. It opposes as two kinds of Revelation what are only two moments of all Revelation, inseparable from one another. All Revelation is essentially supernatural, if under nature is understood the finite natural determinateness of man in opposition to his spiritual destination ; and all Revelation is just as essentially natural, if under nature is understood what lies in the essence." — Christ. Dog. p. 265. Pfleiderer thus sums up : " Revelation is every inward perception of, and consciousness of being laid hold of by (Innewerden und Ergriften- werden), a supersensible truth, which, because it does not originate from external communication, or from arbitrary reflection, but from the un- conscious and undivided ground of the soul, is conceived of as a com- munication of God mediated through the activity of the human soul." — Grundriss, p. 20. H. Schmidt has a good statement and criticism of this theory in his article on " The Ethical Oppositions in the Present Conflict of the Biblical and the Modern Theological View of the World," in the Studien und Kritiken for 1876 (3rd part). " The God whom the Scripture from NOTES TO LECTURE 11. 461 beginning to end preaches," lie says, "is a God of supernatural Revelation, who makes Himself known directly, in distinction from the everyday ordering of our lives ; the God of rationalism is a God who, if He still as really communicates Himself, yet always remains hidden behind the laws of nature, as behind the natural course of the development of the human spirit, who never manifestly represents Himself to the eye of man in His exaltation over the world." NOTE N. THE REASONABLENESS OF REVELATION. EwALD has said, much in the spirit of the passage quoted from Pfleiderer : " How, then, should not He answer the earnestly perseveringly questioning spirit of man — He of whose spirit man's is but a luminous reflection and an enkindled spark, and to Whom in his searching and questioning he can draw near quite otherwise than to the visible things of creation." — Bevelation ; its Nature and Record (Eng. trans, of first vol. of Die Lehre der Bihel von Gott), p. 18. Dr. Walter Morison works out in a very ingenious way the argument for the probability and reasonableness of Eevelation from the analogy of nature. Rebutting the objection that the modern conception of nature \ " is altogether against the idea of any interference by Revelation from Heaven with the closely-linked order existing in nature," and permits " only evolution from within of coiled up energies," he remarks : " In whatever way — whether by evolution or otherwise — the system of nature which we see around us, and of which we are a part, has come about, that system of nature supplies no presumption against there being a direct Revelation of religious truth ; on the contrary, its actual testimony, rightly understood, is in favour of that supposition. What may be called direct revelation is found to be one of the common phenomena of nature or the system of things. As soon as we pass into that region in our world where there is need for communication between individuals possessed of intelligence in any degree, we find ' revelation ' to be the law. There is direct utterance. Even the inferior animals are con- tinually telling out by their many voices, 'none of which is without signification,' their various feelings. Wherever there is what may be called individuality, with power of feeling and volition, there utterance or communication exists ; it being part of the order of nature that there be connecting bond of speech between such as possess any faculty for understanding and fellowship. And when we ascend in our ob- servations to the region of human life as social, we perceive a corre- sponding development of the powers noticed in the inferior creatures. Everywhere over society we observe speech of some sort ; communication I in a direct way from one to another ; a constant immediate revelation of I inward thought and feeling going on. There is really nothing more > familiar in the economy of human life than this phenomenon of direct 462 NOTES TO LECTURE II. communication from mind to mind, sometimes by look and sight, usually by words. . . . There is another world, then, besides this tongueless one of inorganic nature ! There is in the universe this fact, that between individuals capable of it, direct revelation is constantly going on. Where there are beings that require a medium of intelligent communication between them, there we perceive some sort of speech to exist. And hence it is not a suggestion prima facie opposed to the analogy of nature, at all events, which is offered when it is asked whether there may not be some direct personal and articulate utterance made by God to man. Is there to be eternal silence between these intelligences, these kindred natures, with their mutual capacity for love and communion ? Are all creatures in the universe that have any measure of intelligence, or are even sentient, capable of telling out directly what is in them ; and have they the means and the appetency thereto ? Can man commune with man through the high gift of language ? And is the Infinite Mind and Heart not to express itself, or is it to do so but faintly or uncertainly through dumb material symbols, never by blessed speech ? Is there no ' Word of God ' ? To give a negative answer here would be at least to go against the analogy of nature. All beings that we know possessed of any intelligence, — such beings generally, we can at all events say, — and especially the members of the human family, speak to each other in some direct way, make an immediate revelation of what is within them ; and one of the strongest presumptions, surely, is this, that a Personal God, in whose image man was made, would, in His dealings with man, if sufficient occasion called, express Himself in a similar direct manner ; in other words, give a Revelation ! " — Footprints of the Eevealer, pp. 49-52. NOTE 0. THE RITSCHLIAX DOCTRINE OF REVELATION. The Ritschlian theologians found everything on positive Revelation. This is their distinctive position, and their merit as a protest against a one-sided intellectualism and idealism. They will not allow even of the possibility of any knowledge of God outside the Revelation of His grace in Jesus Christ.^ Natural theology and theoretic proofs for the existence of God are tabooed by them. A few remarks may be made here on this theory by way of further explanation and criticism. 1. As regards the nature of this Revelation, the Ritschlians are agreed that it comes to us solely through the self-presentation of Christ in His historical manifestation. He is the only vehicle of Revelation recognised by them. It is not a Revelation through doctrine, but through the felt presence of God in Christ, and through the living and acting in which 1 See this position slightly modifiecl in the second edition of Hermann's Verkehr, p. 49. Hermann's general views on Revelation are stated in his Giessen Lecture on ner Begrijf der Ofenbarung (1887). Kaftan discusses the subject in his Das Wesen, etc., pp. 171-201. NOTES TO LECTURE IL 463 Christ exemplifies to us the right relation of sonship to God, and makes manifest the character and purposes of God, as these bear on our salva- tion and well-being. 2. As regards the content of this Revelation, its central point is found in the design of God to found a kingdom of God on the earth, and to gather men into it, and induce them to make its ends their own, through the right knowledge of His character, and their acceptance of the right relation of Sonship to Him. All Christ's work— His doing and dying- has this for its aim. His unity with God in His world-purpose i's a feature in His Divinity; the significance of His death is, that it guarantees to us supremely the reality of that religious relation to God into which He invites us in His Gospel.^ 3. As regards the 'proof of this Revelation, the Ritschlians are obviously in a difiiculty, since proof means that a thing is shown to be objectively true (apart from our subjective thoughts about it), while yet it is a cardinal principle with them, that religion moves only in the sphere of value-judgments, i.e. judgments on the relation of things to our states of pleasure and pain. They cannot, however, refuse the demand for proof that this which they present as Revelation from God is really such, and not a subjective illusion of our own minds. And here — Fird, and negatively, they reject, as inappropriate to religion, all merely historical evidence, or proof from objective facts, as miracles, or the resurrection of Christ (which it is doubtful if most of them accept as objective fact). Second, and positively, the proof alleged is of two kinds : — 1. Immediate — consisting of the irresistible impression (Eindruck), which Christ makes on the soul historically confronted with Him, com- pelling the acknowledgment that God is with Him. This is the theme on which the changes are incessantly rung by Professor Hermann in his recent writings. 2. Scientific — consisting in showing the correspondence which exists between Christianity and the religious needs of man, as these may be deduced from the consideration of his nature and history; otherwise, the agreement of Christianity with the practical postulates of religion. This is the sort of proof hinted at by Ritschl when he says : " Its repre- sentation in theology will, therefore, come to a conclusion in the proof, that the Christian ideal of life, and no other, altogether satisfies the claims of the human spirit to a knowledge of things ; " i.e. yields a prac- tically satisfying view of the world {Recht. und Ver. iii. p. 25, 3rd ed.) ; and which is undertaken in detail by Kaftan in his Wahrheit d. Christ. Religion (though on diff'erent fundamental lines from Ritschl's). On this view I would offer the following brief criticisms : — 1. It is to be observed that this basing of everything by the Ritschlians on positive Revelation does not harmonise well idth the premises of the school. (1) It does not consist well with their fundamental position that religion moves solely in the sphere of value-judgments. For if we really 1 Kaftan, however, views the kingdom of God as belonging, not to this world, but the next. 464 NOTES TO LECTURE IL get out to objective Revelation, we have clearly broken tbrougli this magic circle of value-judgments, and are in the domain of judgments of fact and truth. Or is our judgment, that this is a Divine Revelation, itself also only a value-judgment % (2) The theory of Revelation does not consist well with the Ritschlian theory of knowledge. For Ritschl is thoroughly at one with Kant in the view that the theoretic reason can give us no knowledge of God, or proof of His existence. We are thus driven back on practical postulates, or " Vorstellungen," beyond which, as it would seem, even Revelation cannot raise us, for Revelation cannot take us outside the essential limita- tions of our faculties. 2. It is to be observed, further, that this theory has no proper answer to give to the question of fke nature of Revelation. With its general avoidance of the speculative, it gives us no distinct specification of what precisely this term means, or how much it is supposed to cover. Enough that we receive from Christ the impression, that — in some undefined sense — God is with Him, and in Him is drawing near to us ; this is to us (subjectively) the Revelation, and nothing else is of importance. Yet it is very obvious, that multitudes of questions may arise just at this point as to the character, degree, purity, limits, reliableness, and authority of this Revelation, which Ritschlianism gives us no help to answer. We cannot but ask, e.g., respecting a Revelation mediated to us in this way through the consciousness of another human being — How did it originate 1 What did Revelation mean to Him, the original recipient % Was it a really super- natural act? or partly supernatural and partly natural, with a correspond- ingly mixed result? How is such a Revelation even possible, since, according to another part of the theory, there is no direct (mystical) com- munication between the soul and God ? ^ Is there not large room left here, which the Ritschlians {e.g., Wendt) are not slow to avail themselves of, for distinction and criticism even in the contents of Christ's own conscious- ness and utterances ? Are we not in danger of coming back to the view, that in the last analysis Christ's religious conceptions do not differ in origin or character from those of any other great religious genius ? 3. It is again to be observed, that the character of this system compels it to limit very greatly the contents of the Revelation. Ritschlianism is, as said, essentially a system of religious positivism. It starts with data of experience, — the direct impression made on us by Christ, and the experimental knowledge we have of His power to give us deliverance and freedom, — and beyond this it declines to go. All in the Christian system which it regards as transcendental or metaphysical — however guaranteed by words of Christ or His Apostles — it refuses to inquire into, or sets aside as of no importance to faith. The pre-existence of Christ, e.g., His supernatural birth. His heavenly reign, the constitution of His Person, the Trinity of the Godhead, the eschatological doctrines, are thus swept aside. It has no doctrine of objective Atonement, but only one of subjective reconciliation. Other great doctrines of Scripture are either absent, or have a large part of their meaning taken from them. 4. Finally, it is difficult to avoid the conclusion, that while the 1 Cf. Hermann's Verkehr des Christen mil Gott. NOTES TO LECTURE II, 465 members of this school profess to derive their theology from positive Eevelation, what really governs their construction is, not the objective Revelation, but their particular theories of religion, and their ideas of what is necessary for the realisation of man's practical ends. Every one of the members of this school has his theory of religion independently deter- mined (the theories, however, widely differing from each other), and agreement with this theory is not only employed for the proof of the Revelation, but is also the standard, practically, of what is accepted or rejected in its contents. The Revelation, in other words, does not come with authority, but rather derives its authority from its agreement with the practical postulates, which are previously established on quite other grounds. This is true of all the leading members of the party — Ritschl, Hermann, Kaftan, etc. So far as relates to the proof of Revelation, it is not easy to avoid the appearance of moving in a circle. E.g., in Kaftan's Wahrheit, while the test of the truth of the Revelation is its agreement with the practical postulates above referred to, these in turn are supposed to be confirmed by the fact of the Revelation, and thus proved to be no subjective illusion. I would not press this too far, since the argument from agreement with rational and moral postulates is in itself a sound one, and the only objection that can be raised is to the particular way of stating it.^ 1 In Kant's hands, as is well known, this method was employed to eviscerate the gospel of all peculiar supernatural content, and to reduce it to a nucleus of moral notions. 30 NOTES TO LECTURE III. NOTE A. PRIMITIVE FETISHISM AND GHOST- WORSHIP. The theory of a gradual ascent in religion from a primitive Fetishism, through Polytheism to Monotheism, made familiar by Auguste Comte, and repeated with unquestioning faith by writers like Mr. Clodd and Mr. S. Laing, receives scant countenance from the best recent authorities. Certainly, no case has been found in which it is possible to trace historically such an evolution. I cite a few statements and opinions on the subject, and on the rival theories of Ghost-worship, Totemism, etc. Principal Fairbairn, speaking of this class of theories in general, says : " They assume a theory of development which has not a single historical instance to verify it. Examples are wanted of people who have grown, without foreign influence, from Atheism into Fetishism, and from it through the intermediate stages into Monotheism ; and until such examples be given, hypotheses claiming to be 'Natural Histories of Religion' must be judged hypotheses still." — Studies in the Philosophy of Eeligion, p. 12. Mr. Max Miiller, speaking as an expert, condemns the theory of a primitive Fetishism. He says: "If it has never been proved, and perhaps, according to the nature of the case, can never be proved, that Fetishism in Africa, or elsewhere, was ever in any sense of the word a primary form of religion, neither has it been shown that Fetishism con- stituted anywhere, whether in Africa or elsewhere, the whole of a people's religion. Though our knowledge of the religion of the negroes is still very imperfect, yet I believe I may say, that wherever there has been an opportunity of ascertaining, by long and patient intercourse, the religious sentiments even of the lowest savage tribes, no tribe has ever been found without something beyond mere worshij) of fetishes. ... I main- tain that Fetishism was a corruption of religion in Africa, as elsewhere ; that the negro is capable of higher religious ideas than the worship of stocks and stones ; and, that many tribes who believe in fetishes, cherish at the same time very pure, veiy exalted, and very true sentiments ot the Deity." — Is Fetishism a Primitive Form of Religion ? Lecture II. p. 105 (Hibbert Lectures). In his more recent Lectures he reiterates this view : " If one con- NOTES TO LECTURE III. 467 siders," lie says, " what Fetishism really is, namely, the very last stage in the downward course of religion, this attempt to make a little-understood superstition of some modern negro tribes the key to the religion of Greeks and Romans, nay of the most civilised nations of the world, is perfectly marvellous."— iVaiwra^ Religion, p. 159. Again: "Fetishism, from its very nature, cannot be primitive, because it always presupposes the previous growth of the Divine predicate. As to the Fetishism of modern negroes, we know now that it represents the very lowest stage which religion can reach, whether in Africa or any other part of the world, and I know of no case, even among the most degraded of negro tribes, w^here remnants of a higher religious belief have not been dis- covered by the side of this degraded belief in amulets, talismans, and fetishes. The idea of De Brosses and his followers, that Fetishism could reveal to us the very primordia of religious thought, will remain for ever one of the strangest cases of self-delusion, and one of the boldest anachronisms committed by students of the history of religions." — Ibid. pp. 219, 220. Mr. Herbert Spencer passes the same judgment. Repudiating Mr. Harrison's theory of an original Fetishism, he says : " An induction, based on over a hundred examples, warrants me in saying that there has never existed anywhere such a religion as that which Mr. Harrison ascribes to ' countless millions of men,' during * countless centuries of time.' ... I have show^n that, whereas among the lowest races, such as the Juangs, Andamanese, Fuegians, Australians, Tasmanians, and Bush- men, there is no Fetishism ; Fetishism reaches its greatest height in considerably advanced societies, like those of ancient Peru and modern India. . . . And I have remarked that, had Fetishism been conspicuous among the lowest races, and inconspicuous among the higher, the state- ment that it was primordial might have been held proved ; but that, as the facts happen to be exactly the opposite, the statement is conclusively disjDroved." — Nineteenth Century, xvi. pp. 8, 9. This also is Pfleiderer's opinion : " In presence of these facts, the 'evolution theory,' as hitherto stated, which finds the beginnings of religion in Fetishism and Animism, appears to me to be as much wanting in evidence as it is psychologically imipossible" — Eeligionsjohilosophie, iii. p. 16 (Eng. trans.). But, then, Mr. Spencer's Ghost theory, which he (and now also Dr. Tylor) propounds as a substitute for that of a primitive Fetishism, meets with an equally decisive rejection at the hands of Mr. Harrison, Max Miiller, and other influential waiters. " I shall say bat little about Mr. Spencer's Ghost theory," says Mr. Harrison ; " I have always held it to be one of the most unlucky of all his sociologic doctrines, and that on psychological as well as on historical grounds. ... It is certain that the believers in the Ghost theory, as the origin of all forms of religion, are few and far between. The difficulties in the way of it are enormous. Mr. Spencer laboriously tries to persuade us that the worship of the sun and the moon arose, not from man's reverence for these great and beautiful powers of nature, but solely as 468 NOTES TO LECTURE III. they were thought to be the abodes of the disembodied spirits of dead ancestors. Animal worship, tree and plant worship, Fetishism, the Confucian worship of heaven, — all, he would have us believe, take their origin entirely from the idea that these objects contain the spirits of the dead. If this is not ' persistent thinking along defined grooves,' I know not what it is." — Nineteenth Century, xvi. pp. 362, 363. Max Mtiller subjects the theory to an historical examination in his Lectures on Anthropological Religion, and rejects it as based on totally mistaken data. " Granting even," he says, " that there are races whose religion consists of ancestor- worship only, though, as at present informed, I know of none, would that prove that the worship of nature-gods must everywhere be traced back to ancestor worship ? ... If a pleader may tell a judge that he has been misinformed as to facts, surely we may claim the same privilege, without being guilty of any want of respect towards a man who, in his own sphere, has done such excellent work. I make no secret that I consider the results of Mr. H. Spencer's one-sided explanation of the origin of religion as worthy of the strongest condem- nation which a love of truth can dictate." — Lecture V. pp. 132, 133. See also the examination of this theory in Pfleiderer's Religions' philosophie, iii. pp. 12-16. M. Renouf has said : "If from pre-historic we pass to historic times, we at once meet on Egyptian ground with an entire system of notions wonderfully (indeed almost incredibly) similar to those entertained l)y our Indo-European ancestors. There is, however, no confirmation of Mr. Herbert Spencer's theory, that the rudimentary form of all religion is the propitiation of dead ancestors. If the Egyptians passed through such a rudimentary form of religion, they had already got beyond it in the age of the Pyramids, for their most ancient propitiation of ancestors is made through prayer to Anubis, Osiris, or some other gods."— Hibbert Lectures, p. 127. Totemisni, or belief in descent from animals worshipped as Divine, is another phase of explanation of the origin of religion which also meets with no favour from the authorities. " Totemism is one of those pseudo- scientific terms," says Max Miiller, "which have done infinite harm to the study of my tholog,j. " — Anthropological Religion, p. 408. See his remarks on it in this work, pp. 121-24 ; and in Natural Religion, p. 159. A careful examination of Professor R. Smitli's theory of Totemism, as applied to the Semitic religions, may be seen in an article already referred to in the Edinburgh Review for April 1892 (art. "Semitic Religions"). M. Renouf remarks on another advocate of the Totem theory : "Many of you have probably read Mr. M'Lellan's articles on the " Worship of Animals and Plants." In order to show that the ancient nations passed through what he calls the Totem stage, which he says must have been in pre-historic times, he appeals to the signs of the Zodiac. . . . Mr. M'Lellan is here more than half a century behind his age," etc. And a note adds : " All Mr. M'Lellan's statements about the ancient nations are based on equally worthless authorities." — Hibbert Lectures, pp. 29, 30. NOTES TO LECTURE III. 469 Max Miiller, Pfleiderer, Edville, and others, reject all these theories, and find the commencement of religion in the worship of the greater objects of nature— such as mountains, rivers, the sun, the sky, etc. But if the other theories begin too low, does not this begin too high, on the supposition that man started as a savage, and that there was no primitive Revelation ? May not the advocate of Fetishism reply, that man must be already far on in his career of development before this grander style of worship, which demands a highly evolved imagination, is possible to him? And is this view historically supported, any more than the others ? Do not the facts point to a higher origin for man, and to a purer primitive perception of the Divine than these theories allow ? See next Note, and Note F to Lecture V. NOTE B. OLD TESTAMENT MONOTHEISM. Two mutually destructive theories are held by naturalistic critics as to the origin of Hebrew Monotheism. The first is that of Eenan, who traces it to a " Monotheistic instinct ' said to be inherent in the Semitic race. " The Semitic consciousness," he says, " is clear, but lacks breadth ; it has a marvellous comprehension of unity, but cannot grasp multiplicity. Monotheism sums it up, and explains all its characters." — Hist, gdherale des Langues s^mitiques, p. 5. See this theory explained in the work cited, and in the more recent Histoire du peuple d'Israel, I. chap. iv. It is a theory which scarcely requires discussion, so palpably contrary is it to all the facts. Cf. in regard to it. Max Miiller's essay on " Semitic Monotheism," in vol. i. of his Chips from a German Workshop ; Baethgen's Beitrdge zur semitischen Reiigionsgeschichte ; Godet's Biblical Studies on the Old Testament, p. 68 (Eng. trans.); and an able article in the Edinburgh Review (April 1888). The second theory is that of Kuenen and the newer school of critics (though it had many older representatives), viz., that the Israelites began as polytheists and idolaters like their neighbours, and only gradually attained to an " Ethical Monotheism " such as we find in the prophets. This theory, therefore, is the precise reverse of the former. See it explained in Kuenen's Hibbert Lectures ; in Wellhausen's Prol. to the Hist, of Israel (Eng. trans.) ; and in Professor Robertson Smith's Old Testa- ment in the J-ewish Church, and Religion of the Semites. The arguments by which it is supported are plausible, yet, when carefully looked into, are found to be much more specious than solid. The most sifting examina- tion is that of Baethgen, in the work above cited, Beitrdge zur sem. Reiigionsgeschichte. See also Konig's Hauptprobleme d. altisi'ael. Rel. ; Uohertsoii' 8 Early Religion of Israel {Baird Lectures) ; and Schultz^B Alttest. Theol. pp. 159-167 (1889). A good discussion of Hebrew Monotheism is found also in Vigouroux's La Bible et les D^couvertes modernes, pp. 1-86, "La Religion primitive d' Israel" (1881). Baethgen sums up the results 470 NOTES TO LECTURE IIL of an exhaustive inquiry, first, into the general character of Semitic Polytheism ; and, second, into the question, " Whether, as Kuenen and others maintain, Israel's faith in God was really, in the older and middle periods of its history, distinct in nothing from that of related tribes ? " in the following words : — "The historical investigations of both parts lead to the result, that Israel's faith in God was from the oldest times speci- fically distinct from that of the related tribes ; and the contention, that the Old Testament Monotheism has originated out of Polytheism, in the way of natural development, is proved on closer examination to be untenable." — Preface. A strong argument against the development theory in question may be drawn from the results of the newer Pentateuch criticism itself. It is surely a remarkable circumstance that, not only in the time of the prophets, but in the documents J and E, originating in the early days of the kings (perhaps earlier), and embodying independently the oldest traditions of the nation, the history already rests on a completely Monotheistic basis, and expresses {e.g. in the call of Abraham) the clear consciousness of the nation's universal mission and destiny. In the documents referred to, e.g.., we have as fundamental, underlying ideas, the creation of the world by Jehovah, the unity of the human family, the destruction of the whole race by a flood, a covenant with Noah embracing the earth, a new descent and distribution of mankind from one centre, the recognition of Jehovah as the God of all the earth, etc. Schultz, in his Alttestament. Theologies also lays weight on these considerations, though with some preliminary qualifications and explanations that the Monotheism involved is a " religious " and not a " metaphysical " Mono- theism. "In the old songs," he says, "alongside of the expression, 'who is like Jehovah?' there stands clearly the other, 'no God besides Jehovah, no rock besides our rock' (Ps. xviii. 