I
 
 , z-3. 
 
 t tf u 
 
 ,/>
 
 /? 
 
 < 
 
 ,J^'
 
 HELLENICA
 
 [c. 47-]
 
 HELLENICA 
 
 & Collection of 
 
 ON GREEK POETRY PHILOSOPHY 
 HISTORY AND RELIGION 
 
 EDITED BY 
 
 EVELYN ABBOTT, M.A. LL.D. 
 
 FELLOW AND TUTOR OF BALLIOL COLLEGE, OXFORD 
 
 RIVINGTONS 
 
 WATERLOO PLACE, LONDON 
 
 Word anfc CambciUjje 
 
 MDCCCLXXX
 
 PREFACE. 
 
 THOUGH each of the Essays in this volume has 
 been written independently of the rest, they are all 
 in a certain sense connected with each other, and I 
 have endeavoured to indicate the link of connection 
 by the common title " Hellenica." 
 
 We have not done with the Hellenes yet. Jn 
 spite of all the labour spent, and all the books 
 written on them and their literature, we have not 
 yet entered into full possession of the inheritance 
 bequeathed to us. It has, indeed, been said that we 
 know nearly as much about the Greeks and Romans 
 as we shall ever know ; but this can only be true of 
 the mass of facts, to which, without some new dis- 
 coveries, we are not likely to add greatly. It is not 
 in the least true in regard to the significance of 
 Hellenic history and literature. Beyond and above 
 the various interpretations placed by different ages 
 upon the great writers of Greece, lies the meaning 
 which longer experience and more improved methods 
 of criticism and the test of time declare to be the true 
 one. From this point of view much remains and will 
 long remain to be done, whether we look to the work
 
 vi PREFACE. 
 
 of the scholar or to the influence of Hellenic thought 
 on civilisation. We have not yet found all the 
 scattered limbs of Truth ; it may be that we are only 
 commencing the search. 
 
 It is not- likely that the great authors of Greece 
 will ever become, like the Hebrew Scriptures, a text- 
 book of daily life. The rapt utterance of the prophet 
 is far mightier " to sway the soul of man " than the 
 calmer reasoning of the philosopher, who often loses in 
 intensity what he gains in breadth. But they may 
 do a great deal more for us than they have hitherto 
 done, if we will allow them. The Gorgias of Plato 
 and the Ethics of Aristotle are more valuable than 
 modern books on the same subjects, for the simple 
 reason that they are nearer the beginning. They 
 have a greater freshness, and appeal more directly to 
 the growing mind. No age can neglect them without 
 suffering a definite and appreciable loss, least of all 
 the present age, for the study of the writings and the 
 contemplation of the lives of men who sought after 
 knowledge as after hidden treasure, who found, or 
 seemed to find, the one great Good, which all men, 
 consciously or unconsciously, were everywhere seeking, 
 who observed the facts of the world around them with 
 calm judgment, and built thereon their own lofty 
 theories of what human life might and ought to be 
 
 " Serene creators of immortal things," 
 become more and more valuable as the course of
 
 PREFACE. vii 
 
 history tends to put things material and practical in 
 the place of things intellectual. 
 
 In many respects modern civilisation contrasts 
 favourably with ancient ; it is, for instance, a trite 
 thing to point out the care taken in modern times of 
 the criminal and the idiot. On the other hand, it is 
 possible that this gain has not been without some 
 accompanying loss. While we are anxious to hide or 
 relieve the degradation to which human nature can 
 sink, we tend to become less careful of the elevation 
 to which it can rise ; we put feeling in the place of 
 thought, and throw away half our birthright. But 
 if a single generation were able to keep before it an 
 ideal of culture which should blend all the elements 
 of human knowledge " into an immortal feature of 
 perfection," if a whole country could unite in one 
 effort to appropriate in any real manner the best that 
 has been thought and written on the great interests 
 of life, we should indeed make a great stride forward, 
 but we should also find that the brightest hope of the 
 future is not far removed from the truest interpreta- 
 tion of the past. 
 
 At present such an effort is impossible, partly 
 because much of the best literature of the world is in 
 the exclusive possession of the few. The most direct 
 method of breaking down this exclusiveness, and bring- 
 ing the great writers of Greece within the immediate 
 reach of English readers, is no doubt to translate
 
 viii PREFACE. 
 
 them ; but it is hoped that a volume like the present, 
 while it helps to increase the interest taken in Greek 
 literature, will also show how that literature may 
 be of service in the present day. 
 
 E. ABBOTT. 
 
 BALLIOL COLLEGE, OXFORD, 
 December 1879.
 
 CONTENTS 
 
 PAGE 
 
 AESCHYLUS 
 
 ERNEST MYERS, M.A., Fellow of Wadham College, Oxford i 
 
 THE THEOLOGY AND ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES 
 
 EVELYN ABBOTT, M.A., LL.D., Fellow of Balliol College, 
 
 Oxford 33 
 
 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION IN PLATO'S REPUBLIC 
 RICHARD LEWIS NETTLESHIP, M.A., Fellow of Balliol 
 
 College, Oxford 67 
 
 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION OF THE STATE 
 
 ANDREW CECIL BRADLEY, M.A., Fellow of Balliol College, 
 
 Oxford 181 
 
 EPICURUS 
 
 WILLIAM LEONARD COURTNEY, M.A., Fellow of New 
 
 College, Oxford 244 
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES 
 
 RICHARD CLAVERHOUSE JEBB, M.A., LL.D., Professor of 
 
 Greek in the University of Glasgow .... 266 
 
 XENOPHON 
 
 HENRY GRAHAM DAKYNS, M.A., Trinity College, Cam- 
 bridge 324 
 
 POLYBIUS 
 
 JAMES LEIGH STRACHAN-DAVIDSON,M.A., Fellow of Balliol 
 
 College, Oxford 387 
 
 GREEK ORACLES 
 
 FREDERIC WILLIAM HENRY MYERS, M.A., late Fellow of 
 
 Trinity College, Cambridge 425
 
 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 " voi ch'avete gl' intelletti sani, 
 
 Mi rate la clottrina che s'asconcle 
 Sotto il velame degli versi strani." DANTE. 
 
 " High actions and high passions best describing." MILTON. 
 
 THE three sons of Euphorion the Athenian, Kynegeirus, Aeschy- 
 lus, and Ameinias, all earned the gratitude of their country 
 and of the world, for all fought in the great battles of the 
 Persian war, and helped to save the brightest hopes of the 
 human race, which then stood in jeopardy of death. But to 
 Aeschylus belongs another and a still more conspicuous fame, 
 for he is the Father of Tragedy ; nor have any of his spiritual 
 sons, save* perhaps one, been able to claim a right to the boast 
 of Sthenelus. 1 And since all European drama derives from 
 the Athenian, it is more than mere idle speculation to say 
 that without Aeschylus there might possibly have been no 
 Shakespeare. 
 
 Aeschylus was born in the year 525 B.C., and died in 456, 
 twenty -five years before the Peloponnesian war began, so that 
 of him, more truly than of Sophocles, it might be said that he 
 departed ovSev vTropeivas /cafcov, taken away from the evil that 
 was to come. When the Persian war was over, during the latter 
 part of his life, he seems, like other poets and artists of the 
 time, to have visited Sicily and Syracuse, once at least, more 
 probably twice, or even thrice. We need not regard the gossip 
 of later times, which attributed his absence from Athens to 
 jealousy of the rising fame of Sophocles, who had become more 
 popular than himself in the Athenian theatre. We may feel 
 sure that the personal relations of Aeschylus and Sophocles find 
 far truer expression in that passage in the Frogs of Aristo- 
 phanes, where Aeacus tells how, when the younger poet came 
 
 1 Iliad, iv. 405. 
 A
 
 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 down among the dead, he clasped the hand of the elder and 
 embraced him, and would not suffer that he should yield his 
 throne. Syracuse was at that time a common resort of men of 
 art and letters ; and the sympathy of Aeschylus may well have 
 been aroused, as Pindar's was, for the Hellenic people and 
 prince who had fought so well against the Carthaginian and 
 Etruscan in the West, while the Hellenes of the mother country 
 were beating back the Persian in the East. Whatever were 
 the cause, there is no doubt that Aeschylus did at least once 
 exchange the fair curve of hills that stand about the Athenian 
 plain for Etna's solitary cone, and the rock-fretted ripple of 
 Ilissus for smooth-sliding Anapus and his reedy banks. In 
 honour of a new-founded Sicilian city, he wrote a play called Tlie 
 Women of Aitna, but of this unhappily only four lines remain, 
 so that we cannot know " how fair a fountain of immortal verse 
 he made to flow" 1 for his hosts, among whom he came like 
 Alpheus rising blended in the Arethusan spring, 
 
 " bearing bridal gifts, 
 Fair leaves and flowers and sacred soil of Hellas." 2 
 
 In Sicily death overtook him, and his ashes were buried at 
 Gela with the honours of a public funeral. On his tomb was 
 engraved a brief epitaph, attributed to himself; and we may 
 well believe that he wrote it, for it makes no mention of the 
 triumphs of his art, only of his share in the common duties of 
 a citizen when he fought in the ranks at Marathon. 
 
 His choice of the new and native field of tragic poetry was 
 symbolised in the legend which told how, when as a boy he 
 had fallen asleep in his father's vineyard, Dionysus appeared 
 to him in a vision, and gave command that he should serve 
 him after this sort at his festival when the vines grew green. 
 So amply had he fulfilled before his death the charge enjoined 
 on him by the God, that no less than seventy dramas, of which 
 only seven have descended to us, were even at the lowest 
 reckoning ascribed to his hand. 
 
 Such external evidence touching the bent and genius of 
 Aeschylus as has been left to us in the shape of contemporary 
 
 1 Ka.1 Ke fj.v6riffa.i0 1 owolav 'A/wceo-tXp 
 
 efy>e vayav a^poffLw eirtuv. PlNDAR, Pytli. iv. 298. 
 J ZSva. <j>tpuv /ca\d <pv\\a KCLI &vdea Kal K&VIV Ipdv. MosCHUS, vi. 3.
 
 AESCHYL US. 
 
 or nearly contemporary criticism and comment, is naturally 
 meagre. The most striking and copious is that found in the 
 Frogs of Aristophanes. In the Frogs, Aeschylus is intro- 
 duced to be contrasted with, and to triumph over, Euripides. 
 The glorious and endearing associations of the elder time find 
 vindication in the victory of the elder poet. The contest is not 
 unlike that waged between Honest and Dishonest Pleading in the 
 Clouds. Simplicity, directness, dignity, heroic magnanimity, 
 and contempt of the frivolous, the egoistic, the morbidly ingeni- 
 ous, are arrayed, to the eyes of Aristophanes, against affectation, 
 meaningless subtlety, inartistic carelessness and triviality, volup- 
 tuousness, shallow and violent passion. It would be difficult to 
 find a modern parallel to Euripides, but if, to illustrate the 
 situation, we imagine some modern English critic, whose indig- 
 nation had determined him to see nothing but prosaic coldness 
 in Wordsworth, nothing but bad workmanship and theatrical 
 declamation in Byron, nothing but voluptuousness in Keats or 
 Mr. Morris, nothing but pretentious oddity and " a well of Eng- 
 lish defiled" in Mr. Browning ; a critic who further saw all these 
 qualities, not dispersed among several poets, but concentrated in 
 the writings of one, and that one far more popular than any of 
 these, and with a popularity which the critic believed to be one 
 of many signs of a fatal degeneracy of the age ; and then if we 
 imagine this critic matching such a poet against such another 
 poet of old time as the " God-gifted organ- voice of England," 
 employing a wit as unscrupulous as brilliant to expose the 
 degeneracy of the later-born, we may thus form some idea of 
 the purpose accomplished by Aristophanes in the Frogs. One- 
 sided as that play is, it is still a most valuable relic of nearly 
 contemporary criticism. But the exigencies of comedy, and 
 possibly even an imperfect appreciation on the part of Aristo- 
 phanes himself, leave the Frogs very far from satisfactory as a 
 criticism not only of Euripides, but also of Aeschylus. And 
 probably the manner in which Aeschylus is there introduced 
 has done something to incline modern estimates of his genius 
 toward judgments which a careful study of his works must 
 pronounce superficial. 
 
 Without doubt, of all the tokens whereby we may estimate a 
 poet, his style is the chief ; but if we go no deeper we shall be 
 apt to err even in our estimate of his style. And the style of
 
 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 Aeschylus, characteristic as it is, has misled some critics by not 
 being viewed in the light of less obvious elements in his work, 
 as well as by having undue emphasis laid on its most salient 
 points ; and the same has been the case in inferences from the 
 structure, the stories, and the dramatis personae of his extant 
 plays. Because his diction is always lofty, and sometimes grandi- 
 ose and excessive in its wealth of pr^ad' iTnroftd/jiova, words on 
 horseback, 1 because among his characters are Titans and Furies, 
 he has been accounted one whose delight was pre-eminently in 
 the colossal and the terrible for their own sake, and whose pre- 
 vailing passion was for stupendous effects produced by a reck- 
 lessly gigantesque imagination. In the Frogs, this is made a 
 chief point of Euripides' attack, and the one defect which 
 Aristophanes seems to allow to exist in his hero. And since 
 then the difference in modern taste has been equally ready to 
 recognise, though less ready to blame, those picturesque extra- 
 vagances. It is not merely that criticism is always willing 
 to lighten its task by making the most of the salient 
 features in its object, but also the standard of comparison 
 between different kinds of literary and artistic merit is very 
 commonly other than it was in the time of Aeschylus and 
 Pheidias, and will sometimes be found wanting in its applica- 
 tion to that time. The value of vigour and passion, of vivid- 
 ness of all kinds, was at least as amply recognised in theory and 
 exemplified in practice by the artistic genius of that age as by 
 that of any other ; but its larger view never lost sight of the 
 supremacy of measure and harmony, the powers whose gracious 
 influence was present in every great effort of the Hellenic mind. 
 And thus in the drama of Aeschylus, behind all the lurid clouds 
 of a mysterious destiny, above the mountainous waves of con- 
 flicting passions, the star of his Athenian soul is never quenched, 
 nor refuses to eyes that wait for it the pure and grave serenity 
 of its light. 
 
 And probably it is the critics' fancy for striking contrasts, 
 above referred to, with the effect produced by the Frogs, which 
 has led also to a somewhat false estimate of the attitude of 
 Aeschylus toward the political and speculative movements of 
 his age. In the Frogs he is made generally a laudator temporis 
 
 1 Frogs, 821.
 
 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 acti, though without commitment to any especial political 
 opinions. Later authors speak of his having been a conserva- 
 tive of the school of Aristeides and Kimon, and opposed to 
 certain innovations made by Pericles and Ephialtes ; it has 
 been also asserted that the honours paid to the Court of the 
 Areopagus in the Eumenides were intended as a protest against 
 the encroachments on its power which the last-named states- 
 men made. On this point, however the question of the signi- 
 ficance of the Eumenides as regards the Areopagus, it will 
 generally be agreed now that the views of K. 0. Miiller, 
 expressed in his valuable dissertations on the play, must be 
 accepted with considerable modifications. As Grote has pointed 
 out, the privilege of the Areopagus on which Aeschylus is 
 dwelling in the Eumenides, namely the judicial power in cases 
 of homicide, is the very privilege which Pericles and Ephialtes 
 left untouched ; it was the senatorial power of the Areopagus 
 which they took from it, and on this point Aeschylus does not 
 reveal either satisfaction or dissatisfaction. To some at least 
 of its readers the play would lose much of its perfection and 
 impressiveness if it seemed no longer to breathe that spirit of 
 peace and concord before which party conflicts are forgotten, 
 and to speak throughout allusively, as well as directly, of those 
 agencies of renouncement and reconcilement to which Aeschy- 
 lus looked for a solution of the perplexities of gods and men. 
 
 The supposed anti-democratic tendencies of the poet have 
 been by some critics exaggerated even to absurdity. We find 
 a widely-read English commentator saying, " His feelings evi- 
 dently incline to an excessive reverence for kings, . . . and a 
 degree of grandeur is thrown over their state such as is wholly 
 incompatible with real dislike or contempt for it." This is in- 
 deed to pervert evidence of dramatic instinct which Aeschylus 
 certainly had into evidence of political leanings which he 
 certainly had not. It would be easy enough to show, from the 
 Persians especially, but also from other passages where he is 
 concerned with a comparison of Oriental with Hellenic manners 
 and customs, 1 that Aeschylus was to the full possessed of the 
 Hellenic contempt for that barbarian surrender of the rights and 
 
 1 Such areAgam. 918-22; Eum. 185-90; Suppl 368-80, 398-401.
 
 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 duties of citizens into the hands of a single person chosen by 
 accident, which brought freemen to the level of slaves. 
 
 " Among the Easterns all save one are slaves." * 
 
 Indeed, neither the oligarchic nor the democratic party in Hellas, 
 though we find both, and especially the former, afterwards 
 tampering with the Persian king, had at that time any of that 
 natural affinity to despotism which in modern times both the 
 courtier-noble and the ochlocratic leveller not unfrequently 
 display. Nor is there any reason to suppose that Aeschylus 
 attached himself to any extreme party or ideas. Both his own 
 genius and character, and also his chronological position, furnish 
 reasons against assigning to him a share in the party spirit 
 which raged so fiercely in Athens and the other Hellenic States 
 in the middle and end of the fifth century B.C. In his time the 
 strife between oligarchy and democracy, while it had somewhat 
 subsided since the days when it had been embittered by the 
 greater pressure of poverty on an increasing population, the fear 
 of demagogic city despots, and other causes, was not yet 
 exasperated by the alternating revenges for which the Pelopon- 
 nesian war gave opportunity. Aeschylus was intensely Athenian 
 and intensely Hellenic. He could not be the first without being 
 democratic; he could not be the second and adhere to any 
 principles which would divide the Hellenes in the face of the 
 barbarian. 2 The battles of Marathon and Salamis and Plataea 
 formed the central point to which his political ideas referred 
 themselves. We can readily believe, as tradition tells, that 
 Aristeides, a hero of the Persian war, the man pre-eminent for 
 his reverence of that altar of Justice as whose priest Aeschylus 
 so often appears, would attract the poet's political as well as 
 personal confidence. But it must be remembered that it was 
 Aristeides, conservative as he was, who proposed the law by 
 which the civil offices were thrown open to election from the 
 
 1 ra ftappdpuv yap 8ov\a -irdvTa IT\T]V evbs. EURIPIDES, Helen. 276. 
 
 2 Among many instances of the Pan-Hellenic feeling of Aeschylus, one less 
 obvious than others may be referred to. We learn from Plutarch that in the 
 drama of the Meusinians, (Fragments, 48,) Theseus obtained from Adrastus 
 the burial of those who had fallen before Thebes by friendly treaty, not 
 by force of arms, as Euripides afterwards represented in the Suppliants. 
 Nor is there any passage in all that remains to us of Aeschylus containing 
 words of hostility or disparagement toward a Hellenic State.
 
 AESCHYLUS. 7 
 
 whole people. Very far removed were such men from the 
 oligarchs who, in the year 411, traded on the agony of their 
 country. And indeed the later oligarchical movements were 
 connected with a sophistic and cynically individualistic spirit, 
 which Aeschylus, and most conservatives of his time, would 
 have disliked far more than the spirit of innovation encouraged 
 and directed by Pericles. Even later, it was rather a change of 
 persons, and sometimes of policy, than a change of constitution, 
 that the Athenian conservative opposition of the older school 
 desired : we may see this in the Knights of Aristophanes, 
 \vhere there is no desire to dethrone Demos, but only to bring 
 him to his right mind, and to inspire him with distrust and 
 contempt of the demagogic schemers who enthral him and lead 
 him into trouble. In Aeschylus, the passage most directly 
 bearing on Athenian politics is the speech of Pallas in the 
 Eumenides (681-710), and the central warning of that, 
 
 " Bright watersprings with mixture of foul mire 
 Stain not, or never hope for wholesome draught," l 
 
 is one which no democrat, who is not a mere ochlocrat, need 
 repudiate. 
 
 Passing onward, then, and upward from the misconceptions 
 of litterateurs and commentators, and the travesty of playful 
 burlesque, let us proceed to the only valid material for a just 
 estimate of Aeschylus his seven remaining plays, first very 
 briefly viewing them in relation to their antecedents and sur- 
 roundings in action, thought, and art. He appeared at a time when 
 Athens was just entering on her prime, on the years when she 
 was to justify the oft-cited eulogy of Pericles, when he called 
 her " the school of Hellas;" when to her sons " the love of beauty 
 brought no extravagance, the love of knowledge no lack of 
 manly vigour ;" when no element seemed wanting to train both 
 heart and head into admirable and harmonious life. The pro- 
 gress of thought, rapid as it was, had not yet the destructive 
 aspect which it afterwards assumed. Already the public law- 
 courts, the increased acquaintance with foreign modes of 
 thought, the joyful exercise of intellectual powers, were shaping 
 a taste for dialectical inquiry ; but the multiform spirit, which 
 
 fwippoaiffi /3op/36/>y ff Sidup 
 \OLfjLiTpbv fualvuv otiirof)' fvp-fiffeis iror6v. Eum. 694-95.
 
 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 may roughly be called sophistic, was yet undeveloped. The old 
 religion, thanks to the elasticity of Hellenic theology, and its 
 identification with the national cause in the Persian war, still 
 kept a strong hold on the minds even of the most thoughtful. 
 Pallas had fought for Athens, and the Parthenon was her thank- 
 offering. Tradition seemed to be reconciled for the time with 
 reason, as aristocracy with democracy, and artistic with political 
 energy. Thus from the union of a sense of self-reliance and com- 
 pleteness with an eager interest in the spectacle and -the action 
 of life, there arose that state of calm without languor, vivid feel- 
 ing without distracting passion, which provides the best atmo- 
 sphere for artistic development. Thus of all the great literary 
 and artistic epochs of Europe this was the most propitious to 
 literature and art. In the Hellenic prime there was more of 
 life and freshness than in the age of Virgil, not to mention 
 that of Corneille and Moliere, more sanity and serenity than 
 in medieval Italy in Dante's time, or than in either England 
 or Italy at the Eenaissance, or during the religious wars of the 
 Beformatioii ; more also, it need hardly be said, than in any of 
 the European countries which felt the stimulating shock of the 
 French Eevolution. Of this age in Hellas the chief artistic 
 interpreters to us are Pindar, Aeschylus, Pheidias, and Sophocles. 
 Three of these are Athenians. But it must be remembered that, 
 splendid as the achievements of Athens were in poetry, she only 
 appeared late upon that field. The genius to which we owe the 
 poems of Homer, though Ionian, was assuredly not Attic ; and in 
 all the famous roll of lyric and gnomic poets who filled the 
 sixth and the beginning of the fifth century, the only Athenians 
 are the ancient Tyrtaeus, who dwelt among Dorians and made his 
 war-songs for the Spartan host, and the lawgiver Solon. Solon, 
 indeed, was both an Athenian patriot and a true, though not a 
 great, poet, so far as we can judge from a few fragments. In the 
 twenty or thirty iambics of Solon's still extant, we can already 
 detect some prefiguring semblance of the mighty march of the 
 Aeschylean line. But Solon was primarily a statesman and law- 
 giver, engrossed in training the first shoots of that law-abiding 
 freedom which was in the appointed time to bear such rich fruits 
 of art. That time was come when Aeschylus received his 
 first mission from Dionysus. Homer had sung for the warrior- 
 prince, and Hesiod for the toiling husbandman, Sappho for the
 
 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 lover, and Pindar for the glory of youth ; but the word of 
 Aeschylus was for the citizens of an august commonwealth, 
 whose acts and thoughts were destined 
 
 " To cast the kingdoms old 
 Into another mould." 
 
 A new form in poetry was demanded, a form which should be 
 congenial to those stirring times of action, and this demand 
 Aeschylus supplied by an unsurpassed effort of original genius. 
 Thespis, Choerilus, Pratinas, and even Phrynichus, are to us 
 mere names, but all testimony agrees in regarding Aeschylus 
 as the virtual creator of the drama. 1 For more than a century 
 before his birth, Hellas had been alive with lyric song, and the 
 fragments of that poetry of the sixth century B.C., the loss of 
 which is one of the heaviest in all literature, show us with 
 what wide range all the chords of personal feeling were swept 
 by it in turn. Moving in a parallel stream with these utter- 
 ances of personal feeling was another kind of lyric poetry of 
 graver ends and more chastened treatment the Dorian odes 
 and hymns, the " solemn music " which accompanied triumphal 
 and religious joy. When toward the beginning of the fifth cen- 
 tury the common Games and the common worship of the greater 
 Gods were at the height of their dignity, when the forces of 
 Hellas were becoming concentrated, and the national life inten- 
 sified, Pindar appeared, and gave the final lyric expression to 
 this side of Hellenic life. Aeschylus also was one of the 
 greatest of lyric poets, but as he grew up he found in the begin- 
 nings of the Athenian drama a new kind of art arising, which 
 was to draw aid from all existing kinds, and combine them into 
 a thing of new beauty and power. When a generation of men 
 is filled with high emotion and interest, as were those who saw 
 Salamis or the wreck of the Spanish Armada, it craves some 
 poetic expression, and has found none happier than the drama, 
 which shares with music the power of uniting an audience by 
 sympathy in a common interest and delight. And in the 
 Hellenic drama music itself was retained in the choric song 
 alternating with iambic dialogue, the form in which it seems to 
 
 1 It is truly astonishing to think that a second actor was only first intro- 
 duced by Aeschylus. Phrynichus, his most eminent predecessor, seems till 
 then to have employed in his dramas (if they might so be called) only choric 
 songs and dialogues of one actor with the chorus.
 
 io AESCHYLUS. 
 
 have been combined with acting with less incompatibility than 
 in any other that has been tried. In such expression the 
 vague body of emotion which might have wasted itself in 
 idle or pernicious channels finds relief in the work of a great 
 artist who interprets souls to themselves, and lifts them into 
 a larger air. Different kinds of poetry shade into each other ; 
 one of the greatest of all poems, Dante's Commedia, cannot 
 be classified it is not a drama, for there is no action, yet 
 there is a unity which makes it more than a romance. The 
 lyric is the essence of poetry, its simplest form, and can flourish 
 under much more precarious conditions of mental soil and 
 climate than either the epic or the drama. The epic is between 
 the drama and the romance, and probably the so-called 
 epics of the Cyclic poets might more properly be classed 
 as romances. 1 Hellenic drama sprang from the lyric and the 
 epic both, though primarily from the lyric; while the elegy 
 and the weighty gnomic line lend their forces blended and 
 transformed. The flexible iambics which had expressed the 
 satire of Archilochus or the wisdom of Solon are developed 
 into the poetic rhetoric of the dialogue, and the lyric odes still 
 appear in the Doric songs of the chorus, the original nucleus 
 from which the drama was expanded. Aeschylus, as has been 
 said, is one of the greatest of lyric poets, but he calls his 
 dramas " morsels left from the great banquets of Homer." In 
 the erection of the Athenian theatre there is the same blending 
 of the new and old, of the venerableness of tradition with the 
 vigour of revolution, which is the especial glory of the Athenian 
 people, who, whether as grasshopper-wearing avro^Oove^ or 
 Eupatrid descendants of gods and heroes, were yet ever the 
 first to spread sail in quest of new adventure, whether in the 
 physical or in the intellectual world. The legends of Thebes and 
 Troy, of the acts and passions of Gods and sons of Gods, were an 
 ancient treasure of the race ; but in the hands of the dramatist 
 they yielded new meaning and delight. There is no stiff and 
 formal allegory ; the figures are scarcely less life-like and real 
 than they are in Homer, but a deep and serious meaning 
 breathes through all : they are individuals still, but they are 
 also more than ever types, and through their separate action is 
 
 1 See Aristotle's Poetics, c. 23.
 
 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 revealed the action of universal laws. The plot is so implicit 
 in the situation that we are irresistibly led to compare the 
 Aeschylean drama to groups of sculpture of the same age, such 
 as those which filled the pediments of the Parthenon. Not 
 that poetry has here foregone its privileges among the arts ; 
 action there assuredly is, and such as potently effects that 
 " purgation of the terrors and pities of the mind " which 
 Aristotle conceived to be the drama's aim. Yet through the 
 whole the sense of some harmonising unity is never absent ; 
 we never feel that we may be hurried to some inconsequent 
 disappointment by the mere caprice, as it \vere, of the writer 
 or of his characters ; all is under the guardianship of those 
 powers of measure and harmony already spoken of, in the 
 general conception as in the details and the feeling. Intensity 
 without extravagance, dignity without coldness, grace without 
 enervation these qualities are found in Aeschylus, as they are 
 found everywhere in the best Hellenic art, though in degrees 
 and proportions varying with the various artists. In the por- 
 trayal of human passion, the tragedians, like Homer, are strong 
 and terrible, yet human. Their tragic agonies have neither the 
 wild and portentous violence which sometimes in the Eliza- 
 bethan drama kindles the ebullient blood to almost preter- 
 natural outbiirsts, such as seem to remove the stage from the 
 dominion of reason altogether, nor yet have they the languor 
 and the self-consciousness which mix so often with the melan- 
 choly of poets of the present age, 
 
 1 ' ove i lament! 
 Non suonan come guai, ma son sospiri." 
 