32; 1 Sam. ii. 2). According to the Book of the Covenant, Jehovah has chosen Israel precisely because all the world is His (Ex. xix. 5), therefore not at all because He, as a particular God, was bound to this land and people. Psalms such as the 8th, 19th, and 29th, praise Him who has made heaven and earth, in whose holy palace the sons of God stand serving. In B and C (the J and E of the ordinary nomenclatui-e), the same Jehovah who is the covenant God of Israel is likewise the Creator of the world, the God of the patriarchs, whom also, as a matter of course, the non-Israelites own as God, the God of the spirits of all flesh (Gen. ii. 4 ft'., iv. 3, 26, xii. 17, xxiv. 31, 50, xxvi. 29 ; Numb. xvi. 22, xxvii. 16). He proves Himself in His miracles and in His majesty the Judge and the Destroyer, the world-ruler in Egypt, Sodom, and Canaan. In fact, therefore, the other Elohim step back as no-gods, who are not able to determine the course of the world. He alone is a God who can call forth faith, love, and trust. He will reveal His glory also to the heathen world, and will not rest till it fills the whole earth (Ex. xv. 2). . . . But a people, which itself worships only one God, and regards this God as the world-creator and the controller of all world- destiny, is for that reason monotheistic. ... A God whose rule is not bound to the land and people in which He is worshipped is no more a mere national God. NOTES TO LECTURE III. 471 Thus the particularism of the God-idea in Israel has already become only the sheltering husk under which the pure Monotheism of the Old Testa- ment could unfold itself and mature."— Pp. 166, 167. NOTE a Kegel's idea of god. The difficulty in maintaining the personality ot God in Hegel's system is very manifest, and is witnessed to by the history of his school. There is no doubt but that with Hegel the world is an essential moment in the life of God— a means to His self-realisation. God is Absolute, Self- conscious Spirit only as He returns to Himself from His objectification in nature, and attains to self-consciousness in the consciousness of man. His self -consciousness and the self-consciousness of man are thus identical quantities. But nature is a developing process : the consciousness of man, too (still more his "philosophical consciousness of himself as the Absolute "), is in process of growth — is finite, partial, and incomplete. What we have, therefore, seems to be a developing God ; a God who only gradually comes to the knowledge of Himself in history. Hegel seeks to avoid this by representing God as above all time. The aspect of temporal development belongs only to our finite consciousness ; for God the whole process is eternally complete. But this in turn imperils the reality of the world, and reduces history, with its development in time, to a semblance. While, therefore, Hegel may have believed that in this way he saved the personality of God— if he would have allowed this term to be applicable to the universal consciousness — we cannot admit that he really did so. The only real consciousness of God is that which He has in the consciousness of finite spirits ; and this is equivalent to saying that there is no eternally complete Divine consciousness at all. The Neo-Hegelians affirm the latter, yet do not get over the difficulty occasioned by their view of the relation of God and the world. See next Note. On this ambiguity in Hegel's doctrine, see Professor Seth, Ilegelianism and Personality, Lecture V. ; and the criticism in Dorner, Person of Christ, v. pp. 147-162 (Eng. trans.). NOTE D. DEFECTS OF THE NEO-HEGELIAN VIEW. An irrefragable part of this theory, as represented by the late Mr. Green of Oxford, is, I think, its fundamental assertion that all exists in and through thought, and has no meaning or reality apart from a thinking consciousness. But Mr. Green's doctrine of "an eternal self-conscious- ness," reproducing itself in man, falls yet very far short of a complete 472 NOTES TO LECTURE TIL 'Theism. I may be permitted to quote on this subject some remarks penned by myself in another connection, apropos of Professor Veitch's book on Knovnng and Being : — The objections which Professor Veitch urges are forcibly put and powerfully driven home. One point strongly insisted on is, the in- compatibility of this eternal Ego, this self-distinguishing consciousness, with a true Theism. It might seem as if the opposite were the case — as if in this philosophy the Deity was reached by the most direct road possible. But we have only to view this conception of the eternal Ego a little more narrowly to see how far it is from answering to any just idea of God. Neither activity nor act can be predicated of this Ego ; it is but the still pool of consciousness, in which the system of relations which constitute the universe eternally reflect themselves ; its sole function is to focus these relations, and collect them to a centre. It is but Kant's * synthetic unity of apperception' deified. As nature is meaningless apart from this central Ego, so it, in turn, has only significance in reference to the manifold of nature which it unifies. Nature and the Ego are not two facts, but one fact with two sides — object and subject in eternal implication. It is clear, as Professor Veitch points out, that the predicates of power or causality cannot apply to such a subject. " The conception of this self as the eternal unity of the one and the many expressly excludes them. It never existed in a state of potency or simple causality, and, therefore, never could manifest activity in any sense we can attach to the term. ... It is not an eternal act ; it is truly, if it is anything, an eternal is. And this is simply to identify it with the sum of being in the universe, and to say that this is two-sided, one and many, or one in many, and eternally so. Anything thus approaching even the idea of creation or creative power is utterly excluded, whatever sense we may attach to these words. . . . The ideas of creation and creative activity are emptied of meaning, and for them is substituted the conception or fiction of an eternally related or double-sided world, not of what has been done, but of what always is. It is another form of the see-saw philosophy. The eternal self only is, if the eternal manifold is, if the eternal self is." —Pp. 20-22. With such a view of the eternal Ego, it is difl[icult not to sympathise with the remark that God seems as dependent on the world as the world is on Him ; only this purely speculative, non-volitional consciousness is not properly God at all. A yet greater difficulty for the theory lies in the determination of the relation of the eternal consciousness to time and history. Ex hypothesis this eternal consciousness is complete. It undergoes no change, and can receive no increment to its knowledge. As it is a consciousness only through the system of relations which it unifies, it follows that these must be eternally complete also, and they are asserted to be so. The one side of the fact must be there—the world in its totality, if the other is to be there— the consciousness which holds the whole together. " We must hold," says Mr. Green, "that there is a consciousness for which the relations of fact that form the object of our gradually attained knowledge, already and eternally exist ; and that the growing knowledge of the individual is a progress towards this consciousness."— ProZ. to Ehics, p. 75. NOTES TO LECTURE III. 473 But what, on this supposition, becomes of process in nature ? What of development in time? What of growth in the individual? What of history in humanity? Does not all become illusory? This is not a question of mere human apprehension. That, we all know, is imperfect and successive. But the object itself has a development, a history. The relations of things are changing from moment to moment ; nature as a whole has been advancing from a relatively simpler state ; society has reached its present point of progress through the long labours of centuries. If this is a reality, what meaning is to be attached to the statement, that for the eternal consciousness "those relations of fact which form the object of our gradually attained knowledge, already and eternally exist." In an ideal sense they might ; in a real sense they cannot. It is acknow- ledged that, on any hypothesis, there is a difficulty attaching to the relation of eternity to time, and to the idea of creation in time, but from the extreme idealistic point of view the difficulty seems insuperable. See further on this difficulty and on the next point of objection — viz., the character of necessity claimed by this theory for nature — the remarks in Lecture IV. pp. 147, 148. These are difficulties attaching to the relation of the eternal conscious- ness to nature ; but the crowning difficulty, as Professors Veitch and Seth have both ably shown, lies in the relation of the eternal consciousness to the finite self — the ego of the individual. On this extremely critical point the representations we get are vague and fluctuating. At one time the individual self seems merged altogether in the universal self, which is described as "reproducing" itself in the finite ego — making it the " vehicle " of its own manifestations. " Our consciousness," we are told, " may either mean a function of the animal organism which is being made gradually a vehicle of the eternal consciousness, or that eternal conscious- ness itself as making the animal organism its vehicle, and subject to certain limitations in so doing. ... It consists in what may properly be called phenomena ; in successive modifications of the animal organism, which would not, it is true, be what they are if they were not media for the realisation of an eternal consciousness, but which are not this consciousness." — P. ^., pp. 72, 73. This is Pantheism, but Pantheism that verges very closely on Materialism, justifying Professor Veitch in his remark, that it " shows what the whole course of absolute Idealism discloses, that it is identical ultimately with absolute Materialism." — P. 238. It is curious also how this same feature of the reduction of finite consciousness to a mere function of the animal organism appears in the elaborated Pessimistic systems of Schopenhauer and Hartmann, which also, in their way, are systems of absolute Idealism. But, after all, what are we to make of this "reproduction" of the eternal consciousness in the finite being? " Keproduction " is as vague a word as the Platonic " participation," and explains as little. The eternal consciousness has an eternally complete life above all finite egos ; again it " reproduces " itself in the latter, under conditions of time, succession, ignorance, error, growth. How are these two sides of the existence of one and the self-same subject — for it comes to this— to be brought together in thought? The eternal consciousness has to go out of its "timeless unity" in which it would 474 NOTES TO LECTURE III. have been complete, and there, as Professor Veitcli says, " it practically breaks down." " The eternal consciousness in the only form we know it or can share in it, is baffled by its own phenomena, its own relations ; creates what it cannot master, spins ropes which entangle it, or is con- stantly employed in weaving a web which it never completes."— P. 250. This is dualism with a vengeance — the same kind of dualism which we meet with in Hartmann's " Unconscious," on the one side all wisdom and foresiglit, on the other all error and illusion. NOTE E. KANT AND THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT. Kant characterises this argument as a perfect "nest" of dialectical assumptions. — Kritik, p. 427 (Eng. trans, p. 374). Yet it might be shown that the objections he takes to it depend almost exclusively on his theory of knowledge — e.g., that the mind is confined to phenomena ; that the law of cause and effect has no application except in the world of pheno- mena (though Kant himself applies it in positing an action of things per se on the sensitive subject, and introduces a "causality" of the noumenal self, etc.).i The same remark applies to the "antinomies," or self- contradictions in which the mind is said to involve itself in every attempt at a theoretic application of the cosmological " Idea." The " antinomies " are rather to be regarded as rival alternatives of thought, which, indeed, are contradictory of each other, but which do not stand on the same footing as regards admissibility. Rather they are of such a nature that the mind is found to reject one, while it feels itself shut up to accept the other. E.g., The world has either a beginning in time or it has not. The alternative here is an eternal retrogression of phenomenal causes and effects, or the admission of an extra-phenomenal First Cause — God. But these do not stand on the same footing. The mind rejects the former as unthinkable and self-contradictory (see next Lecture) ; the latter it not only does not reject, but feels a rational satisfaction in admitting. Again, there is the antinomy between natural causation and freedom of will. But this is only an antinomy, if we hold that the law of causation applicable to physical phenomena is the only kind of causation we know — that there may not be rational, intelligent causation over and above th^ physical and determinate. Something here also depends on the definition of freedom. 1 Cf. Dr. Stirling's Philosophy of Theology, pp. 315-316: "The entire 'nest' may be said to be a construction of bis peculiar system." NOTES TO LECTURE III. 475 NOTE F. KANT ON THE TELEOLOGICAL ARGUMENT. Kant says : " This proof deserves always to be mentioned with respect. It is the oldest, clearest, and the most suited to the common reason of mankind. It enlivens the study of nature, even as it derives from this its own existence, and draws from it ever new strength. It brings ends and purposes into a region where our observation would not of itself have discovered them, and furthers our natural knowledge through the guid- ing thought of a special unity, whose principle lies outside of nature. This knowledge reacts upon its cause, namely, on the idea which occasions it, and raises faith in a highest Author of the universe to an irresistible conviction. It would, therefore, be not only a thankless, but also a vain task, to attempt to detract in any measure from the prestige of this argument." Only, he goes on to say: "Although we have nothing to object to the rationality and utility of this procedure, but have much rather to recommend and encourage it, we are nevertheless unable to assent to the claims which this mode of proof may make to demonstrative certainty," and then proceeds to state his objections to it. — Kritik, p. 436, 437 (Eng. trans, p. 383).^ These, however, as observed in the text, seem more in the direction of limiting its application, than of altogether deny- ing its cogency. The view which obtains in the Kritik of Judgment, that the idea of design has only regulative and not theoretic validity,^ is not dwelt on in the Kritik of Pure Eeason. It is not always noticed, besides, that, intermediate between full theoretic demonstration and mere opinion, Kant has a form of conviction which he calls " doctrinal faith," — distinct from moral faith, — the characteristic of which is that it is an expression of modesty from the objective point of view, but of assured confidence from the subjective ; and that he places the doctrine of God's existence in this region. " Now we must concede," he says, " that the doctrine of God's existence belongs to doctrinal faith. For although, in respect of the theoretical knowledge of the world, my procedure does not necessarily pre- suppose this thought as condition of my explanations of the phenomena of the world, — much more am I under obligation to use my reason as if all were mere nature, — yet is teleological unity so important a condition of the application of reason to nature that I cannot ignore it, since, besides, experience furnishes me with abundant examples of it. But I know no other condition of this unity which makes it a guide to me in my investigation of nature, than the presupposition that a highest intelli- gence has so ordered all according to the wisest ends. Consequently, the presupposition of a wise Author of the world is the condition of an end which is contingent indeed, but by no means unimportant, — that of having guidance in my investigation of nature. Since, also, the result of my attempts confirms so frequently the utility of this presupposition, and 1 The references are to Meiklejohn's translation, but the translations are in- dependent. ^ Cf. Caird's Philosophy of Kant, pp. 477, 489, 526. 476 NOTES TO LECTURE III as notliing of a decisive kind can be adduced on the other side against it, it would be saying far too little if I termed my conviction of its truth a mere opinion ; but it can, even in this theoretical relation, be said that I firmly believe in God. But then this faith is not in the strict sense practical, but must be termed a doctrinal faith, which the theology of nature must always necessarily produce in me." — Kritik, p. 561 (Eng. trans, p. 500). Kant, moreover, lias rendered great service to this argu- ment by his demonstration, in the Kritik of Judgment, of the necessity of applying the teleological conception to nature. See Dr. Bernard's valuable Introduction to his recent translation of this work (1892), and cf. Professor Caird's Philosophy of Kaid, ii. pp. 406-562. NOTE G. SCHOOLS OF EVOLUTIONISTS. It is well to recognise the fact that evolutionists do not constitute a homogeneous party ; and that while there is a growing disposition to acknowledge the reality of Organic Evolution, there is likewise a growing tendency to question the sufficiency of the causes by which Mr. Darwin sought to account for it. 1. From the first there has been an important section of evolutionists, represented by such names as Owen, Mivart, Asa Gray, G. H. Lewes, Dana, and J. J. Murphy (in his Habit and Intelligence), who, with differences among themselves, held that the rise of species could not be accounted for by the Darwinian hypothesis of Natural Selection acting on fortuitous variations. The tendency in this school was to seek the causes of evolution within, rather than without the organism. Most of them were theistic evolutionists — i.e. they held that the development of organisms could not be explained without the assumptions of intelligence and purpose. Not all who opposed the Darwinian hypothesis were of this class. Mr. G. H. Lewes, e.g., writes : "At each stage of differentiation there has been a selection, but we cannot by any means say that this selection was determined by the fact of its giving the organism a superiority over rivals, inasmuch as during all the early stages, while the organ was still in formation, there could be no advantage occurring from it. . . . The sudden appearance of new organs, not a trace of which is discernible in the embryo or adult form of organisms lower in the scale — for instance, the phosphorescent and electric organs — is like the sudden appearance of new instruments in the social organism, such as the printing press and the railway, wholly inexplicable on the theory of descent, but is explicable on the theory of organic affinity "(!). — Physical Basis of Mind, pp. 110, 117. 2. Important differences exist between Mr. Darwin and his fellow- worker in the same field, Mr. A. Wallace, involving a distinction of principle on two vital points. (1) Mr. Darwin's own views underwent considerable modifications in the direction of recognising that Natural NOTES TO LECTURE III. 477: Selection is not an all-sufficient explanation, and that more must be allowed to forces interior to the organism. See his Descent of Man, p. 61 ; and cf. Mivart's Lessons from Nature, viii., ix., and the articles of Spencer and Romanes cited below. He specially supplemented it by the hypothesis of Sexual Selection. These alterations on the theory Mr. Wallace rejects, repudiating Sexual Selection, and maintaining the hypothesis in the form in which Mr. Darwin has abandoned it. (2) Mr. Darwin held his theory to be all-inclusive, embracing man as well as the lower animals ; Mr. Wallace holds that there are provable breaks in the chain of evolution, and that man, in particular, has a distinct origin. See next Lecture. 3. Yet more significant is the recent tendency to revolt against the authority of Mr. Darwin, and to recognise the existence of large classes of phenomena which Natural Selection does not explain. This change of front in recent discussions on Darwinism is too marked to escape notice. I take one or two examples which may show the drift of opinion. Mr. G. J. Romanes, who as late as 1882 wrote a book on The Scientific Evidences of Evolution, in which Mr. Darwin's theory received uncom- promising support, now writes in 1887 : " The hypothesis of Physiological Selection (his own view) sets out with an attempted proof of the inadequacy of the theory of Natural Selection, considered as a theory of the origin of species. This proof is drawn from three distinct heads of evidence— (1) the inutility to species of a large number of their specific characters ; (2) the general fact of sterility between allied species, which admittedly cannot be explained by Natural Selection, and therefore has hitherto never been explained ; (3) the swamping influence, upon even useful variations, of free intercrossing with the parent form." — " Physio- logical Selection," in Nineteenth Century, January 1887. The effect of Mr. Romanes' heresy has been to arouse " a storm of criticism " from the orthodox Darwinian party. Mr. Herbert Spencer has published two papers on " Factors of Organic Evolution," in which, while still according an important place to Natural Selection, he very greatly restricts its field of action. The articles, he says, " will perhaps help to show that it is as yet far too soon to close the inquiry concerning the causes of Organic Evolution."— P. 75. In a subsequent article in the Nineteenth Century, he thus delivers his soul : "The new biological orthodoxy behaves just as the old biological orthodoxy did. In the days before Darwin, those who occupied themselves with the phenomena of life, passed by with unobservant eyes the multitudinous facts which point to an evolutionary origin for plants and animals ; and they turned deaf ears to those who insisted upon the significance of these facts. Now that they have come to believe in this evolutionary origin, and have at the same time accepted the hypothesis that Natural Selection has been the sole cause of the evolution, they are similarly unobservant of the multitudinous facts which cannot rationally be ascribed to that cause, and turn deaf ears to those who would draw their attention to them. The attitude is the same ; it is only the creed that has changed." — Nineteenth Century, February 1888. In a well- written and appreciative Essay on Charles Darwin in " The 478 NOTES TO LECTURE III. Eound Table Series," the same criticism is passed upon tlie theory, that from the standpoint of biology too much stress has been laid on Natural Selection. "Natural Selection obviously can never be the cause of modifications in any given individual. . . . Natural Selection cannot cause an iota of modification in structure. ... In the case of Human Selection, not the least modification in an organism can be produced by the process of selection itself. The modifications somehow produced in the animals selected are transmitted to the oft'spring ; but the cause of modification lies elsewhere than in selection ; and it is largely due to man's own modification of the environment. ... It would undoubtedly have been better had Darwin omitted Natural Selection as a modifying agent altogether."— Pp. 22-26. Even Professor Huxley sounds a wavering note : " How far Natural Selection suffices for the production of species remains to be seen. . . . On the evidence of palaeontology, the evolution of many existing forms of animal life from their predecessors is no longer an hypothesis, but an historical fact ; it is only the nature of the physiological factors to which that evolution is due which is still open to discussion." — Art. " Evolution " in Enc\j. Brit. Good general criticisms of the Darwinian theory may be seen in Mivart's Genesis of Species, Murphy's Hahit and Intelligence, Elam's Winds of Doctrine, Bouverie Pusey's Permanence and Evolution (1882), Van Dyke's Theism and Evolution, Professor Schurman's Ethical Import of Darwinism, Principal Dawson's Modem Ideas of Evolution, Martineau's Studij of Religion, etc. NOTE H. KANT ON THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT. Kant holds firmly to the invalidity of all inference from the idea of God to His reality ; but here also it is to be noticed that he allows to his "Ideal of Pure Reason" an important part in Natural Theology. If theoretic reason cannot prove, neither can it disprove the objective reality of this ideal of a supreme Being ; and given a proof, or a conviction, from any other quarter (from the Practical Reason, or a " doctrinal faith " from design), it is of the highest utility in correcting and purifying our con- ception of this Being. "For," he says, "though Reason in its merely speculative use is far from competent to so great an undertaking as to reach the existence of a supreme Being ; yet it is of very great service in correcting the knowledge of such a Being, provided this can be drawn from some other source ; in making it consistent with itself, and with each intelligible view of things ; and in purifying it from everything which would contradict the notion of a primary Being, and from all mixture of empirical limitations. . . . The supreme Being, therefore, remains for the merely speculative use of Reason a mere Ideal, though one free from error, a notion which completes and crowns the whole of NOTES TO LECTURE III, 479 human knowledge, whose objective reality cannot indeed by this method be proved, but also cannot be disproved ; and if there should be a Moral Theology which can supply this defect, the hitherto only problematic transcendental theology will show its indispensableness in the determina- tion of its notion, and the unceasing criticism of a reason often enough deceived by sense, and not always in agreement with its own ideas. The necessity, infinity, unity, existence apart from the world (not as world- soul), eternity without conditions of time, omnipresence without conditions of space, omnipotence, etc., are pure transcendental predicates, and therefore the purified conception of the same, which every theology finds so necessary, can be drawn from transcendental theology alone."— Zri^iA;, pp. 446, 447 (Eng. trans, pp. 392, 393). NOTE I. RATIONAL REALISM. This argument is well stated by Pfleiderer in the following words : " The agreement, therefore," he says, " of the ideal laws of thought, which are not drawn from the outer world, and the real laws of being, which are not created by our thought, is a fact of experience of the most incontro- vertible kind ; the whole certainty of our knowledge rests on it. But how are we to account for this agreement ? There is only one possible way in which the agreement of our thought with the being of the world can be made intelligible : the presupposition of a common ground of both, in v^hich thought and being must be one ; or the assumption that the real world-ground is at the same time the ideal ground of our spirit, hence the absolute Spirit, creative Reason, which appears in the world-law on its real, in the law of thought on its ideal side. The connection of thought and being, subject and object, in the finite and derivative spiritual being, points back to the unity of the two in the infinite Spirit as the ground and original type of ours. This is the meaning of the ' ontological ' argument, as indicated even in the word. We may find it anticipated even in Plato, in the thought that the highest idea, or the Deity, is the cause both of being and of knowledge ; and Augustine follows him in this, frequently and in a number of turns of thought, tracing back our faculty of knowing the truth to. the fact of our participa- tion in God, who is the substantial truth, the unchangeable law both of the world and of our thought. In modern times this thought forms the foundation and corner-stone of speculative philosophy." — Eeligions- 2>hiloso2jhie, iii. p. 274 (Eng. trans.). The germs of this theory are found in Leibnitz, Herder, Goethe, and most of the deeper thinkers. It is the thought which underlies Mr. Green's Prolegomena to Ethics. Professor Samuel Harris, of Yale College, makes it the ground of his Philosophical Basis of Theism ; and it largely influences current thought. NOTES TO LECTURE IV. NOTE A. THE CREATION HISTORY. The lights and wrongs of the reconcilability of the creation narrative in Gen. i. with modern science, have recently been discussed anew by Mr. Gladstone and Professor Huxley in the Nineteenth Century (vols, xviii. and xix.). I do not enter into this discussion. But if the one disputant imports into this early narrative more than it will bear, the other surely does less than justice to it when he brackets it " with the cosmogonies of other nations, and especially with those of the Egyptians and the Babylonians," as essentially of the same character with these. I content myself with quoting on this point the tribute to this ancient narrative by Haeckel, surely an unprejudiced witness, in his History of Creation. He says: "The Mosaic history of creation, since, in the first chapter of Genesis, it forms the introduction to the Old Testament, has enjoyed, down to the present day, general recognition in the whole Jewish and Christian world of civilisation. Its extraordinary success is explained, not only by its close connection with Jewish and Christian doctrines, but also by the simple and natural chain of ideas which runs through it, and which contrasts favourably with the confused mythology of creation current among most of the ancient nations. First, God creates the earth as an inorganic body ; then He separates light from darkness, then water from the dry land. Now the earth has become habitable for organisms, and plants are first created, animals later ; and among the latter the inhabitants of the water and of the air first, afterwards the inhabitants of the dry land. Finally, God creates man, the last of all organisms, in His own image, and as the ruler of the earth. Two great and fundamental ideas, common also to the non-miraculous theory of development, meet us in the Mosaic hypothesis of creation with surprising clearness and simplicity — the idea of separation or differentiation, and the idea of progressive development or perfecting. Although Moses looks upon the results of the great laws of organic develoj)ment (which we shall later point out as the necessary conclusions of the Doctrine of Descent) as the direct actions of a constructing Creator, yet in his theory there lies hidden the ruling idea of a progressive development and a differentiation of the originally NOTES TO LECTURE IV. 481 simple matter. We can therefore bestow our just and sincere admiration on the Jewish lawgiver's grand insight into nature, and his simple and natural hypothesis of creation, without discovering in it a so-called Divine Revelation."— ifisi. of Creation, i. pp. 37, 38 (Eng. trans.). The grounds on which Haeckel concludes that it cannot be a Divine Revelation are— (1) the geocentric error that the earth is the central point in the universe ; and (2) the anthropomorphic error that man is the premeditated end of the creation of the earth,— neither of which " errors" need greatly distress us. For the rest, the creation narrative certainly goes back on early tradition,i and is not a scientific precis, written in the light of the latest discoveries of modern geology. Yet it is possible to hold that the Spirit of Revelation is active in it, not merely making it the vehicle of general religious ideas, but enabling the writer really to seize the great stadia of the creation process, and to represent these in such a way as to convey a practically accurate conception of them to men's minds. Modern science may supplement, it is astonishing how little it requires us to reverse of, the ideas we derive from this narrative of the succession of steps in creation, assuming that we deal with it fairly, in its broad and obvious intention, and not in a carping and pettifogging spirit. The dark watery waste over which the Spirit broods with vivifying power, the advent of light, the formation of an atmosphere or sky capable of sustaining the clouds above it, the settling of the great outlines of the continents and seas, the clothing of the dry land with abundant vegetation, the adjustment of the earth's relation to sun and moon as the visible rulers of its day and night, the production of the great sea monsters and reptile-like creatures (for these may well be included in " sheratzim ") and birds, the peopling of the earth with four-footed beasts and cattle — last of all, the advent of Man — is there so much of all this which science requires us to cancel ? ^ Even in regard to the duration of time involved, — those dies ineffabiles of which 1 Modern criticism would bring down the age of this narrative to the Exile, and explain its origin by late Babylonian influence ; but Dillmann and Delitzsch have shown strong reasons for rejecting this view, and for regarding the tradition as one of the oldest possessions of the Israelites. — Cf. Delitzsch's New Com. on Oen. pp. 63-66 ; and Whitehouse in Introduction to Eng. trans, of Schrader's Keilinschri/ten, i. pp. 18, 19, on Dillmann. 2 The main objections urged are such as these : — 1. The appearance of light before the sun. This, it seems to me, is rather a point in favour of the narrative, for it is not an idea which would naturally occur to a mind simply speculating on the origin of things, and modern knowledge rather tends to confirm the narrative on this point than to disprove it. 2. The existence of an abundant marine life prior to the fourth "day." Yet it is remarkable that the first fact mentioned in the narrative is the brooding of the life-giving Sjiirit upon the waters. 3. The inclusion of fruit-bearing trees in the vegetation of the third "day," whereas these really appeared much later. Yet it may be argued that, in accord- ance with the design of the narrative, the pictures in these representations of creation are " completive," Le. they gather up into one concentrated view the later as well as the initial results of each creative act. It may be doubted, too, whether the vegetation, e.g. of the carboniferous period, was altogether of a lower kind, and did not include fruit-bearing plants "having every character of the dicotyledons 31 482 NOTES TO LECTURE IV. Augustine speaks,^ — it is at least as difficult to suppose that only ordinary days of twenty-four hours are intended, in view of the writer's express statement that such days did not commence till the fourth stage in creation, as to believe that they are symbols. Delitzsch defends the symbolic interpretation in his New Commentary on Genesis, p. 84 (Eng. trans.). NOTE B. EVOLUTION IN INORGANIC NATURE — THE NEBULAR HYPOTHESIS. This famous hypothesis of Kant and Laplace is frequently spoken of as if it had become an established fact of science ; and it forms an integral part in most sketches of the process of cosmic evolution (as in Strauss, Spencer, Clodd, etc.). Yet so far is it from being established, that the objections to its sufficiency seem to multiply and strengthen as years go on, and many eminent men of science reject it altogether. Mr. K. A. Proctor, in an article on the " Meteor Birth of the Universe," contriT^uted to the Manchester Examiner and Times, May 29, 1888, thus speaks of it : — " The nebular theory of Laplace has long held a somewhat anomalous position. Advanced by its distinguished author as a mere hypothesis, in days when the word 'hypothesis' had still its proper significance (as shown in Newton's saying, * Hypotheses non fingo '), it had from the beginning a fascination for most minds, which led to its acceptance as if it had been a veritable theory. Yet it has never been accepted as a theory by one single student of science who has possessed adequate knowledge of physics, combined with adequate knowledge of astronomy and mathematics." After sketching the theory, he proceeds : " The nebulous speculation of Laplace is open to two most serious objections. In the first place, as I have already pointed out, a vaporous mass of enormous size, and of the exceeding tenuity imagined, could not possibly rotate in a single mass in the manner suggested by Laplace. In the second place, some of the most characteristic peculiarities of the solar system remain altogether unaccounted for by this speculation, ingeniously though it accounts for others." These objections are then developed. Mr. Proctor's rival theory is that of "Meteoric Aggregation." See, further, his More Worlds than Ours, chapter on " Comets and Meteors." highly developed." Cf. Lyell's Elements of Geology, pp. 475, 476 {6tli ed.). I do not press these points, but it is only fair, when discrepancies are urged, that they should be mentioned. 1 "Of what fashion those days were," says Augustine, "it is either exceeding hard or altogether impossible to think, much more to speak. As for ordinary days, we see they have neither morning nor evening, but as the sun rises and sets. But the first three days of all had no sun, for that was made on the fourth day," etc.— De Civitate Dei, xi. 6, 7. Cf. De Geriesi, ii. 14. NOTES TO LECTURE IV. 483 A searching examination of this theory, embodying the views of M. Babinet, may be seen in Stallo's Gonce^pts of Modern Physics (Inter- national Library), pp. 277-286. Dr. Ball, the Astronomer-Royal of Ireland, says regarding it : " Nor can it be ever more than a speculation ; it cannot be established by observation, nor can it be proved by calculation. It is merely a con- jecture, more or less plausible, but perhaps in some degree necessarily true, if our present laws of heat, as we understand them, admit of the extreme application here required, and if also the present system of things has reigned for sufficient time without the intervention of any influence at present unknown to us."— TAe Story of the Heavens, p. 506. NOTE C. THE HYPOTHESIS OF CYCLES. The idea of an eternal succession of cycles of existence— of alternating periods of dissolution and renovation— of the destruction of worlds, and continual birth of new worlds from the ruins of the old— could not but present itself early to the minds of speculative thinkers whose theories did not admit of a beginning of the world in time. We find it in Brahmanism, in some of the early Greek philosophies, among the Stoics, and it has been frequently revived in modern times as an alternative to the doctrine of creation. Zeller says of the Greek Anaximander : " The assertion which ascribes to Anaximander an infinity of successive worlds seems borne out by his system. . . . Plutarch, indeed, expressly says of Anaximander, that from the Infinite, as the sole cause of the birth and destruction of all things, he considered that the heavens and the innumerable worlds arise in endless circulation ; and Hippolytus speaks to the same effect. . . . Cicero, too, makes mention of innumerable worlds, which in long periods of time arise and perish ; and Stobaeus attributes to Anaximander the theory of the future destruction of the world. . . . The same theory of a constant alternation of birth and destruction in the universe was held by Heraclitus, who approaches more closely to Anaximander than to any of the ancient Ionian physicists, and also most probably by Anaximenes and Diogenes. We have reason, therefore, to suppose that Anaximander also held it." — Pre-Socratic Philosophy, pp. 259, 260. This theory was revived by Kant in his Theory of the Heavens in 1755,1 and was adopted from him by Strauss (in his Glaubenslehre and Der alte unci der neue Glauhe, pp. 153-160). Vatke and others also held it. Mr. Spencer, with all his profession of nescience about origins, adopts this theory, as in reason he is compelled to do if he advocates evolution, and yet refuses to admit a beginning in time.— First Principles, pp. 519-537, 550, 551. 1 Kant, however, held a beginning. See Strauss's criticism of him in passage cited. 484 NOTES TO LECTURE IV, There is a fascination and grandeur in this conception of endless cycles of existence, — of new worlds perpetually rising from the ashes of the old, — but it is a theory which cannot be maintained. 1. Philosophically, it involves all the difficulties which, in discussing the cosmological argument, we saw to inhere in the notion of an endless succession of causes and effects. This, as respects the past (regressus in infinitum), is a supposition which is not simply inconceivable, but which reason compels us positively to reject as self- contradictory. 2. Scientifically, it seems disproved by the doctrine of the dissipation of energy, and of the tendency of the material universe to a state of final equilibrium. This doctrine is stated by Sir William Thomson (now Lord Kelvin) in the following terms : — "(1) There is at present in the material world a universal tendency to the dissipation of mechanical energy. ^ "(2) Any restoration of mechanical energy, without more than an equivalent of dissipation, is impossible in inanimate material processes, and is probably never effected by material masses, either endowed with vegetable life, or subjected to the will of an animated creature. " (3) Within a finite past, the earth must have been, and within a finite period of time to come the earth must again be, unfit for the habitation of man as at present constituted, unless operations have been, or are to be, performed which are impossible under the laws to which the known operations going on at present in the material world are subject." — Paper " On a Universal Tendency in Nature to the Dissipation of Mechanical Energy," in Phil Mag. in Ser. iv. vol. x. p. 304 ff. Cf. Tait's Recent Advances in Physical Science, p. 146 ; Stewart and Tait's The Unseen Uni- verse, pp. 93, 94, 126-128, 211-214 (5th ed.) ; and Jevons' Principles of Science, ii. p. 483. Mr. Spencer himself admits that as the outcome of the processes everywhere going on, we are "manifestly progressing towards omni- present death," — that " the proximate end of all the transformations we have traced, is a state of quiescence." — First Principles, p. 514. Stewart and Tait say : " The tendency of heat is towards equalisation ; heat is par excellence the communist of our universe, and it will no doubt ultimately bring the present system to an end." — Unseen Universe, p. 126. Professor Huxley says : " Astronomy, which leads us to contemplate phenomena, the very nature of which demonstrates that they must have had a beginning, and that they must have an end, but the very nature of which also proves that the beginning was, to our conceptions of time, infinitely remote, and that the end is as immeasurably distant." — Lay Sermons, Addresses, etc., p. 17 ("On the Advisableness of Improving Natural Knowledge "). Cf. on the cycle hypothesis, Flint's Philosophy of History, pp. 30-35 ; Dorner in criticism of Vatke, Person of Christ, v. pp. 122, 123 ; and Chapman in criticism of Spencer, Pre- Organic Evolution, pp. 179-190. 1 Professor Proctor says that only the one two hundred and twenty-seventh of the one millionth of all the heat from the sun reaches any planet ; the remainder passes into space and is lost. NOTES TO LECTURE IV, 485 NOTE D. "eternal creation." Origen's views are stated in his Be Princiinis, Book i. 2, iii. 5, etc. In the former passage he argues that God would not be omnipotent if He had not eternally creatures on which to exercise His power. In the latter, he deals with the objection : " If the world had its beginning in time, what was God doing before the world began ? For it is at once impious and absurd to say that the nature of God is inactive and immovable, or to sup2)ose that goodness at one time did not do good, and omnipotence at one time did not exercise its power ; " and gives for answer : " Not then for the first time did God begin to work when He made this visible world ; but as, after its destruction, there will be another world, so also we believe that others existed before the present came into being. ... By these testimonies it is established both that there were ages before our own, and that there will be others after it." — Ante-Nicene Library trans, pp. 28, 255. Origen's view of eternal creation is thus that of an eternal succession of worlds. That profound mediaeval speculative thinker, John Scotus Erigena, held the doctrine of an eternal creation. See the sketch of his system in Ueberweg's Hist, of Phil. i. 358-365. Rothe's views are contained in his Theologische Ethik, i. sees. 40-52 (a special discussion of the point in sec. 52, pp. 193-204, 2nd ed.), and his Dogmatik, pp. 138-160. His theory turns on the notion that in positing his I, God must also, by a necessity of thought, posit his not- 1, which is identified by him with pure matter, and is the product of an eternal act. This is the act of creation proper, and is beginningless ; and from it is to be distinguished the world, which is the product of finite develop- ment, and has its existence in space and time — has therefore a beginning in time. " What has been created in time," he says, " that has naturally a beginning ; but as undoubtedly has that which was created when there was not time, no beginning. For a beginning can only be spoken of where there is time. The world is consequently in no way without beginning (as little in a spatial as in a temporal reference), and nothing belonging to the world is."—Theol Ethik, pp. 198, 199. Rothe's pure matter is almost identified by him with space and time. The idea of a beginning of God's creative activity, Schleiermacher thinks, places Him as a temporal being in the domain of change. — Der Christ. Glauhe, i. pp. 200, 201. The views of Lipsius may be seen in his Dogmatik, pp. 292, 293. "It is only a sensuous representation," he says, " to lead back creation upon a single act now lying in the past, or to speak of a 'first beginning' of creation ; rather is the total world-development, so soon as it is viewed religiously, to be placed under the notion of creation, consequently to be regarded as without beginning or end."— P. 293. Dorner solves the problem by the supposition of a temporal world standing midway between two eternal ones. " Just, therefore," he says, 486 NOTES TO LECTURE IV. " as we have no right to say that this law of succession, and this progress from imperfect to perfect, must continue for ever ... so also we have no right to say that this world, tangible to sense and subject to tem- porality, cannot have been preceded by a world of pure spirits (although spirits not yet subject to laws of historical progress), which are with- drawn in the first instance from all relation of succession, and exist in the simultaneity of all their constituent elements, and in this character surround the throne of God, — a kingdom of which it cannot be said that a time was when it was not, not merely because no time was ere it was, but also because for it there was no time, no succession or becoming. This world can only be brought under the standpoint of time by reference to the succeeding world. From this point of view it appears a preceding one, already belonging to the past. Thus, midway between the eternal world of the end, in which temporal existence merges, and the world of the beginning standing in the light of eternity, may lie, like an island in a broad ocean, the present world bound to temporal existence." — System of Doctrine, ii. p. 33 (Eng. trans.). Lotze teaches " that the ' will to create ' is an absolutely eternal predi- cate of God, and ought not to be used to designate a deed of His, so much as the absolute dependence of the world upon His will, in contra- distinction to its involuntary 'emanation' from His nature." — Outlines of the Phil, of Religion, p. 74 (Eng. trans.). The authors of The Unseen Universe hold that the present visible universe, which had a beginning and will have an end, is developed out of an unseen and eternal one. "We are led," they say, "not only to regard the invisible universe as having existed before the present one, but the same principle drives us to acknowledge its existence in some form as a universe from all eternity." — Unseen Universe, p. 215 ; cf. pp. 94, 95. The theory of an eternal creation is contested, on the other hand, by Van Gosterzee {Dogmatics, pp. 303, 304, Eng. trans.), Gretillat (Theologie Sijstematique, iii. 392-397), Miiller {Christ Doct. of Sin, i. pp. 224-227, Eng. trans.), etc. The diflEiculties which attach to such theories as Eothe's and Dorner's, which only shift the problem from the absolute beginning to the be- ginning of the temporal developing world, are pointed out by Miiller in his criticism of the former : " Do not the difficulties supposed to be involved in a beginning of the world return now as really insoluble, because, while denying its beginning, we have to allow the fact of its eternal creation, and to believe that God, having left it as it was for a limitless period, barely existing as materia hruta, at length began at some definite time to think of it and ordain it, i.e., to begin to develop it towards the goal of its becoming spirit. . . . And if the beginning of the world involves a transition from non-creation to creation incon- sistent with God's unchangeableness, have we not here also a transition on God's part from inactivity to action equally inadmissible, because in this case God's Kevelation of Himself in outward activity becomes a necessity of His nature ? "—Christ. Doct. of Sin, p. 226 (Eng. trans.). NOTES TO LECTURE IV, 487 NOTE E. ETERNITY AND TIME. This difficult problem has exercised the minds of thinkers in all ages. Augustine has profound thoughts on the subject in his Be Civitate Dei, " For if eternity and time be well considered," he says, " time never to be extant without motion, and eternity to admit no change, who would not see that time could not have being before some movable thing were created 1 . . . Seeing, therefore, that God, whose eternity alters not, created the world and time, how can He be said to have created the world in time, unless you will say there was something created before the world whose course time did follow ? . . . Then, verily, the world was made with time and not in time (mundus non in tempore sed cum tempore factus est), for that which is made in time is made both before some time and after some. Before it is time past ; after it is time to come ; but no time passed before the world, because no creature was made by whose course it might pass." — Book xi. 6.^ Kothe goes deeply into the question in his Theologische Ethik, i. pp. 193-204 (2nd ed.) ; and Lotze discusses it with suggestiveness and subtlety in his Microcosmos, ii. pp. 708-713. The following remarks in Dorner are in consonance with a suggestion in the text : " When, therefore, the world comes into actual existence, actual time comes into existence. The actual world is preceded by merely possible time ; of course, not in a temporal sense, else must time have existed before time, but in a logical sense. From the point of view of actual time, merely possible time can only be mentally repre- sented under the image of the past ; and the same is true of the eternal world-idea, and God's eternity in relation to the world's actual existence." — System of Doctrine, ii. p. 30 (Eng. trans.). Dr. Hutcheson Stirling has also his thoughts on this difficulty. " It is easy," he says, " to use the words, the predicates that describe what we conceive to be eternal ; as, for example, in the terms of Plato to say that the eternal, ' what is always unmoved, the same, can become by time neither older nor younger, nor has been made, nor appears now, nor will be in the future, nor can any of those things at all attach to it which mortal birth has grafted on the things of sense ; ' but how to bring into connection with this everlasting rest the never-resting movement of time— that is the difficulty." I confess that his suggestion that "time may be no straight line, as we are apt to figure it, but a curve— a curve that eventually returns into itself," does not seem to me greatly to relieve the difficulty.— P/ii7. and Theol p. 105. 1 Augustine, however, in these remarks does little more than reproduce Plato in the Timeus. See the striking passage, Jowett's Plato, iii. p. 620 (2na ed.). 488 NOTES TO LECTURE IV. NOTE F. MAN THE HEAD OF CREATION. This thouglit of man as the crown and masterpiece of creation— tlie goal of its developments — finds the most varied expression in writers of different schools. I cite a few illustrative instances. Kant finds man to be " not merely like all organised beings, an end of nature, but also here on earth the last end of nature, in reference to whom all other natural things constitute a system of ends." — Kritik d. Urtheilskraft, p. 280 (Erd. ed.). It is the key-thought of Herder's Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichtej that man is the connecting link between two worlds ; on the one hand, the highest of nature's products, crowning its ascent from i^lant to animal, and from lower to higher grades of animal life, till finally it rests in him ; and, on the other, the starting-point of a new order of spiritual existences. " All is bound together in nature ; one condition strives towards another, and prepares the way for it. If, therefore, man closes the chain of terrestrial organisations as its highest and last mem- ber, he likewise begins, just on that account, the chain of a higher order of creatures, as the lowest member of it ; and thus is probably the middle-link between two systems of creation, intimately connected with each other." — Ideen, Bk. v. 6. It is virtually Herder's thought which Dr. H. Stirling reproduces when he says: "There is a rise from object to object. The plant is above the stone, and the animal above the plant. But man is the most perfect result. His supremacy is assured. He alone of all living creatures is erect ; and he is erect by reason of the Divinity within him whose office it is to know, to think, and to consider. All other animals are but incomplete, imperfect, dwarf, beside man." — Phil and Theol. p. 137. That man is the apex of the evolutionary movement is, of course, recognised by all, though not necessarily with acknowledgment of final cause. Professor Huxley, in his Man^s Place in Nature, says : " In view of the intimate relations between man and the rest of the living world, and between the forces exerted by the latter and all other forces, I can see no excuse for doubting that all are co-ordinated forms of Nature's great progression from the formless to the formed, from the inorganic to the organic, from blind force to conscious intellect and will " (p. 108) ; and Professor Tyndall, in his Belfast Address, describing how in the primates the evolution of intellect and the evolution of tactual append- ages go hand in hand, says : " Man crowns the edifice here." And Mr. "Wallace regards man as not only placed "apart, as the head and culminating point of the grand series of organic nature, but as in some degree a new order of being."