 The heroes and heroines of Hellenic story cry aloud in their 
 pain ; the torrent of their anguish is full and strong, yet we 
 feel in it an expression of natures not self-conscious, though 
 sensitive and highly and harmoniously organised, and thus it 
 has something of health in its very disorder, which seems a 
 latent antidote to its bitterness. It is what we feel in Achilles' 
 cry to the vision of his dead friend : 
 
 " But ah ! come near, let each with each embracing, 
 For one short moment feed our fill of woe. " * 
 
 dXXti fjiot S.<Tffov arriOc pivvvOa. 
 
 oi/s, 6\ooio Tf.Ta.pir&fj.fO'Ga. 76010. Iliad, xxiii. 97-8.
 
 12 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 The dramatic achievements of Aeschylus, and the poetic 
 qualities of imagination, diction, and versification which give 
 him his high place among poets, have often been dwelt upon ; 
 and if it might avail to describe what can only be felt, it would 
 be hard to say enough of the terrible and beautiful things which 
 he has revealed to us, of the imploring agony of the Danaid or of 
 the Theban suppliants ; the chivalrous and benignant constancy 
 of the king Pelasgus ; the war frenzy of the sons of Oedipus and 
 the seven chieftains in arms before the seven gates ; the baleful 
 splendours of Clytemnestra ; the piteous soul-solitude of Cas- 
 sandra ; the indignant woe and solemn vengeance of Agamem- 
 non's children ; the confusion of the Persian invader ; the psean 
 of the Hellenic patriot ; the great heart and high bearing of Pro- 
 metheus on his bed of pain. Although the simple structure and 
 few persons of the drama in the time of Aeschylus precluded 
 him, even had he been capable of it, from the " myriad-minded" 
 craftsmanship in human types which Shakespeare showed, yet in 
 Aeschylus also we feel that each character, simple as it is, is an 
 organic whole, a true creation, but the offspring of a brooding 
 imagination rather than of conscious analysis. This is the 
 secret of the great effects which he produces with his severely 
 limited means. Each of his persons, notwithstanding their 
 similarity of diction, seems almost always to bear about him an 
 atmosphere which makes his presence unmistakable. We can 
 readily believe the tradition that on the stage their silence as 
 well as their speech had its meaning and its eloquence: the 
 long silences of the Niobe and the Achilles, whom we know not, 
 sitting beside their dead ; of the Atossa, the Cassandra, the Elec- 
 tra, the Prometheus, whom we know. Let any one imagine to 
 himself what the effect must have been when, " at the limit of 
 the world," the Titan had been thrown upon the rock by the 
 huge hands of Power and Force, and nailed there by unwilling 
 Hephaestus, and after listening to their dialogue above his 
 helpless body in scornful silence, in silence also let them 
 depart, and so remaining till the place should be, as it were, 
 purified of the presence of the ministers of injustice, at last broke 
 the stillness with his despairing yet august appeal : 
 
 1 ' holy Heaven, and ye swift-winged winds, 
 And river-fountains, and the ocean-waves' 
 Innumerable laughter ; Mother Earth,
 
 AESCHYLUS. 13 
 
 And thou all-seeing Sun, I summon you, 
 Behold me, how these Gods entreat a God. 
 
 See in what stress of torment 
 
 Ten thousand years of pain 
 
 Here must I agonise." 1 
 
 If poetry is akin on one side to sculpture and painting, on 
 another side it is akin to rhetoric ; and when Aeschylus wrote 
 his plays, that great school of eloquence had been founded in 
 free-speaking Athens which afterwards produced the oratory 
 which has served as a model to the world. Homer had found a 
 place for oratory in his epic, much more might Aeschylus do so 
 in his dramas. The suppliant Danaiis and Orestes would hardly 
 have pleaded so persuasively, the dialogue of Prometheus with 
 Hermes, or of Apollo with the Furies, would hardly have been 
 so apt and telling, had not Aeschylus been at least a listener to 
 those pleadings of Athenian law-courts which obtained so wide 
 a fame for evil and for good, to the eye of Aristophanes a mere 
 solvent of morality, to the eye of the modern historian an origin 
 of moral philosophy. But in Aeschylus the poet was always 
 foremost, the logic- chopping to which the genius of Euripides 
 descends is alien and remote from him. Even looking to 
 expression alone, to him belongs a witchery of words far beyond 
 that of the orator or the rhetorician ; metrical and verbal 
 harmonies born only in a poet's mind. His imagination is of 
 that most genuinely poetic kind which is concerned primarily 
 with the truthful transfiguration of the real and abiding 
 elements of human life ; but he knows well how to use as 
 accessories the images on which genius of an inferior order 
 might be principally and ultimately employed. Although a 
 child of daylight and the dawn, he has learnt secrets of the 
 encompassing night. No poet has surpassed him in his power 
 of thrilling the mind with a sense of mystery and presentient 
 awe. None has presented more impressively the dim border- 
 land which lies, as men fancy, between the material and the 
 
 1 3) 5?oj aldrjp KO! rax^TfTfpoi irvoa.1, 
 TroTa/j.&v re irriya.1 Trovriuv re KvpaTOW 
 
 KO.I rbv ira.i>6iTTT>)v KVK\OV i)\tov KaXw' 
 /j.' ola. 7rp6s Oe&v irdcrxw Oe6s. 
 ?>ep'X_QT)ff' oi'au alKiaKnv 
 8ia.Kvai6fj.fvos rdv fj.vpieTTJ 
 Xp6voi> ddXevffu. Prometheus Sound, 88-96.
 
 14 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 spiritual. With dreams and visions he deals habitually. In the 
 seven extant plays we find five places where he bodies forth 
 apparitions of the night. There is the dream of Atossa, in 
 which she saw her son Xerxes mount his chariot behind the 
 unequally-yoked pair of woman-steeds, to be hurled to earth by 
 the fierce and fair sister who cast away his yoke from her neck, 
 and turned and rent the harness of his car. There is the dream 
 of Clytemnestra on the eve of her death-day, when she seemed 
 to herself to have brought forth a serpent that sucked from her 
 milk and blood, and a great cry rang at midnight through the 
 palace, where on the morrow her son's sword was to be at her 
 breast. There is the vision of the Furies, when Clytemnestra's 
 phantom rises to upbraid them for their slackness in avenging 
 her blood. There is the vision of Menelaus, born of his yearn- 
 ing desire, the vision that seemed Helen, but when he stretched 
 his arms to it was gone, "with wings that follow down the 
 ways of sleep." Lastly there are the dreams which lo tells, 
 the very reading of which seems to make a midnight awe and 
 ghostly stillness in the air : 
 
 " For ever to my virgin chambers came 
 Strange visions and soft voices of the night, 
 Importunately pleading : Happy maid, 
 Why tarriest thou so long in maidenhood, 
 Seeing how high espousals are awaiting 
 Thy choice ? for lo, the love of highest Zeus 
 Yearns for thy love, to enfold thee as his own." 1 
 
 Aeschylus would seem to have inclined to some such trans- 
 formed survival of a primitive belief as we find referred to in a 
 fragment of Pindar, 2 that in sleep the mind is open to influences 
 
 1 dei yap &\f/eis eVvt/^ot TrwXetf/tei'cu 
 
 ^j irapOevwvas roi)j e/toi>s irapr)y6pow 
 
 \eloiffifjuj0ois' & fj.ty' ftf5ai/J.ov K6pr), 
 
 rl irapOfVfuei dapbv, ^6v ffoi yd/j.ov 
 
 Tvxf.lv [jLeyiarov ; Zei)s yap i/xe/>ou /S^Xei 
 
 irpbs crov T^daXwrai. Kal waipe<?6at. Kvirptv 
 
 0e"Xet. Prometheus, 645-51. 
 
 8 Kal ff<2>fj.a /JLV iravruv eVerai Oavdrif TrepurQevei, 
 
 <>)bv d' <?TI \eiirerai al&vos etduXov' rb yap ecrri fdtvov 
 
 eV TroXXoZs 6velpoi$ 
 
 Sel/cwcri repirvwv e<f>epiroiffav ^aXetrCiv re Kpicriv. (Frag. 96.) 
 (And the body indeed is subject to the great power of death, but there 
 remaineth yet alive a shadow of life ; for this only is from the Gods ; and while
 
 AESCHYLUS. 15 
 
 and capable of intuitions which in waking moments are denied. 
 In one place he says : 
 
 " For oft in sleep comes light upon the soul, 
 But in the day their fate is hid from men ; " * 
 
 and in a different but still move memorable passage : 
 
 ' ' In sleep there doth before man's heart distil 
 A grievous memory of ill, 
 And makes the unwise wise against his will.'" 2 
 
 These last words may not unnaturally lead us to another 
 part of the subject, when, descending below the poetic qualities 
 of the plays, we seek to discover the religious and the moral 
 ideas which underlie them. These are by no means identical, 
 or even closely connected ; among the Hellenes morality grew 
 up separate from religion, and then as it were turned round to 
 it to demand its aid. Gods had always been stronger and 
 more beautiful than men ; men now demanded that they should 
 be also better and greater. In the form Xenophanes had given 
 to this demand it shook rudely the whole fabric of theological 
 belief. Now, whatever opinion may be held as to the existence 
 of the supernatural, it can hardly be denied that when a belief 
 in it becomes forbidden to art, art loses one of its most precious 
 means to attaining elevation and impressiveness. To sculp- 
 ture and painting especially to sculpture the possibility of 
 dealing with supernatural beings is of immense importance. 
 No other adequate symbolism has yet been found for expressing 
 visibly that idealisation of itself which must always be the 
 object of humanity's highest and deepest reverence. From the 
 Hellenic Olympus and the Christian Paradise has come all that 
 is noblest in glyptic and pictorial art. Poetry too, though its 
 resources are less exhaustible, must feel it a chilling hour when 
 the ancient shrines have shuddered at the murmured words, 
 Let us depart hence. No theology, indeed, in its popular shape, 
 
 the limbs stir it sleepeth, but unto sleepers in dreams discovereth oftentimes 
 the judgment that draweth near for sorrow or for joy.) 
 
 1 fvSovtra y&p (ppyv 6/j./j.a<riv \afjLir ptiverai, 
 
 fv rj^pq. 8t fj.o'tp' d.Trp6ffKoiros /3poTui>. Eum. 104-5. 
 
 2 (rrd^fi 8' Zv 0' ijwvtp wp6 Kapdias 
 
 fJLVTf]ffLTrri/J.WI> TT&VOS' K0.1 TTOLp' &- 
 
 KOVTO.S ?i\0e ffu<ppoveiv. Agam. 179-81.
 
 1 6 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 has been pure enough to express unmodified the highest moods 
 of the highest minds, and it was so especially in that time of 
 quickened intellectual activity and of increased acquaintance 
 with new modes of thought. Yet the old religion still kept, 
 as has been said, a real hold on the minds even of the most 
 thoughtful. But if Pindar and Aeschylus treated the primi- 
 tive theogonies with reverence, it was not the reverence of 
 a primitive theogonist ; although the happy blending of tradi- 
 tion with advance enabled them, as it were, to build a New 
 Testament on the foundations of the Old. Pindar's attitude 
 toward Hellenic mythology is comparatively easy to decide ; 
 he flatly refuses to believe or report evil of the Gods, and 
 when tradition conflicts with morality he will not scruple to 
 alter tradition before he admits it to a place in his pure and 
 stately song. At the same time, it is obvious that no compli- 
 cated or reflective scheme of theology is to be gathered from his 
 poems, and therefore no attempt to gather such has been made. 
 It is otherwise with Aeschylus. Eight and wrong, sin committed 
 and curse inherited, the intervention of protecting and punish- 
 ing supernatural powers, form so- large a part of the matter 
 with which Aeschylus deals, that he has left materials which 
 have employed the most earnest and ingenious analytic en- 
 deavour to discern among them the outlines of a system of 
 moral theology of which the poet was the prophet and evan- 
 gelist. In such analysis the most prominent subject for inquiry 
 must be found in the nature of his conception of the moral 
 government of the world, and the hands in which it is placed. 
 The old belief in the infatuation by a supernatural power as 
 the cause of guilt, which is the primitive expression of the 
 bewilderment with which the remorseful soul looks back upon 
 its sin, and the belief in inherited curses and evil destinies 
 which cling to devoted races these beliefs are treated by 
 Aeschylus in a way which makes them at once more moral and 
 more scientific. According to him, man is only blinded and 
 hastened to destruction when he has voluntarily made an evil 
 choice. 
 
 " When the fool to folly hasteth God shall speed him to his fall" 1 
 1 dXX' Srav ffTrftdy rh avrbs, X& Oebs ffwd-irrfrai. Persians, 742.
 
 AESCHYLUS. 17 
 
 are the words which the phantom of the dead Darius pro- 
 nounces on the calamities of his son. Thus, while it is only 
 consistent with the nature of things that wrongs done among 
 kindred beget wrong, and that tendencies to wild deeds are 
 inherited, yet each deed stands on its merits for j udgmeut, and 
 fairly so, because each has its cause in the passions and will of 
 the doer. The family curse is only one form, though a very 
 impressive one, of the means which it is the especial office of 
 tragedy to employ to express the terrific significance and far- 
 working effect of the human actions and passions with which 
 it deals. When the developed human spirit begins to reflect 
 on the terrors and perplexities of its destiny, the "blind 
 hopes" 1 which Prometheus gave them as his first boon grope 
 for some solution or consolation, and the prophet or the poet is 
 moved to reveal it to them in the shape of a moral government 
 of the world, discerned in the history of the generations of 
 mankind and in the conscience of the individual man. 
 
 In whose hands Aeschylus supposes this government to lie 
 is harder to decide. We have but a tithe of his works left in 
 evidence, and even these are not all agreed. If from the seven 
 plays were excluded the Prometheus, we might perhaps find it 
 easier to construct from them by conjecture a systematic theo- 
 logy. In all the other six Zeus occupies a position which is 
 almost monotheistic, so unlimited are the might, majesty, 
 wisdom, and goodness assigned to him. He is the All-causing, 
 All-sufficing, Almighty, All-seeing, All-accomplishing (Travai- 
 Tto?, Travrap/cris, TrajKpar^, Tra^oTrn/?, TravreXijs) Lord of Lords, 
 Most Holy of Holies. 2 " In thy hands is the balance ; what 
 can mortals accomplish without thee V asks one Chorus ; 
 another, " What without Zeus can befall any man V To Zeus 
 Apollo refers every oracle that issues from his shrine ; 3 even 
 Justice is called by Eteokles the child of Zeus. It is Zeus 
 
 ev avrois \irt8a.$ /cary/acra. 
 (Blind hopes I brought to dwell among mankind. ) Prom. 250. 
 
 2 Aval; CLVaKTUV, /JLCLKdpUV 
 
 fj-aKdprare. Suppliants, 524-25. 
 8 oi)7TW7ror' elirov fJ-avriKoiffiv ev 6p6vois, 
 OVK hvSpbs, ov yvvaiKtis, ov ir6Xews irtpi, 
 d /*7J K\v<rat Zeds 'QXvfjiiriuv irar-ftp. 
 
 (Ne'er spake I yet from my oracular throne, 
 B
 
 1 8 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 who "leads mortals to wisdom, in that he ordained that to 
 suffer is to learn." 1 
 
 To the acceptance of this lofty conception of Zeus as the 
 final and consistently held theological theory of Aeschylus, 
 there is one obstacle, but that is one of great importance, the 
 Prometheus Bound. The loss of the Prometheus Fire-bearing, 
 and still more of the Prometheus Unbound, is a loss of which 
 we cannot more accurately calculate the magnitude than to be 
 certain that it is immense. In all literature there is no blank 
 so cruel to our highest desires. But whatever reconciliation 
 may have completed the story, nothing could altogether efface 
 the impression which the poet unmistakably means to convey, 
 that the Power which stretched on his painful rock and hurled 
 to Tartarus the giver of good things to men, was in that act 
 overstepping the limits of wisdom and righteousness, was 
 guilty, in some measure, of the reckless violence which in other 
 plays he judges and abhors. Zeus does not indeed appear 
 himself in the play, but his messenger and representative 
 Hermes cannot but be taken as expressing the spirit of his 
 rule, against which the " anima altera e disdegnosa " of Pro- 
 metheus is exasperated by his own wrongs and the wrongs 
 of men. This Hermes is not the righteous protector of 
 Agamemnon's children and of the suppliant Danaids, not 
 the embodiment of calm and friendly skill and grace, such as 
 Praxiteles wrought him at Olympia, but the harsh official 
 taunter of a fallen adversary, alert with a boyish insolence of 
 new intoxicating success. And his very errand, his threaten- 
 
 Of man, of woman, or of commonwealth, 
 Answer unbidden of the Olympians' sire.) Eum. 616-18. 
 And compare Fragment 79 : 
 
 (rrAXew 6'?rwj ro^iara, ravra yap warijp 
 Zei)s tyKaOiei Aol-lq. 6f<nrtfffJi.aTa. 
 
 (Send with all speed, for thus the Father Zeua 
 
 Gave Loxias charge to speak his oracle. ) 
 
 1 rbv (ppoveiv j3porof>s 68u- 
 ffavra, rbv TraOrj /uuiOos 
 Otv-ra. Kvpiwlx etfr - Agamemnon, 175-77. 
 
 Accumulation of instances in this sense may be found in Dronke's Religiose 
 und sittliche Vorstellungen des Aeschylos und Sophokles. The author does not 
 seem to feel so strongly aa I do the force of the arguments in a different sense 
 which the Prometheus affords.
 
 AESCHYLUS. 19 
 
 ing inquiry of the secret which would save his master from 
 ruin, confesses the limits of the wisdom and power, no less than 
 of the goodness, of Zeus. 
 
 To bring this drama into consistency with the rest, there 
 would seem to be two considerations especially to be taken 
 into account. The first is, that the utterances on the powers 
 and attributes of Gods are, after all, dramatic, even when 
 proceeding from the Chorus. For the Chorus is always in 
 Aeschylus a personage concerned in the drama ; it has ceased 
 to absorb the whole, as in the dithyrambic songs from which 
 the drama arose ; but it never stands quite outside the whole 
 action, as in Euripides, and to some extent in Sophocles. 
 Thus we must remember that when the Danaid or Theban 
 suppliants, or even the chorus of Argive elders in the Aga- 
 memnon, deeply moved as they are for the fate of their king 
 and city, invoke an all-just and all-ruling Power, this is 
 primarily and essentially the expression of that longing for a 
 saviour in the day of trouble which can intensify belief held 
 lightlier in lighter hours, and can even develop what seem 
 intuitions of powers and influences unthought of, because 
 mmeeded, before. 
 
 The second consideration is, that there are indications, though 
 grievously scanty, of the reconciliation which was effected in 
 the Prometheus Unbound. This much we know, that Prome- 
 theus was delivered by Herakles, son of Zeus and of the mortal 
 Alcmene, the seed of the woman To, who had received recom- 
 pense for her maddened wanderings when she rested by the 
 banks of Nile. On his release Prometheus tells the fateful 
 secret, and the danger is turned away for ever from the Olym- 
 pian throne. In Pindar the revelation is made, not by Pro- 
 metheus, but by his mother Themis, in that majestic passage of 
 the seventh Isthmian ode, which may here be cited to fill the 
 gap in the Aeschylean story, and tell the end of the tale of 
 divine renunciations in obedience to that Moipa, or Allotment, 
 which seems a mysterious universal behind the individualities 
 even of Gods, a personification of the law which constrains all 
 forces, personal and impersonal, in nature to fulfil the law of 
 their being by which the cosmic order is sustained : 
 
 " Thereof was the Gods' council mindful, what time for the 
 hand of Thetis there was strife between Zeus and glorious
 
 20 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 Poseidon, each having desire that she should be his fair bride, 
 for love had obtained dominion over them. 
 
 " Yet did not the wisdom of the immortal Gods fulfil for them 
 such marriage when they had heard a certain oracle. For 
 Themis of wise counsels spake in the midst of them how it 
 was predestined that the sea-Goddess should bear a royal off- 
 spring mightier than his father, whose hand should wield a 
 bolt more terrible than the lightning or the dread trident, if 
 she came ever into the bed of Zeus, or of brethren of Zeus. 
 
 " ' Cease ye herefrom : let her enter a mortal's couch, and see 
 her son fall in war, who shall be as Ares in the might of his 
 hands, and as the lightning in the swiftness of his feet. My 
 counsel is that ye give her to be the heaven-sent prize of 
 Peleus, son of Aiakos, whom the speech of men showeth to 
 be their most righteous, an offspring of lolkos' plain. Thus 
 straightway let the message go forth to Cheiron's cave divine, 
 neither let the daughter of Nereus put a second time into your 
 hands the ballot-leaves of strife. So on the evening of the 
 mid-month moon shall she unbind for the hero the fair girdle 
 of her virginity.' 
 
 " Thus spake the Goddess her word to the sons of Kronos, 
 and they bowed their everlasting brows. Nor failed her words 
 of fruit, for they say that to Thetis' bridals came those two 
 kings even with the rest." 1 
 
 Renouncement and reconcilement these are the inseparable 
 healing agencies to which the mind of Aeschylus turned, when 
 he contemplated the tumult of passions and ambitions, whether 
 found in the Assembly of Athens, or in the palace of Mykenae, 
 or in the Olympian council-hall of Gods. The conception which 
 would seem most nearly to solve the difficulties of the subject 
 seems to be one which would certainly also be congenial to the 
 genius of Aeschylus ; it is that he recognised a certain progress 
 and education even among Gods, that in the interval between 
 the binding of Prometheus and his release, Zeus and the new 
 Gods, while retaining supremacy, had not been without their 
 share of care and fear, though not of actual misfortune, and 
 had learnt and unlearnt much of the great teacher, Time. 2 
 
 1 Pindar, Isthm. vii. 26-47. 
 
 2 d\\' fKStddffKei irdvd' 6 y^pdffKUv xpt> v S- 
 
 (All things are taught by the great teacher, Time.) Prom. 981.
 
 AESCHYLUS. 21 
 
 Thus, while he dramatised the deliverance of Prometheus, he 
 seems to have adopted also the tradition which spoke of how 
 the dethroned Kronos had been released from his bonds, 1 and 
 had been given, as Pindar tells, an abode in the Islands of the 
 Blest, not unvisited by his son, and ruling among the spirits of 
 the good and great. 2 
 
 Both the considerations which have been urged on this 
 subject are expressed by that most striking passage in the 
 Agamemnon, where the Chorus most emphasise their appeal to 
 Zeus : 
 
 " Zeus, whosoe'er he be, if this name please his ear, 
 By this name I bid him hear ; 
 Nought but Zeus my soul may guess, 
 Seeking far and seeking near, 
 Seeking who shall stay the stress 
 Of its fond and formless fear. 
 For he who long ago was great, 
 Filled with daring and with might, 
 Now is silent, lost in night : 
 And the next who took his state 
 Met his supplanter too, and fell, and sank from sight." 8 
 
 Here, while Zeus is made the object of glorification and earnest 
 appeal, the mythic account of the divine dynasties is yet 
 accepted, and the strange vagueness of the opening address 
 symbolises the poet's half-unconscious sense of the insufficiency 
 of the mythology to satisfy his aspiration toward an embodi- 
 ment of the highest good. It is difficult for a modern European, 
 accustomed to a religion with a body of doctrine formulated 
 by Greek metaphysic and Roman law, to realise the fluctuating, 
 though always individual, character of the Hellenic Gods, or how 
 
 1 Ewmen. 645. 2 Pindar, 01. ii. 70. 
 
 3 Zei)s, Saris TTOT' tffrlv, el r65' av- 
 
 T(f <f>l\0t> 
 
 Tovrl> vtv 
 
 OVK lx 
 
 ira.vr' 
 
 Tr\r}v Aids, el rb fidrav dirb (ppovrlSot 
 
 ovd' 8o-m irdpoiOev fy 
 
 Ta/j./j.dxv Opdffei fipijwv, 
 
 ovdtv &v X^fat trplv &v. 
 
 8s 5' tTTfir' a<j>v, rpiaK- 
 
 rrjpos outran TWX&V. Ayam. 160-72.
 
 22 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 a belief in them which cannot be called unreal was yet con- 
 sistent with acquiescence in the saying of Herodotus that 
 Homer and Hesiod first settled their genealogies and attributes. 
 A similar but still greater fluctuation seems to have prevailed, 
 and to prevail still, in India; and even in Catholic Europe 
 something like it appeared, in spite of the lateness of the time, 
 when the central controlling force of the Papacy was shaken 
 and maimed; while another unsettlement of the attitude of 
 worshippers towards objects of their worship seems to have 
 occurred among Mahometans when they separated into Sunnis 
 and Shiahs. The Hellenic Gods, while always regarded as 
 stronger and more beautiful than men, only acquired that 
 special claim to allegiance which a moral interference can 
 support, when specialised, so to speak, in relation to some 
 human duties placed under their guarding care. The in- 
 stinctive idea that God will protect the right finds indeed 
 such utterance as the exclamation of the old Laertes in the 
 Odyssey, when he hears of the slaying of the wooers : 
 
 " Still then ye live, Zeus and Olympian Gods, 
 If verily vengeance hath the wooers found." 1 
 
 But it was only Zet"? Eewo?, 'Epicelos, 'I/cea-ios, the Guardian of 
 Host and Guest, of the Landmark, of the Suppliant, who, to 
 the ordinary believer, was reckoned a present God who would 
 avenge or aid. It was thus that the forces outside humanity, 
 which the Hellenic imagination conceived as Gods, took shape 
 and definite relation to human conduct ; a relation in which 
 both sides had, at least for Aeschylus, their several obligations; 
 for Apollo himself shrinks from the thought of having the 
 blood of Orestes on his head : 
 
 "For dreadful among Gods and men alike, 
 The suppliant's curse, if uncompelled I yield him." a 
 
 One very striking proof, among others, of what has been said, 
 occurs also in the Oresteia. 3 It is by the Erinyes, the avengers 
 
 1 ZeO vdrep, ?j pa tr' Zffre Oeol Kara (MKpbv "0\v/j,iroi>, 
 
 el frebv fjLvriffrijpes a.T&ada\ov vppiv UTiffav. Odyssey, xxiv. 351. 
 