— iVa^. Selection, pp. 351, 352. Mr. Fiske may be quoted, who says suggestively : " The doctrine of evolution, by exhibiting the development of the highest spiritual human qualities as the goal toward which God's creative work has from NOTES TO LECTURE IV. 489 , ihe outset been tending, replaces Man in his old position of headship in the universe, even as in the days of Dante and Thomas Aquinas. That which the pre-Copernican astronomy naively thought to do by placing the home of Man in the centre of the physical universe, the Darwinian biology profoundly accomplishes by exhibiting Man as the terminal fact in that stupendous process of evolution whereby things have come to be what they are. In the deepest sense it is as true as it ever was held to be, that the world was made for Man, and that the bringing forth in him of those qualities which we call highest and holiest is the final cause of creation." — Idea of God, Introd. pp. 20, 21. Gf. also the chapters on " Man's Place in Nature as affected by Darwinism," and " On the Earth there will never be a Higher Creature than Man " in his Man's Destiny (1890). I quote further only the following sentences from Kaftan : "The end of nature, of its history and its development, can be sought only in humanity, in the fact that ' man is the crown of the creation.^ We men can find or discover nothing in the whole world environing us which can be put in comparison with man and his spiritual life, still less which surpasses him. . . . We must on this account form the idea of an end of the natural development, and then what scientific knowledge ofi'ers in particulars advances to meet this thought. For this idea would have no support if it were not upheld by the conviction of an end pertaining to man and to his history. That the development of the natural world has its end in man, becomes a rational thought, first of all, when I can speak in turn of an end to which the world of humanity itself has regard." — TVahrheit, etc., p. 418. NOTE G. MIND AND MECHANICAL CAUSATION. It is well to see clearly what this " gradual banishment from all regions of human thought of what we call spirit and spontaneity," which Pro- fessor Huxley speaks of ("On the Physical Basis of Life"), involves; and the matter could not be much better put than it is by Mr. Kennedy in his Donnellan Lectures on Natural Theology and Modern Thought. He calls attention to the way in which this theory must, if true, affect our belief about the agency of God and the agency of the mind of man. " For the latter, the agency of the human mind," he says, " it leaves no room whatever. It tells us that in attributing the railways and steam- ships and cotton-mills of the present day to the fertile mind of man, we have been making a mistake as great as that of the insane astronomer in Swift's satire, who had persuaded himself that it was his watchful care which guided the movement of the planets. The railways, steamships, and cotton-mills would have been constructed all the same, though we had no minds at all ; just as the stars would have remained in their proper places, though the attention of the astronomer had been withdrawn from 490 NOTES TO LECTURE IV, them. It was the boast of Corate, that to minds familiarised with the true astronomical philosophy, the heavens now declare no other glory than that of Hipparchus, Kepler, Newton, and all those who have con- tributed to the ascertainment of their laws ; but if the doctrine of Automatism be true, it is the direct contrary of this which results ; it is the glory of Hipparchus, Newton, and Kepler which is irretrievably destroyed. For the mind of Hipparchus was not the agent which made known to man the Precession of the Equinoxes ; nor were the thoughts of Newton the cause of the writing of the Principia ; nor did those of Kepler cause the enunciation, either by pen or voice, of the laws which bear his name. These philosophers were merely conscious automata ; and had they been unconscious automata, the result would still have been the very same" (pp. 75, 76). This is no travesty of the doctrine, but a serious presentation of the results of the views advocated by Professor Huxley in his i^aper, " The Hypothesis that Animals are Automata " {Fortnighthj Review, November 1874, pp. 575, 576). " It seems to me," says this distinguished scientific teacher, "that in men, as in brutes, there is no proof that any state of consciousness is the cause of change in the motion of the matter of the organism. If these positions are well based, it follows that our mental conditions are simply the symbols in consciousness of the changes which take place automatically in the organism ; and that, to take an extreme illustration, the feeling we call volition is not the cause of a voluntary act, but the symbol of that state of the brain which is the immediate cause of that act. We are conscious automata," etc. It is difficult to see what place is left for virtue or responsibility in such a theory of man as this ! NOTE H. MIND AND CEREBRAL ACTIVITY. This subject is discussed with great care in Professor H. Calderwood's The Relations of Mind and Brain, with the result that a series of facts are established which I do not remember seeing brought out as convincingly anywhere else. The chief value of his book lies in the proof which it leads of the following positions, which I set here in order, with reference to passages in which they are discussed : — 1. That the primary function of the brain is to serve, not as an organ of thought, but as an organ of sensory-motor activity (pp. 196, 290, 302-307, 2nd ed.). 2. That, as demonstrated by experiment, by far the greater part of the brain — if not all — is monopolised for sensory-motor work, leaving little, if any, of it to be employed for other purposes (pp. 302, 361). 3. That in the comparison of animals there is no fixed ratio between degree of intelligence and complexity of brain structure — a highly de- veloped and convoluted brain finding its chief explanation in " the much more complex muscular system to be controlled" (p. 149). "Ad- NOTES TO LECTURE IV, 491 vance in intelligence and advance in complexity of brain structure do not keep pace with each other, they are not correlated so as to harmonise " (p. 148). The dog, e.g., with a brain less elaborate in its convolutions, shows a higher degree of intelligence than the horse, with a more ample and complicated series of foldings on the convolutions of the grey matter. A number of leading cases are examined in detail in Chap. v. "Comparison of the Structure and Functions of Brain in Lower and Higher Forms of Animal Life " (pp. 123 if.). Cf. pp. 260, 261. 4. That the view that special cells are appropriated to mental functions, —as, e.g., the " mind-cells " of Haeckel (pp. 298-303), or the memory-cells of Professor Bain (pp. 356-364),— is not borne out, but is discredited by physiology. As against Haeckel, it presents " a cumulative body of evi- dence adverse to the hypothesis that human intelligence can be attributed to the giant pyramidal cells abounding in the fourth layer of the brain. All available evidence favours the conclusion that these giant cells are motor cells largely concerned in the functions of co-ordination of related intra-cerebral movements. It thus seems warrantable to infer that such co-ordinated movement takes rank as the highest function of brain. In accordance with this view is Dr. Ferrier's conclusion as to the frontal regions in the human brain, based on the whole range of experiments under electro-motor excitation, "that they are 'inhibitory motor-centres' such as may be associated with an exercise of attention " (pp. 302, 303). As respects Bain's theory, "the known laws of cerebral activity do not favour such calculations as are suggested by Professor Bain. The space appropriated for the sensory and motor functions includes a great part of the mass of cellular tissue " (p. 360, see proof in detail). Generally, " physiology does not discover any new function in the higher part of the system, except more detailed ordination " (p. 297). " We must regard equally the frontal and the occipital regions of the grand central organ as concerned with sensory - activity and correlated motor - activity " (p. 316). 5. That the true relation of mind and brain lies in the dependence of the former on the latter in sensory functions, and in the use made by the former (involved in all forms of mental activity) of the brain's motor functions. The following is an enumeration of forms of brain action which must be considered as generally attending on the more ordinary mental exercises : "(1) Action of the special senses, and of the more general tac- tile sense ; (2) action of the muscles concerned in the management of these senses, and specially of the organs of sight ; (3) co-ordination of sensory and motor apparatus required for use of the senses ; (4) action of sensory centres consequent on use of imagination (p. 357), in j)art a renewal of sensory impressions, or a movement of sensory cells conse- quent upon stimulus which imagination supplies ; (5) sensory and motor action consequent upon the stimulus coming from mental emotion, such as weeping, facial expression of sadness or sympathy ... all these phases of brain action, as they involve active use of brain energy, imply trans- formation of energy, consequent waste of brain substance, and inevitable sense of exhaustion. . . . First, there is large use of both sensory and motor apparatus in connection with all the ordinary forms of intellectual 492 NOTES TO LECTURE IV. activity. Second, all thought proceeds, to a large extent, by use of language, and thus seems to involve activity of the cells concerned with the acquisition and use of language and speech. Third, con- centrated thought makes a severer demand upon all the forms of brain action connected with ordinary thought, and so quickens and increases the exhaustion of nerve energy "(pp. 412-415). This defines the sense in which the brain is the organ of mind, and shows that it is not the organ of mind in the same sense in which it is a sensory- motor organ (p. 315). 6. That while the mind is thus manifoldly correlated with brain action, not only are mental-facts, as the highest authorities admit, absolutely distinguishable from brain-facts (pp. 292, 293, 314, 315); but the mental phenomena in man (even in sensation and consciousness of succession in sensations, in memory, language, still more in the higher mental func- tions, self-regulated voluntary activity, intellectual activities, thought on ultimate questions of existence, etc.) transcend brain action altogether, and are non-interpretable through it (pp. 304-307, 366, 367, 385-396 ; chap. XV. " The Higher Forms of Mental Activity "). " Mind transcends all the sensibilities of our organism. The whole range of our thoughts, — as we interpret events under the law of causality, form conceptions of rectitude, and represent to ourselves a scheme of the universe as a whole — transcends all the functions of the nerve system. Known facts are in accordance with this duality ; paralysis of a cerebral hemisphere may leave intelligence unaffected ; though high intellectual life involves good brain development, high brain development does not necessarily involve a distinguished intellectual life ; but the more highly educated a man is, so much the more does his life transcend what his bodily functions can accomplish" (p. 317). The result reached is — " that the intelligence of man, as known in personal consciousness, is of a nature entirely distinct from sensory apparatus, its functions being incapable of explanation in accordance with the laws of sensory activity. . . . The facts of consciousness lead to the conclusion that mind is a distinct order of existence, different in nature from the nerve system, differing in the mode of its action from the mechanical action of sensory apparatus, and capable of interpreting the rational sensibilities of our organism, so as thereby to discover a rational order in things external, or adaptation of related things in nature to rational purpose " (p. 307). In establishing these positions, Professor Calderwood at the same time refutes certain others, viz. : — 1. The theory which identifies mind with brain action (pp. 313, 314). 2. The theory which supposes that there is an exact correspond- ence between the mental and physical facts, — or that, as Bain and Spencer put it, they are but two sides of the same thing (pp. 293-296). " That there is an absolute harmony involving a parallelism or correspondence, and making an exact equation of both organic and non-organic activity in all cases, it is quite impossible to maintain " (p. 316). 3. The theory that mental phenomena can be translated into the NOTES TO LECTURE IV. 493 language of brain changes, or expressed in terms of the motions, group- ings, or electric discharges of the latter (pp. 314, 315). 4. The view that mind does not act on the brain series to alter or modify it—" that action and reaction of nerve tissue carries the explana- tion of all that belongs to human life " (pp. 326-343). " It was inevitable that a theory reducing all human action to the play of nerve force should be propounded" (p. 336); but "(1) There is neither anatomical nor physiological evidence in support of the theory. . . . (3) The facts relied on as auxiliary to the theory do not in reality support it. . . . (4) The facts to be explained — voluntary control of muscular activity under guidance of intelligence— do not manifest resemblance to the known facts of nerve action, but present a decided contrast " (pp. 328, 329). NOTE I. SCHLEIERMACHER AND IMMORTALITY. In his earlier writings Schleiermacher undoubtedly speaks slightingly of personal immortality, and Dr. Martineau enlarges on this as if it were his whole view. — Study of Religion, ii. pp. 355-360. But in his Der christliche Glaube he takes much more positive ground. In Sec. 157 he distinguishes between " propositions of faith " and " propositions received on testimony," which, though their truth is not directly deducible from the contents of the Christian consciousness, are yet so intimately bound up with the credit of Christ and His witnesses, that we cannot refuse to accej)t them. Such, e.g., is the resurrection of Christ Himself, which, as shown in an earlier section (sec. 99), is not directly involved in faith, but yet is to be received on testimony. It is not otherwise, in Schleier- macher's view, with immortality. Here also he takes the ground that personal immortality is not a doctrine so bound up with faith that a man cannot conceivably be a Christian, and yet deny it. For if there is an irreligious denial of personal immortality, there may also, he holds, be a denial of it springing from a worthy and indeed a religious motive. " If, therefore," he says, " any one in good faith should maintain that Christ's words on this subject are to be taken figuratively, and not in their strict sense, and on this account should not attribute personal immortality to himself, faith in Christ, as such an one conceives of Him, certainly re- mains possible ; " though, as he proceeds to explain, it would involve a complete transformation of Christianity if such a mode of interpretation should ever be established in the Church, or should be laid at the foundation of Christian faith (sec. 157, 2). But this is a purely hypothetical case. For in these consequences to Christianity, says Schleiermacher, " it is already implied that we do not presuppose that such an interpretation can be made in good faith." It can be maintained " that faith in the continuance of our personality is bound up with faith in the Redeemer" (ibid.). He rejects all the natural arguments for im- mortality (sec. 158. 1), but he thinks it indubitable that Christ Himself 494 NOTES TO LECTURE IV, taught His own immortality, and that of believers as united with Him in fellowship of life ; and this conviction is therefore given to us as part of our faith in Christ (sec. 158, 2). It must, however, be admitted that this is an exceedingly weak ground on which to rest so weighty an article of faith ; for assuredly faith will not long retain a doctrine for which it experiences no religious need, and which finds no support in the facts of human nature. NOTES TO LECTUKE V. NOTE A. DEFECTS IN CREATION : AN ARGUMENT AGAINST THEISM. Lucretius already uses this argument. Even were he ignorant, he says, of the primordial causes of things, he could venture to afl&rm from the faultiness of the universe that it was not the work of Divine power. " Quod si jam rerum ignorem primordia quae sint, Hoc tamen ex ipsis cseli rationibus ausim Confirmare aliisque ex rebus reddere multis, Nequaquam nobis divinitus esse paratam Naturam rerum ; tanta stat prsedita culpa." — De Rerum Natura, v. 195-199. Seneca held a view akin to Mill's. ^ Among his queries are these : " How far God's power extends ? Whether He forms His own matter, or only uses that which is given Him ? Whether He can do whatsoever He will 1 or the materials in many ways frustrate and disappoint Him, and things are formed badly by the great Artificer, not because His art fails, but because that on which it is exercised proves stubborn and intractable." Qucest. Nat, Book i. Preface. Mr. Rathbone Greg seems in the end of his life to have come round to the views of Mr. Mill. " Thoughtful minds in all ages," he says, " have experienced the most painful perplexities in the attempt to reconcile certain of the moral and physical phenomena we see around us with the assump- tion of a Supreme Being at once all- wise, all-good, and almighty." These difficulties, he thinks, are wholly gratuitous, and arise out of the incon- siderate and unwarranted use of a single word — omnipotent. Only grant that the Creator is " conditioned, — hampered, it may be, by the attributes, qualities, and imperfections of the material on which He had to operate ; bound possibly by laws or properties inherent in the nature of that material,'' — and " it becomes possible to believe in and to worship God without doing violence to our moral sense, or denying or distorting the 1 Mill's views are indicated in the text. They are further discussed by me in two })apers in The Theological Monthly (July and August 1891) on "J. S. Mill and Christianity." 496 NOTES TO LECTURE V, sorrowful facts that surround our daily life." — Preface to Enigmas of Life (18th edition). The Pessimists, of course, lay stress on what they consider the evil and defects of nature, as proving that it cannot have proceeded from an intelligent cause. Hartmann is quoted by Strauss as saying that " if God, before creation, had possessed consciousness, creation would have been an inexpiable crime ; its existence is only pardonable as the result of blind will." — Der alte und der neue Glaube, p. 223. Comte and Helmholtz have urged the defects of nature as disproving design. See their views criticised in Flint's Theism, Lect. viii. ; Janet's Final Causes, p. 45 (Eng. trans.) ; Kennedy's Nat. Theol. and Modern Thought, pp. 130-134 ; Eow's Christian Theism, chap. ix. etc. Mr. S. Laing urges the undeniable existence of evil in the world as a fact irreconcilable with that of an almighty and beneficent Creator, and takes refuge in an ultimate law of " polarity," i.e. dualism. — A Modern Zoroastrian, pp. 170-183 (see next note). Maudsley writes : " The facts of organic and human nature, when ob- served frankly and judged without bias, do not warrant the argument of a supreme and beneficent artificer working after methods of human intelligence, but perfect in all his works ; rather would they warrant, if viewed from the human standpoint, the conception of an almighty malignant power that was working out some far-off end of its own, with the serenest disregard of the suffering, expenditure, and waste which were entailed in the process." — Body and Will, pp. 180, 181. There is much that is exaggerated, jaundiced, and subjective in these complaints, but they point to the existence of great and terrible evils in the world, which Theism must boldly face, and do justice to in some way in its view of the world. NOTE B. DUALISTIC THEORIES OF THE ORIGIN OF EVIL. The hypothesis of two principles in the universe finds classical expression in the Zoroastrian religion. Cf. on this Ebrard's Christian Apologetics, ii. pp. 186-232. Mr. S. Laing makes an attempt at a revival of the theory in his book, A Modern Zoroastrian, under the name of " a law of polarity." He would have us " devote ourselves with a whole heart and sincere mind to the worship of the good principle, without paltering with our moral nature by professing to love and adore a Being who is the author of all the evil and misery in the world as well as of the good ; " and holds that a great deal of what is best in Christianity " resolves itself very much into the worship of Jesus as the Ormuzd, or personification of the good principle, and determination to try to follow His example and do His work" (pp. 179, 180). There is a deceptive simplicity in this idea of dividing oft' the good and evil of the world into different departments, giving all the good to NOTES TO LECTURE V. 497 a good principle, and all the evil to an evil principle, which may impose for a moment on the mind, yet the slightest reflection should suffice to show the crudencss and untenableness of the hypothesis. 1. In respect of physical evil, no such sharp division into good and evil is possible. Eather the terms are relative, and what is good in one rela- tion is evil in another. Good and evil are often simply questions of degree ; the susceptibility to pleasure is involved in the susceptibility to pain, and vice versa. Thus the same nerve which feels pleasure feels pain ; the one susceptibility is involved in the other. Pleasure and pain shade into each other by insensible gradations. If, e.g., I approach my hands to the fire, I feel a grateful warmth ; if I bring them nearer, I am scorched. It is the same sun which fructifies the fields in one part of the world, and burns up the herbage or smites with sunstroke in another. On the hypothesis in question, the sun's heat would belong in the one case to the good, in the other to the evil principle ; so with the fire, etc. 2. In respect of moral evil, a self-subsisting evil principle is an im- possible abstraction. Moral evil is a term which has no meaning except in relation to character and will ; and a character or will cannot be evil, unless along with the evil there is some knowledge of the good.^ Natural forces, as heat and electricity, are neither good nor evil, for there is no knowledge. Bound up, therefore, with the evil principle, there must be some knowledge of the good, else it would not be evil. But a principle which participates in the knowledge of the good cannot be originally or essentially evil, but can only have become such through its own choice. Evil, in other words, has no reality, save as the negation or antithesis of the good, which is its necessary presupposition. Abs- tracted from knowledge of the good, the so-called evil principle sinks to the rank of a mere nature principle, of which neither good nor evil can properly be predicated. This is ultimately the reason why in dualistic systems natural and moral evil always tend to be confounded. NOTE C. hegel's doctrine of sin. Hegel's view, as stated in his ReligionspMlosophie, may be briefly summed up thus : — 1. Evil exists by a metaphysical necessity. " The notion must realise itself. . . . Man is essentially spirit ; but spirit does not arise in an immediate way. It is essential to spirit to be for itself, to be free, to oppose itself to naturalness, to raise itself out of its state of immersion in nature, to set itself at variance with nature, and first through and by this variance to reconcile itself with nature, and not only with nature, but with its own essence, with its truth."— Vol. i. p. 268. 1 "By its very essence," says Mr. Bradley, "immorality cannot exist except as against morality; a purely immoral being is a downright im\)0ssi\iility."— Ethical JSiudies, p. 210. 32 498 NOTES TO LECTURE V. % As respects his original condition, man exists first in a state ot pure naturalness. It is hardly correctly named even a state of innocence, for innocence implies moral ideas, whereas this is a state " in which there is for man neither good nor evil ; it is the state of the animal, of lack of knowledge, in which man knows nothing of either good or evil, in which what he wills is not determined either as the one or the other ; for if he does not know evil, neither does he know good. ... In truth, that first state of mere existence in unity with nature is not a condition of innocence, but of rudeness, of appetite, of barbarism generally." — Vol. i. p. 269. 3. As respects man's essential nature in this state, two opposite defini- tions are to be given — Man is by nature good ; and man is by nature bad. To affirm "that man is by nature good, is essentially to say that man is spirit in himself, is rationality ; he is created with and after the image of God. . . . The other statement arises from what has been said, that man raust not remain as he is immediately, but must transcend his immediateness. . . . His being-in-self, his naturality is the evil. ... He is evil for this reason, that he is a natural being. . . . The absolute demand is that man shall not remain as a mere natural being, — not as mere natural will. Man has indeed consciousness ; but he can, even as man, remain a mere natural being, in so far as he makes the natural the aim, content, and determination of his will." — Vol. ii. pp. 258-260. 4, That through which the transition is effected from the natural to the moral state is hnoioledge. With the awakening of consciousness, man recognises that he is not what he ought to be ; hence arises the sense of sin, the pain of discord, of contradiction with himself. As the l^ible has it, man becomes evil by eating of the tree of knowledge. " In this representation lies the connection of evil with knowledge. This is an essential point Man's nature is not what it should be, and it is knowledge which acq[uaints him with this and sets before him the fact of, his being as he ought not to be. . . . It is not that consideration (knowledge) has an external relation to evil, but the consideration itself is the evil. Man, since he is spirit, has to proceed to this opposition, in order to be altogether for himself," etc. — Vol. ii. pp. 263-265. It is the annulling of this self-diremption in man — represented as an essential stage in his development — which constitutes, according to Hegel, the atonement. NOTE D. ritschl's doctrine of guilt. See a searching examination of Ritschl's doctrine on this subject in Dorner's System of Doctrine, iv. pp. 60-72 (Eug. trans.). Of. also Pfleiderer's Die RitschVsche Theologiey pp. 63, 69, 70 ; Bertrand's Une nouvelle Conception de la Redemption, pp. 256-273 ; Sttihlin's Kant, Lotze, and Ritschl, pp. 210-212, 226. All these writers agree that the logical effect of Ritschl's doctrine is NOTES TO LECTURE V. 499 to reduce guilt to a subjective illusion. This is borne out by the follow- ing particulars of his system : — 1. By the denial to God of everything of the nature of punitive jus- tice. In so far as the sinner's guilty fears lead him to represent God as angry with him, or as visiting him with punishment, he is tormenting himself with needless apprehensions. Punitive justice is a conception borrowed from the sphere of civil right, and has no application in the sphere of the Divine. He teaches expressly that "external evils can only be reckoned as Divine punishments from the point of view of the subjective consciousness of guilt." — Eecht. und Ver. iii. p. 346. 