 2 dfivi) yhp v f}poToi(ri KO.V 6eois TrAet 
 
 17 irpocrrpoTraiov fJ.rjvis, et TrpoSui <r<p' CKUV. Eumen. 233-34. 
 8 Under this name is generally known the trilogy composed of the Aga-
 
 AESCHYLUS. 23 
 
 of blood, that Orestes is pursued for slaying his mother, and 
 yet it was also by foretelling the wrath of these very Erinyes 
 that Apollo urged him to the deed. 1 So fluctuating is the 
 personification, though the idea is clear beneath each shape it 
 takes. 2 And we feel that the real worship of Aeschylus, 
 though it may attach itself to this God or to that, to Zeus, 
 Apollo, or Pan, 3 when he comes to avenge the orphan nestling 
 or the orphan child, is really independent of the persons, and 
 belongs to the moral law which they execute and represent. 
 
 It is not however for the poet, especially the dramatic poet, 
 directly to inculcate moral or religious doctrine ; the essentially 
 important question under this head is, In what region of 
 ethical feeling does he chiefly move, what ethical qualities and 
 laws does he present most impressively, and what ethical ideal 
 do they indicate and indirectly communicate to the spec- 
 tator or reader of his work ? Here Aeschylus ranks with 
 Dante and Milton, and in some ways above both. We may 
 distinguish two ethical qualities especially which he has glori- 
 fied, and with which he is above all to be identified. One 
 is the self-control, the sound-mindedness (awc^poo-uvrf), and 
 respect for the rights and feelings of others which the artistic 
 
 memnon, the Choephoroe, and the Eumenides. But when in the Frogs of 
 Aristophanes Euripides requires Aeschylus to recite the prologue of the 
 Oresteia, he answers by the first lines of the Choephoroe. The evidence 
 against the statement (commonly accepted since Welcker wrote) that dramas 
 were habitually exhibited in trilogies or tetralogies, is succinctly stated in a 
 paper by Mr. H. Richards in the Journal of Philology, 1878. 
 
 1 #XXas 8' t<f>uvfi Trpcxr/SoXas 'Epivvuv. Choephoroe, 283. 
 
 2 It must of course be understood too, that even after Homer and Hesiod 
 an immense body of infinitely various local traditions as to supernatural 
 persons remained, which the most curious theologian could not expect to 
 master entirely. Thus for instance we read in Pausanias that the legend of 
 Glaucus was told (plainly for the first time) to both Pindar and Aeschylus 
 when they were at Anthedon, the legend's home, that Pindar made some 
 slight mention of it in his poetry, while Aeschylus took it for the subject of 
 a play. 
 
 8 viraros 8' diow % TIS 'Air6\\ut>, 
 1) H&v, $ Zfvs, olwv60pooi> 
 y6oi> 6!-v(36av rCivde fJ-eroiKuv 
 i>ffTp6iroii>ov 
 
 Trowel Trapaficiffiv ''Epivtii'. Agam. 55-59. 
 The use of the indefinite rts is of still further significance.
 
 24 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 instinct of the Hellene helped to make a capital and constant 
 virtue in his ethical ideal. With this virtue the Pythago- 
 reanism of Aeschylus, 1 like the Catholicism of Dante and the 
 Puritanism of Milton, may have mingled something of 
 asceticism, but with him, as with those other two, it was very 
 far from the morbid asceticism of the fanatic, who thinks that 
 by maiming his own humanity he shall gratify a fiend dis- 
 guised as God ; it was an asceticism based on a recognition of 
 a supreme and harmonious order, by conforming whereto, and 
 so only, human nature entered through discipline into the pos- 
 session of its full privileges and capacities. The other quality is 
 more peculiarly emphasised in Aeschylus than in other Hellenic 
 poets, partly owing to his individual character, partly to the time 
 when he lived, and the mighty acts in which he had borne a 
 part: this was the virtue of indomitable resistance to unjust 
 oppression, and of valour in a righteous cause. The issue of 
 the Persian war seemed to the Hellenes the most signal judg- 
 ment more signal even than any overthrow of their own city- 
 despots and oligarchies which had ever descended on that sin 
 which was the opposite of the virtue of measured self-control, 
 the sin of vftpis, of insolence, ready to trample in violence over 
 law and liberty to gratify selfish lust and pride. The feelings of 
 the religious Hellene who had fought at Salamis and Plataea 
 were in this like those of the English Puritan who had fought 
 at Marston Moor and Naseby ; so clearly did a righteous God 
 seem to have triumphed through their arms. Nowhere could 
 this feeling be so strong as in Athens, where the ruins of her 
 temples in the Acropolis, profaned and burnt by the invader, 
 had looked down a few months after on the Persian wrecks round 
 Psyttaleia. And when Aeschylus wrote the Persians, Athens 
 as yet bore her exceeding weight of glory with majesty and self- 
 control. Perhaps even a more peculiar triumph for her than 
 
 1 It is impossible that anything definite should be known of the relation 
 of Aeschylus either to the Pythagoreanism or to the religious mysticisms of 
 his day. As to the latter, the results of such interesting and valuable 
 researches and speculations as those of Kreuzer and Guigniaut, and the like, 
 seem to point to the conclusion that this period of Hellenic civilisation was 
 less inclined to mysticism than either the earlier time in which the worship of 
 "pre-Dorian" divinities was more prominent, or a later time which inclined 
 to ascetic or sensual rites and mysteries of the East.
 
 AESCHYLUS. 25 
 
 Salamis itself was when the allied fleet turned away from the 
 corrupted Pausanias, affecting with his Persian dress, with his 
 Egyptian and Median bodyguards, the bearing and habits of a 
 despot, to Aristeides, simple and open, strong and self -controlled, 
 the perfection of an Athenian gentleman, a trusted leader 
 among soldiers, an equal citizen among citizens, dwelling ever 
 with high thoughts and working for great and patriotic ends, and 
 chose him with one accord to be their chief. And Aristeides 
 was the object of Aeschylus' warmest devotion, the man to 
 whom he did felicitous and noble homage in the lines in which 
 the Theban messenger describes Amphiaraiis, 
 
 " Who bare no blazon on his shield, 
 Who only cares to be, not seem, the best, 
 Gathering the harvest of a soul profound, 
 Wherefrom grow forth his counsels pure and high." 1 
 
 But it was the companionship of that other virtue of indo- 
 mitable valour in a good cause which made so bright the gentle 
 moderation of Aristeides and of Athens, the spirit in which the 
 city of Pallas had arisen to face the invader alone, when in the 
 other states of Hellas " there were great searchings of heart," 
 when some of the mightiest quailed, and shrank more from 
 danger than from the coward's curse the curse pronounced by 
 the Hebrew Deborah against the men of Meroz, " because they 
 came not to the help of the Lord, to the help of the Lord against 
 the mighty." No Athenian could ever forget the day when a 
 second storm of invasion threatened his devastated land, and 
 there came into his Agora the Peloponnesian envoy, who prayed 
 Athens to forget the desertion of her allies and stand forward 
 once more as the bulwark of Hellas ; and over against him the 
 Macedonian prince, who in the name of the Persian king 
 offered her safety for herself and dominion over her fellow- 
 Hellenic states, on that one easy-seeming condition, " if thou 
 wilt fall down and worship me ;" nor how each had his answer 
 from the Athenian people : how they told the Spartans that they 
 thanked them for their offer of shelter and supplies, but that 
 
 ffij(i.a 5' otiK tirTJv KVK\(f' 
 ov yap 5oKeii> Hpiaros, d\\' elvai 8^\ei, 
 v &\oKa dia <(>pfvbs KO.piroviJ.evos, 
 TO. KeSfii p\affTdvet ftov\fvfj.ara. 
 
 The Seven against Thebes, 591-94.
 
 26 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 was not what they desired ; let Sparta send men to fight 
 beside them against the barbarian : how they bade the Mace- 
 donian go back to those who sent him, and say that so long as 
 the sun should hold his course in heaven they would be the 
 irreconcilable enemies of the invaders who had desolated their 
 homes and burnt with fire the temples of their Gods. 
 
 One worthy poetic monument of the great war has been left 
 to us by Aeschylus in unmistakable form in the drama of the 
 Persians. It is the counterpart of that colossal statue of 
 Nemesis which stood eloquent upon the plain of Marathon. 
 But the spirit of the struggle can be discerned also in the Seven 
 against Thebes ; that drama, as Aristophanes called it, " full of 
 the War-God," 1 and more profoundly still, even if less obviously, 
 in the Prometheus Bound. It may be permitted to dwell briefly on 
 the consummate art with which, under the simplest and severest 
 forms, Aeschylus has made the mighty central figure stand out, 
 how admirably its qualities are relieved and accentuated by the 
 successive surrounding personages, even in the one play which 
 is left to us. It would indeed have been of the deepest interest 
 to have known from his treatment of the story how the 
 Deliverer's Deliverer, Herakles, was in turn portrayed in the 
 Prometheus Unbound; how these great souls greeted one another 
 in the wilderness, when in the year of redemption the process 
 of the ages had brought them face to face. In the Prometheus 
 who remains to us, the time-serving good-nature of his would-be 
 counsellor Oceanus, the sight and foresight of the sufferings 
 of his fellow-victim lo, the remorse of Hephaestus under 
 constraint of his hateful office, the taunts and threats of 
 Hermes, or of the giant Power, all call forth the bitter- 
 ness of just resentment, and intensify the grim and scornful 
 endurance which he has summoned to meet his torment. 
 One softer element there is to relieve the sombre stern- 
 ness of the whole, the bright and tender personality of the 
 daughters of Ocean, who come to visit Prometheus in his woe, 
 and form the chorus of the play. Aeschylus was reproached 
 by the partisans of Euripides for making small account of 
 female character in his works, but whether this was due to real 
 indifference or to a reserve which will bear another interpreta-
 
 AESCHYLUS. 27 
 
 tion, may at least be questioned. A Beatrice was impossible 
 to Hellenic art; this was the one thing lacking to it; but 
 within Hellenic limits, and they were not narrow, Aeschylus 
 was less deficient on this point than has been supposed. He 
 is more careful to preserve the feminine attributes of Electra 
 under her dire mission of vengeance than is either of the other 
 great tragedians. His judgment of Helen is sterner than 
 Homer's, but the vision he evokes of her is not less magi- 
 cally fair. For pity and beauty nothing in poetry can surpass 
 his contrast of the hour when Iphigeneia's pleading eyes " as in 
 a picture " struck her sacrificers to the heart, with the happy 
 times when her pure voice sang free and joyously in her home, 
 to gladden the same father whom fate now made her murderer. 
 But no character is more truly womanly, more winning in its 
 weakness and in its strength, the weakness of inexperienced 
 timidity, the strength of self-forgetful devotion, than is the fair 
 collective personality of these sisters of the sea. Their first 
 approach is perceived before they are arrived ; Prometheus 
 breaks off the " large utterance " of the iambics of his first 
 soliloquy, he feels another presence than he had known of late : 
 
 " Ah, ah, but what fragrance 
 
 Is wafted anear ? 
 What murmur comes stealing 
 
 Untraced to my ear, 
 Of God, or man, or blended of the twain I" 1 
 
 Tears are in their eyes, and words of compassion on their lips, 
 while yet at first a half-timid glee at their own daring in 
 visiting the victim of the wrath of the new king of heaven, an 
 eager curiosity as to his eventful story, give a touch of child- 
 like nature to their speech. Their traditional sympathies are 
 with the old order of things which Zeus has supplanted, but 
 they cannot see how it can be of profit to resist the supreme 
 power once established as supreme ; they are little conversant 
 with ideas, and when Prometheus imfolds the history of his 
 championship of the human race, and enumerates the benefits 
 he gave it, they are but slightly moved to sympathy with the 
 
 1 a, a, e , ea 
 
 ris ax&j r ^ <55yU& irpoatirTO. fj.' d^e-yxrjs, 
 
 debffvros, -fj /3/36reios, -f) KeKpa^vrj ; Prom. 114-16.
 
 28 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 " creatures of a day," whom they have never known ; they are 
 still absorbed by the sight and prospect of the Titan's pain, 
 and press him to end it, even if it must be by submission. 
 But when Hermes, baffled and scorned by Prometheus, bids 
 them flee from the wrath to come, which is to hurl the rock 
 they stand on into hell, then at last their reply makes it plain 
 that it was from no selfish indifference to the hero's honour, 
 but only from an over- anxious care for his wellbeing, that they 
 counselled him before : 
 
 ' ' Other bidding bear if thou wouldst bend us ; 
 
 Tak'st thou us for traitors to our friend ? 
 Nay, with him, with him, unbowed to baseness, 
 Be it ours to suffer to the end." 1 
 
 On their heads then be the consequences of their folly such 
 are Hermes' last words : and he is scarcely gone when the 
 wrath of Zeus descends upon the rock, and Prometheus' last 
 cry of indignant defiance is heard amid the tempest and the 
 fire: 
 
 " Lo in deed, no more in word, the earthquake ! 
 Hark, the thunder ! lo, the lightnings leap ! 
 Dark with dust and torn with warring whirlwinds 
 Crash the skies, confounded with the deep. 
 
 Zeus himself amid the awful onset 
 
 Hurls me hellward to Tartarean gloom : 
 Earth, my mother ! Heaven, thou light of all things ! 
 
 Hear ye, see ye, my unrighteous doom I" 3 
 
 1 fiXXo TI falivfi Kal impa/jivOov fj.' 
 6 TI Kal irelaeis' ov yap 77 irov 
 Tovr6 ye r\i]Tbv iraptcrvpas ZTTOS. 
 TTWS /J.e K\eveis K 
 /j.era rovS 1 8 ri x 
 TOVS irpoS&ras yap fj.iffe?v Z/j.a0ov, 
 
 KOVK tffTl v6<TO$ 
 
 Tiv' awiirTvaa. fj.a\\ov. Prom. 1063-70. 
 
 tpyt{> KOVK^Tl /J.v6<{) 
 
 la 5' lyxw irapa/jLVKarai 
 jSpovrrjs, XiKes 5' fK\dfj.irovffi 
 ffTepoirfjs fdrrupoi, 
 ffTp&/j.j3oi St Kbvw dXiffffovffi, 
 aKtprq. 5' avt/j.uv Trvev/j-ara iravrtav
 
 AESCHYLUS. 29 
 
 The Prometheus Bound, as is the case with a few of the 
 highest works of genius, is laden with mighty meanings which 
 wait on Time to be unrolled. Prometheus himself may be 
 called a type at once of the Past and of the Future ; he 
 belongs to the primeval race of deities, but he suffers for having 
 anticipated the process of the ages, for having helped the new- 
 born race of man, for having acted on his own vision of things 
 to come which others could not see. Zeus represents the 
 Present, with its exigencies, its imperiousness, and its force ; 
 for the time he forgets the traditions and benefits of the Past, 
 and ignores and would stifle the Future ; his only concern is to 
 keep in being the order and administration with which he is 
 identified, and to which it is not unnatural, it is almost neces- 
 sary, though it is still unjust, that he should be resolved to 
 make all claims bow. There have been situations in modern 
 revolutions which might well remind us of this contrast. 
 
 It could hardly be that the august and beautiful conception 
 of a champion and saviour of men, enduring for their sake the 
 extremity of agony, yet not suffered to remain in Hell, should fail 
 to strike the Greek-speaking Christian Fathers as a prefigure- 
 ment of the great tide of human yearning which found its most 
 impressive manifestation when the western world swore alle- 
 giance to the Son of Man crucified on Calvary, foreshadowed 
 by the Son of Earth crucified on Caucasus, and claiming the 
 supremacy of Godhead by virtue of his oppressors' taunt, He 
 saved others, himself he cannot save. 
 
 The only work of Aeschylus later than the Prometheus which 
 we possess is the trilogy in which he tells the fortunes of the 
 house of Agamemnon. If it is the passion for freedom which 
 finds pre-eminent expression in such Aeschylean treatment of 
 the story of Prometheus as remains to us, it is the equally vital 
 desire for Order and Harmony which is satisfied in the last play 
 which came from the poet's hand, the Eumenides. From this 
 
 j-WTerdpaKTai d' aldrip irbvrtf. 
 Totd5' fir' /j.ol pnri] Ai6dev 
 revxovffa <j)b^ov ore/xet tpavepus. 
 c3 /j,T)Tpbs ^/ii;s (Tafias, w irdvTUv 
 alOrjp Koivbv <pdos elXicrffuv, 
 
 j.' ws /c8ca ird<rx u '> Prom. 1080-93.
 
 30 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 we may indeed divine somewhat of how the Prometheus 
 Unbound must have ended. Here the half-blind worship of 
 half-blind forces, though arrayed in its full pomp of terror, 
 yields to a more excellent revelation. In so doing it yields in 
 fact to what is best in itself. Blood for Uood, the old law had 
 said : this was enough for it. The new law is awful as the old, 
 but juster, and will distinguish between degrees of homicide. 
 Vengeance for Iphigeneia may be the plea of Clytemnestra, as 
 vengeance for Agamemnon is the plea of Orestes. But the 
 new tribunal shall discover beneath the plea of Clytemnestra 
 the selfish motives of lust and guilty fear. The plea of Orestes 
 shall be allowed to save the slayer, though after an agony such 
 as must needs follow a deed of so wild justice. For, as has 
 been said, the old law yields to what was its own best part. 
 The Eumenides are not deprived of their office, but resume it 
 in allegiance to the new dispensation. All through the Oresteia 
 the moral judgment is appealed to by revenges and recrimina- 
 tions of varying justice. And thus the stories of Orestes and 
 of Hamlet, while they have much of likeness, have much more 
 of difference. The interest in Hamlet is primarily in the 
 persons and in the situation : the interest in the Oresteia is 
 primarily in the disentangling of the laws which govern the 
 moral development of the race. 
 
 It is significant that the last arbitrament which lays finally 
 the demon of the house of Tantalus rests not with the Zeus of 
 either the upper or the under world, 1 but with a council of just 
 men, as though to show that to the conscience of humanity the 
 ultimate appeal must lie. It is only when the votes of the 
 Areopagites are equally divided that Athene adds hers, and 
 turns the balance for acquittal. Then the whole tumult of 
 conflicting passions, rights, and duties is resolved in an august 
 harmony, and passes upward into a stormless air. 
 
 If we are thrilled and awed by merely reading this majestic 
 drama, what must it have been to see and hear as it was pre- 
 
 1 See the Suppliants, 230-31 : 
 
 Kd/cet ducdfei ra/j.Tr\aK^fj.ad', us \6yos, 
 Zei)s $\Xoj tv Kafj.ov<riv vcrTdras diKas. 
 
 (Among the dead, they say, that other Zeus 
 Holds a last judgment of the sins of men. )
 
 AESCHYLUS. 31 
 
 sented on the Athenian stage ? And when at evening the play 
 was played out, and its solemn voices still were in his ears, 
 the Athenian whose path home lay north-westward passed 
 thither under the very hill of Ares where the momentous 
 verdict was pronounced, and beside the cave haunted by the 
 dread powers so hardly appeased ; but his lifted eyes met the 
 sunlit western front of her shrine who had prevailed for mercy 
 and right, and could discern the statuary of the pediment, the 
 monument of the primeval triumph when she won his Athens 
 to be her own. 
 
 This was the last drama written by Aeschylus, and its calm 
 ending, while it deprives it of none of the solemnity of tragedy, 
 seems to cast back a mild light over all the terrors which his 
 spell had called into being before, over the troublous mysteries 
 of theology and human fate. He leaves us rejoicing in the 
 triumph of the two brightest and wisest, the "highest and 
 most human," of all the Hellenic divinities. One is Athene, 
 queen of light, the most cherished child of Zeus, 
 
 " Who only of gods may know that chamber's keys 
 Where sleeps the sealed thunder of her sire," 1 
 
 yet for her people's sake is now most patient, and " will not 
 tire of speaking gentle words " 2 to the resentful brood of Night. 
 The other is Apollo, " la lieta delfica Deita," the god invoked 
 as healer and helper in time of pestilence and war, the Apollo 
 on whom Herakles called to guide his arrow straight against 
 the eagle which preyed upon Prometheus, when the hour of 
 his deliverance drew nigh. 3 And those whom such coinci- 
 dences affect may remember that to these two deities, among 
 all the Gods of Hellas, belong, as it happens, the only two cer- 
 tainly ascribed temples of which more than the merest ruins 
 are still standing on Hellenic soil. Athene's is on the Acro- 
 polis of Athens, beneath which a new life struggles feebly, yet 
 not all ignobly, toward some glimmer of the ancient day. 
 Apollo's is at the lonely verge of the Arcadian mountain- 
 
 1 KO.I K\ySas olda. Sw/j-druv fjrf>vr) Oeuiv 
 
 v olj Kepctw6s tanv to'tfipa.yi.o'ij.ti'os. Eum. 827-28. 
 3 otiroi Ka/jLov/j.a.1 <roi Xtyovaa. ra.ya.6d. Eum. 881. 
 8 'Aypttis 5' 'AT^XXwp 6p6bv Wvvoi /3Aos. 
 (Hunter Apollo guide my arrow straight.) Fray. 191.
 
 32 AESCHYLUS. 
 
 forest, high above forgotten Phigaleia, and looking south beyond 
 Eira and Ithome toward his unredeemed Cretan home. 
 
 Until Aeschylus was forty-one years old no play of his was 
 crowned at the Dionysiac competition, and again in his later 
 years the growing fame of Sophocles seems to have somewhat 
 overshadowed his. But he had dedicated his works to Time, 1 
 and the dedication was approved. To his plays the Athenians 
 assigned the unique privilege that they should be acted after 
 his death at the public cost, and to Hellenic colonies he 
 became, in the phrase of M. Victor Hugo, the guardian of their 
 minority, their preserver from barbaric contamination. 2 In a 
 quaint but touching simile M. Hugo has compared the function 
 of the colossal poet among these children of Hellas to that of 
 the huge and kindly elephants (" ces bontes enormes ") who 
 watch over infants at play in the jungle round an Indian 
 homestead. To us at this distance of time and thought his 
 relation must rather be expressed by some figure of less fami- 
 liar intercourse. There are a few great poets of past ages 
 who seem to us, by a not dishonourable illusion, even greater 
 than themselves, who have become in our eyes as it were 
 invested with the attributes of the wonderful and beautiful 
 things of inanimate nature, of ever-flowing rivers and solemn 
 hills, or of the signs of heaven. And we may liken Aeschylus 
 to some golden-armoured constellation, whose first rising was 
 when the sky was thronged with potent fires, yet found there 
 no radiance of which his own was less than peer. Then the 
 mists and storm-clouds of barbarism hid him a long time, and 
 when he again became visible he seemed to have receded far 
 into the vault ; he reveals a mere fragment of his effulgence, 
 and of his seventy stars but seven. These at least remain to 
 us, and shall now be taken away no more. Well is it for the 
 reasoning soul that has received their influence on her birth, 
 and can still feel their presence in the firmament, austere and 
 yet benign. E. M. 
 
 1 Athenaeus, viii. 347. 
 
 s Le theatre eschylien gtait comme chargg de surveiller le bas age des 
 colonies. Victor Hugo's "William Shakespeare," p. 216.
 
 THE THEOLOGY AND ETHICS 
 OF SOPHOCLES. 1 
 
 IN his own generation Sophocles was eminent for his piety. 
 Though he lived at a time when most men were disengaging 
 themselves from their traditional religion, he remained true to 
 the old faith ; he believed in the gods of his age and nation. 
 At the same time we find in his writings some of the noblest 
 thoughts on religion and ethics recorded in antiquity. Thus 
 it is that two elements of Greek religion, the mythological and 
 the ethical, are combined in his dramas, and, incongruous as 
 these elements often are, there is no attempt to separate them. 
 Zeus is the upholder of the eternal laws of justice ; he dwells 
 beyond the reach of time, in a light " which no man may 
 approach unto." Zeus is also the lover of Semele and Alcmene, 
 the father of children half-human, half-divine. The incon- 
 sistency of such a presentation of the divine being would be 
 fatal if the dramas of Sophocles were a treatise on theology ; 
 but when we remember that they are pictures of a mind partly 
 influenced by the contemporary age, and partly in advance of 
 it, the contradiction is intelligible and true to nature. It is 
 from this point of view that I have attempted to describe the 
 attitude adopted by Sophocles towards the deities of his national 
 religion, and to indicate some of the ethical and religious 
 thoughts underlying the situations and characters which he 
 has chosen to depict. 
 
 I. 
 
 The gods of the old Homeric mythology appear in 
 Sophocles, but while some are little more than names, others are 
 represented as having a real influence on human life and action, 
 
 1 Dronke, Die religidsen und sittlichen Vorstelluiigen. des Aeschyloa und 
 Sophocles. Leipzig, 1861. 
 
 C
 
 34 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 and take a prominent part in the development of the dramas. 
 For this reason we may conveniently speak of these deities of 
 mythology under three heads. There are, in the first place, 
 the deities mentioned only in connection with certain places 
 or isolated facts, local and tutelary gods, present or absent as 
 the case may be, and having no influence beyond their own 
 sphere ; then there are the deities which are mere personifica- 
 tions of human passions, Eros and Cypris deities which 
 obviously must take a prominent part in any representation of 
 human life ; and thirdly, distinct from either of the foregoing, is 
 the great triad of Greek mythology Zeus, Apollo, and Athena. 
 Without being of any intrinsic value in analysis, this triple 
 division will enable us to bring out the aspects under which 
 the gods of mythology appear in Sophocles. 
 
 Under the first head come all the gods of the Homeric 
 Olympus, and even more, with the exception of those set 
 apart in the other divisions. For the most part these deities 
 are mentioned in the choruses only. Sophocles adds little or 
 nothing to their attributes ; he speaks of them in reference to 
 certain places or facts, as any other Greek of his time might do. 
 Thus in the final chorus of the Antigone Bacchus is the god 
 of Thebes. As in the myth, he is the "joy of the Cadrneian 
 bride," " dwelling beside the seed of the fell serpent," seen by the 
 gleaming fires on Parnassus, sent forth with loud acclamations 
 from the vine-clad shores of Nysa. Bacchus is also the 
 lacchus of the mysteries, and therefore, as we read, the hymn 
 becomes more mystical in tone : " leader of the fire-breathing 
 stars, master of the voices of night, son and seed of Zeus, beam 
 thou upon us with thy Thyiads from Naxus, mystic maidens 
 who in nightlong dance glorify thee, their lord lacchus." 
 Bacchus loves to wander near Colonus, which is also the haunt 
 of the Muses, of Aphrodite, and Poseidon, and has been made 
 famous by their gifts. In Homer, Ares is, of all the gods who 
 dwell in Olympus, the most hateful to Zeus. He is " the two- 
 faced deity to whom strife, war, and battle are ever dear." l In 
 Sophocles, Ares is the personification of all evil powers. He 
 
 /j.ri ri fj,oi, d\\OTrp6ffa\\f, 
 
 txOicrTos St fiol ia<n 6e&v ot"Q\v(j.irov ^x ovffiv ' 
 
 old ydp roi fyts re (f>i\i) iroXepol Tf /taxa* re. II. v. 890.
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 35 
 
 is the pestilence which desolates Thebes (0. T. 190) ; he is the 
 god whom the gods put far from honour (ib. 215). Ares lifts 
 the cloud of misery from the eyes of the Salaminian mariners 
 (Aj. 706), i.e. it is Ares who has placed it there. Artemis is 
 implored to come to the aid of plague-stricken Thebes, in which 
 city she has a temple (0. T. 160 ff.) ; she is also the goddess 
 whose torches flash along the Lycian hills, the sister, that is, 
 of the Lycian god of light, whom the Greeks identified with 
 their own Apollo. In the Electro,, 1. 563, Artemis is said to 
 have caused the many winds to blow at Aulis in consequence 
 of an outrage inadvertently committed in her precincts by 
 Agamemnon, and thus she brought about the sacrifice of 
 Iphigeneia. Of Hera, the queen of heaven, there is no men- 
 tion in the extant plays of Sophocles, except in one passage, 
 Electra, 1. 8, where she is mentioned incidentally in connection 
 with her temple at Argos. Demeter and Persephone are 
 spoken of in reference to the holy mysteries at Eleusis 
 (0. C. 1049 ff.), "the torch-lit shore, where the queenly 
 goddesses cherish their rites for men on whose tongue rests the 
 golden key of the ministrant Eumolpids." Persephone is also 
 the goddess of the dead, the unseen goddess (0. C. 1556), to 
 whom Antigone goes down, the last of a sad company. In 
 Philoctetes, 1. 391, the chorus invoke Cybele, the all-nurturing 
 mountain-goddess, by whose bounty Pactolus flows with gold, 
 whose chariot the lions draw. Aidoneus, " the king of the 
 benighted," is entreated to suffer Oedipus to pass easily into 
 his realm (0. C. 1557). Hades, the god of night and death, is 
 of course frequently mentioned; in Ajax, 1. 1035, he is the 
 cruel workman who wrought the baldrick by which Hector 
 was torn to death. Prometheus, the fire-god, is one of the 
 deities of Colonus (0. C. 56). But of none of these can it be 
 said that they are brought before us in an aspect peculiarly 
 Sophoclean, or that they enter in any great degree, if at all, 
 into the action of the drama, and influence the plot. They 
 hold here the place allotted to them in the ordinary Greek 
 mind, which connected certain places with tutelary gods, and 
 looked to particular deities for protection under particular 
 circumstances. 
 
 More important than any of the deities hitherto mentioned
 
 36 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 are the Eumenides, the deities which occupy so prominent a place 
 in the theology of Aeschylus. Yet even they, as we find them 
 in Sophocles, must be brought under this head. They cannot 
 be said to exercise any influence on the actions of any of the 
 extant dramas. They are, it is true, the cause of a scene in 
 the Oedipus at Colonus, but only in so far as they are the local 
 representatives of higher and more universal powers, Local 
 customs are needed to propitiate them as local goddesses ; as 
 universal deities Oedipus claims to be reconciled to them by 
 his long-suffering and humiliation. Nor is it the Eumenides 
 who have brought him to ruin, but Apollo (0. T. 1329), and 
 from Apollo and Zeus comes his restoration. In many cases 
 where we might expect to find the operation of these goddesses, 
 we do not find it in Sophocles. In the case of Oedipus and 
 Polynices it is Zeus and Apollo who undertake the work of 
 vengeance, and demand expiation. There is no trace of the 
 Eumenides in the Sophoclean Orestes ; and though Electra 
 invokes them to come to her aid in avenging her father, the 
 deed of vengeance is really accomplished under the guidance 
 of Apollo and the auspices of Zeus. 
 
 In any delineation of human life and action there will 
 necessarily be a place for those deities which are the personi- 
 fications of human passions. Such are Eros and Aphrodite, 
 or Cypris, the deities of passionate love. Tradition tells us 
 that Sophocles knew their power too well. In his poems Eros 
 is invincible in strife; his power none can escape, whether 
 mortal or immortal ; and he who is wise will not contend with 
 him. Eros puts madness in the heart, and leads astray the 
 soul of the righteous ; he stirs up strife between kindred blood, 
 and desire sways a sceptre no less powerful than justice. 
 Without the intervention of Eros the Antigone would have no 
 denouement. The love of Haemon for Antigone leads to the 
 altercation of father and son, and to the suicide of the latter on 
 finding his betrothed dead. The death of Haemon is the direct 
 cause of the death of his mother Eurydice. Thus it is through 
 the operation of Eros that the vengeance of the gods overtakes 
 Creon, and a natural passion becomes the instrument of divine 
 justice. 
 
 In another passage the personification is less complete.
 
 E THICS OF SOPHO CLES. 3 7 
 
 The passion is more than the deity. Love, we are told in Frag. 
 162 (Dindorf), is a pleasant plague, which may be figured thus : 
 When the air is frosty, and children take the dry ice in their 
 hands, at first the experience is something strange and sweet ; 
 but soon the ice is frozen to the hand, and the pleasure passes 
 into a pain, of which the child would fain be rid, and even 
 such is the impulse which sways the lover. 1 
 
 Here Eros is spoken of in a figure, but not personified. 
 Indeed, the Greeks, however acutely sensible of the power of 
 Eros, had not made up their minds whether he was a god or 
 not. He is at once a human passion and a " great spirit." 
 
 Equally important is the action of Aphrodite in the 
 Trachiniae. Cypris is triumphant ever ; she beguiled the son 
 of Cronos, Hades, and Poseidon; from her came the famous 
 strife of Achelous and Heracles for the hand of Dejanira ; and 
 now she has ensnared Heracles in a new passion for lole. The 
 fear of a rival in her husband's affections induces Dejanira to 
 send the fatal robe ; and thus Cypris brings about the death of 
 Heracles, and takes part in the accomplishment of the will of 
 heaven. In a beautiful and well-known fragment (678) we 
 are told that Cypris is not Cypris only, but a goddess named of 
 many names. Death and Immortality, Frenzy, Passion, and 
 Grief, these are her titles. Eagerness, gentleness, violence, are 
 blended and united in her. She enters into all living things 
 and consumes them : hers are the fish that swim in the sea, 
 the four-footed kind that tread the earth; her pinion waves 
 among the birds, in creatures of the field, in men, and heavenly 
 gods. Even in the heart of Zeus for the truth is blameless, 
 though we speak it of the gods Cypris is queen; without sword 
 or spear she cuts down the counsels of men and gods. 
 
 In Aphrodite or Cypris the personification is more complete 
 than in Eros. But personifications of this kind are of course no 
 invention of Sophocles. What we can perhaps claim for him 
 is, that he was the first to make them of importance in the 
 progress of the dramatic action, and to point out the manner in 
 which they assist in the development of divine purposes. The 
 motive of love is well known to Homer: it is present in 
 
 rods tpuvras avr&s t/iepos 
 6pai> Kal rb JJ.T] Spav roXXcim irpoffleTat.
 
 38 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 both the Iliad and Odyssey, but it can hardly be said to 
 govern the events and assist in the catastrophe of either poem, 
 though it is true that the love of Helen and Penelope forms the 
 basis on which the poems are built. "None can blame the 
 Trojans and Achaeans that their strife for such a woman is 
 long and sore." " I too know well that Penelope is not beauti- 
 ful as thou art : she is mortal, and thee nor age nor death can 
 touch : still, even so, I yearn to visit my home and behold the 
 day of return." These passages remind us of touching scenes, 
 in which the charm of beauty is deeply felt, and brought into 
 contrast with the love of home and country. But Sophocles 
 has gone much further than Homer. He has distinctly recog- 
 nised these passions as elements in a dramatic action, binding 
 individuals together so that wrong cannot be done to one with- 
 out affecting another, or as forming the weak and assailable 
 point in some otherwise superhuman character. 
 
 Zeus, Apollo, and Athena are deities far more exalted and 
 sublime than any hitherto mentioned. Yet even they are not 
 always, or at least the first and greatest of them, Zeus, is not 
 always represented by Sophocles in the same light. Zeus 
 is at times the god of the old Olympus, at others the god 
 of the Athenians of the age of Sophocles, while, in other 
 passages, the poet seems to be speaking his own thoughts, and 
 to elevate Zeus, with Apollo and Athena as his ministers, into 
 a supreme deity of justice and truth. How such various con- 
 ceptions of one and the same deity which was also the great 
 national god became possible, the history of Greek religion 
 will explain. The interval between the earliest conception 
 and the latest was a long one, but the Greeks did not allow 
 the mythology which stood to them in the place of doctrine 
 to restrain them from the endeavour to bring their conception 
 of the Supreme Being into harmony with their conceptions of 
 justice and law. Their religious conceptions became ethical at 
 an early period, and continued to be so to the last, ever grow- 
 ing higher and higher as the conception of life and duty became 
 more elevated. To this development and progress Sophocles 
 contributed his part, without breaking away from what was 
 traditional in religion or imposed upon him by the limits of 
 poetry.
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 39 
 
 As a god of the old mythology, Zeus is the son of Cronos 
 (Tr. 127, etc.); Earth is his mother (Phil. 391), Hades his 
 brother (Tr. 1041), Apollo his son (0. C. 623). By Semele he 
 is the father of Bacchus (Ant. 1116); by Alcmene, of Heracles 
 (Tr. 1148, etc.). His daughters are Athena (Aj. 91) and 
 Artemis (Aj. 172). He is the progenitor of Ajax (Aj. 389); 
 he slays Capaneus (Ant. 134 if.), descends in a shower of gold 
 upon Danae (Ant. 950), and punishes Ixion (Phil. 680). 
 
 Here we find Zeus mentioned as the lover of Semele, 
 Alcmene, and Danae. These connections, so far from being 
 regarded as out of harmony with his nature as a god and the 
 first of gods, are rather brought into prominence as connecting 
 certain cities or families more directly with the deity, and mak- 
 ing them, as it were, his elect. The inconsistency of connect- 
 ing immoral actions with a moral being is hardly felt. In the 
 same way, Aeschylus in his Supplices speaks of Zeus as efycnrrop 
 'lou? i.e. the sensual story is adopted to bring the daughters 
 of Danaus under his immediate protection, but this does not 
 prevent the same chorus in the same ode from appealing to 
 Zeus as the highest and most perfect of the gods. 1 In the 
 Prometheus Vinctus, on the other hand, the conduct of Zeus 
 towards lo is spoken of as tyrannical in the extreme. 
 
 In other passages of Sophocles Zeus is addressed by 
 epithets which express the popular contemporary feeling from 
 a moral or religious point of view. Such are ar/atvux; (Tr. 26), 
 atetfirop (0. C. 143), apato? (Ph. 1182), e/weetb? (Ant. 487), 
 e^eoTto? (Aj. 492), t/eeoYo? (Ph. 484), Trarpwos (Tr. 753), rpo- 
 7raio<? (Ant. 143). These epithets are interesting as showing 
 how Zeus is brought into relation with various sides of human 
 life and action. A path is thus prepared by which polytheism 
 can pass into monotheism, the special spheres of human life 
 being made special sides, as it were, of the universal pro- 
 vidence. Zeus is still Zeus, whether invoked as aywz/to? or 
 ep/celos, but the epithets may not be interchanged, and he who 
 invokes the god by a wrongly chosen epithet will not, such was 
 the Greek conception, obtain a hearing. 
 
 S.va.1; &VO.KTUV, 
 fjMKdprarf Kal 
 Tf\fi6raTov Kpdros, 6\pie ZeO. AESCH. Suppl. 524.
 
 40 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 In a similar manner, Zeus was popularly connected with cer- 
 tain localities, as Oeta, Athos, and Lemnos. Other passages (as 
 0. C. 1464, 1502, 1650 ; Phil. 1198, etc.) represent him as lord of 
 the thunder and god of the physical world. From a more elevated 
 and ethical point of view, Zeus is almighty and all-wise Zevs 
 Travrap^of dewv, nravroTrra^ (0. C. 1086); Tray/cpar^ (Phil. 
 680) ; iravr avda-acov (0. T. 904) ; jravt)' opwv (Ant. 184). Zeus 
 and Apollo know the affairs of mortals (0. T. 498). But in all 
 these passages, and in many more which might be added to 
 them, the poet is only reproducing the religion of his day, and 
 using language which any pious Athenian would naturally 
 use. Those who believed in gods at all, believed in the Power 
 dwelling in heaven, whose eye beheld and hand guided all 
 things. 
 
 There is yet another point of view r from which is presented 
 to us, so far as we can tell, the poet's own conception of the 
 Supreme Being. Zeus is the eternal ruler in heaven, the up- 
 holder of the highest laws of morality and religion, exalted 
 beyond the reach of human pride and power. The poet has 
 attained to the idea of an order of the world which is just and 
 good, and this order he identifies with the empire of Zeus. In 
 Zeus the highest laws of the family and the state have their 
 origin and birth, and though these may clash with the appetites 
 and ambition of men, and bring " not peace, but a sword," Zeus 
 is nevertheless a just and righteous ruler. His kingdom is 
 founded on law, not on caprice. " It was not Zeus," Antigone 
 declares, when speaking of the edict of Creon, " who made this 
 proclamation, nor Justice, who abides with the deities of the 
 under- world; they have established among men the laws which 
 I obey" (Ant. 450). That is, Zeus and Justice uphold the laws 
 of family affection and the burial of the dead. The power of 
 Zeus is also eternal and immutable. "Thy power, Zeus, 
 what proud advance of men can repress ? that power which 
 sleep never overtakes, nor the divine unwearying progress of 
 the months. Through undying time thou dwellest in the 
 brightness of Olympus ; thy laws are all-pervading ; they have 
 been and shall be for ever" (Ant. 605-614). Reverence for 
 Zeus is reverence for the highest law, so that Electra in her 
 abnegation of self in the cause of her dead father is pious towards
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 41 
 
 Zeus. 1 Loftier still is the conception of Zeus in the Oedipus 
 Tyrannus. Here indeed the name of Zeus seems too narrow for 
 the poet's thought : " Zeus, if thou art rightly named, let it 
 not be hidden from thee and thy everlasting rule that men are 
 disregarding oracles, and that religion is passing away " (0. T. 
 902). The poet appeals to the highest of divine powers, for 
 which he has no other name than Zeus, whether that be the 
 right name or no. 2 In another passage he substitutes Olympus 
 for Zeus, as though the highest laws were the outcome of the 
 whole host of heaven : " May it be mine in every act and 
 word of life to preserve the piety and purity ordained by those 
 high laws of which Olympus is the only sire, whose birth was 
 in the sky above, 3 and nothing human gave them being. In 
 them is a divine power, which grows not old " (0. T. 863). 
 
 Of the two deities which remain, Apollo is prominent in the 
 Oedipus Tyrannus, the Oedipus at Colonus, and the Electra. It 
 is however necessary to distinguish between two deities called 
 Apollo. There is Apollo the son of Zeus, who announces 
 and executes his father's will Apollo Pythius, the Delphian 
 Apollo, and there is also Apollo Lyceius, the protector of his 
 worshippers and destroyer of their enemies, whose temple is at 
 Argos (El. 7), and whose shrines are found beside the palace- 
 doors (El. 635). To this latter god oracular functions are not 
 ascribed in Sophocles, nor is he connected with Delphi, or 
 regarded as the prophet of Zeus. 4 But Apollo, the Pythian god, is 
 the son of Zeus, and makes known by oracles his father's will. 
 The oracle of Delphi occupies a very prominent place in the 
 Sophoclean drama. It influences largely the development of 
 the action in the two plays concerned with Oedipus. It was 
 
 AptffTa T$Zrjv6s evffefidq.. El. 1095. 
 
 * Cf. Aesch. Ag. 160 : Zei)j, 6'cms TTOT' tffrlv, ei roS' avrtp (f>[\ov 
 8 Cf. Bergk, Litteratur-Gesch. p. 330. The idea that the highest laws 
 have their birth in the " heavenly ether " is perhaps, as Bergk suggests, an 
 intimation that the highest law is realised in the movements of the heavenly 
 bodies. Cf. Heraclitus, Fr. 29 : "HXioj OVK lurep/STjcrercu n^rpa- ei 5 /}, 'Epii>ves 
 Hiv SiKrjs tirlKovpoi tevp-fi<rov<ri, and Wordsworth's Ode to Duty, 
 11 Thou dost preserve the stars from wrong, 
 
 And the most ancient heavens through thee are fresh and strong. " 
 1 Aeschylus, Ag. 1080, identifies the Apollo "of the street" with the god 
 whom Cassandra rejected, the Delphian god of prophecy.
 
 42 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 the oracle which induced Oedipus to fly from Corinth in the 
 hope of avoiding the doom foretold to him that he should slay 
 his father and marry his mother. It was the oracle which in- 
 duced Laius and Jocasta to expose their child to death. It is 
 the oracle which gives the true reason for the plague which has 
 visited Thebes, and requires the expulsion or death of the mur- 
 derer of Laius. It is the oracle which announces to Oedipus that 
 he shall, after many wanderings, find a place of rest and recon- 
 ciliation. It is the oracle which induces the Thebans to make the 
 attempt to recover Oedipus, so that his bones may lie in their land. 
 In the Electra it is the oracle which supports Orestes in his 
 attempt to avenge the death of his father, and points out the way 
 in which vengeance is to be taken. In the Trachiniae also it is 
 the oracle which "warns Heracles, before his last venture, that 
 he will either fail, or, if successful, enjoy rest for ever. In 
 nearly all these cases the oracle points out what will certainly 
 happen. No place is left, apparently, for the freewill of the 
 doer. Oedipus is destined to slay his father ; Laius is destined 
 to fall by his son's hand. Both Oedipus and Laius take measures 
 to avoid the doom foretold, but in vain. Apollo therefore 
 would seem, in some cases, to be the prophet of a harsh fatal- 
 ism which has no regard for guilt or innocence, and which no 
 one can escape. But the other side of fatalism is human weak- 
 ness, and the prophetic announcement of destiny is no more 
 than the complete foreknowledge of what will happen as the 
 result of such weakness. Laius knows that his child is destined 
 to slay him, but this does not prevent him from becoming the 
 father of the child. Oedipus is aware of the doom in store, yet 
 ov& opwv, QV& la-Topwv he slays a man in his haste, and takes to 
 wife the queen of Thebes. From thus announcing the suffering 
 which will fall upon men, Apollo is sometimes regarded as the 
 author of that suffering. Thus Oedipus (0. T. 1330) declares 
 that it was Apollo who brought to pass upon him the miseries 
 which the chorus behold. 1 
 
 1 In such passages as these something must be allowed for the supposed 
 etymology ('Air6\\uv &irb\\vni), a play upon words for which we have distinct 
 authority in Aesch. Ag. 1080 : 
 
 "ATTO\\OI>, '' Airo\\ot>, 
 
 ayviar', d.w6\\uv tfj.6s. 
 
 d.7rwXe<ras yap ov /j.6\is T& Sftjrtpov.
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 43 
 
 Bebellion against the authority of Apollo, and disregard of 
 his oracles, are regarded by Sophocles as the height of impiety, 
 inasmuch as Apollo is the servant of Zeus, and directly conveys 
 his will to man. This rebellion is conspicuous in Jocasta, and 
 makes that character the darkest in the Sophoclean drama. In 
 impiety Jocasta far surpasses Clytemnestra ; her language not 
 only excites a certain impatience in Oedipus, but is denounced in 
 no measured terms by the chorus, who are at once startled and 
 shocked by her declarations. We may observe that the feeling 
 entertained by Sophocles for the great religious institution of 
 his time, the Delphian oracle, stands in marked contrast to the 
 attitude of Thucydides. 
 
 If the conception of Apollo inspires awe, inasmuch as it shows 
 how a man's weakness and want of foresight may act as an 
 inevitable doom, the picture of Athena in the Ajax of Sophocles 
 is perhaps more terrible still. When Ajax parted from his father 
 Telamon to join the host for Troy, he received the wise counsels 
 of age, " My son, strive for victory, but with the help of God ! " 
 Proud and impious was the answer : " With the help of the 
 gods, my sire, even a mean man may win the victory ; I, 
 without them, trust to make this glory mine." And when, at 
 a later time, Athena offered the hero her aid in battle, he 
 replied with scorn, bidding her go elsewhere : " Where I stand 
 the battle shall not break bounds." Such words betrayed a 
 spirit too proud for a human breast, and brought upon Ajax the 
 anger of the goddess. She sends madness upon him, so that he 
 slays the sheep and oxen of the spoil, believing them to be the 
 Atreidae and Odysseus, and on his recovery he is overwhelmed 
 by such sovereign shame that he takes his own life. 
 
 At first sight there seems to be something inhuman and cruel 
 in the cold nature of this goddess, who punishes her victim 
 without the least regard to his nobler qualities, and exhibits 
 him in his degradation to the eyes of Odysseus, his greatest 
 enemy. But a goddess is necessarily superhuman ; to speak of 
 a want of humanity or of cruelty in Athena is as though we 
 should complain of the cruelty or inhumanity of the laws of 
 nature. These go on their way without regard to time and cir- 
 cumstance, and often cause great suffering, but this does not in
 
 44 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 the least affect their excellence and perfection as laws. In a 
 similar way Athena is a controlling intellectual force, offences 
 against which bring their own punishment. Ajax has rejected 
 her, and spoken scornfully of her help ; he has presumed 
 " beyond the goal of ordinance," and exalted human power at 
 the expense of the gods. Hence the wrath of Athena visits 
 him. Yet the visitation is but for a day, and could Ajax 
 have been preserved through that day his life was safe 
 (Aj. 756). 
 
 The scene at the beginning of the Ajax exhibits the opera- 
 tion of this law of vengeance. Just as a natural law may 
 paralyse the body, so has this divine power paralysed the mind 
 of Ajax. In this phrenetic state he is exhibited to Odysseus, 
 not to excite exultation for Odysseus knows the limits of 
 humanity too well to triumph over a slaughtered enemy, but 
 to awaken his compassion and deepen his sense of the frailty 
 of human nature, and the dependence of all men in all things 
 on the gods. It is thus that Odysseus is brought to insist on 
 the burial of Ajax. He alone, with Calchas, knows the reason 
 of this frenzy, and he shrinks from depriving an enemy when 
 dead of the funeral rites which are fitly his. 
 
 Athena then is the spirit of o-co^poa-vvrj she is the divine 
 power who keeps watch over the impulses of men, and punishes 
 them when they would pass beyond the appointed limit. 
 Those who most acknowledge their dependence on the divine 
 power she is most willing to aid, but she punishes with all the 
 resistless and relentless persistence of a natural law all who 
 rebel against her. In her we see that intellectual conception 
 of life which makes men responsible for their mistakes as well 
 as their crimes, and punishes with equal severity the presump- 
 tion and the baseness of men. 
 
 II 
 
 From this examination of the conception of Athena in her 
 relation to Ajax we may pass on to the wider question : " In 
 what way does Sophocles conceive the relation of man and 
 God ? " Often, instead of naming any special deity, the poet
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 45 
 
 speaks vaguely of Oeos, 6 #eo?, Oeoc, Satfj-wv words which seem 
 to be used, without much difference of meaning, for the divine 
 power ; but which have the effect of emancipating us entirely 
 from the old mythology, and enabling us to put the question 
 just mentioned in its widest form. 
 
 We cannot read much of Sophocles, or of any Greek 
 tragedian, without arriving at the conclusion that the relation 
 of man to his God is conceived under two different and almost 
 contradictory aspects. On the one hand, God is beneficent, the 
 author of good to his creatures ; just and holy ; the upholder 
 of right, the avenger of wrong. On the other hand, God is the 
 author of evil, and men are even divinely deceived in order to 
 bring them the more certainly to their ruin. 
 
 In support of the first or optimist view, we may refer to 
 the passage already quoted from the Oedipus Tyrannus (1. 871), 
 in which the high laws are divinely sustained : " There is a 
 mighty divine power in them, which grows not old." In the 
 Antigone the gods are the guardians of justice (1. 369); and 
 justice is said to have her home with the deities of the under- 
 world (1. 450). In the Ajanc (1. 1343) the gods require the 
 burial of the dead. To the gods also Philoctetes looks for 
 vengeance of the wrong that has been committed against him : 
 " Ye will perish for the wrong that ye have done to me, if the 
 gods have regard for justice ; and that they have I know : 
 never would ye have made this voyage hitherward for a help- 
 less man had not some heaven-sent yearning for me impelled 
 you." l In like manner Electra trusts to the gods for venge- 
 ance of her wrongs. 2 The justice of God may however in 
 appearance be at variance with the justice of man : " "With 
 God to lead him, a man may wander from the way of justice, 
 for where God is guide reproach follows not." 3 The gods are 
 holy as they are just ; Oedipus in his horror of the crime 
 which he fears that he may have committed appeals to the " pure 
 
 1 el ^77 TI Ktvrpov Gflov Tjj' V/J.8.S t/j.ov. Phil. 1039. 
 
 2 o?s 0e6s 6 fJ.tyas '0\vfJ.irio$ 
 
 irolvifj.a irdOea. iraOeiv iropoi. El. 209. 
 8 d\\' ts 6fovs bpGivTO., K&V w S/K^S 
 Xupew KeXeijy, /ceur' odonropeiv xpf^' 
 
 V ovdtv &v v<p-riyovvra.i. Ofol. Frag. 234.
 
 46 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 holiness" of the gods. 1 They are also beyond the reach of 
 human pollution. 2 
 
 As a natural result of their justice and holiness the gods 
 punish the wicked. In Electra, 1. 1383, Apollo is entreated by 
 Electra to show to the world what are the wages of impiety. 
 This divine vengeance may linger, 3 or it may come quickly, 4 or 
 the sins of the father may even be visited on the children. 5 
 But whether the vengeance is swift or slow, that it will come, 
 that all morality and religion depend on its coming, is the faith 
 of Sophocles. 6 As the gods disregard and punish the evil, so 
 they love and honour the good. 7 They are helpful to men, and 
 from them comes the wisdom of the wise. It was by divine 
 aid that Oedipus was enabled to save Thebes from the Sphinx. 8 
 No one is truly wise whose wisdom is not from above. 9 The 
 utterances of the gods are indeed dark at times, but the 
 wise will understand them, and those who will not will never- 
 theless find them true. 10 In understanding the mysteries of 
 life a righteous and loving soul sees further than cunning or 
 
 1 & OeZv ayv&v fftfias.O. T. 830. 
 
 2 e5 yap o75' #ri 
 
 0eoi)j fjualveiv otiris dv6puir<ai> aOtvei Ant. 1043. 
 
 3 6eol yap e5 ptv, 6\l/ d' dcrop&ff' , Srav 
 
 ra 6eV dfais TIS 4s rt> jaaivecrflcu rpairfj. 0. C. 1536. 
 
 ffvvr^fjo'ovffi yap 
 Oe&v TroSw/ceis rovs KaK6<ppovas ^3Xd/3cu. Ant. 1103. 
 
 6eots yap Ijv oi/rw <f>l\ov t 
 rax' &" TI fjii)vlovffu> els ytvos ird\ai. 0. G. 964. 
 
 6 0. T. 883 ff. 
 
 ' TOI)J 8 ffd>(f>povas 
 
 0eol <j>i\ovffi Kol ffrvyovffi rovs Kaicovs. Aj. 132, and Ant. 288. 
 
 a\\a Trpoffd^K-rj deov 
 
 \yei vofdfret 6' i)fd.v bpOGxrai fiiov. 0. T. 38. 
 
 On this point the relations of Athena and Odysseus as described in the open- 
 ing scene of the Ajax are abundant evidence. 
 
 ' ffo<pos yap ovdels ir\j)v 6c av TI/J,$ 6e6s. FTag. 234. 
 
 10 Kal TOV Ofbv TOIOUTOV ^eirlffTa/juu, 
 <ro<pois jj.v alviKrrjpa dfetpdruv del, 
 ffKatois 8 <j>av\ov K&V fipaxft StSda/caXoc. Ibid. 707.
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 47 
 
 cleverness, 1 and even the capacity for sound judgment is 
 derived from the gods. 2 Lastly, the gods have power to 
 remove misery. 3 
 
 Such is what may be called the optimist relation of man to 
 God : we find in it that which is the " central light of all re- 
 ligion," the justice and truth of God ; but we miss from it many 
 ideas with which Christianity has made us so familiar that 
 they seem to us a part of the necessary relation of the human 
 and the divine. There is little trace of the paternal relation 
 so prominent in modern conceptions of the same subject. No 
 doubt, in Greek religion Zeus is the father of men and gods, 
 but not much is meant by the title. There is nothing said of 
 the love of God for his creatures, or of their love for him. 
 The picture is severe, even in this the most favourable light. 
 
 What then is the darker side of this relation of man and 
 God ? The poet does not hesitate to speak of the gods as 
 heartless. 4 They are the fathers of human children, whom 
 they leave to perish miserably, even as Heracles was consumed 
 by fire. They are also jealous of the power of man. In the 
 Ajax the divinely-inspired bard Calchas says of Ajax, and 
 those like him " Men over mighty in stature are plunged by 
 the gods into dire misfortune." 5 They also injure men, so 
 that the evil may outstrip the good, such at least is the utter- 
 ance of Ajax in his despair. 6 It is the gods who, for purposes 
 
 1 i/vXT) yap ffivovs /col <f>povov<ra rofivSiKov 
 Kpdffcruv ffo<t>urrov iravrds karw evperis. Frag. 88. 
 
 a Ant. 603. 
 