2. By his doctrine of reconciliation. Reconciliation is defined as the removal of the separation which has come to exist between man and God in consequence of sin ; and as it is the consciousness of guilt which keeps sinners far from God, pardon consists essentially in the removal of this guilt-consciousness (iii. p. 52). But this is not to be understood as if in tliis removal of guilt anytliing objective took place. Rather Christ's work was, as Dorner expresses it, " to reveal God to us as fatherly love, and scatter the gloomy terrors of an angry God and a punitive justice ;" " to give deliverance from these erroneous notions of God's retributive and specially punitive justice, which interfere with Divine communion." — System of Doctrine, iv. p. 71. 3. The doctrine of guilt is attenuated on another side by Ritschl's view that all existing sin is sin committed in ignorance. It is on this ground that he declares it pardonable. But here again pardon does not mean the laying aside of any real displeasure on the part of God, but solely the removal of the sinner's (groundless) guilty fears. The one sin which Ritschl exempts from pardon is that of definitive unbelief— a problematical transgression which he thinks we have no reason to suppose ever existed. Here Ritschl's doctrine falls into an obvious inconsistency. He holds that if such a sin did exist, the one way the Divine Being could deal with it would be by annihilating the sinner. But surely this would be an exercise of punitive justice, if anything is ; yet Ritschl denies that punitive justice resides at all in God. On the whole, there is good ground for Dorner's charge, that "no clear, connected doctrine respecting punishment, God's punitive justice, moral freedom, and guilt, is to be found in Ritschl " (iv. p. 67). NOTE E. ALLEGED PRIMITIVE SAVAGERY OF MANKIND. The hypothesis of man's original savagery rests on certain unproved assumptions. I. So far as it is a deduction from the law of evolution, it rests on the' unproved assumption that man has developed by slow gradations from the condition of the animal. See on this the passages quoted in footnote to the Lecture, p. 213. 500 NOTES TO LECTURE V, II. As respects existing savages, the hypothesis — 1. Rests on the improved assumption that the state of existing savages represents (or most nearly represents) that of primitive nian.^ Of late, says Max Miiller, there has been a strong reaction in the study of un- civilised races. " First of all, it has been shown that it was certainly a mistake to look upon the manners and customs, the legends and re- ligious ideas of uncivilised tribes as representing an image of what the primitive state of mankind must have been thousands of years ago, or what it actually was long before the beginning of the earliest civilisation, as known to us from historical documents. The more savage a tribe, the more accurately was it supposed to reflect the primitive state of man- kind. This was no doubt a very natural mistake, before more careful researches had shown that the customs of savage races were often far more artificial and complicated than they appeared at first, and that there had been as much progression and retrogression in their historical development as in that of more civilised races. We know now that savage and primitive are very far indeed from meaning the same thing." — Anthrop. Religion, pp. 149, 150. Evidence is constantly accumulating that behind the existing condition of savage races, there stood a state of higher culture and civilisation. E.g. , Dr. Tylor says : " Dr. Bastian has lately visited New Zealand and the Sandwich Islands, and gathered some interesting information as to native traditions. The documents strengthen the view which for years has been growing up among anthropologists as to the civilisation of the Polynesians. It is true that tliey were found in Captain Cook's time living in a barbaric state, and their scanty clothing and want of metals led superior observers to class them as savages ; but their beliefs and customs show plainly traces of descent from ancestors who in some way shared the higher culture of the Asiatic nations." — Nature, 1881, p. 29. Tylor's own pages furnish ample evidence of similar retrogression of the African and other tribes. — Primitive Culture, pp. 42, 43. On the earlier extinct civilisations of Mexico and Peru, the mound-builders of the Mississippi Valley, and other evidences of earlier culture in America, see Reville's Hibbert Lectures, 1884, TJie Native Religions of Mexico and Peru; Dawson's Fossil Men and their Modern Representatives; Argyll's Unity of Nature, pp. 429-437. A fact of the greatest importance here is that pointed out by the Duke of Argyll, viz., that the degraded races of the world are those farthest from the centres of distribution of population. " It is a fact," he says, " that the lowest and rudest tribes in the population of the globe have been found, as we have seen, at the farthest extremities of its larger continents, or in the distant islands of its great oceans, or among the hills and forests which in every land have been the last refuge of tlie victims of violence and misfortune." — Unity of Nature, p. 426. See for illustra tion, chap. x. of this work. Whately's statement stands yet unoverturned. "Facts," he says, "a stubborn things ; and that no authenticated instance can be produced o ^ Of course, from the evolutionist point of view, even savage life, as Tylor point out, would be "a far advanced condition."— Prm. Cnlture, i. p. 33. lis ] its d NOTES TO LECTURE V. 501 savages that ever did emerge unaided from that state is no theory, but a statement, hitherto never disproved, of a matter of /ocf."— Exeter Hall Lecture on the Origin of Civilisation. 2. It overlooks the higher elements which exist even in the present condition of savages. See these brought out, as respects the African tribes, on the basis of Waltz's AnthrojJology, in Max MilUer's Hibbert Lectures, 1878, On the Origin and Growth of Religion, pp. 106-113. III. As respects prehistoric man, the main points are noticed in the Lectures. 1. Here, again, the assumption is unproved that these cave-men, etc., on whose rudeness the argument is founded, represented primitive man, and were not rather a degradation of an earlier type. Against this assumption is the fact of their distance from what seem to have been the original centres of distribution of the race, combined with the very- different spectacle which mankind presents as we approach these centres. On the argument based on the antiquity of prehistoric man, see Note G, and cf. Reusch's Nature and the Bible, ii. pp. 265-366 (Eng. trans.). 2. Many erroneous inferences may be drawn from stone implements and the like as to the intellectual and moral calibre of the people using them. See on this the most suggestive treatment in Sir Arthur Mitchell's lihind Lectures on " Past and Present," and " What is Civilisation ? " (1876 and 1878). 3. The greatest civilisations of antiquity do not show traces of an earlier period of barbarism. These civilisations certainly did not spring into existence ready-formed, but there is nothing to indicate any such slow rise from an antecedent state of savagery as the modern hypothesis supposes. This is pecViliarly the case with the oldest civilisation — that of Egypt. " In Egypt," says Canon Rawlinson, "it is notorious that there is no indication of any early period of savagery or barbarism. All the authorities agree that, however far we go back, we find in Egypt no rude or uncivilised time out of which civilisation is developed."— On^/m of Nations, p. 13.^ The same writer says of Babylon : " In Babylon there is more indication of early rudeness. But, on the other hand, there are not wanting signs of an advanced state of certain arts, even in the earliest times, which denote a high degree of civilisation, and contrast most curiously with the indications of rudeness here spoken of" (ibid. p. 14). Cf. also this writer's tract on " The Antiquity of Man Historically Considered," in Present Day Tracts (No. 9). NOTE F. EARLY MONOTHEISTIC IDEAS. It has been shown (Note A to Lecture III.— Primitive Fetishism and Ghost Worship) that man's earliest religious ideas were not his poorest. 1 On son)e supposed traces of prehistoric man in Egypt, see Dawson's ICgypt and Syria, pp. 128-136. 502 NOTES TO LECTURE V. It may now "be aflBrmed that liis earliest ideas were in some respects liis- Ingliest— that tlie consciousness of the one God was with him in the dawn of his history, and has never been wholly extinguished since. Ebrard, after an exhaustive examination of ancient religions, thus sums up: "We have nowhere been able to discover the least trace of any forward and upward movement from Fetishism to Polytheism, and from that again to a gradually advancing knowledge of the one God ; but, on the contrary, we have found among all peoples of the heathen world a most decided tendency to sink from an earlier and relatively purer knowledge of God."— C/imt Apol. iii. p. 317 (Eng. trans.). The ancient Egyptian religion was at heart monotheistic. M. de Rouge says : " Tlie Egyptian religion comprehends a quantity of local worships . . . Each of these regions has its principal god designated by a special name ; but it is always the same doctrine which reappears under different names. One idea predominates, that of a single and primcival God ; everywhere and always it is one substance, self- existent, and an unapproachable God." (Quoted by Renouf, p. 90.) This, he says, was the doctrine of the Egyptians in the earliest period. M. Renouf confirms this statement. " It is incontestably true," he testifies, " that the sublimer portions of the Egyptian religion are not the comparatively late result of a process of development or elimination from the grosser. The sublimer portions are demonstrably ancient ; and the last stage of the Egyptian religion, that known to the Greek and Latin writers, heathen or Christian, was by far the grossest and most corrupt." — Hibbert Lectures, p. 91. The early Babylonian religion was polytheistic; but here also the mono- theistic consciousness breaks through in tlie exalted predicates applied to the great gods by their respective worshippers. Each god seems at first to have been worshipped by its own city as supreme— the moon-god at Ur ; the sun-god at Sippara ; Ann, the sky, at Erech ; Ea, the deep, at Eridu ; Nebo at Borsippa, etc. Thus the moon-god was celebrated as the "lord and prince of the gods, who in heaven and earth alone is supreme ;" Nebo, in the belief of his worshippers, was the supreme god, the creator of the world ; Anu, the sky-god, became a supreme god, the lord and father of the universe, then " the one god " into whom all the other deities were resolved ; Asshur developed peculiarly exalted traits. " We can, in fact," says Professor Sayce, " trace in him all the linea- ments upon which under other conditions there might liave been built up as pure a faith as that of the God of Israel."— Sayce's Hibbert Lec- tures, 1887, p. 129 ; cf. jjp. 116, 160, 191, etc. Others go farther, and see in Ilu = Heb. El, " the Babylonian supreme deity " (cf. Schrader, Keilinschriften, i. p. 11, Eng. trans.) ; and conclude, with Duncker and Lenormant, that the Babylonians in the earliest times worshipi^ed one ^ god. El, Ilu. (In Ebrard, ii. p. 330.) fll The religion of the Vedas in India, in like manner, is purer than the ^' later Hindu developments, and points back, through philology, to an earlier stage still, when the Polytheism of the Vedas was as yet non- existent. "Behind the Homeric poems," says Dr. Fairbairn, "and the Vedas, and the separation of the Iranic-Indian branches, lies the period I NOTES TO LECTURE V. 503 when Celt and Teuton, Anglo-Saxon and Indian, Greek and Roman, Scandinavian and Iranian, lived together, a simple, single people. . . . Excluding the coincidences natural to related peoples developing the same germs, we find two points of radical and general agreement— the proper name of one God, and the term expressive of the idea of God in general ... A name for God had thus been formed before the dispersion. . . , The result is a Theism which we may name individualistic." — Studies in Phil, of Religion, pp. 22-29 ; "The younger the Polytheism, the fewer its gods," p. 22. Ebrard says : " Immediately after the separation of the Iranians and Indians, that is, during the first Vedic period, the consciousness was fully present among the Indians that the Adityas did not represent a multi- tude of separate deities in a polytheistic and mythological sense, but only the fulness of the creative powers of the one God, and that the holy God, and that in each of these Adityas it was always the one God who was woi'shipped. And the farther back we go into the past, the more dis- tinct do we find the consciousness among the Indians. In the second, the Indra period, it dwindles away, and gives place to a polytheistic conception."— C7i?-is<. Ajjol. ii. pp. 213, 214. He finds the common root of the Indian and Iranian religions in " a primitive Monotheism, or Elohism, as we might call it, since there is no real distinction between the Elohim and the Adityas" (p. 214). The Iranian religion in the form in which we find it in the Zend- Avesta (Zoroastrian) is dualistic ; but the conception of Ahura-Mazda, as we find it in the earlier portions, is so exalted that it may almost be called monotheistic. It unquestionably springs from the common Aryan root indicated above. Herodotus has the striking statement that the ancient Pelasgi, the early inhabitants of Greece, gave no distinct names to the gods, but prayed to them collectively. " They called them gods, because they had set in order and ruled all things." But as for the special names attached to them, and the functions severally assigned to them — all this, he thinks, goes no farther back than Homer and Hesiod. "These framed a theogony for the Greeks, and gave names to the gods, and assigned to them honours and arts, and declared their several forms" (ii. 52, 53). Max Miiller does not hesitate to say, following Welcker : " When we ascend to the most distant heights of Greek history, the idea of God as the Supreme Being stands before us as a simple fact." — Chips, ii. p. 157. This strain of Monotheism in the religion of the Greeks is never absolutely lost, but reappears in the beliefs of the philosophers, the Orphic mysteries, and the lofty conceptions of the great tragic poets. Plutarch, in like manner, tells us of the early religion of the Romans, that it was imageless and spiritual. Their religious lawgiver, Numa, he says, "forbade the Romans to represent the deity in the form either of man or of beast. Nor was there among them formerly any image or statue of the Divine Being ; during the first one hundred and seventy years they built temples, indeed, and other sacred domes, but placed in them no figure of any kind ; persuaded that it is impious to represent things Divine by what is perishable, and that we can have no conception 504 NOTES TO LECTURE V. of God but by the understanding."— Xilws, on Numa. The legendary form of the tradition need not lead us to doubt that it embodies a substantial truth. On this subject, see Ebrard's Christian Apologetics; Loring Brace's The Unknown God; Pressense's The Ancient World and Christianity (Eng. trans.) ; Vigouroux's La Bible et les Decouvertes modernes^ iii. — " On Primi- tive Monotheism ; " Eawlinson's Tract on " The Early Prevalence of Monotheistic Beliefs," in Present Day Tracts (No. 11), etc. NOTE G. THE ANTIQUITY OF MAN AND GEOLOGICAL TIME. In illustration of the tendency in recent science greatly to restrict the period formerly claimed for man's antiquity, the following passages may be cited from an able article on the Ice Age in The Edinburgh Review for April 1892, based on Dr. Wright's Ice Age in N. America, and its bearings on the Antiquity of Man (1890). "The Falls of Niagara," says this writer, "indeed constitute of them- selves, in Dr. Wright's apt phrase, ' a glacial chronometer.' Much trouble has been bestowed upon its accurate rating ; and repeated trigonometrical surveys since 1842 afford so sure a basis for calculation that serious error in estimating, from the amount of work done, the time consumed in doing it, need no longer be apprehended. . . . The average rate of reces- sion, arrived at through careful weighing of these and other analogous facts, is iive feet per annum, or nearly a mile in a thousand years. Hence from seven to eight thousand years have elapsed since the foam of Niagara rose through the air at Queenston ; and the interval might even be shortened by taking into account some evidences of pre-glacial erosion by a local stream, making it probable that from the whirlpool downward the cutting of the gorge proceeded more rapidly than it does now. The date of the close of the Glacial Epoch in the United States can scarcely then be placed earlier than 6000 B.C. . . . Their testimony does not stand alone. . . . Pre-glacially, it (the Missis- sippi) followed a wide bend from Minneapolis to Fort Snelling ; now it- flows straight across the intervening eight miles to its junction with the Minnesota. On its way it leaps the Falls of St. Anthony ; and the rate of their retreat since 1680, exactly determined from the observation of Father Hennequin, proves them to be about eight thousand three hundred years old. This second glacial timepiece accordingly, which, owing to its more southerly position was started earlier than the first, gives sub- stantially the same reading. . . . The ravines and cascades of Ohio, studied by Dr. Wright, agree with the two great Falls in giving a com- paratively recent overthrow of the ice regime. The unworn condition of the glacial deposits, the sharpness of glacial groovings, above all, the insignificant progress made by the silting up of glacial lakes, testify as well, and in some cases quite definitely, to a short lapse of time. ■ NOTES TO LECTURE V. 505 But if the Ice Age in America terminated — as we seem bound to •iduiit — less than ten thousand years ago, so, beyond question, did the Ice Age in Europe. There is no possibility of separating the course of glacial events in each continent. The points of agreement are too many ; the phenomena too nearly identical in themselves and in their sequence. Elevation and depression of continents, the formation, retreat, and second advance of the ice-sheet, the accompaniment of its melting by tremendous floods, the extermination of the same varieties of animals, the appearance and obliteration of Palaeolithic man, all preserved identical mutual relations in the Old and New Worlds. . . . The point has an important bearing upon the vexed question of the antiquity of man," etc. — Edinburgh Review, April 1892, pp. 315-319. The same view was advocated by Mr. P. F. Kendall in a paper pre- pared by Mr. Gray and himself on " The Cause of the Ice Age," read in the Geological Section of the British Association, August 4th, 1892. He said : " Another fact of great importance bearing upon this question was the exceedingly recent date of the glacial period. It was the custom of geologists not long ago to talk about the glacial period as perhaps a quarter of a millic>n years ago, or, at all events, to make a very liberal use of thousands and hundreds of thousands of years. But now it was found that all the physical evidence was in favour of a very recent departure of the ice. They could, for instance, put the date of the commencement of the great cut of the Niagara Falls at the close of the glacial period, and other like evidence in America pointed clearly to the recency of the departure of the ice." — Scotsman Report, August 5th. The remainder of the paper was an examination of the theories of the late Dr. Croll, Dr. Ball, and Mr. Warren Upham, and the exposition by the authors of a theory of their own connected with the variability in the heat of the sun. Sir Archibald Geikie, in his President's Address at the same meeting of the British Association, while himself putting in a plea for longer periods on the ground of the geological record, grants that the recent drift of physical science has been enormously to reduce the unlimited drafts on time formerly made by geologists. Lord Kelvin " was in- clined, when first dealing with the subject, to believe that from a review of all the evidence then available, some such period as one hundred million years ago would embrace the whole geological history of the globe. . . . But physical inquiry continued to be pushed forward with regard to the early history and antiquity of the earth. Further con- sideration of the influence of tidal rotation in retarding the earth's rotation, and of the sun's rate of cooling, led to sweeping reductions of the time allowable for the evolution of the planet. The geologist found himself in the plight of Lear when his bodyguard of one hundred knights was cut down. 'What need you five-and-twenty, and ten or five?' de- mands the inexorable physicist, as he remorselessly strikes slice after slice from his allowance of geological time. Lord Kelvin is willing, I believe, to grant us some twenty millions of years, but Professor Tait would have us content with less than ten millions." — Report of Address. One argument of Professor Geikie for lengthening the time is the ex- 5o6 NOTES TO LECTURE V. treme slowness witli which, on the evolution hypothesis, the changes in species have been brought about — a very distinct petitio princijni. It is worth while in this connection to note his admission : "So, too, with the plants and the higher animals which still survive. Some forms have become extinct, but few or none which remain display any transitional gradations into new species." Professor Tait's own words are : " I daresay many of you are ac- quainted with the speculations of Lyell and others, especially of Darwin, who tell us that even for a comparatively brief portion of recent geological history three hundred millions of years will not suffice. — OHgin of Species, 1859, p. 287. We say : So much the worse for geology as at present understood by its chief authorities ; for, as you will presently see, physical considerations from various independent points of view render it utterly impossible that more than ten or fifteen millions of years can be granted "—Recent Advances in Physical Science, pp. 167, 168. " From this point of view we are led to a limit of something like ten millions of years as the utmost we can give to geologists for their specula- tions as to the history even of the lowest orders of fossils" (p. 167). See further on this subject Dawson's Origin of the World, and Fossil Men and their Modern Representatives ; Reusch's Nature and the Bible, ii. pp. 265-366 ; an acute little book on Tfie Remote Antiquity of Man, by B. C. Y. (1882), etc. NOTE II. THE CONNECTION OF SIN AND DEATH. RiTSCHL agrees with the modern view in dissolving the connection between human death and sin. Paul, indeed, he grants, affirms this connection ; but the mere fact that this thought was formed by an apostle does not make it a rule for us {RecliL und Ver. pp. 341, 342). An able article appeared in the Revue de ThMogie (Montauban) for July 1882, on " Physical Death and Sin," by M. Charles Ducasse, which may be referred to as in agreement with, and confirmatory of, the posi- tions taken up in the Lecture. The writer speaks of the problem created by the appearance of death in the world before sin. Before the appear- ance of man on the earth, death reigned ; death was the law even of the organic world. He shows that from the first death entered into the Divine plan for the lower creation — is implied in what the Bible says of the reproduction of plants and animals, in the command given to Adam, etc. But he finds no contradiction in the thought that a new order of things should enter with man. Man forms part of nature. The roots of his organism penetrate into the past of other beings, and of the material world. But is man only a superior animal ? Does not a new kingdom appear in him ? The terminating point of the organic world, is he not equally the point of departure of the world of spirit, of reason, of morality ? He is the bond of union between the world of nature and the Divine world. Why, then, should it not have been precisely his NOTES TO LECTURE V. 507 vocation to spiritualise matter, and lead it up to the conquest of new attributes ? What hinders us from affirming that man was placed here to acquire corporeal immortality, and that if he had not sinned, he would have been able to graft eternal life in his body on changeable and transient matter ? This view, he thinks, agrees with both Scripture and science. Impartial science brings out the almost complete identity of our organism with that of the animals, but it establishes not less de- cisively the originality of our mental being, the superiority of our faculties of reason. The human kingdom constitutes in its eyes a kingdom by itself. There is, then, nothing improbable in the supposition that originally and in the plan of God the conditions of death for man were different from those for animals. The actual deatli of man would still in this view be the consequence of his sin ; and this is in full accord with the Biblical teaching. See also a suggestive treatment of this subject in Dr. Matheson's Can the Old Faith Live with the New ? pp. 206-218. NOTES TO LECTUKE VI. NOTE A. THE DOCTRINE OF PRE-EXISTENCE. The more recent theology admits the application of the notion of pre- existence to Christ in the New Testament, but explains it out of current Jewish modes of thought on this subject. See on this Harnack's I)og- mengescMchte, i. pp. 89-93, 710-719 ; Baldensperger's Das Selbsthewusstsein Jesu, pp. 85-92 (2nd edition) ; Bornemann's Unterricht im Chrutenthum^ pp. 92-96, etc. According to these writers, the conception of pre- existence was a current one in the Rabbinical schools and in apocalyptic literature. Not only distinguished persons, as Adam, Enoch, Moses, but distinguished objects, as the tabernacle, the temple, the tables of the law, were figured as having had heavenly arche- types, i.e. as pre-existent. Various causes are assigned for this mode of representation : — 1. There is the desire to express the inner worth of a valued object in distinction from its inadequate empirical form, which leads to the essence being hypostatised, and raised above space and time (Harnack). 2. There is the conversion of an " end " into a " cause " — this specially in the case of persons (the Messiah), peoples (Israel), a collective body (the Church). "Where something which appears later was apprehended as the end of a series of dispositions, it was not unfrequently hypostatised, and made prior to these arrangements in point of time ; the conceived end was placed in a kind of real existence before the means through which it was destined to be realised on earth, as an original cause of them."— Harnack, pp. 89, 90. 3. There is the thought of predestination, which leads to an ideal pre-existence being realistically conceived as an actual one (Baldens - perger). This category, existing in Jewish circles, was, it is thought, simply taken over and applied to Christ, believed in as the Messiah, risen and exalted to heaven. In this way, Harnack thinks, the first Christians " went beyond the expressions developed out of the Messianic conscious- ness of Jesus Himself upon His Person, and sought notionally and speculatively to grasp the worth and absolute significance of His Person " NOTES TO LECTURE VI. 509 (p. 90).