 3 vvv yip Oeol <r' 6p0ov<ri, irpbffOe 5' &\\vva.v. 0. C. 383; 394. 
 
 fldbrts Hpyuv -rCiv Trpaffffo/J.^vwv, 
 
 Ol <f>6ffaVTS KO.I K\ri'6/J.tVOl 
 
 irartpes roiaur' <pop>cri irdOrj.Tr. 1266 ff. 
 
 6 TO. yap irepiffffa Kav6vr)ra crd/j 
 jriiTTfiv /Sapet'cus irpbs 0fu>v dvffTrpa%tais 
 tfatffx' 6 in6.vri.s, 6'<ms avdpdnrov 0i/<rw 
 P\a.ffTwv Ijretra /xrj /car' &v8puirov <f>povy. Aj. 758 ff. 
 
 et 54 rtj 0ftav 
 
 /SXdirrot, (jtvyoi r&v x Ka/cds rbv Kpeiffffova. Aj. 455.
 
 48 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 of their own, have sent on Philoctetes his pain and loneliness, 1 
 while the chorus in their dismay at the frenzy of Ajax can 
 only say, " I fear that some heaven-sent evil may have over- 
 taken him." 2 When God so determines, the change from evil 
 to good is easily brought about, and no one can escape the 
 " stroke of God." 3 Not only are the gods the authors of 
 misery, but they even lead men into calamity, and deceive 
 them to their ruin. " It was wisely uttered of old," so we are 
 told in the Antigone, " that evil often seems good to the man 
 whom God is leading to his ruin" (Ant. 623). In a fragment, 
 Phaedra excuses her fault by saying that no one can escape 
 the evils sent by Zeus. 4 It is the gods who have placed strife 
 between the two sons of Oedipus the gods assisted by an evil 
 mind. 5 
 
 Thus the religious feeling which runs through the plays of 
 Sophocles does not scruple to attribute to the gods the evil 
 which falls upon men. And the power of the gods is supreme ; 
 man is absolutely helpless before them. The gods are indeed 
 just and holy, and regard the good before the evil : but this 
 justice is consistent with the suffering even of the good. 
 Hence we cannot expect to find in Sophocles a cheerful view 
 of life, or a high value placed upon existence. And in truth, if 
 there is one point on which the poet insists more than another, 
 it is the " Nichtigkeit " of human life. However light-hearted 
 and happy we may picture the inhabitant of Athens to have 
 
 1 $e?ct yap, el Kal Kayib TI ippovu, 
 Kal ra ira.6-fifj.a.TO. Keiva 7rp6s avrbv 
 
 rrjs w/dxppovos X/JI/CTTJS eirefl-ri. Phil. 192 ff. 
 8 Aj. 278. 
 3 tv yap Ppaxe? KaOfi\e 
 
 jrd/j.ir\ovTov 8\j3ov dalftovos KUK 
 
 Srav fjLerdffTji Kal Oeois doKy rd5e. Frag. 572. 
 
 Geov Se ir\TjyT)i> o&x virepirrjdi} fiporfa. Frag. 656. 
 
 4 atcrxn f^ v > & yvvalices, o$8' av eh <pijyot 
 ppor&v irod', $ Kal Tievs <(>opiJi-f)ari /ca/cd, 
 
 vbaovs d' avayicr) ras 6(rj\dTovs <pe"peit>. frag. 611. 
 
 5 vvv 8' IK Oedjv rov Ka dXeiTtjpov <f>pevbs 
 elafjXOe roiv rpiffadXioiv />is /ca/c^. 0. C. 371.
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 49 
 
 been, his reflections on life were melancholy and sombre. 
 Life is an evil : it were better not to be born at all ; and next 
 best to die in infancy. Life is only good so long as youth 
 continues, and the joys of youth are idle follies (Kov$ai atypo- 
 crvvat, 0. C. 1225 ff.). Mortals in the prime of life are but as 
 nothing. ISTo one gains more than a mere phantom of happi- 
 ness, and even this he loses in the gaining (0. T. 1186 ff.). We 
 are as shadows, and wander to and fro, a superfluous burden on 
 the earth (Fr. 682). " I know," says Theseus in his glory to 
 the outcast Oedipus, " that I too am a man, and that in the 
 morrow I have no greater share than thou hast" (0. C. 567). 
 Odysseus, gazing on the ruin of his enemy, is saddened with 
 the thought that " all of us who live are no more than 
 phantoms, than fleeting shadows" (Aj. 125, 6). The misery 
 of age is intolerable ; age is the home of every evil ; the hand 
 of the aged is feeble, his mind fails, his thoughts are nothing 
 worth. 1 Even when life is most prosperous a change may 
 quickly come, and no man's happiness can be estimated till 
 the day of his death. 2 
 
 Against this melancholy picture we have little to set on 
 the other side. There is a chorus of the Antigone in which 
 the inventive genius of man is celebrated. By the help of his 
 art he has made himself master of sea and land, of beast and 
 bird and fish. By this he has found out the secret of language 
 and reason and civic life ; the comforts of house and home and 
 remedies from disease. Yet these victories only remain to him 
 so long as he cherishes a righteous and pious mind; they 
 are lost to the daring and the impious. In the Trachiniae, the 
 women of Trachis comfort their mistress with the thought that 
 " heaviness endureth for a night, but joy cometh in the morn- 
 
 1 0. C. 1235 ff. 
 
 TT&VT t/J.wt<pVKe T(J) /J.ClKp({) "fflpq. KO.K<i, 
 
 vovs (ppoudos, l/ry' dxpe'a, <ppovrl5es Keval. Frag. 684. 
 
 * oil xpti TOT' eD irpaffffovTOS 6\[3iffa.i rv 
 dv5/xSs, irplv atiTif iravreXias tfSr) pios 
 5ifKwfp6.vdri Kal reXevrTjcrri /3t'<w. (?). Ibid. 572. 
 
 The sentiment is repeated in other words at the end of the Oedipus Tyrannus 
 and the Antigone. 
 
 D
 
 ing." l But even in these words of comfort, joy and sorrow are 
 closely united, and the issue of the play shows how "ironically" 
 they are spoken, for in another sense, and with a deeper mean- 
 ing, there comes on Dejanira ^alpeiv re KCU o-repeaOai. 
 
 But the sadness of life is a theme as old as the lyric poets, 
 and equally old are the sorrows of age. Mimnermus has told 
 us what existence is worth when the joy of youth is gone ; the 
 sentiment that judgment cannot be passed on life till its close 
 is attributed to Solon ; it is the central thought in his famous 
 dialogue with Croesus, a dialogue which, if genuine, would have 
 to be placed about a century before the literary activity of 
 Sophocles. Moreover, to most of the sentiments about the 
 sadness of life here illustrated from Sophocles parallels could 
 be found in the History of Herodotus. They are the strongly 
 expressed maxims of the moral philosophy of that period. In 
 truth, the melancholy view here taken of human life is no 
 fancy of a poet sighing after an impossible happiness, or of a 
 diseased mind which finds the world out of joint. The Greek 
 was no doubt free from much that distresses and almost 
 paralyses the modern world. In him there was not that 
 struggle of inward and outward, of flesh and spirit, which 
 plays so large a part in modern ethical reflection. Yet in other 
 respects life pressed upon him far more heavily. Few were 
 the years in which the Greek was not at war for interests 
 more or less vital ; few the households in which there was not 
 one slain in battle. And even in peaceful times the race of 
 life was severe. The battle went to the strong. Here and 
 there we find passages which betray a certain tenderness to- 
 wards suffering and weakness, but these are exceptions to 
 the general rule. The Greek at his best was a fierce 
 partisan, who rejoiced in the calamities of his enemies. 
 At his worst he did not scruple to rob the weak and help- 
 less, the orphan and the widow, while relentless vengeance 
 on an enemy in an unguarded moment was exalted into a 
 moral duty. And when a man turned his eyes away from 
 himself, there was little to comfort him. The gods might 
 
 yu^i/ei yap otir' ai6\a 
 
 vv!; jSpOTOiffiv ovTe Kijpfs oCre irXoOros, 
 
 dXX' &<pap j3^3a.K. rtf 5' twtpxeTai, 'xo.Lpei.v re KO.I ffr^peadai. Tr. 131 ff.
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 51 
 
 indeed be good and just; it was dangerous to speak evil of 
 them; but they were certainly jealous and exacting. Their 
 wrath was easily kindled, and no one could tell how their 
 anger would be shown. For there remained the inexplicable 
 mystery that evil overtook the good as well as the wicked, a 
 Nicias as well as an Alcibiades. Poets spoke of a future world 
 beyond the grave ; but did it really exist ? Or was it more 
 than a place of punishment? Even if all that Pindar said 
 were true, how could a life beyond the grave compensate for 
 misery in this life ? Thoughts such as these must have passed 
 through the minds of many Greeks in the time of the Pelopon- 
 nesian war ; so that Sophocles is true to nature in his picture 
 of the evils of human existence, and if we find him attempting 
 to explain them, he is explaining a fact and not a fiction. 
 
 The deepest note is touched in the passage already quoted 
 from the Antigone: "With wisdom was it declared of old, 
 that good often appears evil to one whose mind God is leading 
 to ruin." The passage occurs in the ode in which the chorus 
 dwell on the woes of the house of the Labdacids ; and nothing 
 can represent life under a more hopeless aspect than that 
 picture of a house stricken with a curse which penetrates from 
 generation to generation, till every member of the family is 
 Hestroyed. This hopeless ruin, though induced immediately 
 by frenzy and infatuation (\o<yoi; T avoia real (frpevwv 'Epivv<i), 
 is nevertheless part of the ordinance of Zeus " whom neither 
 age nor sleep can touch, who sits supreme throughout never- 
 ending time in the splendour of Olympus." Even the hopes 
 of mankind are but deceptions, leading them unawares to 
 destruction ; the heart of the doomed is blinded, so that good 
 is evil, and evil good, and few are the days that are not days 
 of sorrow (Trpda-crei 8' o\.lyt<TTOV xpovov e^ro? ara?). 
 
 This chorus is, no doubt, in designed contrast to that which 
 immediately precedes it in the play, and which tells us of the 
 power and inventiveness of man (cf. supra, p. 49). It raises 
 the question, "Is this unhappy condition of man whose 
 wisdom is so great -this angry temper of the gods, due to the 
 wickedness of man, or is it mere caprice on the part of 
 potentates desiring to keep within due bounds a rebellious 
 race, or is it a severe inexplicable destiny? The presence
 
 52 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 of misery in the world is shown by abundant testimony. What 
 explanation can we give of it ? " 
 
 In part the misery of life is due to the foolishness and 
 pride of men. Pindar had spoken of arrj as the child of 
 vfipts, and Sophocles is penetrated with this feeling. A 
 rebellious spirit breaking the bounds imposed on humanity 
 (dvYjTos ov OvrjTa typovcov) will not go without punishment. It 
 is this which brings upon Ajax the punishment of Athena 
 (cf. supra, p. 44), and the goddess herself declares that this is 
 the lesson to be drawn from the picture of Ajax sitting among 
 the dead sheep and oxen. 1 In such a punishment the justice 
 of the gods is apparent. Ajax has sinned, and he suffers. But 
 even here the punishment, in its worst form, is not inevi- 
 table. For one day only will the wrath of Athena pursue 
 him. If for this day he can be saved, he will hereafter be 
 free. The frenzy will pass away, and with it the sense of 
 humiliation. Ajax will return to a better mind. 
 
 But the instances in which this close connection between 
 the fault and the punishment is apparent are few in Sophocles. 
 We may trace it, of course, in Clytemnestra, and, though the 
 case is widely different, in the Creon of the Antigone. But of 
 Antigone herself what can we say ? Is she to be placed beside 
 Ajax, or beside Creon? Is her death the punishment of a 
 rebellious spirit, or is she a martyr in the cause of sisterly 
 affection and the rights of the dead ? We must not answer 
 this question according to our own views and feelings ; we 
 must ask, What was the view and the meaning of Sophocles ? 
 As A. Bockh has seen, a strong case may be made out against 
 Antigone. She defies the civic authority ; she goes beyond the 
 limits imposed upon a woman. Her own sister Ismene 
 regards the deed which she contemplates as rash and un- 
 womanly. It is in fact impossible, and the mere attempt is 
 foolishness. 2 The chorus also, aged chiefs of the State, speak 
 with strong reprobation of Antigone's conduct. Her act is the 
 
 1 roiavTo. roivvv elffopCiv virtpKoirov 
 H-rjd^f TTOT' eiwrjs avrbs fis Oeoi/s TTOS. Aj. 127. 
 
 a.Tr&ppT)TOv 7r6Xet, 1. 44; v6/J.ov /3tg, 1. 59; fliq. iroXiruv, 1. 79; dfj.rjxd.viin> 
 s, 1. 90 ; foovs, 1. 99.
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 53 
 
 rash deed of youth, prompted by folly and infatuation. 1 It is 
 an offence against justice; the work of defiant passion. 2 
 Bockh is also of opinion that unless it be assumed that 
 Antigone, no less than Creon, is guilty of rashness and re- 
 bellion, the play is deficient in unity. This view has been 
 examined elsewhere. It is enough to say here that the words 
 of Ismene and the chorus cannot be taken to be the judgment 
 of the poet, and that an action which involves a double cata- 
 strophe is not necessarily wanting in unity ; it may be the 
 manifestation of a single central idea. The leading idea of the 
 Antigone, is not merely that rebellion is a crime ; rebellion against 
 injustice, and such is Antigone's rebellion, can never be placed on 
 the same footing as the outrage of natural rights consecrated by 
 religion, in which lies the guilt of Creon. It is rather that the 
 laws of nature are not to be overridden by the law of the 
 State. That the assertion of this law involves both Antigone 
 and Creon in destruction does not in the least destroy the 
 unity of the drama. 
 
 But we may perhaps, from another point of view, ask : If 
 Antigone is in no way guilty, is not her death, in the language 
 of Aristotle, fiiapov, or shocking ? Does not the play decline 
 in this respect from the standard of the Poetics, 3 where we 
 learn that a character, to be tragic, must be good, but not 
 perfect ? 
 
 The explanation is, that men fall by their good qualities as 
 well as by their bad qualities ; and it is possible to be daring 
 and incautious in the cause of right no less than in the cause 
 of wrong. The afiapTia rt9, which Aristotle regards as a neces- 
 sary part of the tragic character, is not to be limited to moral 
 imperfection. It implies any flaw, however slight, of temper 
 or prudence. Such a flaw we may allow in Antigone without 
 detracting from her heroic character. She is hasty with her 
 
 1 ev d0po<riV>7 /ca0eX6i>res, 1. 383 ; \6yov T' &.VOLO. KOJ. <f>pfvwv 'Epicfa, 1. 603. 
 
 z Trpoj33.ff' fir' Hffxarov Opdffovs 
 v\f/vi\bv ^s At'/cas ftdOpov 
 Trpoffe'irtcres, & TKVOV, iro\v. 
 
 <rt 5' auT&yi'UTOs &\e<r' dpyd. Ant. 853 ff. 875. 
 8 Poetics, c. 13, 2.
 
 54 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 sister, abrupt and resolute in her own determination, and con- 
 temptuous towards Creon. Her nature is by no means concilia- 
 tory ; on the contrary, it is made up of extremes, a passionate 
 tenderness and love alternating with no less passionate resolu- 
 tion. This intensity of nature is not to be put on a level with 
 moral guilt. Antigone is righteous in her transgression (ocrto. 
 Travovp^rja-aaa). Ismene and the chorus may stand apart 
 from her they have neither her vision for right nor her will 
 to do it, but the gods justify her actions, as does also the 
 popular voice of Thebes. In defending her conduct she speaks 
 the law of nature and God, though she breaks the ordinance of 
 a man who identifies the law of the State with his own will. 
 Her suicide is her own act ; it is a rash deed, and for it we 
 may gently blame her, pleading in her defence that she takes a 
 life already doomed, and hastens from a lingering death to be 
 at rest with those whom she loves. 
 
 In Antigone then we must admit that we have a case in 
 which the lower nature (Creon) and the lower law is allowed 
 to triumph over the higher one. The triumph is short-lived, it 
 is true, and the scale is quickly turned. But the victory of her 
 cause cannot restore Antigone to life ; she is beyond the reach 
 of earthly comfort ; she suffers, so far as we can see, without 
 offence and without compensation. The evil has prevailed 
 against the good, and this, if false to any supposed canons of 
 art, is true to human nature. 
 
 Let us turn now to the two dramas which deal with the fate 
 of Oedipus. Here again we ask : Is it not piapov that a character 
 so noble and exalted as Oedipus should be involved in unmerited 
 destruction ? For who can say that his sufferings are deserved ? 
 Throughout he defends himself as an unconscious actor in the 
 crimes which have brought him into the abyss of ruin. "I 
 was the victim in wickedness, the victim, be God my witness, 
 for nothing in it was my own deliberate act." 1 When in the 
 Oedipus at Colonus, the chorus would speak of his deeds, he cries : 
 " Deeds they were not; I did nothing; I accepted a gift, which 
 
 eyKov KO.KOTO.T . . . 
 
 eyKOf eKiliv /J.v, 6fbs tffru, 
 
 VTW 5' avdaiperov ovdtv, 0. C. 521.
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 55 
 
 I would that I had never taken." 1 And again, in reference to 
 his incestuous connection with Jocasta, he declares, " She was 
 my mother, and we knew it not, and to her shame my mother 
 bore me children." 2 Indeed, the plea that the evil was uncon- 
 scious cannot be denied. There is nothing in the character of 
 Oedipus that can be brought forward as any sufficient reason 
 for his calamities. Headstrong, rash, and over-confident in 
 some respects he is, but once more we must not confuse weak- 
 ness of this kind with moral guilt. How different, for instance, 
 is Oedipus from Jocasta ! 
 
 There still remain the instances of Philoctetes and Dejanira. 
 The question whether the years of agony endured by Philoctetes 
 in Lemnos are brought upon him in retribution of some crime 
 of his own, or whether he is to be regarded as wholly guilt- 
 less, has been much discussed. Hasselbach and others contend 
 at great length for the guilt of Philoctetes ; Hermann and 
 Schneidewin are in favour of his innocence. There can hardly 
 be any doubt that the latter are right. The passages most to 
 the point are these : In 1. 192 ff., when making reply to the 
 chorus, who express their sympathy with the loneliness and 
 misery of Philoctetes, Neoptolemus says : " By heaven's will, 
 if there be wisdom in ine, these sufferings came upon him from 
 the ruthless Chryse." 3 And he adds the reason for the suffer- 
 ing : Troy was not to be destroyed before the appointed time, 
 and the affliction of Philoctetes was the divinely-appointed 
 means for delaying the destruction. Again, in 1. 1326 ff., Neo- 
 ptolemus tells Philoctetes: "This affliction is sent upon thee 
 by a divinely-ordered chance, in that thou didst approach the 
 guardian of Chryse, the hidden serpent, who keeps watch and 
 
 d&pov, 5 /XTJTTOT' eyil) raXawipSios 
 
 a. -rroXeos ^eX^ffdai. 0. C. 539. 
 
 8 triKTf ydp /j.' triKTfv, &fiot fj.oi KCLK&V, 
 OVK et'56r' OVK fl5vla, KO.1 reKovffd fJ.e 
 avrrjs 6vei5os vaidas e^<pvffe poi. Ibid. 982 ff. 
 
 3 6fca yap, eiirep Kdytii ri eppovu, 
 KCU TO. TT a.6 '77 yuara neiva ?r/)6j avrbv 
 rijs v[j.6<f>poi'os Xpvff-rjs iirtprj. Phil. 192 ff.
 
 56 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 ward in the open shrine." 1 These passages are as much 
 evidence as can be reasonably required to prove that there was 
 no intentional violation of the sanctuary of Chryse, whoever she 
 may have been, by Philoctetes. For the righteousness of his 
 dealings with his fellow-men w r e have evidence in a passage 
 where the chorus speak of him as one " who did no wrong to 
 any, nor defrauded him, a just man among the just." 2 Other 
 passages may no doubt be quoted, as, e.g. 1. 446 ff., in which 
 Philoctetes displays a certain vehemence against the gods ; but 
 this vehemence is induced by an experience of life in which the 
 evil has outstripped the good. If Philoctetes wonders that such 
 things as the triumph of Odysseus and the Atridae can happen 
 in a world governed by just gods, he is not alone in his wonder. 
 And with him such impatient thoughts are only on the surface. 
 He is not at heart sceptical of the justice of the gods ; he even 
 recognises it in his own case. 3 
 
 The misery which descends on Philoctetes is therefore due 
 to a dela rvxn- It serves a definite purpose in the economy of 
 the world, inasmuch as it delays the vengeance of the Greeks 
 upon Troy till the time appointed. 4 Dramatically, it serves 
 to bring out the character of Philoctetes in its strongest and 
 most sublime lines. It is therefore a fit object for a dramatic 
 poet to delineate, and Sophocles, as a rule, does not inquire into 
 the motive of a legend which he finds serviceable for dramatic 
 purposes. It is the more remarkable that in this instance he 
 has chosen to raise very clearly the further question of the 
 guilt or innocence of the sufferer. 
 
 Lastly, in the case of Dejanira there can be hardly any 
 question of guilt. Her action, perfectly innocent in itself, 
 except in so far as it may be called an experiment, is done 
 without the least suspicion of the results which flow from it, 
 
 1 ffi> yap voveis r6S' (LXyos tic Gfias TI/X*?*, 
 Xpijcrrjs irtXaffOds <f>v\a.Kos, 6s TOC a.Ka\v<f>T) 
 ffTjKov <f>v\dff<rfi Kpixpios oiKovpuv 6(pis. Phil. 1326 ff. 
 
 8 8s ofir' ?/)aj Tiv 1 oCrf vo<r<f>iffas, 
 dXX' foot ?i> -y' tcrois a.vT]p, 
 &\\v6' &6' ava^ius.Ibid. 684 ff. 
 
 Ibid. 1306. 4 Cf. Aesch. Ag. 365, 736.
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 57 
 
 and for a motive which cannot be condemned. She sees the 
 beauty of lole, she knows the weakness of Heracles, and seeks 
 to keep for herself the first place in the affection of her husband. 
 We may accuse her of aftovKla want of prudence, but of 
 nothing more. Even Heracles, at first so furious and eager for 
 vengeance upon the wife that has destroyed him, and Hyllus 
 admit, in the end, her complete innocence. 1 The miserable end 
 of Heracles is one divinely appointed for him ; and Dejanira 
 was but the agent in carrying out the divine purpose. 2 
 
 In all these cases, from Antigone onwards, the calamity 
 which overtakes the actor in the Sophoclean drama is not to be 
 attributed to moral guilt. Rashness and want of circumspec- 
 tion there may be, but the punishment is out of proportion to 
 such weakness. It is hopeless to attempt to find in Sophocles 
 a poetical justice measuring out sorrow and joy to every one 
 according to his deeds ; and such " poetical " justice would be 
 unworthy of so great a poet, because it is out of harmony with 
 the facts of human life. 
 
 Yet the gods are just, of this Sophocles has not a doubt. 
 And so once more the question presents itself, How are we 
 to account for the calamities which overtake the noble and 
 high-hearted among men ? What is the meaning of the suffer- 
 ing inflicted upon them ? 
 
 Can we fall back on the idea of an inherited curse ? In 
 Aeschylus this conception runs through a large part of his 
 theology, and is brought forward very strongly in the Seven 
 against Thebes and the Agamemnon. The Erinyes will not 
 leave the accursed house of the Atreidae, but remain there from 
 generation to generation till the last blow of divine vengeance 
 is struck. But in Sophocles this conception plays a far less 
 important part, though there are clear traces of it. In the 
 chorus already quoted more than once from the Antigone we 
 find it stated that when "a house is shaken from heaven, 
 
 1 K&V ffov ffrpa<f>fli] 0v/j.6s, el rb TTO.V /adflois . . . 
 
 jflfjiapre xpTjord. fj.w/j.^vij. Tr. 1134 ff. 
 
 1 ffj-ol yap J]v irp6<pavTov (K Trarpbt TrdXeu, 
 
 Trpis rCiv irvebvruv fj.-rjSfvbs Oaveiv Giro, 
 
 d\\' &mj"At5ov tydipevos oiKrfrup ire'Xoi. Ibid. 1159 ff.
 
 58 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 calamity never leaves it ; it advances upon the whole race ; 
 and one generation frees not another : a god dashes them 
 to earth and there is no release," x In the Electro, we find the 
 evils of the house of the Pelopidae traced back to the murder 
 of Myrtilus by Pelops. 2 Oedipus, in looking back on the misery 
 of his life, can only account for it by saying, " Such was the 
 will of the gods ; perhaps they cherished some anger of old 
 against my race." 3 
 
 Of these passages those taken from the Antigone and the 
 Electro, occur in the songs of the chorus, where the poet is 
 perhaps expressing the popular view of such miseries as those 
 of the Labdacids and Pelopids. The language of Oedipus 
 hardly amounts to more than a conjecture : " It may have been 
 some guilt of my father's which caused my woe; it was certainly 
 not any guilt of my own." In the case of Philoctetes and 
 Dejanira there is not the slightest allusion to anything of the 
 kind. They do not suffer for their own sins nor for the sins 
 of their fathers. Nor again is there in the play of Oedipus 
 Tyrannus an allusion to anything of the kind. In truth the 
 notion of an inherited curse, if held in its naked strength, is 
 calculated to limit the freedom of the individual so much as 
 to make a drama of character nearly impossible. But the 
 drama of Sophocles is a drama of character. 
 
 The mystery of suffering has not been cleared up yet, and 
 Sophocles may well have found it an almost insuperable 
 difficulty. His conception, so far as we can gather it from the 
 fate of Oedipus, Antigone, Philoctetes, and Dejanira, would seem 
 to be that suffering is part of the appointed order of the world, 
 alternating, at the best, with happiness, as night with day. But 
 to him suffering is not altogether an evil. It may further the 
 purposes of divine wisdom, as in Philoctetes ; it may develop, 
 
 1 aits yap av ffeurGy 6e6dev 56/x.os, &TTJS 
 ov5v ^XXetTret yeveas enl Tr\fj6os 'eptrov . . . 
 ovd' aTra\\d<Tffii yeveav yevos, dXX' tpetirct 
 Oe&v rts, ovd' %x ei ^vffu'- Ant. 584 ff. 
 
 2 Si n^XoTros a irpocrdev 
 ird\inrovos iTrireta, 
 
 wx fyioXes alavj) rq.5e yq., K.T.\. El. 504 ff. 
 
 0eo?s yap rjv ourw (f>i\ov, 
 rdx' & v TI fj.rjviovinv ej -y&oj TrdXat. 0. C. 964.
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 59 
 
 deepen, and enlarge a character, as in Philoctetes or Oedipus ; it 
 may establish a higher law, as in Antigone. This is the end of 
 suffering in its highest aspect ; but Sophocles does not exclude 
 the fact that there are accidents in life such as that which 
 caused the supposed death of Orestes, though even these 
 accidents, as we see from the case of Philoctetes, who suffers 
 ere 6eia$ TV^TJ^, are often divinely sent and of high importance 
 in life. There are, besides, the rash acts of men in moments 
 of excitement, the sins of vfipis, and the suffering caused by 
 deliberate wickedness extends to those who are in no way 
 guilty. But the truth which underlies these facts of human 
 nature is that the moral order of the world does not of necessity 
 mean the happiness of all men. From some it may demand 
 endurance and sacrifice, and he that loses his life shall find it. 
 Yet two questions still remain : 
 
 1. Is there no compensation for the suffering which falls 
 upon the guiltless, as part of the divine government of the 
 world ? 
 
 2. Do the gods intentionally bring calamity upon men in 
 order to accomplish certain ends ? or, to put the question more 
 plainly, Do the gods deceive men to their ruin ? 
 
 In the Philoctetes a definite recompense is made to the 
 wounded hero. Troy cannot be taken without him. Heracles, 
 the type of triumphant endurance, is sent to announce to him 
 the divine will. Heracles has won immortality by labour and 
 endurance, and Philoctetes has a similar lot. 1 Philoctetes will 
 be deemed the foremost warrior at Troy (1. 1425). He will slay 
 Paris, the arch-enemy, sack Troy, and return home to the 
 plain of Oeta with the prize of valour. Aesculapius will 
 be sent to cure his wound. He is not left without his reward ; 
 it comes to him in full measure, and it comes to him before his 
 death. 
 
 Oedipus again is greater in his death than in his life. His 
 position as king of Thebes is only apparently majestic ; the 
 true majesty is seen when the Eumenides permit him to enter 
 their holy place, when Theseus gives him welcome, when Thebes 
 strives in vain to recover possession of his body, when Poly- 
 
 1 /cat crol, ffd(f>' ladi, TOUT' 6(f>fi\eTai iraBelv, 
 IK TUIV KaKuv -rCivS 1 evK\ea 6{<rdai {Hov. Phil. 1421.
 
 60 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 nices prays for his help in the attempt to regain his throne, 
 and, above all, when the divine voice summons him to his last 
 resting-place ; and he is allowed to pass away from life in a 
 mysterious manner, taken, as it were, to his rest without the 
 trial of death. His tomb becomes a holy place, bringing pro- 
 sperity to those who possess it. The life of suffering has its 
 reward in the final triumph of him who endured nobly. 
 
 Moreover, as has been pointed out by Dronke, calamity when 
 undeserved is represented by Sophocles as having no power 
 against the inward conviction of rectitude. " Thou wilt keep 
 him in perfect peace whose mind is stayed on thee." These 
 words of the greatest of Hebrew prophets, uttered at a time 
 when ruin was impending on his nation, denote the peace 
 which Israel may yet gain by trusting in Jehovah. No Greek 
 could have uttered them, for no Greek was ever so deeply 
 penetrated with the love of the Deity for the nation. But 
 what Isaiah extends to the nation Sophocles can say of the 
 individual. The peace of the spirit which rests on the highest 
 and holiest deities is not easily disturbed. Secure in that 
 repose, it can rise above the distress of unconscious errors and 
 involuntary crimes. If Creon accuses Oedipus, the accusations 
 only serve to reveal his own baseness. He is not worthy to 
 tread the soil of Attica, but Oedipus may recline in the hallowed 
 shrine of the Eumenides. 
 
 But Antigone : In her case there is no final triumph. The 
 consolation offered by the chorus, that her death is glorious, 
 exempt from disease and bloodshed, is rightly rejected by her 
 as no equivalent for the brightness and hope of life. There is 
 no compensation for Antigone in this life, and what does 
 Sophocles tell us of the next ? 
 
 Even when she is brought face to face with death, and the 
 " pity of it " becomes more deeply felt, Antigone speaks with 
 cheerful hope of that other world in which she will join her 
 friends : " When I come there, such is the hope I cherish, I 
 shall find love with my father, love with my mother, and love 
 with thee, my brother." l The life which will be hers then will 
 
 v TJ^ftV TTCLTp, 
 
 fj.Tjrep, (f>l\r) 5 crol, KaffiyvyTov Kapa. Ant. 897
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 6r 
 
 be far longer than the life of this world. 1 And in that future 
 life there will be no misapprehensions and mistakes. " Justice 
 has her home with the gods below." '' 
 
 Hence for the righteous there is a good hope in death, and 
 the life to come is a real existence in which the broken ties of 
 this world will be united, never to be severed again. Heracles 
 is now an immortal being abiding in heaven. 3 Electra speaks 
 of her father's spirit as alive (El. 459), and Clytenmestra will 
 live in the under-world (El. 437). By thus conveying the 
 mind to another life, Sophocles in some measure softens the 
 weight of injustice and misery in this. Antigone, in the con- 
 sciousness that her act is accepted before the higher powers 
 " in those pure eyes and perfect witness of all-judging Jove," 
 is content to undergo the sentence which man pronounces 
 upon her. And her death achieves the victory which her life 
 could not have achieved. Not only is her brother buried, but 
 the ordinance of burial is established by higher and holier laws. 
 We see then that in a certain sense compensation comes to 
 those who suffer innocently such compensation as a noble 
 spirit would seek to gain. But there are passages which seem 
 to intimate that God leads a man to ruin. And if this be so, 
 how can we any longer speak of the justice and truth of God ? 
 In Antigone, 1. 623, the passage so often quoted, we are plainly 
 told " that evil seems good to a man whom God is leading to 
 ruin " (p. 48). This is the reflection of the chorus on the house 
 of Labdacus, and it probably reproduces with accuracy the 
 ordinary Greek conception. Many a man looking back on 
 actions done in moments of passion or excitement can hardly 
 give any other account of them than that he was not himself 
 when he did them. So Helen excuses her weakness arrj fie 
 Traprjjaye, and in a religion where dualism was unknown, this 
 deception or bewitchment is naturally referred to the gods. 
 But if the chorus mean this sentiment to apply to Antigone in 
 the sense that she has confounded good and evil in her act of 
 self-devotion, neither Sophocles nor we can agree. In the life 
 
 tirel ir\eiuv -xpbvos 
 
 &v Set /j.' aptaKeiv TOLS Karw r(av ev6A8f. Ant. 74. 
 * r) fftivoiKO'i rCiv K&TU deuv ALKIJ. Ibid. 451. 
 3 aOdvarov a-perty lffx ov t us irdpecrd' opav. Phil. 1420.
 
 62 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 of Oedipus we have indeed evil seeming good. His success at 
 Thebes in destroying the Sphinx and gaining the hand of 
 Jocasta is an instance of the way in which evil may seem good ; 
 but it is the shortsightedness of man rather than the decep- 
 tion of God which brings him to ruin. Oedipus, who has been 
 forewarned of his destiny, acts ov& opwv ovd' icn-opwv in the death 
 of Laius and the marriage of Jocasta. In the case of Dejanira 
 we may also observe a similar want of caution. The suffering 
 in either case is not a thing apart from the aj3ov\ia of the 
 sufferer. The deception of God is not to be charged with that 
 which is due to the blindness of man. If man were all-wise, 
 and could in every act proceed with perfect knowledge, he 
 would be saved from much, if not all, the suffering which comes 
 upon him ; being imperfect, he must accept the suffering which 
 comes from ignorance as well as that which comes from crime 
 and its punishment. 
 
 Still it is possible to ask Is this divine order of the world, 
 which entails suffering on men, more than mere destiny ? Can 
 we deny, in spite of the lofty tone of many passages, that in 
 Sophocles man is the slave of a relentless destiny whose will 
 he is powerless to resist or escape ? 
 
 It is often assumed that the tragedy of the Greeks, especially 
 in the hands of Aeschylus and Sophocles, is no more than a 
 tragedy of destiny. That is, it exhibits man not as suffering in 
 consequence of his own misdeeds, or as the slave of his own 
 passions, but as the sport of destiny doomed at birth to a 
 certain pre-ordained fate, which he strives in vain to resist. 
 Every man has his fwlpa, and the interest of the tragic situa- 
 tion lies in showing how this ftolpa is fulfilled. Often this 
 fjbolpa is announced in an oracle, often it is not known till the 
 end of life, but, known or unknown, it is inevitable and uncon- 
 trollable by the will of man. Even those who do not find this 
 " destiny " in the work of Sophocles regard it as the ground- 
 work of the tragedy of Aeschylus. 
 
 If destiny, as something apart from and superior to the will 
 of the gods, plays such an important part in Greek tragedy, it 
 is remarkable that Aristotle should have no allusion to it in his 
 Poetics. It is more than remarkable, it is impossible that if 
 he entertained such a view of destiny he should have written
 
 ETHICS Of SOPHOCLES. 63 
 
 the description of the " tragic " character in the thirteenth 
 chapter of that work. For with Aristotle the truly tragic 
 character is not, as we might expect, a good man struggling 
 with an evil destiny, but a good man failing St' afj.aprlav 
 rivd. The tragic character is not tcrcs ct rotundus, a perfect 
 sphere on whose smooth surface no speck can be found, 
 but a character with faults, and yet suffering beyond the 
 desert of the faults. Such a character implies freedom of 
 will, which on the hypothesis of an overruling destiny is 
 annihilated. And therefore in any severe system of fatalism 
 tragedy becomes impossible. There must be room for the 
 individual choice, for the individual development of character, 
 or the " tragic " element becomes " shocking " (p,iapov). There 
 is no relation between a man's moral guilt and his actions, 
 without which a drama is impossible. Hence Aeschylus, in 
 whom, if anywhere, we may look for the idea of destiny, is 
 nevertheless at pains to show that the actions of men are free. 
 It is open to Eteocles to go forth to meet his brother Polynices, 
 or to remain. He declares that he must go, that it is the 
 curse of his father which is driving him along a fatal path. 
 But the chorus plead against his resolution, though they plead 
 in vain. In the same way it is open to Agamemnon, if he will, 
 to return home from Aulis, and save his daughter from sacrifice. 
 But he will not return TTCO? \i7rovavs yevcopat, ; and thus both 
 Eteocles and Agamemnon place themselves within the reach 
 of the curse of their house. In Sophocles, Antigone urges 
 Polynices not to pursue his march to Thebes, but to save him- 
 self from the curse of Oedipus by returning to Argos. But 
 Polynices, like Agamemnon in Aeschylus, cannot be false to 
 his army. He goes on his way, though he is going to certain 
 destruction. The principle which urges these heroes to their 
 doom is not unlike that false sense of honour which has pre- 
 vailed in modern times. It is not destiny. 
 
 Again: Such an idea of destiny as that described is impossible 
 when the gods have been recognised as omnipotent and just. 
 So long as there is a question about the justice of the reign of 
 Zeus, the " triple Moerae and mindful Erinyes " may have power 
 against him, but this power is gone when Zeus is himself the 
 centre and source of justice. An unjust destiny is at variance
 
 64 THE THEOLOGY AND 
 
 with the will of the Almighty ; a just destiny is merely the ex- 
 pression of his will : in no case is there room for destiny outside 
 and above the deity. There is therefore no destiny apart from 
 the will of God. By obedience to that will man may escape 
 from evil, by opposing it he may bring evil on himself and 
 on his descendants. Labdacus consciously opposed the will of 
 heaven ; Oedipus, when informed of the evil in store, does the 
 very actions which he should most have avoided. In the case of 
 Antigone there is no question of destiny at all. She acts of her 
 own will, in defiance of an authority which has the power to 
 punish by death. Dejanira dies by her own hand, in consequence 
 of her own act. Her conduct may have been a part of an order 
 of things which the gods foreknew, but there was no irresistible 
 destiny compelling her to act as she did. She acts from 
 human motives ; she takes human counsel, and her act is a 
 mistake. Philoctetes suffers eic Oeias TV^T)?, by an accident, as 
 it were, which serves the purposes of heaven. Whether he could 
 have escaped his accident or not it is useless to inquire, for 
 the drama of Sophocles is founded on the fact that he did not 
 escape it. He has his reward, and his suffering is not due to 
 a blind destiny, but to the conscious purpose of the gods. 
 
 Aeschylus and Sophocles are not religious teachers as the 
 Hebrew prophets and St. Paul are religious teachers. They are 
 not conscious of a divine mission, or carried out of themselves in 
 an ecstasy of faith and love. They are poets, desiring to give to 
 a nation the pleasure which poetry can give. But the greatness 
 of the themes on which they wrote, and of the times in which 
 they lived, brought them into close contact with the truths 
 and difficulties underlying all faith and morality. These 
 they did not pass over, or treat in any merely formal manner. To 
 them, therefore, and to Plato, we must look for the best that the 
 Western world can tell us on the nature of God, on the relation 
 of the divine and the human. In the popular Hellenic view, all 
 the calamities of men were either the result of crime in the 
 individual, or some ancestor of the individual, or they were the 
 work of a capricious power known as " destiny." This popular 
 conception Aeschylus strove to elevate and refine. He elimi- 
 nated the caprice of destiny as irreconcilable with the justice 
 of the divine nature, and sought, in every case, to connect the
 
 ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 65 
 
 calamity of the sufferer with some deliberate act of wrong- 
 doing : " Sin and sorrow, the old, old story." l In this severe 
 conception the justice of God is, if we may use the expression, 
 saved at the expense of facts. The popular view is right in 
 maintaining that the guiltless do suffer : yet how can destiny 
 be anything but the will of God ? and how can the will of God be 
 anything but just ? Here Sophocles takes up the problem. He 
 accepts the mysterious fact that the guiltless do suffer, but seeks 
 to explain it by taking a higher view of the nature of such 
 suffering. For him the calamities of the guiltless are part of 
 human life as a whole, not punishments dealt out to indi- 
 viduals. They are often necessary to the development of char- 
 acter ; without them we should know nothing of the strength 
 and majesty of Oedipus or Philoctetes. They assist in the 
 general purposes of humanity ; and thus at times, as in the case 
 of Antigone, suffering comes near to the modern conception of 
 self-sacrifice. They help to bring before us the true nature 
 of life, and separate the accidental from the real. It is not 
 prosperity and success, it is often failure and endurance, which 
 become the most effective and truly real factors in the advance- 
 ment of mankind. Hence it is only a superficial judgment that 
 can ascribe to the injustice of the gods or the caprice of destiny 
 the evil which overtakes the good. In part, no doubt, that evil 
 is the result of some want of foresight, which, though not 
 morally culpable, is yet sufficient to bring calamity upon a man, 
 or even on a race. In part it arises from the imperfection of a 
 world in which justice and power are not always in the same 
 hands. It may also arise from the wise purposes of the gods, 
 " whom no weak pity moves " to regard the happiness of one 
 man more than the elevation of all, more than the illustration 
 of some great moral truth. In any case, it must not be taken 
 alone ; it must always be considered in reference to the whole, 
 just as in human life isolation is impossible. Calamity, again, 
 is a wholesome check on the conceit of knowledge and power. 
 To the Greek prosperity was a snare ; it tended to raise him 
 above the appointed limit, and kindle ambitions which brought 
 about their own overthrow. Even in the ordinary course of life 
 
 dpd.aa.vTi vaOelv rpiytpwv fj.v8os rdSe 

 
 66 THE THEOLOGY AND ETHICS OF SOPHOCLES. 
 
 it was difficult to know the bounds of human nature and " think 
 human thoughts." To live entirely free from danger in this 
 respect would require perfect wisdom, the knowledge what to do 
 and what to leave undone in every circumstance, every moment 
 of life. Such knowledge is not attainable by men ; it is divine ; 
 and only by submission to the divine power may we hope to 
 gain something of it. For the gods are accessible by oracles, 
 and declare their will to men, darkly indeed, but yet in tones 
 which a simple heart may understand. Finally, when calamity 
 has been thus separated from guilt so Sophocles seems to 
 teach us, and the lesson is the more striking in a nation so 
 excessive in its regard for prosperity and its dread of misfor- 
 tune as the Greeks it loses half its terrors. It has still an 
 outward power in so far as it may bring poverty and distress ; 
 it may mar the body and make life heavy to be borne, but 
 it has no inward power against the mind. Vain is the 
 remembrance of his past agony, vain the prospect of help- 
 less distress to subdue the mighty heart of Philoctetes in his 
 lonely island ; vain are all promises of glory and dominion to 
 move the spirit of the outcast Oedipus. Each is the guiltless 
 victim of a grievous calamity, and the inward consciousness 
 of innocence makes the outward suffering of less moment. In 
 the end the reward of patience, endurance, and submission 
 comes, either in this world or the next. The lowly is exalted, 
 the rejected is victorious. The undertone of divine vengeance 
 running through the dramas of Aeschylus seems in Sophocles 
 to pass away into an echo of divine compassion, and we move 
 from the gloom of " sin and sorrow " towards the dawning of a 
 brighter day in which strength is made perfect in weakness. 
 
 E. A.
 
 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 
 
 SOME apology may seem to be due for printing an Essay 
 upon a subject so well worn as the Platonic conception of 
 Education, the more so as I have no new discoveries to detail 
 and no new theories to advance. But it seems true that 
 Greek thought is in a sense ever young ; that while its lessons 
 are always being learnt, they are always being forgotten and 
 misunderstood ; and that though much has been done for its 
 interpretation, and the study of it has established itself in the 
 curriculum of our schools and Universities, we are still in many 
 respects only at the threshold, and often see it through a veil of 
 conventional platitudes, pretentious antiquarianism, or senti- 
 mental finery. All that I have here attempted is to draw 
 renewed attention to some of the salient and familiar points in 
 a subject which concerns us all, and to suggest reflection upon 
 our own corresponding theory and practice. 
 
 The subject of Education is treated by Plato in the 
 Republic as an integral and vital part of the wider subject 
 of the wellbeing of human society, and it is scarcely possible 
 to give an intelligent account of his treatment without first 
 indicating the scope and plan of the work as a whole. The 
 Republic opens by asking the question, What is the nature of 
 justice ? and the first four books of it pursue the answer to this 
 question without any serious deviation. The real bearing of 
 the question is but poorly represented to us in its English 
 dress ; it would be better expressed, if (following the sugges- 
 tion of Plato himself 1 ) we substituted for it the question, How 
 
 1 1. 344 e ; 352 d.
 
 68 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 are men to order their lives so as to live best ? which naturally 
 involves the further question, What is to live well ? Various 
 representative answers to these questions are first propounded 
 and examined ; the personal experience of the good old man of 
 the good old time, the half-understood maxims of the educated 
 man of the world, the sounding formulas of the unscrupulous 
 and cynical rhetorician, all these are passed in review, and 
 found to be inadequate, ill-considered, or self-destructive. Then 
 the voice of society or its leaders is listened to ; current theories 
 of the origin of law and morality, which resolve the one into 
 arbitrary convention and the other into a calculation of rewards 
 and punishments, or a system of indulgences, are exhibited in 
 their most naked form ; until at last we seem to be left with 
 the whole of popular opinion and experience arrayed upon the 
 side of what is called injustice, and upon the other side nothing 
 but a bare conviction, to which the moral sense of man still 
 clings, though unable to justify itself for doing so. 
 
 Such a justification Socrates is now called upon to give. 
 We Jiave had enough of verbal discussions x in which every- 
 thing seems to depend upon the sense in which the particular 
 disputant takes the particular word in dispute; nor can we 
 rest satisfied with theories which reduce morality to its material 
 consequences, whether in this world or the next. If justice 
 and injustice, right and wrong, are not merely the same thing 
 viewed from different sides, but express real and radical dis- 
 tinctions, they must admit of being exhibited " as they are in 
 themselves," that is, not in their current equivalents of wealth, 
 success, popularity, and the reverse, but as forces working for 
 good or ill in the very soul of man. 2 With the demand for 
 such an exhibition, the inquiry passes from the domain of 
 verbal definition and popular opinion to that of psychology, and 
 the question, How are we to order our lives for the best ? 
 becomes the question, What is the nature of the living prin- 
 ciple 3 within us which Plato calls the soul ? Though, however, 
 this is the real import of the transition now made in the 
 dialogue, it is made in a form which would be little expected 
 
 1 '2. 367 b, /J.r] ot'v ijfjuv JMVOV evdei^r) TU \&yy, K.T.\. 
 3 2. 360 e ; 367 b and d ; 358 b. 
 3 Cf. 4. 445 a, O.VTOV TOUTOV < fu>/j,fi>.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 69 
 
 by a modern student of moral psychology. Instead of meet- 
 ing the new requirement by analysing the human soul, Plato 
 proceeds to analyse human society. The reason for this is 
 to be found in his conviction that in society (to interpret his 
 own familiar simile x ) we see man " writ large ; " in other 
 words, that in the broad outlines of the state, with its classes, 
 its trade and industry, its military and political institutions, 
 the secret and subtle elements of human nature come to the 
 surface, take visible shape, and are unmistakably legible to the 
 observer. If then we would study human life successfully, we 
 must begin from the outside and work inwards ; we must take 
 the obvious facts and principles without which society would 
 not go on, and ask, what they mean, of what inner facts and 
 principles are they the exponents ? And in order to do this, 
 we must have a method. It will not do to take society at any 
 chance point on its surface and probe it there ; we must begin 
 at the beginning, we must look at it "in its growth." 2 Not, 
 however, in its historical, but in its logical and psychological 
 "growth;" for this seems to be the explanation of the picture 
 which Plato gives of " the genesis of the State." He has begun 
 with what he considered the lowest stratum of life, at the point 
 where it is most nearly the mere keeping life alive, the mere 
 satisfaction of necessary wants ; to this rudimentary basis he 
 has gradually added the higher factors of human nature, with 
 their accompanying needs ; and throughout the structure, alike 
 in its lower and its higher ranges, he has shown us the same 
 principle of efficiency and well-being, a principle writ large on 
 the face of society, 3 but to be ultimately traced back to its 
 analogue in the constitution of the human soul itself. That 
 principle, to which he gives the name of justice, may be briefly 
 
 1 2. 368 d. 2 2. 369 a, yiyvo^vijv iro\iv. 
 
 8 Cf. 4. 443 b-c, where it is stated that the principle of the division of 
 labour in trade and industry was a sort of "initial outline " (apx-riv Te Ka ^ 
 Tijirov riva) of justice, the first suggestion and rudimentary form of it, and 
 further, that this principle was really only " an image " (ttSu\6v rt) of justice, 
 the truth being that justice is not merely concerned with ' ' the external doing 
 one's own work," but with " the inward doing of what is in very truth one's 
 own ; " so the harmonious working of the soul within itself is the really 
 essential condition of which external organisation is merely the " image " or 
 outward expression.
 
 7 o THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TWN 
 
 explained as follows : Every man has wants, of which he can- 
 not get rid, but which he cannot himself satisfy. 1 They are as 
 various as the want of food and clothes, the want of protection 
 from external violence, the want of assistance against his own 
 lower nature; but whatever their character, they make him 
 individually insufficient for himself. On the other hand, while 
 all men need others, all men are, or may be, needed by others ; 
 the same limitation which forces the individual into society 
 also makes him a useful member of it; for the diversity of 
 individual character is not a mere diversity of atoms, but has 
 in it the capability of organisation, or, in other words, of form- 
 ing a whole. These primary facts suggest, as the true principle 
 of human life, that each social element should do that which it 
 is most fitted to do, thus contributing to the common stock the 
 best that it has to give, and receiving from each other element 
 that of which it is itself most in need. The more society is so 
 ordered that this twofold principle of division and association 
 of work is carried out, the more nearly will it approach its 
 most natural and most perfect form. The main part of the first 
 section of the Republic, from the middle of the second to the 
 end of the fourth book, is occupied with the sketch of a society 
 as it might be conceived to be if this principle of harmonious 
 co-operation were realised, and it is as an element in its reali- 
 sation that what may be called the first system of education is 
 developed. 
 
 Before considering that system in its details, it will be well 
 to see what was Plato's conception of education in general, for 
 by it his whole treatment of the subject is in a great measure 
 determined. We know in our own time what a difference it 
 may make in the spirit and working of an educational method, 
 whether the idea with which it starts is that of culture, or of 
 training, or of useful accomplishment. Plato's idea of the 
 essence of education is most simply and comprehensively 
 
 1 The " insufficiency " of the individual is first illustrated from the most 
 obvious sphere, that of the necessary wants (2. 369 c ff.); but it holds 
 good in higher spheres too ; cf. 9. 590 d-e (the divine reason which it is 
 good for a man to be governed by, if he has not got it in himself, is supplied to 
 him from outside). Similarly the industrial principle of association is applied 
 to the relation of the philosophers to the society of which they are members 
 (7. 519 e 520 a).
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 71 
 
 expressed in the word "nurture." 1 To him the human soul 
 is emphatically and before all else something living, something 
 which in the strict sense we can neither create nor destroy, 
 but which we can feed or starve, nourish or poison. As in 
 the case of other living things, of plants and animals, 2 the 
 stronger and better the nature of the soul, the more important 
 is it what nourishment it gets, and a gifted soul in a corrupt 
 society is like a good seed sown in a strange soil; it grows 
 crooked and unlike itself, loses its proper virtue, and sinks at 
 last to the level of its surroundings. And in another famous 
 passage, 3 to which we shall have to refer more than once, the 
 young citizen who is being educated is compared to an animal 
 at pasture ; from the things which he sees and hears about him 
 he assimilates, little by little, the good or the evil which they 
 embody, till " many a little makes a mickle," which becomes 
 part and parcel of himself. It is this feeling of the assimilative 
 power of the soul which leads Plato to attach such immense 
 importance to the circumstances and environment of life, and 
 makes him on the whole more disposed to attribute moral evil 
 to bad nurture than to inherent vice. Amongst the various 
 elements which make up the complex creature man, he con- 
 ceives that there are few which are not open to good influence. 
 Of what are usually called the lower desires there are indeed 
 some that are radically " wild," 4 and with these there is only 
 one course possible, to stop their growth ; but the others admit 
 of being " tamed," and made to take service under the higher 
 self. And thus it is with a sort of compassion that Plato 5 
 looks upon some of the great criminals of the world, who in 
 his eyes had the capability of being its greatest benefactors, 
 and owe their failure to its corruption or neglect. Against the 
 all-powerful influence of society, 6 he thinks that no private 
 teaching can hold its ground. It is not the so-called en- 
 lightened leaders of public opinion, the sophists of the day, 
 who really teach and demoralise the youth ; 7 the real educator 
 
 1 Cf., for the use of rpo<J>ri or cognate terms, 3. 401 b, e ; 402 a ; 403 c ; 
 412 b ; 4. 424 a ; 6. 491 d-e ; and Phaedrus, 247 e ff., where the metaphor 
 is enlarged upon. 
 
 3 6. 497 b ; 491 d 492 a. s 3. 401 c-d. 4 9. 589 b ; 591 b. 
 
 5 6. 491 e. 6 6. 492 c-e. 7 6. 492 a-b.
 
 7 2 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 and the real sophist is public opinion itself, whose voice, 
 resounding in the assembly and the law-courts, in the theatre 
 and the camp, is practically irresistible by the isolated efforts 
 of individuals. Such a power for evil can only be counter- 
 acted by creating a power for good as penetrating, as uncon- 
 scious, and as universal, and to do this is the true function of 
 a public system of education. On the other hand, while the 
 inherent vitality of the soul makes the question of its nourish- 
 ment all-important, it also precludes a merely mechanical treat- 
 ment of it. We can place it in a healthy atmosphere, but we 
 cannot compel it to assimilate only the healthy elements. 
 The " eye of the soul " l is not, as some " professors of education" 
 seem to think, a blind eye into which knowledge can be put ; 
 its power of vision can neither be originally produced by edu- 
 cation, nor entirely destroyed by the want of it ; it can only be 
 " turned to the light," for which it has an intrinsic capacity. 
 And the same holds good of the lower extremity of human 
 nature ; as in the " wild " and unteachable element there is a 
 power of growth which can only be dealt with by being re- 
 pressed, so among men there are found moral "incurables," 
 for whom society has no course but to put them out of the 
 way. 2 
 
 The very simplicity of these ideas, as in the case of some 
 others of Plato, is apt to conceal their importance. Everybody 
 admits in theory that the human self is a living being, requir- 
 ing a certain environment in order to grow properly, and 
 capable of growing improperly in an immense variety of ways. 
 But it is mainly in dealing with the material circumstances of 
 life that the truth of the principle is practically realised, because 
 there the consequences of its neglect are palpable : when we 
 have to do with the mental atmosphere we are liable to forget 
 it. Then again, the greater specialisation of modern life makes 
 it difficult for us to keep our hold on universal elementary 
 truths, which to the Greeks seemed neither old nor simple. 
 Modern education inevitably divides itself under many heads 
 it is primary or higher, technical or liberal, scientific or reli- 
 gious ; the distinctions are real and cannot be ignored ; but in 
 
 1 7. 518 b-c. 2 3. 410 a ; cf. 10. 613 e.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 73 
 
 the controversies to which they sometimes give rise it is well, 
 just because it is hard, to remember, that the ultimate subject 
 of all education is a living organism, whose vital power, though 
 divisible in thought, is really one and undivided ; that its 
 vital wants are equally such, whether they be for fresh air, for 
 useful knowledge, or for religious truth ; and that it will starve 
 or degenerate in mind if its natural mental nourishment be 
 denied it, as surely as it will in body if its bodily wants be 
 neglected. 
 