^ " The thought of pre-existence," says Bornemann, " was not supernaturally communicated to the apostles, nor was formed for the first time by Paul, nor generally was unusual in that time ; but we have to do here with a self-evident application to Jesus of an attribute already firmly established in Judaism as belonging to the Messiah." — Unterricht, p. 93. In short, the predicate of pre-existence was only one of several ways which the early Church took to express its sense of the abidini^ worth and felt mystery of the Person of Jesus. Bornemann mentions three of these — 1. The supernatural birth; 2. The thought of pre- existence ; 3. The incarnation of the eternal Divine Word of Revelation — " ideas," he says, " subsisting independently of each other, and alongside of each other, as distinct but disparate attempts to ground the mystery of the life of Jesus in its Divine origin " (p. 92). It appears from this that the application of the category of pre- existence to Jesus was a mere deduction of faith on the part of the first disciples — the application to Him, as Bornemann says, of one of " the religious and philosophical notions and forms of * Vorstellung ' generally current in that time," — and is therefore of no normative value for the Church to-day. I presume that not one of the writers I have quoted holds that Christ really pre-existed as the apostles thought He did. Before we accept this view, we would require to be satisfied of several things. 1. That this Babbinical mode of representation was really so widely current as is alleged, and that it was indeed the source from which the apostles derived their belief in Christ's eternal pre-existence. 2. That this belief had not its origin in very distinct utterances of Christ Himself, proceeding from the depths of His Divine self-knowledge (John viii. 58, xviii. 5, etc.). 3. That there is a true analogy between the New Testament concep- tion of Christ's pre-existence and this Rabbinical notion. The Jewish notion, according to Harnack, was that " the earthly things pre-exist Avith God just as they appear on earth, with all the material properties of their being" (p. 710). They do not exist eternally — at least the Law (which was exalted most highly of all) did not (two thousand years before the creation of the world, the Rabbis said). But Christ (1) exists from eternity ; (2) as a Divine Person with the Father ; (3) one in nature and glory with the Father ; (4) His Divine nature is distinguished from His humanity which He assumed in time ; (5) His appearance on earth is the result of a voluntary act of self-abnegation and love— an ethical act. It is only confusing things that differ to pretend that the Rabbinical absurdities alluded to explain a Christian doctrine like this. 4. Many special facts testify against the sufficiency of this explanation. (1) The support sought for it in the New Testament is of the most flimsy character, e.g. Gal. iv. 26 ; Heb. xii. 22 ; Rev. xxi. 2. (2) It is admitted that " the representations of a pre-existent Messiah in Judaism were in no way very widespread " (Harnack, p. 89), and that 1 On Harnack's distinction between the Jewish and Hellenistic forms of this notion, see the criticisms by Baldensperger in his Das Selbsthewusstsein Jesu, 2ud ed. p. 89. 5TO NOTES TO LECTURE VI. they do not appear in all the New Testament writings. In truth, the writings in which they do appear are not specially the Jewish ones, hut those in which scholars liave thought they detected most traces of Hellenistic influence. (3) It is plain that in the writings in which they do appear, these Jewish modes of thought were not dominant. Paul, e.g., regards believers as eternally chosen and foreordained in Christ to salvation ; but he does not attribute to them any such pre-existence as he ascribes to Christ. On this hypothesis, he ought to have done so. I cannot therefore accept this new theory as adequate to the facts. Nor do I believe that the apostles were left simply to their own gropings and imaginings in this and other great matters of the Christian faith. I take it as part of the Christian view that they were guided by the Spirit of Revelation into the truth which they possessed, and that their teachings laid the foundations of doctrine for the Church in all time. NOTE B. PHILO AND THE FOURTH GOSPEL. The most diverse opinions prevail as to the extent to which the Fourth Gospel and other books of the New Testament have been influenced by the Alexandrian philosophy — some, like Harnack and Weiss, denying its presence altogether ; others, like Pfleiderer, seeing its influence in John, Hebrews, Ephesians, and Colossians, etc. It will put the matter in a clearer light if we look briefly, first, at Philo's own philosophy, and at the sources from which it was derived. The three main sources of Philo's philosophy were Platonism, Stoicism, and the Old Testament. 1. From Plato, the chief contribution was the theory of ideas— of an ideal or noetic world in the Divine mind, after the pattern of which this visible world was made, (cf. the Timceus). It is to be observed, however, that there is not the slightest indication in Plato that this idea of the world was conceived of as a personal agent, or as anything else than an attribute of the Divine mind, in which it resides like a plan in the mind of an architect.^ 2. The indebtedness of Philo to Plato is very obvious ; but it is not from Plato that Philo derives the term Logos. He obtains this term from the Stoics. By the Logos, however, the Stoics as little as Plato understood a distinct hypostasis in the sphere of the Divine — a second Divine Being. The Logos, with the Stoics, is simply the Divine Eeason itself; that eternal Divine Reason which is immanent in the universe, and in substance is one with it (fire). There was a further doctrine which the Stoics held, however, whicli is of great importance for the understanding of Philo. Together with their fundamentally pantheistic 1 The "ideas," however, are also regarded as the immanent forms or essences of things, which become what they are through "participation" in them, — a point of contact with the Stoical doctrine noted below. NOTES TO LECTURE VI. 511 conception of the all-pervading Divine Reason, they held that this Reason develops or manifests itself in a multitude of powers or forces, called also >.6yoi. This is the famous Stoical doctrine of the "Koyot vKipuoLTiKdi — the Logos -seeds or powers (hwui^iii) — which develop themselves in particular things. The theory is very different from Plato's ; yet the step was not great to identify these seed-like ^.oyot of the Stoics — the immanent rational principles of things — with the " ideas " of Plato, which also in their own way were active powers or principles. Here, then, we have another premiss of the theory of Philo. Philo takes over this doctrine of the Stoics bodily, — identifies their active "hoyoi with the " ideas " of Plato ; identifies them, further, with the Old Testament angels and Greek demons, — and gathers them up, finally, as the Stoics also did, into the unity of the one Logos. 3. But Philo went a step further. It is the peculiarity of his theory that this Logos is distinguished from God Himself as the absolute and highest Being — is hypostatised — projected, as it were, from the Divine mind, and viewed, though in a very wavering and fluctuating way, as a ])ersonal agent.^ Now, where did Philo get this last conception ? Not from Platonic or Stoical philosophy — not from Greek philosophy at all. He got it from the same source whence he derived his Immovable Monotheism, his firm faith in Divine Providence, his doctrine of angels, etc. , — from the Old Testament. The Old Testament also has its distinc- tion between God in His hidden and incommunicable essence, and God as revealed ; and has its names for this Revelation-side of God's nature (His name, glory, face, word, angel of Jehovah, etc. Of. Oehler's Theol. of the Old Testament, pp. 181-196 ; Newman's Avians, pp. 92, 153). There is, in particular, the doctrine of the (personified) Divine Wisdom in the Book of Proverbs. These germs did not lie without development on the soil of Judaism, as seen in the curious doctrine of the Memra, or word of Jehovah, in the Targums (cf. Edersheim's Jesus the Messiah, i. pp. 47, 48 ; ii. pp. 659-664 — Appendix on "Philo of Alexandria and Rabbinic Theology ") — the Memra being a distinct hypostasis whose name is sub- stituted for Jehovah's ; and that they were developed on Greek soil is evidenced by the apocryphal Book of Wisdom, in which we have, as Schiirer points out, nearly all the elements of Philo's doctrine already present {Hist, of Jewish People, Div. ii. vol. iii. p. 232). We cannot err, therefore, in attributing Philo's doctrine of the hypostatic Logos to the same Old Testament source. Once this is granted, many things are clear. The predicates with which Philo clothes his Logos—those of Creator, High-Priest, Archangel, In- tercessor, etc.— are plainly drawn over upon it from the Old Testament. But it is also clear how Philo's doctrine should become in a certain way a preparation for the gospel. Comparing his view with that of the Gospel of John, we see indeed— notwithstanding assertions to the con- trary—a fundamental contrast. The evangelist has his feet on a fact which he seeks to interpret ; Philo moves throughout in the region of 1 It is a point on which opinions differ as to whether Philo's Logos was conceived of as a personal agent— was hypostatised (see Drummond's Philo of Alexandria^ which upholds the negative) ; but the above seems the preferable view. 512 NOTES TO LECTURE VI. speculation. An incarnation would conflict with the first principles of his philosophy. The whole substance of the doctrine in the Fourth Gospel is different from Philo's speculations. Even in their respective con- cejDtions of the Logos, John and Philo are at variance ; for Philo means by Logos the internal Reason, never the spoken word ; while John means the word uttered, spoken. His view is in accordance with the Palestinian, not with the Greek conception. I cannot therefore but agree with Harnack when he says : " John and Philo have little more in common than the name" {Dogmengeschichte^ i. p. 85). Even the term Logos does not occur after the Prologue. But suppose the resemblances had been greater than they are, would this necessarily have been to the prejudice of the Gospel ? I cannot see it ; for it has just been shown that the one peculiar thing in Philo's theory,— that which brings it into relation with the Gospel,— viz. its hypostatisation of the Logos, is pre- cisely that feature which he did not get from Greek philosophy, but from the Old Testament. It was a very different thing for one whose mind was stored, as Philo's was, with the facts of the Old Testament Revelation, to come in contact with the suggestive teachings of Plato, from what it would have been for another with no such preparation (cf. Newman's Avians, pp. 91, 92). Philo, working with these ideas, struck out a theory which is not unchristian, but goes forward rather to meet the Christian view, and find its completion in it. That there is a Divine Reason in the universe, and that this universal Logos is none other than He who is the life and light of men, and who in the fulness of time became flesh, — this is not less Christian teaching because Philo in some respects was in accord with it. John, if we assume him to have heard of this doctrine of Philo's, had no reason to reject it so far as it went. It harmonised with the truth he held, and furnished a fitting form in which to convey that truth. Whether even this much of Alexandrian influence is present in the Gospel, it is not easy to determine. Meanwhile, it is only doing justice to this great Jewish thinker to see in him an important link in the providential preparation for Christian conceptions— even if we do not go further, and speak of him, with Pfleiderer, as " the last Messianic prophet of Israel, the Alex- andrian John the Baptist, who stretches out a hand to John the Evangelist" {Reli(jionsj)hilosophie, iii. p. 176, Eng. trans.). On Philo's philosophy, and his relation to the Gospel, the works of Siegfried, Drummond, Zeller, Schiirer, Edersheim, Harnack, Pfleiderer, Hatch {Hibhert Lectures), Martineau (Seat of Authority), Godet, Dorner, etc., may be consulted. NOTE C. THE RESURRECTION OF CHRIST AND THE REALITY OF HIS DIVINE CLAIM. If the premises of the Christian view are correct as to Christ's claim to be the Son of God, and as to the connection of sin with death, it was NOTES TO LECTURE VI. 5131 impossible that He, the Holy One, should be holden of death. The Prince of Life must overcome death. His resurrection is the pledge that death shall yet be swallowed up in victory. On the other hand, the denial of Christ's resurrection leads to a sub- version of His whole claim as unfounded.^ If historically real, the resurrection of Christ is a confirmation of Christ's entire claim ; if it did not happen, this alone negates it. The resurrection is thus an integral part of the Christian view. In this respect also — as well as in its bearings on our justification — we may say : "If Christ hath not been raised, your faith is vain ; ye are yet in your sins " (1 Cor. xv. 17).^ It is only what might have been anticipated, therefore, when we find the advocates of the modern view — those who refuse Christ's claim — emphatic in their denial of the resurrection, and unceasing in their efforts to demolish the evidence of it. It is more surprising to find writers who claim to be upholders of the true Christianity playing fast and loose with this fact of the Gospel, and doing their best to belittle the importance of it for Christian faith. I refer particularly to the attitiide of certain writers of the Ritschlian school. It is extremely doubtful if leading representatives of this school, as Harnack and Wendt, accept the resurrection of Christ in the literal sense at all. Harnack expressly avers that there is no satisfactory historical evidence of the resurrection of Christ. He goes further, and pours contempt on the attempt to find such evidence. He not merely argues — what all will admit — that a faith in Christ based on mere historic evidence is no true faith ; but he scouts the idea of being dependent on historic evidence at all. Such evidence, if we had it, would give us, he thinks, no help. Faith must be perfectly independent of evidence coming to us through the testimony of others. " To believe on the ground of appearances which others have had, is a levity which will always revenge itself through uprising doubt." This is professedly an exaltation of faith ; but it directly becomes apparent that faith is not intended to give us any guarantee of the physical resurrection— that, in truth, this part of Christianity is to be given up. The Christian " has nothing to do with a knowledge of the form in which Christ lives, but only with the conviction that He is the living Lord." The determination of the form was dependent on the widely differing general representations about a future life, resurrection, restora- tion, and glorification of the body, which prevailed at that particular time (see the whole note, Dogmengeschichte, i. pp. 75, 76). Wendt speaks in quite similar terms. Christ's sayings on His own resurrection are interpreted as conveying only the idea that "Jesus would after the briefest delay be awakened from death to the heavenly life with God" ; and the Cliurch misinterpreted them in applying them on the ground of " appearances which were held by them as certain facts of experience 1 On the same principle that in a hypothetical syllogism the denial of the con- sequent leads to the denial of the antecedent. If Christ was the Divine Son, He could not be holden of death. If He was holden of death, His claim to be the Divine Son is refuted. 2 The resurrection has a constitutive place in the Christian view in connection with Redemption ; but into this I do not enter here. 33 514 NOTES TO LECTURE VL to a literal bodily resurrection " {T>ie Lehre Jesu, ii. p. 543). One would like to know how much objective reality Wendt is disposed to attribute to these "appearances." To Hermann also the exaltation of Christ is "a thought of faith," indemonstrable through historical evidence. It is an ill service to name the resurrection to us living to-day as a fact likely to convince unbelievers. "For it is related to us by others" (Verkehr, 2nd edition, p. 239).^ This minimising of the importance of the historical resurrection on the part of Kitschlian writers accords only too well with the general subjectivity of the school. A theory which resolves religion wholly into "judgments of value," or, as Hermann prefers to call them, "thoughts of faith," has clearly no room for an objective fact like the resurrection. A view which lays the whole stress on the impression (Eindruck) pro- duced by Christ's earthly life, has no means of incorporating the resur- rection into itself as a constitutive part of its Christianity. It remains at most a deduction of faith without inner relation to salvation. It is apt to be felt to be a superfluous appendage. It might almost be said to be a test of the adequacy of the view of Christ and His work, taken by any school, whether it is able to take in the resurrection of Christ as a constitutive j)art of it. I cannot therefore but regard the Eitschlian position as virtually a surrender of faith in Christ's resurrection. The attempt to set faith and historical evidence in opposition to each other is one that must fail. Since it is implied in Christ's whole claim that death cannot hold Him, — not merely, as with the Ritschlians, that He has a spiritual life with God, — faith would be involved in insoluble contra- dictions if it could be shown that Christ has not risen ; or, what comes to the same thing, that there is no historical evidence that He has risen. It may be, and is, involved in our faith that He is risen from the dead ; but this faith would not of itself be a sufficient ground for asserting that He had risen, if all historical evidence for the statement were wanting. Faith cherishes the just expectation that, if Christ has risen, there will be historical evidence of the fact ; and were such evidence not forthcoming, it would be driven back upon itself in questioning whether its confidence was not self-delusion. In harmony with this view is the place which the resurrection of Christ holds in Scripture, and the stress there laid upon its historical attestation (1 Cor. xv. 1-19). I cannot enter here into detailed discus- sion of the historical evidence. The empty grave on the third day is a fact securely attested by the earliest traditions. The undoubting faith of the first disciples in the resurrection of their Lord, and in His re- peated appearances to themselves, is also beyond question. Baur and most candid writers acknowledge that something extraordinary must have happened on that third day to lay a basis for this faith, and to change their despair into joyful and triumphant confidence (see Baur's 1 Bornemann is the most explicit on this subject, and seems to hold a literal resurrection. But even he regards it as insoluble whether Christ really appeared in the body to His disciples, or "whether those appearances rested on a miraculous working of the Person of Jesus on the soids of the disciples," i.e. were subjective impressions ; and treats the question as indiflFerent to faith. — Unterricht, p. 85. NOTES TO LECTURE VI, 515 Church History^ i. p, 42, Eng. trans.). Tlie hypothesis of imposture has now no respectable advocates. The idea of a " swoon " finds little sup- port. The " vision-hypothesis," which would reduce the apostles to the level of hysterical women, is inexplicable out of psychological conditions, and has been refuted almost to weariness (see good remarks on it in Beyschlag's Lehen Jesu, in his chapter on the Resurrection, i. pp. 406-450). The attempt to make it appear as if Paul believed only in a visionary appearance of Christ, can hardly convince anybody. In all these discus- sions the alternative invariably comes back to be — conscious imposture, or the reality of the fact. This is the simplest explanation of all of the narratives of the resurrection — that it really took place. As Beyschlag says : " The faith of the disciples in the resurrection of Jesus, which no one denies, cannot have originated, and cannot be explained otherwise than through the fact of the resurrection, through the fact in its full, objective, supernatural sense, as hitherto understood " (p. 440). So long as this is contested, the resurrection remains a problem which the failure of rival attempts at explanation only leaves in deeper darkness. For a good statement and criticism of the various hypotheses, see Schaff's Hist, of the Church, i. pp. 172-186 ; Godet's Defence of the Chris- tian Faith (Eng. trans.), chaps, i. and ii. (against Reville) ; and Christlieb's Moderne Zweifel, Lect. VII. (Eng. trans.). NOTES TO LECTUEE VII. NOTE A. RECENT THEORIES OF THE TRINITY. Some examples may be given of recent theories of the Trinity which seem defective from the Christian point of view. Of these, three classes may be named — I. Speculative Theories, which do not start from the basis of Christian facts, but are the products of a priori deduction. These theories are abstract, speculative, cosmological, with little relation to distinctively Christian interests. The typical example here is Hegel's, in his Religions- philosophie, ii. pp. 223-251. Hegel speaks of an immanent Trinity in God — a Trinity of God's being before or outside of the creation of the world. He does not disdain even the name "persons," — "person, or rather subject,"— speaks of Father, Son, and Spirit. Yet this Trinity is little more than the play of pure thought with itself in the element of highest abstraction : thought eternally distinguishing itself from itself, and as eternally sublating that distinction. The Father is the pure abstract idea ; the Son is the element of particularity in that idea ; the Spirit is the sublation of this in individuality. The distinction is only ideal, does not become real till the passage is made into the actuality of the finite world. Here Hegel is careful to remind us that though in the domain of science the idea is first, in existence it is later — it comes later to consciousness and knowledge (p. 247). This Trinity has therefore no existence prior to the world or independently of it ; it is simply potentiality and basis. [Hegel's own formula for his immanent process is — " God in His eternal universality is this : to distinguish Himself, to determine Himself, to posit another to Himself, and again to annul this distinction — therein to be in Himself, and only through this act of self-production is He Spirit" (p. 237).] The supreme abstraction of all this is very evident. The names of Christian theology are retained, with no agreement in content. What possible resemblance has "the idea in its abstract universality" to the Father in the Christian con- ception ? Yet Hegel's treatment contains many profound and suggestive thoughts. In consonance with this speculative mode of thought are the theories which make the world, or the idea of the world, the mediating factor in the Divine self-consciousness. NOTES TO LECTURE VII, 517 II. Imijersonal Theories, which recognise an immanent distinction in the Godhead, but one only of potencies, of momenta in the Divine life, of modes of existence, therefore not a true personal Trinity. Thus Schelling (whose "potencies," however, become personal later in the \vorld-process),i Rothe, Beyschlag, etc. This view lies near akin to Sabellianism. E.g. Rothe's distinctions of nature, essence, and personality have nothing to do with the Biblical distinctions of Father, Son, and Spirit, which he takes to relate only to the sphere of Revelation. A recent example of this type of theory is afforded by F. A. B. Nitzsch in his Lehrhuch der evangelischen Dogmatik (1892). Nitzsch holds that we are compelled to postulate, not simply a Trinity of Revelation, but a Trinity of essence (ii. p. 442). But it is a Trinity of potencies, principles, modes of subsistence (pp. 439-446), not persons. A Trinity of persons, he thinks, would be Tritheism (p. 444). He grants that the Scripture teaches the personality of the Spirit, in part also of the Logos (pp. 440, 444). But this representation cannot be dogmatically used (p. 444). The personality of the Son lies in the human nature (p. 441), and the Spirit is not a person, but a principle. It is, however, a Divine nature, in the strict sense of the word ; is not to be interchanged with the holy disposition or religiously- elevated state of feeling of man,^ but is con- sidered as an objective, real Divine power, which is essentially equal with God (p. 439). Nevertheless, when we go on to ask what this three- fold mode of subsistence in the Divine nature is, we find it difficult to distinguish it from a Trinity of Revelation. God as Father is God in Himself in distinction from His relation to the world ; the Logos is the Revelation principle in God ; and the Spirit is the principle of the Divine self-communication (pp. 445, 446). Christ is the one in whom this Revelation finds its highest expression ; in this sense He is the Incarnation of the Logos, and has "Godhead." "This expression," he tells us, "is quite in place" (p. 514). It is evident (1) that this so-called ontological Trinity is barely distinguishable from an economical or Sabellian one ; (2) that Christ has not real Godhead— is, in truth, purely man, only the highest organ of Divine Revelation ; and (3) that the Trinitarian doctrine sought to be established is awkward and confused, and has little relation to the scriptural doctrine. It is made to rest primarily on God's relation to the world (p. 442), and not on the facts of Redemption. Its representation of " God in Himself" as the Father has nothing in common with the New ipfleiderer remarks on Schelling's Trinity— "The interpretation of the three potencies by the three persons of the Church's doctrine of the Trinity, and the more than bold exposition of dogmatic formulae and passages of Scripture, we may pass by as a mere hors d'ceuvre, without value for philosophy. Orthodoxy could feel no gratitude to our philosopher for his deduction of a triple Divine personality which only began with the creation, and was only to be fully realised at the con- clusion of the world-process. The trinity arrived at is that of Montanism or Sabellianism, rather than that of the Church."— Religionsphilosophie, iii. p. 21 (Eng. trans.). A good criticism of Beyschlag's Trinitarian view may be seen in Dorner, Syst. of Doct. iii. pp. 258-260. spfleiderer explains the Holy Spirit rationalistically as "the arrival of the Divine reason at supremacy in our hQd,xV—ReUgionsphilosophie, iii. p. 305. 