 Such being Plato's general conception of the nature of 
 education, we may expect that any system of education which 
 he propounds will be a system for providing proper nurture to 
 the growing soul, or for adjusting its surroundings to its higher 
 needs. It is also clear that the particular character of the 
 system for attaining these ends must be determined by the 
 conception of the human nature which has to be fed, and the 
 needs to which its circumstances have to be adjusted. And 
 thus, in order to understand Plato's theory of education, we 
 must understand his psychology. 
 
 In giving some account of the psychology of the Republic, 
 we shall have to notice that, while the ground-plan of the 
 account of the soul remains on the whole the same, the position 
 assigned to its various elements changes considerably in different 
 parts of the work ; and these changes are necessarily accompanied 
 by changes in the view taken of education. We will begin with 
 the psychology of the first section of the work, only combining 
 that of later sections where it seems to be in substantial agree- 
 ment. From this we gather that Plato regarded the human 
 soul as a complex whole, consisting of three " forms," " kinds," 
 or "parts," 1 as he variously calls them. The first of these, 
 beginning at the lower end in the scale of worth, is vrnQvpla 
 or " appetite." Plato 2 was aware that in what he called the 
 "appetitive " form of the soul he was dealing with something 
 too various to be easily described by a single name. He seems 
 to have chosen the name in question because the bodily appe- 
 tites, to which it was most commonly appropriated, are, from 
 
 1 elSos, 4. 435 c ; 439 e, etc. ; ytvos, 4. 441 c ; 443. d ; jutyoj, 4. 442 b. 
 
 2 9. 5SO d-e.
 
 74 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 their intensity, the most obvious and conspicuous instances of 
 their class. He has, however, another name, suggested, not by 
 the degree of intensity of the activity, but by what seemed to 
 him its most typical object; 1 " because wealth is the principal 
 instrument by which the bodily appetites are satisfied, we call 
 this element of the soul the wealth -loving or gain-loving ele- 
 ment." This close association of things sometimes supposed to 
 be so far apart as sensuality and avarice, 2 is very characteristic 
 of Plato ; and we shall see later on by what facts he illustrates 
 it. For the present it is enough to observe that, though Plato 
 by no means confines the word translated " appetite " to the 
 above-mentioned instances, 3 yet when he speaks of the " appe- 
 titive " as a specific form or part of the soul, he intends primarily 
 those desires of which bodily satisfaction and wealth are the 
 typical objects. Of such appetites he distinguishes in a later 
 book two kinds, " necessary " and " unnecessary." 4 Necessary 
 appetites are those which we cannot get rid of, or those of which 
 the satisfaction does us good ; unnecessary are those which are 
 superfluous or harmful. In these latter, 5 again, there is a sub- 
 division into those which, though in themselves unproductive 
 and wasteful to the organism, are yet capable of regulation, and 
 those which are incurably " wild," " bestial," " lawless," which 
 make themselves felt, even in the best men, when reason is in 
 abeyance, but which, unless repressed or reduced to a minimum, 
 bring ruin into life. These distinctions are graphically repro- 
 duced in a somewhat generalised form in one of the allegorical 
 figures under which Plato represents his conception of human 
 nature. He asks us to imagine a being having the outward 
 semblance of a man, 6 but combining within three creatures, a 
 man, a lion, and " a beast with many heads, heads of beasts tame 
 and wild, and able to breed and change them at its will." Of 
 the first two there will be more to say presently ; in the third 
 we readily recognise the psychological element of appetite in 
 the sense just described. The hydra-like creature has in it an 
 inherent capacity of growth and reproduction ; some of its off- 
 
 1 9. 580 e 581 a. 2 3. 390 b 391 c ; 4. 442 a ; 8. 548 a-b. 
 
 8 Cf. e.g. 5. 475 b; 9. 5SO d. 4 8. 558 d ff. 
 6 9. 571 b ff. 9. 588 b ff.
 
 AV THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 75 
 
 spring can be "tamed " and " domesticated," 1 and made service- 
 able to life ; others are radicably untameable, the inorganic, 
 inhuman, " unnecessary," and possibly destructive, appendage 
 of our nature, which, while it can never entirely divest itself of 
 its humanity, touches God at one extremity and the beast at 
 the other. 
 
 Though Plato represents appetite as the element which 
 occupies the largest space in the soul, 2 and though the men who 
 live for appetite more than for any other part of themselves 
 are, in his view, the majority of mankind, we shall not expect 
 it to occupy the chief share of attention in his system of educa- 
 tion. The degree of education of which the appetites are 
 capable is expressed by his own word "taming," 3 and by this 
 he seems to mean such a regulation of them as shall prevent 
 them from interfering with the higher psychical activities, and 
 train them to contribute to the good of the whole soul that 
 basis of healthy physical life which is the necessary ground- 
 work of those activities. 
 
 The second element in the Platonic analysis of the soul 
 is not quite so easily described or understood. The Greek 
 words Ovfjio^ rb dv/jioei&es, by which it is designated, are com- 
 monly translated " spirit," and though this term covers only a 
 part of their meaning in the Republic, it will serve as well as 
 any other in the absence of a real equivalent. " Spirit " is 
 first introduced as being the indispensable foundation of cour- 
 age, 4 that element of hardihood and intrepidity which is common 
 to men with dogs and horses, and which makes them " never 
 say die ; " at the same time it is represented as the source of 
 pugnacity and aggressiveness, with their possible developments 
 into ferocity and cruelty. It is only another form of the same 
 view, when " spirit " is said to be that part of the soul which 
 is peculiarly fostered and stimulated by athletic exercises ; 5 it is 
 the " hard" element in human nature, which, if rightly nurtured, 
 becomes true bravery, but if exclusively encouraged degenerates 
 into blind brutality, surliness, quarrelsomeness, or self-will. In 
 
 1 9. 589 b, necuretuv. 2 4. 442 a ; 9. 588 d ; 4. 431 c. 
 8 Cf. 4. 442 a ; 8. 559 a-b ; 9. 591 c d. 4 2. 375 a-b. 
 
 2 3. 410 c-d ; 411 c-e ; 9. 590 a-b.
 
 76 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 all this we at once recognise the " lion " of the allegorical figure 
 of man mentioned above. 
 
 So far the account of the "spirited" element is simple enough. 
 It has two other senses which are not quite so obvious ; the one 
 attaching to the sense of anger which $17^69 so commonly has, 
 the other to that of pugnacity. From the former point of view 
 " spirit " appears as what we may call righteous indignation. It 
 is that which makes a man's blood boil at the consciousness of 
 suffering unjustly, 1 while it is characteristically absent when the 
 suffering is felt to be deserved. It is that, again, 2 which makes 
 a man angry with himself when he feels that he has let his 
 appetites get the better of his reason, whereas no one ever feels 
 this anger when he has let his better judgment prevail over his 
 appetite. These observations lead Plato to represent " spirit " 
 as the natural ally or servant of the rational or better self; 3 not 
 that it is never irrational, or may not be perverted by bad edu- 
 cation, 4 but that it never seems to act with the lower appetites 
 against the reason ; or, to use more modern phraseology, if we 
 are once convinced that in refusing to satisfy an appetite we 
 are acting reasonably, we may feel dissatisfaction, but we do 
 not feel indignation. In its third and last distinctive use, 5 
 " spirit " is the root of ambition or the competitive instinct. In 
 this sense it is, as was said, a modification of the fighting 
 spirit, for the essence both of ambition and of pugnacity is the 
 desire to do better than somebody else. And as in the other 
 two senses, so here " spirit " may have a good or a bad develop- 
 ment, into honourable rivalry on the one hand, on the other 
 into mere contentiousness. 
 
 It is not difficult to see how these various representations 
 of " spirit " may be connected. In all of them there is an ele- 
 ment of w r hat we may call self-assertion and self-consciousness. 
 It is this, in the form of not choosing to be " put upon," which 
 makes us resist what we think injustice ; it is this, in the form 
 of honourable pride, which makes us face danger without flinch- 
 ing, and prompts us to measure ourselves against others ; it 
 is the consciousness of a self which deserves respect that 
 makes us angry when we have disgraced ourselves ; and it is 
 
 1 4. 440 c-d. 5 4. 440 a-b. 3 4. !40 b. 4 4. 441 a. 5 9. 531 a-b.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 77 
 
 the feeling that there is no such self to fall back upon which 
 weakens us when we know that we are in the wrong ; ami 
 lastly, it is often an exaggerated sense of our own importance 
 or power which breaks out into aggressiveness, hardens into 
 self-will, or is nursed into bad temper. 
 
 It now remains to consider the third, and in Plato's mind 
 the highest, element in the constitution of the human soul, that 
 which he calls " the philosophic." And here much more than in 
 the case of the other two we shall have to notice considerable 
 modifications in his account in different parts of the RcpvMic. 
 
 Bernnnino 1 with what we have called the first main section of 
 
 o o 
 
 the work, we find the " philosophic " element at first charac- 
 terised in a way very far removed from what the English word 
 would lead us to expect. It is introduced 1 as a necessary 
 psychological complement to the element of " spirit." Unmiti- 
 gated or unbalanced, the latter element would be a source of 
 mere indiscriminate pugnacity, and would result in a destruc- 
 tive war of all against all. Clearly if human nature is to be 
 adapted to the higher functions of civic society, it must contain 
 some counterbalancing factor, some quality of gentleness to 
 soften ferocity, some tendency to union to counteract the feeling 
 of mutual antagonism. The germs of such an element Plato 
 finds in some of the lower animals : the well-bred dog, who had 
 been already chosen to typify the quality of " spirit," is found 
 to exhibit, along with the greatest fierceness towards strangers, 
 the greatest gentleness towards those whom he knows ; and 
 this suggests, what is found to be the fact when we come to 
 look at human nature, that this combination of qualities so 
 opposite is not only possible but natural. But the question 
 arises, Why call this softening, unifying element " philosophic " ? 
 Here again, half-playfully perhaps, yet not without a deeper 
 meaning, Plato helps himself with the analogy of the dog. The 
 dog judges of friends and enemies by the test of knowledge ; 
 
 1 2. 375 b 376 c. In this passage a selection of men is being made who 
 are to be " guardians " of the ideal state which is being constructed. But it 
 is clear (cf. 9 581 a-c ; 4. 435 e 436 a) that while here appearing to pick 
 out certain qualities for a certain purpose, Plato is really enumerating the 
 qualities which he conceived to be present in different proportions in all 
 human beings.
 
 7 8 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 those whom he knows he treats as friends, those whom he does 
 not know as enemies ; with him, in a word, to know is to be 
 fond ; and as it is the feeling of knowing those whom he knows 
 which excites his fondness, he may be said in a sense to be 
 fond of knowing, much as a person who likes the society of his 
 inferiors might be said to be fond of superiority. In so far 
 then as the quality of gentleness attaches to the consciousness 
 of knowledge and the pleasure which that consciousness excites, 
 it may be said to arise from fondness of knowledge, and this is 
 almost equivalent to " philosophy " in its literal sense of " love 
 of knowledge " or " wisdom." 
 
 The first and simplest application of this somewhat curious 
 train of thought is obvious enough. Every one has felt in one 
 form or another the power of knowledge or familiarity to breed 
 a sort of liking. It is an instinctive feeling, which often does 
 not rise to the height of affection, but remains a sense of quiet 
 pleasure or comfort ; it attaches to things, to places, to persons ; 
 much of the love of home and of country, and even of humanity, 
 is traceable to its presence ; much of the antipathy to foreigners 
 or to novelties, to its absence. In such a rudimentary feeling 
 of attachment for what belongs to us Plato saw the first germ 
 of that which seemed to him highest in human nature. We 
 shall see shortly how the germ developed under his hands. 
 
 Our next introduction 1 to the "philosophic" element of the 
 soul is in a somewhat different context. It is still, indeed, the 
 " gentle " or " tame " part in contradistinction to the " wildness " 
 and " hardness " of the " spirited " part, and it is still intimately 
 associated with knowledge ; but the gentleness of which it is 
 now said to be the source is the result of culture instead of 
 dog-like attachment, and the knowledge in which it takes 
 delight is the sense of something understood rather than of 
 something familiar. It now includes susceptibility to the 
 influences of language, of music, of painting, of beauty in the 
 widest sense of the word; it includes also the quickness of 
 perception which makes learning pleasant and welcomes every 
 fresh form of truth. It has also a more purely moral aspect ; 
 it is that which produces love of order and quietness, the 
 
 1 3. 410 b-412 a.
 
 AY THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 79 
 
 impulse to obey rather than to resist, and to use persuasion 
 rather than force. Like " spirit," it is capable of exaggeration 
 and perversion; under the exclusive or excessive influence of 
 culture and refinement it develops softness and effeminacy, or 
 nervous sensibility and unstableness. 
 
 When we again 1 meet with the highest form of the soul it is 
 no longer under the name of " philosophic ; " the intellectual 
 character in it now predominates over the emotional ; it is the 
 calculative, deliberative, reasoning element in the soul, that in 
 virtue of which it guides and rules, that which when fully 
 developed becomes, not love of wisdom, but wisdom. Its rela- 
 tion to the " spirited " element is also changed ; from being a 
 merely complementary factor to it, it has come to be its natural 
 master, from whom issue the dogmas and principles which in 
 the well-trained soul " appetite " cheerfully obeys and " spirit " 
 fearlessly carries out. 
 
 Such is the account of the " philosophic " part in the first 
 section of the Republic ; in its most primitive character it is 
 the impulse of attraction to what is familiar because it is 
 familiar ; then the substratum of gentleness and of culture ; 
 lastly, reason in its regulative and ruling capacity. 
 
 To sum up then briefly the results thus far arrived at, the 
 human soul, in Plato's view, is a triple being. It has for its 
 largest constituent appetite, the simple craving for present 
 satisfaction, capable of indefinite expansion, mostly amenable, 
 but also partially unamenable, to reason. Secondly, it implies 
 an element of self-assertiveness and pugnacity, which gives rise 
 to qualities as various as courage and brutality, ambition and 
 contentiousness, just indignation and unreasoning bad temper. 
 Lastly, there is in it a capacity of attraction and receptivity, 
 which if not perverted into weakness of character, develops, on 
 the one side, into gentleness, sociableness, love ; on the other, 
 into refinement, culture, and wisdom. 
 
 Proceeding now to the later modifications of this psychology, 
 we find, as has been already observed, that they are modifica- 
 tions not so much in the general constitution of the soul as in 
 
 1 4. 439 d ; 441 e ; 442 c. In the fourth book the word <f>i\6<ro<t>ov is dropped, 
 and the highest element in the soul is generally called XoyumKbv or (436 a ; 
 cf. 9. 580 d) $ na.v6avotJ.ev.
 
 8o THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 the relationship of its constituent elements. They consist 
 mainly in the widening and deepening of the conception of the 
 ''philosophic" element, and in the assignment to it of a much 
 more predominant position in the formation of human character 
 and the regulation of human conduct. It is scarcely possible 
 to make this clear without again referring shortly to the general 
 structure of the Republic. The first four books of it, as we 
 saw, contain the discovery and exhibition of a principle of 
 human life, social and individual, such as, if carried out, would 
 realise the greatest wellbeing of which man is capable. That 
 principle is most simply described as the harmonious co-opera- 
 tion of various elements, whether those of the individual soul 
 or those of the state ; and the ultimate hypothesis upon which 
 the principle rests is that these various elements have the 
 capacity of forming a whole, and that, therefore, in performing 
 each their separate function in the best way, they are also in 
 the best way working for the good of the whole. According to 
 this view, in a normally constituted society each class would 
 consist of those individuals in whom a certain psychological 
 quality predominated, and who were therefore best fitted for a 
 certain k'ind of work ; and the chief interest and duty of the 
 society would be to secure, firstly, that each of its members 
 should have his proper place in the organisation of work ; and, 
 secondly, that having found his proper place, he should be 
 fitted by education or other means to do the particular work of 
 his life as well as possible. Of the work necessary to the well- 
 being of a state, Plato thought that there were three principal 
 kinds, the work of producing the material commodities essen- 
 tial to life, the work of protecting the state against external 
 enemies and of preserving order within it, and the work of 
 legislation and government. For the class of citizens engaged 
 in the first kind of work he apparently did not think that any 
 public system of education was necessary, a fact which, however 
 much at variance with modern ideas, will not startle any one 
 who is familiar with the position of the industrial classes in 
 Greek society, and with the opinions entertained of them both 
 by the public and by philosophers. It was then for the classes 
 who are engaged in military and political functions, that is, in 
 what a Greek would consider the functions of a citizen proper,
 
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. Si 
 
 that the education sketched in the earlier part of the Republic 
 is exclusively intended. That education is a method for pro- 
 viding the natural and proper nurture for the souls of the 
 persons in question. Its character (to anticipate for a moment 
 what must be said later) is emphatically non-technical; it 
 teaches no knowledge or mental accomplishment having a 
 direct bearing upon the functions eventually to be exercised by 
 those who receive it ; it comes to an end at about twenty, when 
 those functions have not yet begun, and its main object is to 
 predispose the soul, intellectually and morally, to the perception 
 and execution of ideas and principles of which it does not as 
 yet understand the full bearing, but upon which it will after- 
 wards find that the welfare of itself and society depends. 
 
 We may now return to the point at which it was necessary 
 to make this digression. It seems to have been in Plato's mind, 1 
 even at the time when he was writing the first part of the 
 Republic, that the system of education contained in it was 
 imperfect and inadequate. Whether it was from design that 
 he deferred the expression of this feeling, or whether it was 
 forced from him by subsequent criticism, this is not the place 
 to discuss ; it is at any rate certain that in what may be called 
 the second section of the work, comprising the fifth, sixth, and 
 seventh books, the education described in the preceding books 
 is referred to and criticised as insufficient for the purpose of 
 preparing citizens for the exercise of the most important public 
 functions. This attitude of criticism adopted in the later 
 towards the earlier section is however by no means the only 
 symptom of change on the part of the writer. The question under 
 discussion, the tone in which it is discussed, and the answer 
 which is given to it, are very different in the two parts. In 
 the first the question is, What is the true principle which 
 should regulate human life, and what would be the form of a 
 society in which it was carried out ? In the second it is, How 
 could such an ideal society, with all the consequences which it 
 seems logically to entail, be actually realised, and what is the root 
 
 1 Indications of this feeling are found 3. 414 a and 416 b, compared with 
 6. 503 a-b, e. The want of "exactness" or completeness in the account of 
 education in the early books is parallel to that in the psychology (cf. 4. 435 d 
 with 6. 504 a-e.
 
 82 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 of the existing evils of mankind which hinder its realisation ? 
 In the first part, again, the tone is that of a man who certainly 
 sees much to criticise in existing institutions, but who is never- 
 theless disposed to make the best of them, and does not despair 
 of doing so. In the second it is that of one oppressed by the 
 sense of the evil in the world, hoping for salvation only from 
 remedies which are themselves almost hopeless, diffident and 
 yet defiant, daringly paradoxical and yet terribly in earnest. 
 And lastly, the two answers are different. To the earlier 
 question the answer is : Allow, and if necessary compel, human 
 nature to develop normally, and provide it with the nurture 
 which its development demands; the rest will manage itself. 
 To the later it is : The cause of the ills of mankind is ignorance 
 of their true good and neglect of their noblest natures ; train 
 those natures rightly and they will see what is the true good of 
 mankind ; give them unlimited power and they will carry out 
 what the good requires. Such is the significance of the start- 
 ling demand made in the fifth book of the Republic, that 
 philosophers should be kings. We are here concerned with it, 
 not in its political, but in its psychological and educational, 
 aspect ; in other words, we have to see how Plato's conception 
 of what we have already learnt to know as the " philosophic 
 part " in the soul has expanded to the point at which we now 
 find it, giving its name to the whole man, embodying all gifts 
 and excellencies, and claiming to rule the world. 
 
 Between the account of the " philosophic " element which we 
 have gathered from the first four books of the Republic, and 
 that of the " philosophic nature " which we are about to gather 
 from the following three, the references made to the same 
 subject in the ninth book seem to occupy an intermediate 
 place, 1 and to form a kind of transition. In the ninth book, 
 taking his departure from the triple division of the soul with 
 which we are now familiar, Plato divides mankind into three 
 "primary kinds," 2 according as one or other of the three 
 psychical elements predominates in the character. To those in 
 
 1 I do not mean to imply that the ninth book was necessarily composed 
 before the sixth, though there is some ground for the supposition. 
 
 2 9. 580 d ff.
 
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 83 
 
 whom " appetite" predominates, the chief object in life is the 
 wealth by which appetite is satisfied ; to the " spirited " class it 
 is the honour which rewards successful competition ; while to 
 those in whom the " philosophic " side is the strongest, it is 
 truth. And accordingly they are called respectively lovers of 
 gain or wealth, lovers of contention or honour, lovers of learn- 
 ing or wisdom, that is, " philosophers," and of these the last are 
 said to enjoy the fullest experience and to live the highest life. 
 Here then we find the love of knowing, which has all along 
 underlain in different senses the " philosophic " form of soul, 
 interpreted as the love of " knowing the nature of the truth," * 
 or, to use an equivalent Platonic phrase, " the nature of what 
 is," and further, when present in sufficient force, giving its 
 name to a definite type of character, and that the highest. 
 The allegorical figure of man in the same book, to which refer- 
 ence has already been made, supplies some more additions to 
 the conception. In the triple creature which we are there asked 
 to imagine, the " man," or, as he is called to distinguish him 
 from the external human semblance, the " inward man," clearly 
 represents the " philosophic " element ; and from this we see 
 that in Plato's view it is this element which constitutes the 
 real humanity, and therefore the real personality, in our com- 
 plex nature. But this is not all. The " inward man " is dis- 
 tinctly asserted to be that which is " divine " or " the most 
 divine " in man. 2 To Plato there is a revelation of God in the 
 human soul, as there is in the physical world ; his " celestial 
 city " 3 is not only a visionary type, it is also, like the " kingdom 
 of heaven," within us, and he who will may enter in and dwell 
 there. And once more, as it is this divine humanity which is 
 in the truest sense the self, the other parts of human nature 
 are conceived by Plato to find their highest activity and their 
 most real satisfaction in following and serving it as far as they 
 are able ; to become as human as possible, to live for humanity 
 in this sense, is the highest end of the half-animal nature which 
 forms the larger part of man. 
 
 Turning now from the ninth to the three central books of 
 
 1 581 b, e ; 582 b, c. 
 
 8 9. 589 d, e ; 590 d ; cf. too, 6. 497 c, and 10. 611 e. * 9. 592 a-b.
 
 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 the Republic, we find the attributes with which the "philo- 
 sophic" nature is invested in the former confirmed and developed 
 in the latter. The point of departure is the same : the " philo- 
 sopher " is described, in accordance with his name, 1 as one who 
 loves knowledge or wisdom, and " philosophy " is the instinctive 
 and indiscriminate craving to learn. The man endowed with 
 this passion is like a man with a great appetite and a strong 
 digestion ; everything that will stay the hunger of his soul is 
 welcome food. Or again, he is like a man who is in love, not 
 once or twice, but always and everywhere ; as the lover finds 
 nothing that is not beautiful in the face of his beloved, so to the 
 man born to be a " philosopher " there is nothing in the face of 
 truth which is not loveable. This is the germ, the elementary 
 condition, of philosophy ; it does not of itself make a full-grown 
 philosopher, any more than the possession of " spirit" necessarily 
 makes a brave man ; but no true philosopher can be without 
 it, any more than a spiritless man can have real courage. But 
 (and here Plato takes his next great step) 2 these elementary 
 qualities are not only the germ of the true philosophic character, 
 but of all human excellence as well ; or rather, the philosophic 
 spirit cannot exist in its fulness and integrity without involv- 
 ing all that is called good and noble in human character. 
 Plato explains this somewhat startling idea by showing how 
 the whole company of virtues flows naturally and necessarily 
 from the single passion for truth. In one whose desires " set 
 strongly" towards one all-absorbing object, the channels of the 
 bodily appetites must run dry ; and the " vision of all time and 
 all existence" which he enjoys will make human life seem but 
 a little thing, and death nothing to be feared. In a mind 
 which "reaches out after all that is human and divine" there 
 is no room for meanness or pettiness, nor can such a mind be 
 harsh or unfair in dealings with other men, for the motives 
 which make others so avarice, conceit, or fear do not touch it. 
 Add to these ethical qualities the intellectual gifts without 
 which love of knowledge is impossible, quickness to learn and 
 slowness to forget, with that mental grace or proportion which 
 
 1 5. 474 c^75 c ; 6. 485 b. 
 
 8 6. 485 b 487 a ; 489 e-^90 c.
 
 AV THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 85 
 
 predisposes the soul to receive truth, and we have a fully-endowed 
 nature, such as " the god of blame himself could find no fault in." 
 
 We have here reached the culminating point in the develop- 
 ment of Plato's conception of " philosophy" in the Republic. 
 Beginning with the instinctive attraction to what is familiar, 
 passing on into the ready receptivity for all that is admirable 
 in nature and art, with the unconscious grace and refinement 
 which accompanies it, it has now become the consuming pas- 
 sion for what is true and real, at once the most human and the 
 most divine attribute of the soul, the crowning gift and com- 
 plete embodiment of perfect manhood. 
 
 Neither the later uses of the word "philosophy," nor its 
 literal interpretation as " love of wisdom," will much help the 
 modern reader to enter here into the spirit of Plato. Philo- 
 sophy to most of us is too much wrapt up in the associations 
 of books and systems, of technicalities and jargon, to let us feel 
 the living spirit which it still is when it is anything more than 
 a set of phrases. And the love of truth, in spite of the boasts 
 of modern science, is still but rarely found to dominate the 
 character and mould the life as Plato conceived that it might 
 do. The difficulty of understanding him is further increased 
 by the dispersion and differentiation which his idea has under- 
 gone. When he spoke of " the truth," or of " what is," we see 
 that there entered into his feeling not only the enthusiasm of 
 the scientific discoverer, but also the passion of the poet for 
 beauty and the devotion of the saint to the object of his wor- 
 ship. It would be beyond our present scope to dwell at length 
 upon this point ; a reference to two passages in the Republic 
 will sufficiently illustrate it. One is that in which he describes 
 the philosophic spirit as the desire for union of the mind with 
 reality i 1 "It is in the nature of the real lover of learning to be 
 ever struggling up to being, and not to abide amongst the 
 manifold and limited objects of opinion ; he will go on his way, 
 and the edge of his love will not grow dull nor its force abate, 
 until he has got hold of the nature of being with that part of 
 his soul to which it belongs so to do, and that is the part which 
 is akin to being; with this he will draw near, and mingle 
 
 1 6. 490 a-b.
 
 86 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 being with being, and beget intelligence and truth, and find 
 knowledge and true life and nourishment, and then, and not 
 till then, he will cease from his travail." The imagery of this 
 passage shows us that to Plato the process of knowledge was 
 very far from being the mechanical and external operation as 
 which we are apt to regard it. To him the world of reality or 
 fact, that which really is in spite of what appears or what we 
 fancy, is something of kindred nature with what is highest in 
 the human mind ; the impulse to know is the impulse to become 
 one with that which is " bone of our bone and flesh of our flesh," 
 and truth is the birth which allays the " travail of the soul." 
 