5i8 NOTES TO LECTURE VII. Testament idea of Fatherhood. Then the personality is made to reside only in the first principle. God as Father is personal ; the other two potencies (Logos and Spirit) are not personal. Further, in this Trinity there is no room for the Son. The Divine second principle is named " Logos," not " Son," — the Son comes into being with Jesus Christ. We have, therefore, the contradiction of an Eternal Father without an Eternal Son ; the Logos is not the Son of the Trinitarian formula. The first and third members in this formula are truly Divine — one personal, the other impersonal ; the middle member is personal, but not truly Divine. The ordinary doctrine of the Trinity may be difficult, but it certainly is more coherent and less contradictory than this of Nitzsch's, which seems to originate rather in a desire to keep in touch with ecclesiastical phraseology, than in any real need arising out of its author's Christology or Pneumatology. Dr. Dorner is a powerful defender of the Godhead of Christ, yet it is doubtful whether in his later views he has not surrendered the only basis on which this doctrine can be consistently maintained. In his History of the Doctrine of the Person of Christ, Dr. Dorner goes on the view (or seems to do so) of a Trinity of personal distinctions (cf. e.g. his remarks on Hegel's theory in vol. v. p. 150). In his System of Doctrine, on the other hand, he abandons this ground, and falls back on a Trinity of impersonal modes — momenta in the constitution of the one Divine Personality. The Hypostases are to be thought of as " the eternal points of mediation of the Absolute Divine Personality" — as "intermediate between attributes and Egoity and Personality" (i. pp. 382, 383, Eng. trans.) ; as " not of themselves and singly personal," but as having " a share in the one Divine Personality in their own manner" (p. 448). As against a view which would make the Divine Hypostases "three severed subjects, with separate self- consciousness, and divided self- determination," this has perhaps its truth. But Dr. Dorner evidently so regards these momenta of the Divine Personality that neither is the Father a Person, nor the Son a Person, nor the Spirit a Person ; but the three constitute together the One Personality, or Divine self-consciousness. There is not such a distinction between Father and Son as could be expressed by the pronouns I and Thou. The strained character of this construction is seen in the attempt to retain the names Father and Son for these internal modes of the Divine self-consciousness. It is not, it is to be observed, the completed Personality who is the Father, and the historical Christ who is the Son ; but Father is the name for the first "point of mediation," Son for the second point. Spirit for the third, in the one self-consciousness. But how, it may be asked, can an impersonal moment in a process be described as Father, or how can an impersonal principle be described as Son ? In accordance with this view. Dr. Dorner does not admit that a personal Divine Being became incarnate in Christ, but only that a principle incorporated itself with the humanity derived from the virgin (iii. p. 163). "God as Logos, as that special eternal mode of being of the Deity, unites Himself perfectly and indissolubly with Jesus, and thus may be said to have become man in Him, because as NOTES TO LECTURE VI L 519 Logos He has His being, His perfect Eevelation in this man, and has become a living unity with this man" (iii. p. 303). Christ is not simply human or simply Divine, but the Divine and human natures coalesce to form a " God-human Ego " or personality (pp. 308, 309). Here, again, one cannot but feel that Dr. Dorner's theory leaves the Divinity ot Christ in an exceedingly ambiguous position. He is constantly objecting to the orthodox doctrine that it imperils the integrity of the humanity of Christ— makes it unlike ours. But what of his own theory of Christ's peculiarly constituted Personality? Either it must be held that this union of the Divine principle with His humanity is akin in character to that which takes place in every believer— in which case his ground is taken away for asserting a sole and exclusive Divinity for Christ ; or it ceases to be a truly human person (as, on the other hand, it is not a Divine Person), and can only be thought of as a tertium quid, a peculiar product of the union of Divine and human factors. The Church doctrine at least avoids this ambiguity by saying boldly — it is a Divine Person who appears in humanity,— one who submits Himself to the conditions of humanity, yet in origin and essence is eternal and Divine. It is difficult to see how, on Dr. Dorner's view, Christ should be a truly Divine being ; but if He is so— and there can be no mistake about Dr. Dorner's earnestness of conviction on the subject — the con- clusion cannot be avoided that, as in the theories of Eothe and Beyschlag, a new Divine Person has since the Incarnation been added to the Godhead. There was but one Divine Personality before— not the Father, but the one God, constituted through the three " modes " ; there is now a second, as the result of the Incarnation of one of these modes — true God and Man. Surely the mere statement of such a view is sufficient to show its untenableness. III. Neo-Sahellian Theories, which resolve the Trinity into aspects of the Divine in the process of its self-manifestation or Eevelation. The ground is abandoned of an immanent or ontological Trinity, and the names Father, Son, and Spirit are taken but as expressions for the phases of the Divine self- manifestation in nature or grace. Schleiermacher inclines to this view (Der christ. Glauhe, sects. 170-172), and we have seen that theories like Eothe's and Nitzsch's tend to pass over into it. The Eitschlian theologians have no alternative but to adopt it. It is a view which will always have a certain popularity, seeming, as it does, to evade metaphysical subtleties, while giving a plausible, easily apprehended interpretation of the Trinitarian formula. Its simplicity, however, is all upon the surface. The moment it is touched with the finger of criticism, its inadequacy is revealed. The forms of these Neo-Sabellian theories are as varied as the minds that produce them. We may distinguish, first, certain popular forms. The old Sabellianism confined itself to the stadia of Eevelation (the Father in the Law, the Son in the Incarnation, the Spirit in the Church). In modern times we have a wide variety of triads — God as Creator, Eedeemer, and Sanctifier ; God in Creation (Father), in Christ (Son), in the inward fellowship of believers (Spirit) ; God in nature (Father), 520 NOTES TO LECTURE VII. in history (Son), in conscience (Spirit) ; God in Himself (Father), as revealed (Son), as the principle of inward communion (Spirit), etc. A common feature in nearly all these triads is the identification of God as Creator with the Father ; or again, God in His absolute, self-enclosed being, is viewed as the Father. But it cannot be too often repeated that it is not peculiarly as Creator that God, in the Christian view, is revealed as the Father. Creation is not the Eevelation of God's Fatherhood. It is in Christ only that the Fatherhood of God is perfectly revealed (Matt. xi. 27). We know the Father through the Son. Still less does Fatherhood, in the Christian sense, denote God in the depths of His absoluteness. The truth in these views is that the Son is the principle of Eevelation in the Godhead ; that the Father, apart from the Son, is undisclosed and unrevealed. But that to which the Son leads us back in God is a true Fatherhood of knowledge, love, and will. The second criticism to be made on these theories is that they do not give us a truly Divine Trinity of Father, Son, and Spirit. Whether the Son is identified with the " world," or with " humanity," or with " Christ," the second member of the Trinity is not Divine as the first and third are. It is not God who is the Son, but the (non-Divine) Son reveals God. This, it may be observed, is a principal distinction between the ancient and the modern Sabellianisms. The old Sabellianism sought to hold by a real Godhead of Christ, though it failed in doing so. It was the same God, according to it, who, in the old dispensation, revealed Himself as Father, who afterwards became incarnate as Son, and later was manifested as the Holy Spirit in the Church. The defects of this view were glaring ; for if the phases were, as the Sabellians held, successive, then the one God ceased to be Father before He became Son, and had ceased to be Son before He became Spirit. Then Father and Son are terms without meaning. But, further, in ceasing to be Son, the Divine must be supposed to have left the humanity of Christ. Thus the reality of the Incarnation is again denied.^ We have only a temporary union of the Godhead with the man Christ Jesus. In the Neo-Sabellianisms, on the other hand, the Person of Christ is regarded as Divine only in a figurative and improper way, i.e. as the bearer of a Divine Eevelation, or in an ethical sense ; and the successive phases of the Divine self-manifestation are not regarded as necessarily sublating each other ; i.e. God remains Father, while revealed as Son, while manifested as Spirit. Kaftan's view of the Trinity in his I)as Wesen der christ. Religion does not rise above a Trinity of Eevelation or manifestation. "The Christian believes in God," he says, "the supra- terrestrial Lord of the world, who was from the beginning, and is in eternity. He believes in the Godhead of Jesus, the historical Founder of our religion, in whom God has revealed Himself, through whom God has entered into that relation to mankind which from eternity He had in view. He believes in a power of the Divine Spirit in the history of mankind which, since the appearance of Jesus Christ, and more precisely since His resurrection 1 Or reduced to a mere theophany. Ancient Sabellianism spoke of an absorption even of the humanity of Christ. NOTES TO LECTURE VJI. 521 from the dead, has come to its perfection in Christendom, and which transplants the man, who allows himself to be possessed by it, into the blessed fellowship of the Divine life. But still it is one God in whom he believes. . . . How can this be otherwise brought to a single expression than by designating the Christian faith in God as the faith in a three-one God. The Christian has and knows God only through Christ in the Holy Spirit" (p. 388). "Understood in a Christian sense, God is personal Spirit ; as such we find Him in the historical personal life of Jesus Christ ; as such we believe in Him ruling in history ; this is the signification of the Christian faith in the three-one God" (p. 390, first edition). This is a much higher position than the ordinary Ritschlian one [note the emphatic assertion of Christ's resurrection from the dead, and the connection of this with the mission of the Spirit]. The crucial point is the affirmation of Christ's Divinity. Now, what- ever this means to Kaftan, it is certain it does not mean the entrance into time of a pre-existing Divine Being ; nor would he allow the in- ference to a personal distinction in the Godhead as the ground of the Incarnation (p. 391). His Trinitarian doctrine, therefore, does not mean more than that God has a super-earthly mode of being, that He has revealed Himself historically in Jesus Christ, and that He has wrought since as a spiritual power in the hearts of men. He refuses, indeed, to admit that this is a mere economical Trinity. The Revelation, he says, expresses the essence. But Sabellianism never denied that there was that in God which determined the modes of His self -revelation, or that to this extent they expressed His nature. Kaftan's midway position is untenable. Either he must deal earnestly with the "Godhead" of Christ, which he so strenuously maintains, and then he can hardly avoid moving back on personal distinctions ; or holding to his modal view of the Trinity, he will find it increasingly difficult to regard Christ as truly Divine. NOTE B. DR. MARTINEAU AS A TRINITARIAN. Dr. Martineau advocating Trinitarianism is a veritable Saul among tlie prophets. Yet this is the drift of his striking essay (first published as late as 1886) on " A Way Out of the Trinitarian Controversy." The object of the essay is to find a way of reconciling the differences of Unitarians and Trinitarians, which Dr. Martineau thinks might be accomplished if parties only came better to understand each other. He says with great truth, " Religious doctrine may be only theory to the critic, but it is the expression of fact to the believer— fact infinite and ever present, the vital breath of every moment, deprived of which the soul must gasp and die. ... It is from the depth of such natures that theology and churches arise ; and if you would harmonise them when they seem discordant, you must descend into the depths ; you must feel their truth ere you criticise their errors, and appreciate their difference 522 NOTES TO LECTURE VIL before you can persuade them that they are one. ... To feel charity towards a sin, you must understand the temptation ; towards a sorrow, you must know its depth ; towards an erring creed, you must appreciate its meaning and its ground " (Essays, ii. pp. 526, 527). In this spirit he aims at setting forth what he conceives to be the truth about the Trinity. The intention is excellent, but the success of the attempt must be pronounced doubtful. It is, however, exceedingly interesting as coming from Dr. Martineau. For his thought leads him to recognise a certain real Trinitarian distinction in God ; and, so far as one can judge, he does not object even to Trinitarians speaking of these distinctions as in a sense personal. The gist of his view is expressed in the following passages : " God then, as He exists in Himself ere He at all appears, — God, alone with the void, — God as a still presence, — a starless night, a dumb immensity of intellect, is intended by the First Person in the received creed. Let now the silence be broken, let the thought burst into expression, fling out the poem of creation, evolving its idea in the drama of history, and reflecting its own image in the soul of man ; then this manifested phase of the Divine existence is the Son. . . . The one fundamental idea by which the two personalities are meant to be distinguished is simply this — that the first is God in His primeval essence, — infinite meaning without finite indications ; the second is God speaking out in phenomena and fact, and leaving His sign whenever anything comes up from the deep of things, or merges back again. . . . Eespecting the Third Person in the Trinity, and the doctrine of the Holy Spirit . . . the separation of His personality from the others, as not proper to be merged in them, is founded on a feeling deep and true, viz. that the human spirit is not a mere part of nature. . . . We are persuaded of something diviner within us than this — akin in freedom, in power, in love, to the supreme Mind Himself. In virtue of this prerogative, we have to be otherwise provided for, in our highest life, than the mere products of creative order; we need, not control, simply to be imposed and obeyed, but living communion, like with like, spirit with spirit. To open this communion, to bring this help and sympathy, to breathe on the fading consciousness of our heavenly aflinity, and make us one with the Father and the Son, is the function, truly of a (|uite special kind, reserved in the doctrine of the Church for the Holy Ghost. What God is in Himself ; what He is as manifested in the universe and history, brought to a focus in the drama of Redemption ; what He is in communion with our inner spirit : these are the three points of view denoted by the ' Persons ' of the Trinity " (pp. 332, 334, 335). The " Eternal Sonship " he connects with the doctrine of eternal creation. The most paradoxical part of the essay is where he seeks to prove that the Unitarians, while imagining they were worshipping the "Father," have all the while been worshipping the "Son" — that the Father "is really absent from the Unitarian Creed " (p. 536). After the remarks in last note, it is not necessary to say much in criticism of this theory. It is, after all, only a modal theory — the sub- stitution of " phases " and " points of view " for the orthodox " Persons." AZOTES TO LECTURE VII, 523 The distinction of " Father " and " Son " is that of the hidden and the revealed God ; and the " Son " has His raison d'itre in the existence of a world. There is no room for a special Incarnation. The "Son" is manifested in Jesus not otherwise than He is manifested in all history — only in higher (or highest) degree. But it has already been pointed out that this identification of the "Father" with God in Himself, "dormant potency," "still presence," "dumb immensity of intellect," has no resemblance to the Christian idea of the Father. Dr. Martineau goes here on an altogether wrong track. His theory does not express the Christian facts. NOTE TO LECTUEE VIII. NOTE A. THE GERM THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION. This subtle theory of justification, according to which the manifoldly imperfect believer is accepted on the ground of his germinal holiness, — " for in the first moment," as Schleiermacher says, " the whole develop- ment is implicitly given " (p. 105), — is not without many advocates. Its phraseology is found in some who are far from wishing to remove the ground of acceptance from the doing and suffering of Christ ; and it finds favour with others who reject this objective ground, and need another explanation. Dr. M'Leod Campbell finds this view in Luther, whose doctrine he expounds thus — " secondly, because this excellent condition of faith is in us but a germ— a grain of mustard-seed — a feeble dawn, God, in imputing it as righteousness, has respect unto that of which it is the dawn — of which, as the beginning of the life of Christ in us, it is the promise, and in which it shall issue" {Nat. of Atonement^ p. 34 (4th ed.)). There is no doubt that some of Luther's expressions in the Commentari/ on Galatians give colour to this statement. E.g. " Wherefore Christ appre- hended by faith, and dwelling in the heart, is the true Christian righteousness, for the which God counteth us righteous, and giveth us eternal life" (on ii. 16). "We conclude, therefore, upon these words, 'It was imputed to him for righteousness,' that righteousness indeed beginneth through faith, and by the same we have the first-fruits of the Spirit ; but because faith is weak, it is not made perfect without God's imputation. Wherefore faith beginneth righteousness, but imputation maketh it perfect unto the day of Christ. . . . For these two things work Christian righteousness ; faith in the heart, which is a gift of God, and assuredly believeth in Christ ; and also that God accepteth this imperfect faith for perfect righteousness, for Christ's sake, in whom I have begun to believe " (on iii. 6). No one can doubt, however, taking the general drift of the Commentary, that in Luther's view the sole objective ground of the sinner's pardon and acceptance is the cross and righteousness of Christ. In a similar way Martensen expresses himself — "For faith is like the grain of mustard-seed, a small, insignificant, but fructifying seed NOTE TO LECTURE VIII. 525" corn, which contains within it the fulness of a whole future. In His gracious contemplation God beholds in the seed corn the future fruit of blessedness ; in the pure will, the realised ideal of freedom " {Dogmatics, p. 392). Yet Martensen is emphatic in declaring — "The evangelical Church teaches that Christ alone, received by faith, is the Righteousness of man ; and thus she leads man back from what is imperfect and multifarious to One who is Himself perfection ; she brings him back from his wanderings in the desert to the pure Fountain where freedom springs from grace ; to the holy centre where God looks upon man, not in the light of the temporal and finite, but in the light of Christ's eternity and perfection" (p. 393). There is no question of the truth of the view in itself that, as Martensen further says, " Justifying faith cannot possibly exist in the soul in a dead or merely stationary condition, but that, like the living, fruit-bearing seed corn, it contains within itself a mighty germinating power which must necessarily beget a holy development of life" (p. 393), and that God sees in this germinal holiness all that is to proceed from it, and even, if we please, imputes to the believer anticipatively the yet future result. But confusion is introduced if we confound or exchange this with the sinner's justification. The imputation in question is not in order to acceptance, but is a mode of contemplating the fruition of holiness in 'persons already accepted. It is an act of the Divine complacency in and towards believers already justified and adopted on the sole and all- suflScient ground of Christ's work done on their behalf. This view, translated into their own peculiar phraseology, is naturally the one adopted by idealistic writers who treat of religion. Kant led the way here when, in rationalising the doctrine of justification, he represented it as meaning that, for the sake of our faith in the moral good, we are already held to be what, while on earth, and perhaps in any future world, we are no more than about to become {Religion inn^rhalb der Grenxen der bloss. Vernunft, Bk. II. sec. 3). I quote two illustrative passages from Mr. Bradley and Mr. T. H. Green. " Justification by faith means," says Mr. Bradley, " that, having thus identified myself with the object, I feel myself in that identification to be already one with it, and to enjoy the bliss of being, all falsehood (jvercome, what I truly am. By my claim to be one with the ideal, which comprehends me too, and by assertion of the non-reality of all that is opposed to it, the evil in the world and the evil incarnate in me through past bad acts, all this falls into the unreal ; I being one with the ideal, this is not mine, and so imputation of offences goes with the change of self, and applies not now to my true self, but to the unreal, which I repudiate and hand over to destruction. . . . Because the ideal is not realised completely and truly as the ideal, therefore I am not justified by the works, which issue from faith, as works ; since they,remain imperfect. I am justified solely and entirely by the ideal identification; the existence of which in me is on the other hand indicated and guaranteed by works, and in its very essence implies them."— Ethical Studies, pp. 293-294. Mr. Green says : " We most nearly approach the Pauline notion of 526 NOTE TO LECTURE VIII. imputed righteousness when we say that it is a righteousness com- municated in principle, but not yet developed in act." — Paper on Justification by Faith, in JVorks, iii. p. 202, In the former of these extracts (as also in Mr. Green's own view) we are away from the historical Christ altogether, and have to deal only with "ideals," in relation to which we pass an act of judgment on ourselves in accordance with the metaphysical truth of things, and there is neither room nor need for a special justifying act of God. NOTES TO LECTUEE IX. NOTE A. KENAN'S ESCHATOLOGY, Hartm ANN'S tlieory of cosmic suicide by the concurrent decision of the race is bizarre enough, but it is outdone by the extraordinary eschatology sketched by M. Renan in his Dialogues et Fragments Philosophiques, which, apparently, though he heads the section " Dreams," it is not his intention that we should take otherwise than seriously. It is a curious further illustration of how every theorist feels the need of some kind of eschatology, as well as of the lengths to which credulity will go in minds that deem themselves too wise to accept Eevelation. In Kenan's view the great business in which the universe is engaged is that of organising God.i God as yet only exists in ideal ; the time will come when He will be materially realised in a consciousness analogous to that of liumanity, only infinitely superior (p. 78). The universe will culminate in a single conscious centre, in which the conception of personal Mono- theism will become a truth. An omniscient, omnipotent being will be the last term of the God - making evolution {revolution deifique) ; the universe will be consummated in a single organised being— the resultant of milliards of beings whose lives are summed up in his— the harmony, the sum-total of the universe (pp. 125, 126). The climax of absurdity is reached in the notion that the personal Deity thus realised proceeds, now that he has come into existence, to raise the dead and hold a general judgment ! M. Renan may be allowed here to speak for himself — " Yes, I conceive the possibility of the resurrection, and often say to myself with Job, Eeposita est hcec spes in sinu meo. If ever at the end of the successive evolutions the universe is led back to a single, absolute being, this being will be the complete life of all ; he will renew in himself the life of beings who have vanished, or, if you will, in his bosom will revive all those who have ever been. "When God shall be at once perfect and all-powerful, that is to say, when scientific omnipotence shall be concentrated in the hands of a good and just being, this being will wish to resuscitate the past in order to repair its innumerable injustices. God will exist more and more ; the more he exists, the more just he will be. He will attain to this fully on the day when whoever has wrought 1 This is not among the " Dreams," but among the " Probabilities " (pp. 78, 79). 528 NOTES TO LECTURE IX. for the Divine work shall feel that the Divine work is finished, and shall see the part he has had in it. Then the eternal inequality of beings shall be sealed for ever," etc. (pp. 435, 436). Comment on such " dreams " is needless. Yet the spinning of such theories by a cultured intellect which has parted with its faith is not without its lessons. NOTE B. THE GOSPEL AND THE VASTNESS OF CREATION. An interesting article on the subject treated of in the Lecture is con- tributed to the Contemporary Review for April 1889, by the late Prof. Freeman, under the title— " Christianity and the 'Geocentric' System." The article is full of suggestive and acute remarks. Prof. Freeman states the objection in its full strength. "It is unreasonable, it is urged, to believe that such a scheme as that of Christianity, implying such awful mysteries and so tremendous a sacrifice, can have been devised for the sole benefit of such an insignificant part of the universe as the earth and its inhabitants" (p. 541). He does not, however, think there is much in it. "If it is meant," he says, "not merely as a rhetorical point, but as a serious objection, it really comes to this : we cannot believe that so much has been done for this earth as Christianity teaches, because this earth is so little ; if this earth were only bigger, then we might believe it. . . . Surely nobody ever believed or disbelieved on this kind of ground. An objection of this kind is a rhetorical point, and nothing more" (p. 542). As a rhetorical point, nevertheless, he grants that it is telling, and proceeds to deal with it for what it is worth. He points out, first, how little the change from the " geocentric " view has done to alter the general tenor of our thoughts and feelings. It is not the case that the "geocentric" view led man to take an exaggerated view of his own importance. On the contrary, the sight of the starry heavens, even when looked at with " geocentric " eyes, has always been to make man feel his littleness (Ps. viii.). "The truth is that the objection attributes to scientific theories a great deal more practical influence than really belongs to them. Whether the earth goes round the sun, or the sun goes round the earth, does not make the least practical difference to our general feelings, to our general ways of looking at things. . . . We are all ' heliocentric ' when we stop to think about it . . . but I suspect most of us are ' geocentric ' in practice. That is, we not only talk as if the sun really rose and set, but for all practical purposes we really think so. . . . Nobody really accepts or rejects the Christian religion or any other religion, merely through thinking whether the sun is so many thousands or millions of times bigger than the earth, or whether it is only the size of a cart-wheel, or, at the outside, about the bigness of Peloponnesus " (p. 544). Next, he touches the question whether we have any reason to suppose that other worlds are inhabited. " Astronomers do not even attempt to tell us for certain whether even NOTES TO LECTURE IX. 529 he other members of our own system are inhabited or not. ... I believe I am right in saying that they tell us that Mars is the only planet of our system where men like ourselves could live ; that, if the other planets are inhabited, it must be by beings of a very different nature from ours" (p. 545). But the peculiar part of his argument, developed with great ingenuity and force, is a working out of the idea that it is, after all, quite in accordance with analogy that our world should be a very small one, and yet should play a most important part in the universe. Here the analogies of his own science of history furnish him with abundant illustration. " If it should be true that our earth does hold a kind of moral place in the universe out of all proportion to its physical size, the fact will be one of exactly the same kind as the fact that so small a continent as Europe was chosen to play the foremost part in the world's history, and that so small a part of Europe as Greece was chosen to play the foremost part in Europe " (p. 658). Incidentally, in developing this argument, he refers to the fact noticed in the Lecture, that the past history of our own world takes away in large part the force of the argument from the vast empty spaces of creation. " Here both the certain facts of geology and the less certain doctrine of evolution, instead of standing in the way of the argument, give it no small help. . . . We know that our own world remained in this seemingly useless and empty state for untold ages ; there is therefore at least no absurdity in supposing that other worlds, some or all of them, are in the same state still. . . . The past emptiness and uselessness of the whole planet, the abiding emptiness and seeming uselessness of large jDarts of it, certainly go a long way to get rid of all a jpriori objection to the possible emptiness and seeming uselessness of some or all of the other bodies that make up the universe" (p. 548). A lengthy and valuable note on the subject will likewise be found in Dorner's History of the Doctrine of the Person of Glirist, vol. v. pp. 265-270. Dorner reviews, with his usual thoroughness and learning, the opinions held by others, but finds nothing to shake his confidence in the Christian view. " Concerning our planet, as compared with a thousand others, we must say that it is the Bethlehem amongst the rest, the least city among the thousands in Judah, out of which the Lord was destined to proceed " (p. 267). He reminds us that Steffens and Hegel, like Whewell, " regard our planetary system as the most organised spot of the universe ; the earth, this consecrated spot on which the Lord appeared, as its absolute centre, which both Hegel and Becker designate the Bethlehem of worlds "(p. 269). Ebrard likewise discusses the objection in his Christian Apologetics^ i. p. 253 (Eng. trans.). Fiske, in his little book on Man's Destiny, is another who refers to it. Chap. i. is headed " Man's Place in Nature, as affected by the Copernican Theory." He concludes — "The speculative necessity for man's occupying the largest and most central spot in the universe is no longer felt. It is recognised as a primitive and childish notion. With our larger knowledge we see that these vast and fiery suns are after all but the Titan-like servants of the little planets which they bear with them in their flight through the abysses of space. ... He 34 530 NOTES TO LECTURE IX. who tlius looks a little deeper into the secrets of nature than his fore- fathers of the sixteenth century, may well smile at the quaint conceit that man cannot be the object of God's care unless he occupies an immovable position in the centre of the stellar universe" (pp. 16, 17). Finally, I may refer to the beautiful treatment of the higher and more spiritual aspects of the subject by Dr. John Ker in his sermon on " The Gospel and the Magnitude of Creation" {Sermons, p. 227). NOTE C. ALLEGED PAULINE UNIVERSALISM. The two strongest passages in favour of Pauline universalism are undoubtedly 1 Cor. xv. 21-28 and Eph. i. 10, yet the ablest exegetes concur that in neither can Paul be held to teach the doctrine of universal salvation. With this view I cannot but agree. It is easy to read such a meaning into certain of Paul's universalistic expressions, but an unbiassed study of the passages and their context makes it plain that it is far from the apostle's intention to affirm any such doctrine. As respects 1 Cor. xv. 21-28, we have first the statement — " For as in Adam all die, even so in Christ shall all be made alive '"' (ver. 22). But to affirm that in Christ all shall be made alive is a very different thing from affirming that all shall be made alive in Christ. And that the latter is not the apostle's thought is made evident from the next verse, which declares that this making alive of those that are Christ's takes place at His coming. " Each in his own order : Christ the first-fruits ; then they that are Christ's, at His coming " (ver. 23). This making alive, therefore, is the making alive at the resurrection at the Parousia. But no universalist maintains that at that period "they that are Christ's" embraces all humanity. The subsequent clauses are not more decisive. " The last enemy that shall be abolished is death" (ver. 27) ; but here again it is foreign to the context to suppose that Paul has in view any other abolition of death than that he has been speaking of throughout the chapter, viz. its abolition at the resurrection. The putting down of all (rival) rule, authority, and power (ver. 24), the putting all His enemies under His feet (ver. 25), the subjection of all things to the Son (vers. 27, 28), do not naturally suggest reconciliation or conversion, but rather forcible subjugation — the destruction of all hostile authority and influence. In this sense, accordingly, must be interpreted the final expression — the strongest of all — " that God may be all in all." Meyer observes — " Olshausen and De Wette find here the doctrine of restoration favoured also by Neander, so that SI/ TToiai would apply to all creatures, in whom God shall be the all- determining One. . . . The fact was overlooked that su 'TrSe.at refers to the members of the kingdom hitherto ruled over by Christ, to whom the condemned, who, on the contrary, are outside of this kingdom, do not belong, and that the continuance of the condemnation is not done away even with the subjugation of Satan, since, on the contrary, the latter NOTES TO LECTURE IX. 531 himself by his subjugation falls under condemnation" {Gtm. in loc). Weiss similarly says: "Even the context of this passage excludes any referring of it to a restitution of all things (Apokatastasis), for the dominion which God henceforward wields immediately can be no other than that which Christ has received and given up to Him ; and that does not consist in this, that all hostile powers are destroyed or converted, but in this, that they have become powerless, and are subject to His will"— Biblical Theol, ii. p. 73 (Eng. trans.). The second passage, again, Eph. i. 10, speaks of a summing up of all things in Christ as head (I agree with Weiss that there is no need for weakening or denying the force of the composite word) in the dispensa- tion of the fulness of the times— a truly wonderful and comprehensive expression. The rd. '7r»vret here is in itself quite general, — all created things and beings,— and might therefore quite well suit a universalistic sense. But, first, the roi tcxutu. is limited by the succeeding clause, — " the things in the heavens, and the things on the earth,"— which excludes the demoniacal powers, certainly not conceived of as " things in the heavens" ; and, next, it is a question whether the annulling of the divided state of "things on earth" is effected by the conversion of hostile powers, or not rather by their subjugation, and separation from the holy part of the creation. This is a question to be determined by Paul's general mode of thought, and Meyer and Weiss agree that such an idea as the final conversion of the unbelieving and the demons is not within his view. "With the Parousia," says Meyer, "there sets in the full realisation, which is the ec-TroKXToiaTecffis Trauruv (Matt. xix. 28 ; Acts iii. 21 ; 2 Pet. iii. 10 ff.) ; when all antichristian natures and powers shall be discarded out of heaven and earth, so that thereafter nothing in heaven or upon earth shall be excluded from this gathering together again. . . . The restoration in the case of the devils, as an impossibility in the case of spirits radically opposed to God, is not in the whole New Testament so much as thought of. The prince of this world is only judged" {Com. in loc, and Remark 2, on the Doctrine of Restoration). "A bringing back of the world of spirits hostile to God," says Weiss, — " which, moreover, is considered as definitely bad, — is as far away from the Biblical view as is also a need of Redemption on the part of the angel world, and therefore the author felt no need to guard his expressions against either of these thoughts. . . . Enough that they by their sub- jection to Christ are stripped of any power which can hurt the absolute dominion of Christ" {Biblical Theul of N. T., ii. pp. 107, 109). The one thing which would be really decisive in favour of a uni- versalistic interpretation, would be some passage from Paul (or any part of the New Testament), which explicitly affirmed that fallen spirits or lost men in eternity would ultimately repent and be saved ; but no such expression can be found. Dr. Cox has no scruple in telling us that those condemned in the judgment will yet, after a remedial discipline, all be brought to repentance, to faith ; will be restored to God's Fatherly love, etc. If this is the Scripture doctrine, why do Christ and His apostles never explicitly say so ? Why do they not use expressions as clear and unmistakable as Dr. Cox's own? Why only these general 532 NOTES TO LECTURE IX. expressions, of wliicli the application is the very question in dispute? The ancient prophets, e.g.^ had no difficulty in making clear their belief that a day of general conversion would come for sinful and rejected Israel. Why does Jesus, or Paul, or John not tell us as plainly that a day of general forgiveness and restoration will come for all God's backsliding children — that those whom they describe as perishing and destroyed, and under wrath, and undergoing the second death, will yet be changed in their dispositions, and made sharers of God's eternal life 1 It is not simply that this is not declared of all, but it is not, in one single utterance, declared of any ; and while this is the state of the case scripturally, universal restoration, however congenial to our wishes, must be held to be a dream in the air, without solid basis in Revelation. What many passages do teach is the complete subjugation of those found finally opposed to Christ ; and in this way the restoration of a unity or harmony in the universe, which involves the cessation of active, or at least effective, opposition to Christ's rule. What may be covered by such expressions, — or what yet unrevealed may in future ages be disclosed, — who can tell ? Reference may be made to a careful study of the whole New Testament teaching on this subject in a series of papers by the Rev. Dr. Agar Beet in the Expositor , vol. i. (4th series) 1890. I K D E X. AcKERMANN, Madame, 86. Acosmism, 307, 417. Agnosticism, alternative to Christian view, 60-4 ; tends to Pessimism, 65 ; involves a negation, 97, 93 ; Mr. Spencer's discussed, 98-104 ; truth in, 14, 102 ; Agnostic systems, 417 ; controversy on, 425. Antiquity of man, bearings on Chris- tian view, 215-6 ; BoydDawkinson, 216 ; in relation to geological time, 504-6. Argyll, Duke of, on primitive man, 500. Arianism, defeat of, 57, 445-6 ; Har- nack on. 446 ; Carlyle on, 446. Astronomical objection to Christianity, 371-6, 528-30; Professor Freeman on, 528-9. Atoms, structure of, 149; creation of, 150 ; Herschell on, 150. Atonement, see Redemption. Meaning of word, 333. Augustine, on cognisability of God, 103 ; on the Trinity, 309, 312-3 ; on eternity and time, 487. Baethgen, on Old Testament Mono- theism, 469-70. Baldensperger, on claims of Jesus, 253 ; on self-consciousness of Jesus, 294- 6 ; on pre-existence, 508-9. Ball, Professor, on planets, 373 ; on nebular hypothesis, 483. Baring-Gould, 13. Baur, A., on "Weltanschauung," 42-4. Be3'schlag, his Christology, 255 ; on "Godhead" of Christ, 273, 278, 301 ; on sinlessness of Christ, 268 ; on self-consciousness of Christ, 289- 91 ; on Second Advent, 383 ; on glorification of Christ, 385 ; on modern views, 424, Biedermann, his Theism, 74, 443 ; on Revelation, 76, 460; his Christology, 53 ; on *' Heavenly Man " theory, 255 ; on the Trinity, 310. Bohme, Jacob, quoted by Hegel, 68 ; on existence of evil, 222, 227 ; on the Trinity, 312. Bornemann, on ** Godhead " of Christ, 449 ; on pre - existence, 509 ; on resurrection of Christ, 514. Bradley, F. H., on moral end, 207 ; on dualism, 497. Browning, R., on immortality, 185, 187 ; on evil, 223. Bruce, Professor A. B., on Kenotic theories, 281 ; on kingdom of God, 384, 402, 405 ; on modern substi- tutes for Christianity, 437. Buddhism, Divinity of its founder, 252 ; its redemption, 332 ; its escha- tology, 369 ; in what sense a religion, 436. Bushnell, on Gospel picture of Christ, 265 ; his theory of redemption, 346- 52, 364; on fate of the wicked, 387. Caird, Profesor E., on Comte, 6, 421, 437 ; on Kant, 114, 119, 156, 160, 186, 197, 475-6; on Kant's view of the end of creation, 130 ; on uncon- scious metaphysics, 421. 534 INDEX, Caird, Principal J., on theistic proofs, 114, 116 ; on Materialism, 177. Cairns, Principal J., on Yoltaire, 81 ; on Unitarianism, 447. Calderwood, Professor H., on mind and cerebral activity, 179, 490-3. Calvin, on the Trinity, 308-9. Campbell, J. M'Leod, his theory of atonement, 358-62. Candlish, Professor J., on kingdom of God, 402 ; on Christianity and pro- gress, 453-4. Caro, on Pessimism, ^^, 87, 370, 454 ; on God, 439. Cheyne, Professor, on doctrine of re- surrection, 237-8, 242-5 ; on Zoro- astrianism, 237-8. Christ, the centre of His religion, 4, 51-4, 444-5 ; His view supernatural, 11, 62, 77 ; modern views regarding, 51-4, 249; His doctrines of God, 77, 94-6 ; of man, 142-3 ; of re- demption, 334-8 ; His eschatological teaching, 253, 266-7, 383-6 ; His self-witness, 55, 251 ; His claims, 265-7 ; His sinlessness, 267-8 ; His miracles, 268-9 ; His resurrec- tion, 269-70, 512-5. Divinity of, view of, in apostolic Church, 252 ; in Fourth Gospel, 253-4, 263 ; in Paul, 254-8 ; in Hebrews, 258 ; in Apocalypse, 259 ; in minor Epistles, 261 ; in Acts, 262 ; in synoptic Gospels, 264-75 ; modern theories of, 54, 272-4 ; ob- jection to, from His lowliness, 249- 51 ; views of Schleiermacher, 59, 272-6 ; of Eothe, 273, 277 ; of Bey- schlag, 273, 278, 290, 301 ; of Ritschl, 54, 60, 273-6, 448 ; of Lipsius, 274 ; of Schultz, 293 ; of F. •A. B. Nitzsch, 517 ; of Dorner, 518 ; speculative Christologies, 58, 443, 459-60. Self-consciousness of, 287-98 ; views of Beyschlag, 289-91 ; of H. Schmidt, 291-3 ; of Grau, 293-4 ; of Baldensperger, 294-6 ; of Wendt, 296-8. Christianity, involves a view of the world, 9, 17, 26, 38-41 ; a super- natural system, 11, 12, 422-4 ; rela- tion to philosophy and science, 9, 29- 36, 440-3 ; relation to doctrine, 18, 19, 22-9 ; unites the truths of other systems, 12 ; its spirituality, 24 ; involves Revelation, 9, 25, 93-4 ; the religion of the incarnation, 4, 38-9, 51-2 ; the religion of redemp- tion, 193, 331-2 ; the Christian view and its alternatives, see Lecture II. Clifford, Professor, 83 ; on atoms, 149. Comte, A., his " Weltanschauung," 6 ; his religion, 14, 378, 436-7 ; his metaphysics, 417, 421 ; on defects in nature, 496 ; affinities with Chris- tianity, 14, 378. Cox, Dr. S., on Universalism, 386, 531. Creation, Scripture doctrine of, 37, 144 ; importance of doctrine, 145 ; connection with doctrine of man, 145, 157-60 ; opposed to dualism, 146 ; to logical derivation of the universe, 147 ; to self-existence of the universe, 149 ; evidence of, 149- 52 ; difficulties of a beginning in time, 152 ; theory of an eternal creation, 153, 485-6 ; motive and end of, 155 ; man the head of, 157- 9 ; hypothesis of cycles, 150, 483-4; the creation history, 480-2 ; defects in, an argument against Theism, 495-6. Cycles, hypothesis of, 150, 369-71, 483-4. Darwinism, not the only form of evolution, 119, 476-8 ; and design, 119-22 ; G. H. Lewes on, 476 ; G. J. Romanes on, 477 ; H. Spencer on, 477. See Evolution. Davidson, Professor A. B., on immor- tality in Old Testament, 241-2. Dawkins, Professor Boyd, on antiquity of man, 216. Dawson, Sir J. W., on evolution, 121 ; on primitive man, 217, 500 ; on antiquity of man, 501, 506. Death, in nature, 219-21 ; of man, see Sin. Deism, and Christian view, 14 ; its weakness, 450-1 ; definition, 418. Delitzsch, F., on prevision of fall, 227 ; INDEX, 535 on immortality in Psalms, 243-4 ; on angel of Jehovah, 305 ; on anti" supei naturalism of the modern view, 423. Dorner, A., on religious and theoretic knowledge, 440-1. Dorner, Dr., on world- view in Chris- tianity, 10 ; on relation of God to the world, 14, 318 ; on teleology, 17, 371 ; on religion, 21 ; on Christo- logy, 54 ; on Feuerbach, 71 ; on personality of God and of man, 141 ; on creation, 153, 485-6 ; on sin 200, 211, 227, 228 ; on Aquinas, 221 ; on Christology of Synoptics, 271 ; on Trinity, 270, 311, 518-9 ; on in- carnation and sin, 320 ; on substitu- tion, 347 ; on *' modern " views, 424 ; on eternity and time, 487 ; on astro- nomical objection, 529. Dualism, Persian, 17, 204 ; and crea- tion, 146 ; and sin, 204, 496-7 ; of Martineau, 146 ; of J. S. Mill, 146-7 ; of S. Laing, 496. DuBois-Reymond, on Materialism, 168, 173. Ebrard, on Zoroastrianism, 17, 496 ; on early Monotheism, 502-3 ; on astronomical objection, 529. Eliot, George, on Meliorism, 196 ; on immortality, 178. Ellicott, Bishop, on vanity of creation, 227. Energy, dissipation of, 151, 484 ; bear- ings of conservation of, on Material- ism, 171-2. Erskine, of Linlathen, on atonement, 356. Eschatology, in Christian view, 39, 370 ; of philosophy and science, 369-70 ; Christ's teaching on, 253, 266-7, 383-6 ; laws of interpretation, 377 ; destiny of the believer— conformity to Christ, 380 ; the resurrection, 380-3 ; transformation of nature, 383 ; the Second Advent, 383-5; the Judgment, 385-6 ; destiny of the wicked — theories on this subject, 386-7 ; fundamental positions, 388- 90 ; dogmatic Universalism, 390-1 ; conditional immortality, 391-4 ; future probation, 394-7; result, 397; Kenan's eschatology, 527-8. Eternal series, inadequacy of the hypo- thesis, 115, 151 ; theory of cycles, 483. Eternity and time, 155, 487. Evil, problem of natural and moral, 193-5 ; recognition of, in modern thought, 195-200 ; connection of natural and moral, 194, 218, 225-8 ; in inorganic world, 218 ; in organic world, 219 ; animal suffering and death, 219-22 ; natural evil in rela- tion to man, 222-5 ; and moral go- vernment, 225; groaning of creation, 226-8 ; theory of anticipative conse- quences, 227, 323 ; sin and death, 228-33. See Sin. Evolution, scope of theory of, 9, 421-2 ; in religion, 91, 215, 466-9 ; and design, 118-22 ; and a beginning in time, 150 ; breaks in, 151, 214 ; nebular hypothesis, 150, 482-3 ; and doctrine of sin, 206, 209-12 ; and primitive man, 212-6 ; and the in- carnation, 250-1 ; schools of evolu- tionists, 476-8. Fairbairn, Principal A. M., on meta- physics in science, 7, 421 ; on cosmic theories, 9 ; on conflict of views, 422 ; on evolution in religion, 466 ; on Vedic religion, 503. Fairbairn, Principal P., on immortality in Old Testament, 234 ; on incarna- tion and sin, 320-1, 324-5. Fall, The, Scripture doctrine of, 38, 201 , 203, 217 ; Hegel on, 205, 497-8; denial of, by modern view, 38, 210 ; relation to death, 229-33, 506-7. Farrar, on loss of the soul, 390. Feuerbach, his theory of religion, 21, 433, 439 ; on Christ, 62 ; his Materi- alism, 72. Fichte, J. G., and Theism, 72-3 ; his later philosophy, 458-60 ; referred to, 68, 71. Fiske, J., on Theism, 102 ; on person- ality of God, 112 ; on immortality, 178, 186 ; on original sin, 197 ; *'Physicus" on, 426-7 ; on man as goal of creation, 488-9 ; on astro- nomical objection, 529. 53<5 INDEX, Flint, Professor R., on Trinity, 152, 303 ; on Pessimism, 196. Freeman, Professor .E. A., on astro- nomical objection to Christianity, 528-9. Future probation, 394-7. Getkie, Sir Archibald, on geological time, 505. Gladstone, W. E., and S. Laing, 425 ; on Old Testament, 429 ; on creation, 480. God, Old Testament view of, 15, 16, 428-9 ; in Christian view, 14, 37 ; Christ's doctrine of, 94-6 ; self-re- vealing, 75, 77, 80, 93, 96 ; know- ableness of, 14, 22, 102-3 ; person- ality of, 111-12 ; proofs of existence of, 112-33 ; as religious postulate, 134-7 ; connection of doctrines of God and of man, 141 ; higher concep- tion of God involved in the incarna- tion, 302-19. 5'ee Theism, Trinity, etc. Goethe, on vanity of life, 82. Gore, Principal C, on miracles, 151. Grau, on self-consciousness of Jesus, 293-4 ; criticism of Schultz, 293. Green, T. H., his Theism, 74 ; on on- tological argument, 124 ; on crea- tion, 147 ; on eternity and time, 154 ; on moral end, 207 ; on resur- rection, 381 ; defects of his theor\% 471-4. Greg, W. R., on Theism, 63 ; on im- mortality, 178 ; on retribution, 388 ; and F. W. Newman, 426; his Uni- tarianism, 446 ; on defects in crea- tion, 495. Haeckel, E., Materialism of, 169, 418 ; on Mosaic cosmogony, 480-1 ; on '* mind-cells," 491. . Harnack, A., on Christian view of the world, 26 ; on Arianism, 446 ; on pre-existence, 508-9. Han-ison, F., on Mr. Spencer's Un- knowable, 425 ; and Professor Hux- ley, 425 ; on Fetishism, 467 ; on ghost-worship, 467. Hartmann, E. Von, on "Weltanschau- ung," 20; on Trinity, 14; philo- sophy of, 67-70 ; theory of religion, 70, 75, 456-7 ; on Pessimism of Christianity, 196, 199 ; on creation, 204 ; his eschatology, 370, 527 ; on modern views, 424, 452 ; on Strauss, 427 ; on Christology, 445. Hegel, his system, 9 ; theory of re- ligion, 36, 135, 442-3 ; on Christ- ology, 53, 444 ; on creation, 68 ; on God, 111, 116, 147, 471 ; on immor- tality, 178 ; on sin, 200, 205, 208, 497-8 ; on Ti-inity, 308, 312, 315, 516 ; on " Weltanschauung," 415. Herder, on man's place in nature, 488. Heredity, 198-9, 390, 396. Hermann, Professor W., on "Weltan- schauung," 46, 47 ; Christology of, 449 ; on Revelation, 462-5. Hutton, R. H., on the incarnation, 317. Huxley, Professor, on man's j>lace in nature, 8, 488 ; on progress, 85 ; on Agnosticism, 97 ; on Materialism, 167-74 ; no hope of immortality, 178 ; on Mr. Harrison, 425 ; on S. Laing, 425 ; on natural selection, 478 ; on a beginning in time, 484 ; on human automatism, 489-90. Ice age, 504-5. Immortality, Bible doctrine of, 177, 229-33 ; and modern view, 177 ; scientific objections to, 179 ; evi- dences of, 180-9 ; in Old Testament, 235-46 ; conditional, 180, 387, 391-4 ; Egyptian, Babylonian, and Assyrian views of, 234, 235, 238. Incarnation, its place in the Christian view, 4, 11, 38, 51-2; relation to other doctrines, 38, 39 ; objections to, 51, 250-1 ; view of man implied in, 143 ; modern theories of, see Christ; Kenotic theories, 280-1 ; higher concept of God involved in, 301-19 ; and plan of the world ; relation to sin, 319-27; connection with redemp- tion, 285, 331, 341-2. Irenreus, on incarnation, 321, 342. Iverach, Professor, on personality, 112. JOTJFFROY, T., 84. Justification, germ theory of, 524-6. INDEX, 537 Kaftan, on "Weltanschauung," 47 ; on Trinity, 302, 520-1 ; on king- dom of God, 377-8, 403, 411, 463 ; on religion, 432, 434, 438 ; on religious and theoretic knowledge, 441 ; of "Godhead" of Christ, 445, 449 ; on Revelation, 463, 465 ; on man's place in nature, 489. Kant, idea of a world-whole, 5, 415 ; on theistic proofs, 112-3 ; on cosmological argument, 114, 474 ; on teleological argument, 112, 116, 475 ; on ontological argument, 123- 4, 478; on moral argument, 129-31 ; on end of creation, 150, 186 ; on "doctrinal faith," 187, 475 ; on im- mortality, 187 ; on boundlessness of desire, 185 ; on radical evil of human nature, 197 ; his cosmogony, 370, 483 ; moral view of Christianity, 465 ; man the end of nature, 488. Kingdom of God, in Christian view, 39; Ritschl on, 377, 404; Kaftan on, 377-8, 403, 411 ; on earth, 378-9, 405 ; in eternity, 379 ; idta of, 401-12 ; place in recent theology, 401-5 ; teaching of Jesus on, 405- 10 ; and new life of humanity, 410-2. Kittel, R., on Old Testament Revela- tion, 430. Kuenen, on "Ethical Monotheism," 79, 428, 469. Laidlaw, Professor J., on Mr. Spencer, 109 ; on Trinity, 303. Laing, S., Professor Huxley on, 425 ; his dualism, 496. Lange, A., 169, 439. Laveleye, Emile de, 86-7. Lewes, G. H., on evolution, 476. Liberal Protestantism, Strauss on, 451 ; Hartmann on, 452 ; in Holland, 452-3. Lightfoot, Bishop, on Pauline Christ- ology, 257, 322, 326. Lipsius, R. A., on Revelation, 75, 76; on sin, 206-9 ; on natural evil, 225 ; on justification, 209 ; on Christ- ology, 53, 250, 256, 274, 445 ; on sinlessness of Christ, 268 ; on nature of religion, 434 ; on creation, 485. Littre, E., 87. Logic of history, 55. Lotze, H., on Zoroastrianism, 17; on personality of God, 112 ; on creation, 148, 153, 166, 486 ; on Materialism, 176 ; on Old Testament religion, 427. Lucretius, his " Weltanschauung," 6 ; on defects in creation, 495. Lnthardt, on Pessimism, 66, 454. "Lux Mundi," on Monotheism, 105. Man, Christian view of, 37, 141 ; son- ship to God, 142 ; ideal in the in- carnation, 143 ; relation to nature, 143 ; head of creation, 157-9, 488-9 ; link between two worlds, 160 ; his body, 161 ; his soul and spirit, 161-3 ; image of God in, 142-3, ]64-7 ; immortality of, 177-89 ; primitive, 210-7, 499-501. Martensen, on evil in nature, 222, 227 ; on Trinity, 303, 316 ; on incarna- tion and sin, 321. Martineau, Dr. James, on religion, 21 ; on Revelation, 77, 79 ; on Materi- alism, 171 ; on animal suffering, 221 ; on Christology of Fourth Gospel, 253-4,264; on Unitarianism, 446-8 ; on the Trinity, 521-2. Materialism, as a stage of thought, 65, 71 ; in Germany, 71, 457-8 ; its relative right, 161 ; criticism of, 167- 77 ; denial of immortality in, 178 ; annuls sin, 194 ; its systems, 418. Maudsley, on heredity, 199, 390 ; on defects in creation, 496. Maurice, F. D., on atonement, 355-6, Metaphysics, unconscious, 7, 419, 421 ; in theology, 35. Meyer, on "Heavenly Man" theory, 256 ; on Pauline Universalism, 530. Mill, J. S., on Theism, 105, 120 ; on fundamental truths, 125 ; his dual- ism, 146-7 ; on immortality, 179, 184-5, 188 ; indictment of nature, 193, 217. Mind, and mechanical causation, 173-5, 489-90 ; and cerebral activ- ity, 175, 490-3. Miracles, Max Miiller on, 11 ; relation to Christian view, 12 ; Ritschl on, 538 INDEX. 31 ; Theism and, 92 ; Gore on, 151 ; Bushnell on, 165 ; Christ's, 268-9 ; denial by modern view, 423. Mivart, St. George, on animal suffering, 220 ; on evolution, 476. * * Modern " view of the world, its anti - supernaturalism, 10, 422-4 ; its internal conflicts, 10, 424-7 ; rejects a fall, 38, 210 ; and the in- carnation, 51 ; its witness to sin, 195 ; its Pessimism, 66, 81, 195 ; opposes Christian doctrine of sin, 200, 203, 210-17. Monier-Williams. Sir M., on Buddh- ism, 369 ; on Sacred Books of the East, 429. Monotheism, in Israel, 17, 79, 427-9, 469-71 ; not a development from Fetishism, etc., 91, 215, 466 ; only tenable form of Theism, 105 ; early, 215, 601-4. Miiller, Max, on miracles, 11, 423 ; on sense of the Divine, 128 ; on immortality, 180, 182 ; on ghost- worship, 182, 467-8 ; on Fetishism, 466 - 7 ; on Totemism, 468 ; on origin of religion, 469 ; on primitive man, 500. Murphy, J. J., on evolution, 119 ; on original sin, 200 ; on incarnation, 343. Myers, F. W. H., on the disenchant- ment of France, 87. N BANDER, on essence of Christian religion, 12 ; on kingdom of Go ^' 44^ T^Ai^ i-u^^AR Li' UERARY USE DLG 1 ^ 1957 LD 21-100m-7,'39(40? ^"Tii^nfe THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA UBRARY