 In another passage l the effect of the same spirit upon the 
 formation of character is brought out in a way equally remote 
 from ordinary modes of thought. "The man whose mind is 
 really set upon the things that are, has not leisure to look down 
 at the concerns of men, and to fight with them, and fill him- 
 self with envy and bitterness ; that which he sees and gazes 
 upon is set fast and ever the same, it neither does nor suffers 
 wrong, but is all reasonable and in order. This he imitates, 
 and, as far as is possible, becomes like it, for it surely cannot 
 be that a man can live in fellowship with what he admires 
 without imitating it. So then the philosopher, living in fellow- 
 ship with what is divine and orderly, grows himself orderly 
 and divine as far as man is able." Such is Plato's conception 
 of what in modern phrase we should call the genuine study of 
 the laws of nature and the world. In the unchangeable order and 
 beauty of the universe he sees the image on a vaster scale of the 
 same reason which is imperfectly reflected in human life, and he 
 might have said to Justice what Wordsworth has said to Duty : 
 
 "Thou dost preserve the stars from wrong, 
 And the most ancient heavens through thee are fresh and strong." 
 
 We have now passed in review the main elements of that 
 human nature for which, as Plato conceived, it was the function 
 of education to provide nurture. It may seem, perhaps, that 
 a disproportionate space has been given to what belongs not to 
 education but to psychology. But it is just the inseparableness 
 of the two that is so characteristic of Plato's treatment, and, 
 
 1 6. 500 b-c.
 
 AV THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 87 
 
 whatever we may think of his analysis of the soul in its de- 
 tails, we shall hardly escape the conclusion that some such 
 analysis is an indispensable condition of a really rational 
 theory of education ; in other words, that neither a state nor 
 an individual can undertake to educate in a systematic way 
 unless they start with some idea, not only of what they wish 
 to teach, nor only of the type of character which they wish to 
 produce, but also of the living being to which the matter to 
 be taught is relative, and upon which the given character is to 
 be impressed. The " practical " man, who believes in " results," 
 will be disposed to regard such psychological considerations as 
 fanciful or far-fetched. And yet the most fatally unpractical 
 thing in the world is to go on testing methods by results which 
 take every factor into account except the one upon which the 
 whole result ultimately depends. That factor in man is the 
 human mind, in Englishmen the English mind, in different 
 classes of Englishmen the minds of those classes ; and to dis- 
 cuss what kinds of education are in themselves the best, 
 without considering mental organisation, is as idle as to discuss 
 what is the best kind of food in the abstract without regard to 
 the stomach which has to digest it. 
 
 Before passing on to our main subject, the methods by 
 which Plato proposed to meet the educational needs of the 
 soul, one preliminary observation must be made. It appears 
 from what has been already said that there is a certain want 
 of continuity in his psychology. Instead of following the soul 
 in an unbroken series from its earliest to its most advanced 
 phase of development, he has first given a picture of its educa- 
 tion up to a certain point, which is apparently meant to be 
 final, and has then made a fresh start, and represented the 
 previous course as a merely preliminary stage in a larger and 
 more elaborate system; and this fresh start coincides with a 
 fresh point of departure in the account of the highest or " philo- 
 sophic" element in the soul. The questions suggested by 
 these facts as to the composition of the Republic do not con- 
 cern us now ; whatever they may be, and however they may 
 be answered, it may be assumed here that Plato, at some time 
 in his life, intended the sections of the Republic, as we now 
 have it, to form parts of one work. On this assumption,
 
 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 the accounts which it contains both of the soul and of educa- 
 tion have been considered in this Essay as forming a logical if 
 not a literary whole, and as supplying a fairly complete and 
 coherent representation of what Plato conceived human nature 
 in its fulness to be and to require. It must, however, be 
 remembered once for all that the Eepullic gives us, not a de- 
 tailed treatise on education, but certain leading principles 
 which admit of being applied under various circumstances and 
 in various ways. Our present object is not primarily to dis- 
 cover the modifications which these principles admit or 
 require, but to exhibit the principles themselves in their 
 clearest light and fullest bearings. 
 
 The education of the average Greek gentleman, like that of 
 the average English gentleman, comprised a certain amount of 
 mental cultivation and a certain amount of athletic exercise. 
 The former, besides reading, writing, and some elementary 
 mathematics, consisted mainly in the reciting and learning by 
 heart of poetry, along with the elements of music, and some- 
 times of drawing. Perhaps because so much of the poetry 
 was originally sung or accompanied, the word "music" was 
 sometimes applied to the education in literature as well as in 
 music proper, and it is in this wider sense that Plato habitu- 
 ally uses it. Under the term " gymnastic " was understood the 
 whole system of diet and exercise which, varying with the 
 customs of different states, had for its common object the pro- 
 duction of bodily health and strength, and the preparation for 
 military service. In this twofold method of education, which 
 the wisdom of the past had handed down, Plato sees an un- 
 conscious recognition of the psychological requirements of 
 human nature on its two most important sides. 1 At first sight 
 it would seem that " music " and " gymnastic " were related to 
 one another as mental to bodily training, and this was no doubt 
 the ordinary way of distinguishing them ; but Plato, while him- 
 self adopting the popular phraseology at first, afterwards corrects 
 it by asserting that the soul, and not the body, is the primary 
 object of "gymnastic" as well as of "music," 2 and appeals 
 
 1 2. 376 e, 1) \a\eirbv evpeiv /SeXrta TTJS vvit rov iroXXoC xp6vov evprifdvT}s ; cf. 
 3. 411 e, 6ebv 170*7' to, x.r.X. * 3. 410 b-c.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 
 
 to the fact that exclusive devotion to physical exercises affects 
 the character no less markedly than exclusive devotion to 
 literary and aesthetic culture. The truth is, that " music" 
 educates, 1 not the soul merely, but specifically the "philo- 
 sophic " part of the soul, through the medium of the eye and 
 ear, while " gymnastic," through bodily exercises, not only pro- 
 duces bodily health and strength, but disciplines the psycho- 
 logical element of " spirit." It is through the gentle, responsive, 
 loving element that the soul is open to the influences of litera- 
 ture and art; it is this which makes it quick to assimilate, 
 ready to obey and to imitate, open-eyed and open-eared to 
 catch the sights and sounds of the living world. To satisfy 
 its cravings with the right food, to offer true nobility to its 
 admiration and true beauty to its love, to keep its perceptions 
 wakeful and clear, to refine and balance its emotions, these are, 
 in Plato's opinion, the functions of " musical " education. But 
 it will not be truly " musical," truly " harmonious," unless it be 
 counterbalanced by something different. 2 If the " philosophic " 
 side of the soul be exclusively fostered, its gentleness will turn 
 into effeminacy, its sensitiveness into irritability, its simple 
 love into feverish desire. 3 It is not enough (though this is 
 important) that the material presented in "music" should 
 itself be such as to brace the softer qualities in the soul ; it 
 must be supplemented by nurture of an altogether different 
 kind acting upon altogether different qualities. This is the 
 office of " gymnastic," which, by bodily exercises, develops and 
 educates the element of " spirit." For " spirit," though it has an 
 instinctive tendency to ally itself with reason, requires training 
 if the tendency is to become a habit. Proper " gymnastic" will 
 discipline the wild impulses of violence and pugnacity, de- 
 veloping the intelligent courage of the citizen-soldier, instead 
 of the blind ferocity of the barbarian or the wild beast, 4 while 
 it will counteract the yielding, voluptuous, or nervous tenden- 
 cies by encouraging competition, endurance, and presence of 
 mind. On the other hand, excessive attention to it brings 
 with it evils as great as its undue neglect. The body then 
 
 1 3. 410 e 412 a. 2 3. 412 a ; cf. 9. 591 d. 
 
 Cf. 3. 403 a ; 404 d-e ; 410 a. 4 4. 430 b-c.
 
 9 o THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 gradually swallows up the mind ; the whole man swells with 
 the pride of conscious strength ; by degrees his courage sinks 
 into brutality, and his high spirit into insolence; his senses, 
 the windows of the mind, are clogged and darkened, and his 
 intelligence, neglected and starved, grows "weak, deaf, and 
 blind." The problem then of education is to adjust these two 
 complementary but conflicting elements in human nature. 1 
 The soul is like a stringed instrument, and education has to 
 time it, tightening here and slackening there, that it may 
 become one instead of many, and its life a harmony instead of 
 a discord. The man who can thus educate himself or others, 
 who can " combine music and gymnastic, and apply them in due 
 proportion to the soul," deserves, far more than any musician, 
 to be called a " musical " man. 
 
 Of the two branches of education, "music," in its widest 
 sense, 2 will clearly begin before " gymnastic," for we tell stories 
 to children before they can take athletic exercise. The means 
 employed by "music" in the Platonic system are literature, 
 music proper, and the other fine arts. Each of these, in its 
 different way, is capable of expressing certain ethical charac- 
 teristics, and by each these characteristics are conveyed, through 
 the eye or ear, to the soul. 3 Of the various means, literature, 
 in the shape of stories and poetry, naturally comes first, 4 and 
 the questions which Plato 5 raises regarding the educational 
 use of literature are two, firstly, what should it express ? and 
 secondly, how should it express it ? The first question explains 
 itself; the second concerns literary form or style, and, as the 
 ethical influence of form depends mainly, in Plato's view, on 
 the degree to which it is dramatic, this question to him comes to 
 be, How far is the dramatic element in literature good or bad for 
 education ? Such a problem would not arise until a compara- 
 tively late stage, for in young children the susceptibility to 
 literary influence is as yet too embryonic to admit such distinc- 
 tions as dramatic or undramatic, personal or impersonal, and 
 the like. The first question then is not as to the form but as to 
 the substance of literature, regarded as an educational agent. 
 
 1 3. 412 a ; cf. 4, 443 d-e. 2 2. 376 e. 3 3. 400 c 401 a. 
 4 2. 376 e ; 377 a. " 3. 392 c ; 398 b.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 91 
 
 " In all work the beginning is of the greatest importance, 
 especially when we have to do with a young and tender creature, 
 for then, more than at any other time, it receives the particular 
 fashion and stamp which we wish to impress upon it," 1 and so, 
 "what the child hears when it is young generally becomes 
 fixed fast and indelibly in its mind." 2 This is Plato's reason for 
 giving so much consideration to the beginnings of education. 
 The young soul, like the young body, is plastic and malleable, 
 and mothers and nurses, who take such care that their chil- 
 dren's limbs shall grow straight, should remember how much 
 more care is needed in the handling and shaping of their minds. 3 
 What then are the ideas which should be impressed most 
 deeply on the minds of children ? Speaking generally, they 
 will be such as we should wish them to retain when they are 
 grown up. 4 The education of childhood should lay a foundation 
 of character which will not have to be cut away as years go on, 
 but will invite and sustain the superstructure of manhood. 
 Such a foundation Plato would see laid in certain religious or 
 semi-religious ideas ; he would, in other words, have the funda- 
 mental elements of character developed in the first instance by 
 habitually putting before the minds of the young the true nature 
 of God and of what is most godlike in man. In this sense, 
 then, that he would represent the primary moral ideas to chil- 
 dren as embodied in divine or superhuman beings, Plato may 
 be truly said to invest those ideas with a religious sanction, 
 and to give his system of education a religious basis. The 
 child is to be bred up in the belief that beings greater and 
 better than himself have behaved in a certain way, and his 
 natural impulse to imitate is thus to be utilised in forming 
 his own character. 5 It would, however, be an inversion of the 
 real order of Plato's thought, to say that he conceives the ideas 
 in question to owe their validity to their superhuman embodi- 
 ment. On the contrary, it is clear that with him the moral is 
 
 1 2. 377 a-b. 2 2. 378 d-e. 3 2. 377 c. 
 
 4 2. 377 b, ttreiSav TeXfuOdxriv ; cf. 383 c, el /j.t\\ov(ru>, K.T.\. 
 
 6 This impulse is mostly insisted on by Plato in connection with what is 
 bad (2. 378 b; 3. 391 e), but it is implied in all that he says of early 
 education. Cf. 6. 500 c, T) ote: TU>& fjLT)xa.v7]v eli>ai, STI? TIS 6/iuXet a.yAfiei'os, pi) 
 exelvo;
 
 9 2 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 the criterion of the supernatural, not the supernatural of the 
 moral ; and that if, and so far as, a religious sanction means a 
 sanction derived from a story of miraculous events, he considers 
 that sanction to belong to a rudimentary stage of education and 
 intelligence. This will appear more plainly if we examine the 
 form in which what we may call religious truth is supposed by 
 him to be imparted. Education, Plato says, 1 must begin with 
 literature, and " literature is of two kinds, true and false ; it is 
 with the latter kind that education must begin, for the literature 
 which we read to children consists of myths, and myths, speak- 
 ing generally, are false, though they contain elements of truth 
 as well." The whole circle of Greek religious ideas, so far as 
 they found expression in language at all, did so mainly in the 
 form of myths. Instead of an authorised collection of more or 
 less historical books, with a mass of authorised doctrine more 
 or less directly depending upon it, the Greeks had a number of 
 floating mythical stories, local and national, some of which, 
 receiving glorified shape from the genius of poets or artists, 
 exercised a special ascendency over the popular imagination. 
 The bulk of these stories Plato unhesitatingly pronounces 
 " false," and what he means by " false " appears from a passage 2 
 where he is enumerating the cases in which " falsehood in 
 speech " may be useful and admissible. One of these cases is 
 " the falsehood of the poet ;" for " in mythology, owing to our 
 ignorance of the actual truth of what happened long ago, we 
 make the falsehood as like the truth as we possibly can, and so 
 render it useful." The old myths, then, are untrue, not because 
 they necessarily misrepresent facts, but because the lapse of 
 time prevents us from knowing whether any facts underlie 
 them, and what those facts are. They are like pictures of 
 which we are no longer able to test the accuracy. And yet, in 
 the same sentence which tells us that myths are false because we 
 do not know the truth of what they say, we are told that we can 
 " make them like the truth." The explanation of this apparent 
 contradiction is found in an important distinction in the sense 
 of falsehood. In the sense that they can at best be only an 
 uncertain approximation to the truth, all myths and mythic 
 
 1 2. 376 e 377 a. a 2. 382 d.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLA TO. 93 
 
 poetry are necessarily untrue. They may, however, be untrue 
 in another, and, to Plato, more serious sense; they may not 
 only veil our want of historical knowledge, they may also con- 
 tradict our fundamental ideas about the subjects of which they 
 treat ; they may be not only unhistorical, but morally or meta- 
 physically inconsistent and illogical. 1 Their subject-matter is 
 the divine nature, gods and demigods ; of this nature we must 
 have a more or less definite conception, and wherever a myth 
 contradicts that conception, we must pronounce it false. It is in 
 this sense that Plato speaks of the poet " telling his falsehood 
 badly," 2 " when he makes a bad likeness in language of the 
 characters of gods and heroes, like a painter who paints a 
 picture not at all like what he means to copy." And he gives 
 numerous illustrations of his meaning ; the dismal accounts of 
 Hades are "not, true;" 3 the stories of the changes of Proteus 
 and Thetis, of the robberies of Theseus and Peirithous, are 
 " calumnies ;" 4 and it is a sort of "blasphemy" against Achilles 
 to say or to believe that he was so avaricious as to accept 
 Agamemnon's presents, and not to give up the body of Hector 
 without a price. 5 In one sense, then, (to recapitulate) all myths 
 must be false, in so far as we cannot know whether they re- 
 present what actually happened ; in another sense they may be 
 true or false, according as they do or do not conform to the 
 logical laws of their subject-matter. And as Plato seems to 
 consider myths to be the appropriate form for speaking of the 
 divine nature, when it has to be spoken of as a person or 
 persons, he would seem to conceive of specifically religious 
 truth, so far as it implies such a personal representation, as 
 belonging to a rudimentary stage of mental development. On 
 the other hand, he clearly sees no objection to employing this 
 admittedly inadequate form of expression as an agent in educa- 
 tion, nor to telling children religious stories which cannot pre- 
 tend to be historical. 
 
 This entire subordination of historical to moral truth in 
 religious education, strange as it may seem to us, was natural 
 to Plato. The mythology which occupied the Greek mind 
 
 1 2. 380 c, oflre &fjL<f>uva aira avro'is. 2 2. 377 d-e ; cf. 3. 388 c. 
 
 3 3. 386 b-c. 4 2. 381 d ; 3. 391 c-d. 6 3. 391 a ; cf. 2. 381 e.
 
 94 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 was its own creation, the offspring of its early contact with 
 nature, developed by subsequent reflection ; and the mind from 
 which it sprang felt itself competent to judge it. The element 
 of dogmatic fixity in their religion attached much more to its 
 ritual than to its ideas ; these latter were a plastic material, 
 growing in accordance with the secret laws of psychology and 
 language, or the conscious design of poets. In applying to 
 them canons of criticism resting on no authority but that of 
 his own moral consciousness, Plato might expect to offend 
 many popular beliefs and prejudices, but they would not be the 
 beliefs or prejudices of a priesthood or a church. It seems to 
 be incident to religious movements and ideas, that they rapidly 
 gather round them an accretion of mythical events and con- 
 ceptions, and neither the Jewish nor the Christian religion is an 
 exception to the general rule. But there is this great difference 
 between them and the Greek religion, that the literature to 
 which the former attach themselves, large as is its infusion of 
 poetry and mythology, still purports in its most important parts 
 to be historical, and that with its historical character its 
 religious significance has come to be almost inseparably 
 associated. And thus, in religious education, we are not only 
 met by the question which Plato asked, Whether the whole of 
 this literature is consistent with our ideas of the divine nature ? 
 but we have also to settle the question, which did not present 
 itself to Plato, Whether it is consistent with our canons of 
 historical evidence ? Had Plato been writing now, he would 
 have found the second a more prominent question than the 
 first, and we cannot say with certainty what his advice would 
 have been to those who find themselves in the dilemma of 
 teaching, or seeing others teach, their children religious stories 
 which they themselves do not believe to be true. We may, 
 however, conjecture that he would have made the moral worth 
 of those stories the final test, and that if they had seemed to 
 him to embody ideas really vital to human life and character, 
 he would have retained them, trusting to the child's mind to 
 assimilate what was valuable, and to later education to preserve 
 or to rectify its sense of historical truth. 
 
 The increased appreciation of the distinction between truth 
 of fact and truth of idea, is often and rightly represented as a
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 95 
 
 characteristic acquisition of modern, as compared with ancient, 
 thought. Yet, in its ultimate analysis, the distinction is seen 
 to exist only in abstraction. Neither " mere " facts nor " mere " 
 ideas form any part of our knowledge, but facts which are 
 interpreted into our mental experience, and ideas which are 
 referred to something independent of that experience. The 
 importance of a historical fact must depend, in the last resort, 
 upon its moral or ideal significance, or, in other words, upon 
 what it tells us of our own nature ; and our conception of the 
 use and value of evidence is in advance of that of the Greeks, 
 not because we have discovered a new sort of truth which was 
 unknown to them, but because our whole mental horizon has 
 enormously expanded, and we are far more vividly conscious 
 of the possible bearings of one part of our experience upon 
 another. Our truth of fact is more pregnant with thought than 
 theirs, and our truth of idea goes back into a deeper reality. 
 
 We have seen in what sense Plato bases education on reli- 
 gion, and how he conceives that the mythical form in which 
 religious ideas are presented may be, in different ways, both 
 true and untrue. The next question is, What is that religious 
 truth which mythical literature may approximately express, 
 and by its conformity to which its educational value is to be 
 determined ? Clearly it can be no other than the most perfect 
 and consistent conception which can be formed of the divine 
 nature. Plato accordingly begins by laying down certain 
 " outlines of theology, which the makers of stories must not 
 be allowed to transgress," for " God must always be repre- 
 sented as he really is, whether in epic or in tragedy." 1 The 
 doctrines of Plato's state-religion are only two, but they go to 
 the root of the matter ; the first is, that God is good and the 
 cause of good only; 2 the second is, that God is unchangeable 
 and true. 3 Thus simply stated, they are the common property 
 of all higher religious thought, but Plato's application of them 
 is to some extent peculiar. The primitive conception of the 
 deity as the simple embodiment of power, readily leads in one 
 direction to the belief that he sends good and evil upon man 
 
 2. 379 a. 2 2. 379 a 380 c. 8 2. 380 d 383 b.
 
 96 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 according to his caprice, and in another to the idea that he is 
 jealous of human success. To these deep-rooted tenets of the 
 Greek popular religion Plato opposes the simple logical posi- 
 tion, that what is in its essence good cannot produce what is 
 not good. As to the difficulty of accounting for the undoubted 
 preponderance of evil in the world, 1 " either we must say that 
 it is not the work of God ; or that, if the work of God, its in- 
 fliction is just and good, and those who suffer it are the better 
 for being chastised. ... To say that bad men are miserable 
 because they need chastisement is allowable, but not to say 
 that God is the cause of their misery.", 2 In the emphasis with 
 which Plato insists on this truth, we see not only the resolu- 
 tion of the philosopher to uphold his logical conception of the 
 divine nature, but also the anxiety of the legislator and teacher 
 to press home human responsibility. To encourage the natural 
 tendency to lay to the door of an irresponsible being the evil 
 which we ourselves have caused or deserved, is what no state 
 will do " if it is to be well governed." 3 In the oracular words 
 of the daughter of Necessity to the souls about to enter on their 
 earthly life, "Virtue owns no master; as a man honours or 
 dishonours her he will have more or less of her. The guilt is 
 with him who chooses. God is guiltless." 4 
 
 The application of the other great religious principle is 
 still more strongly coloured by Greek or Platonic ideas. The 
 liability to change by external influences, whether in organic 
 bodies, or in products of art, or in the human soul itself, 
 seems to Plato a universal symptom of inferiority or weak- 
 ness ; least of all in the divine being, the absolutely best, 
 can he admit any variableness. 5 Nor again in another and 
 more obvious sense can he conceive of God as liable to 
 change. 6 The metamorphoses which play so large a part 
 in the stories about the Greek divinities are impossible to 
 a being who is already perfect ; for no one, God or man, will 
 voluntarily change for the worse. It is not the representation 
 of the deity as having shape or similitude which offends Plato, 
 
 1 iroXi) y&p \di~rti> T&ya6a, TWV KaKuv i)fj,iv, 2. 379 c. 2 2. 380 a-b. 
 
 * 2. 380 b ; and cf. 10. 619 c, o yap eavrbv aiTia<r6ai TWV KO.K&V, K.T.\. 
 4 la. 617 e. 6 2. 380 e 381 b. 6 2. 381 b-e,
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 97 
 
 
 us it did the great Jewish teachers, but the indignity offered 
 to the divine essence by supposing it capable of wantonly 
 taking lower forms. Lastly, it is inconceivable that God 
 should be otherwise than true, 1 whether in the peculiarly 
 Platonic sense of untruth, 2 in which it means want of con- 
 formity in the mind to fact, ignorance of that which it is vital 
 to know, the " delusion " which makes us " believe a lie," or in 
 the ordinary sense of deceiving others by word or deed. 3 In 
 the first sense no man, much less God, could choose to be 
 untrue ; in the latter, there are some circumstances under 
 which men think lying admissible, but none of these circum- 
 stances can apply to God. 
 
 Such is Plato's conception of the divine nature ; and as such, 
 in its essence and its operation, he would have it presented by 
 poets to the imagination of his future citizens, " if they are to 
 be men who reverence God and are like God as far as it is 
 possible for man to be so." 4 These general religious ideas, 
 however, are not the only ideas which he would see embodied 
 in poetry, and by which he would judge of its right to a place 
 in the education of a people. It should be its function also to 
 exhibit the moral ideal in all its various manifestations ; and 
 we have next to ask how Plato conceived of that ideal, and 
 what are the specific qualities and principles which he con- 
 sidered to be at once the true elements of moral greatness, and 
 the legitimate material of poetical art. Plato's " whole duty of 
 man " is comprised in the following list : honour to parents, 
 love of fellow-citizens, courage, truthfulness, self-control. Each 
 of these deserves a few words of notice. The honour due to 
 father and mother is set by Plato next to the honour due to 
 the gods, 5 and he denounces the stories of the treatment of 
 Cronos by his son Zeus as " the greatest of lies about the 
 greatest of things." The mixed sentiment of awe, admiration, 
 and modesty, which the Greeks associated with the untrans- 
 latable word at&9, and which they regarded as the germ of all 
 youthful virtue, has its earliest and simplest expression in the 
 feeling of children for their parents ; and to diffuse this feel- 
 
 1 2. 381 e 383 b. 2 382 a-b. * 382 c-e. 
 
 4 2. 383 c. 8 3. 386 a ; 2. 377 e ; 378 b. 
 
 G
 
 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 ing through society, knitting old and young together by an 
 instinctive bond, and superseding the law of the state by the 
 finer law of family affection, was one of the fairest though most 
 impossible dreams of Plato's life. 1 Equally important in his 
 eyes was the sense of fellowship amongst citizens. 2 The false 
 tales of the battles of the gods with one another are not to be 
 told to children, who should see in the Olympian community 
 the glorified image of their own. Kather they are to be taught 
 that it is " very disgraceful lightly to quarrel amongst them- 
 selves," " that citizen never falls out with citizen, and that it is 
 wicked to do it." Thus the earliest lessons of education are 
 to appeal to that element in the soul which, as we have seen, 
 Plato regarded as the highest and most distinctively human in 
 man, the element in virtue of which he is not a mere isolated 
 atom and centre of resistance, but capable of attraction both to 
 what is higher than himself and to what is like himself. 3 
 
 From the common groundwork of citizenlike feeling we pass 
 to the specific virtues of public life, and the first of these is 
 courage, 4 or, as we might more literally and more instructively 
 translate the Greek word dvSpeia, " manliness." Plato's treat- 
 ment of this quality is characteristically Greek. The child who 
 is to be one day a soldier and to fight for his country must 
 learn before all things not to be afraid of death. Death, as 
 the inevitable end of youth and strength and beauty, as the 
 entrance to a joyless and ineffectual phantom world, seemed to 
 the Greek imagination of all terrible things the most terrible, 
 and the man who could face it without flinching the most 
 worthy to be called a man. Plato, as usual, has both a specu- 
 lative and a practical interest in banishing from poetry the 
 ghastly pictures of Hades ; they " are not true," 5 and they " do 
 no good." " Not true," for to Plato it is clear that a good 
 man can have no reason for being afraid of death ; 6 and " they 
 do no good," 7 for whatever scope they may give to descriptive 
 power, and however pleasant it may be to feel the pulse quicken 
 and the skin creep at reading them, they only unnerve the 
 
 1 5. 463 d ; 465 b. 2 3. 386 a ; 2. 378 b-c. 
 
 8 Cf . 2. 375 c-d, and 376 b-c, with 378 c. 3. 386 a 388. 
 
 5 3. 386 c. 387 d. 7 387 b-c.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 99 
 
 character, and are bad for children who are to learn " to be 
 freemen, fearing slavery worse than death." 1 But if a man 
 need not be afraid' to die himself, neither need lie be afraid 
 for his friend to die, 2 and the expenditure of tears and lamenta- 
 tions over the departed is both uncalled for and unmanly, for a 
 man ought to learn as far as possible to lean upon himself, not 
 upon others. And if it is weak to give way to excess of grief, 
 it is no less so to give way to the opposite emotion ; laughter, 
 like tears, is not to be allowed to get the better of us, for the 
 violent expression of one feeling tends to produce an equally 
 violent reaction. 3 
 
 These precepts, to which Plato is led by his conception of 
 moral truth, remind us of those which Lessing arrived at by 
 thinking out the laws of artistic propriety. Perhaps few Eng- 
 lishmen will feel themselves or their children to be much in 
 need of such precepts. Many of us would be only too glad 
 sometimes if our sense of the pathetic or the ludicrous could 
 find more relief in expression. To the Greek of Plato's time, 
 as to some southern peoples now, the tendency to sudden and 
 violent revulsions of feeling was a real cause and symptom of 
 weakness of character. To us, taught as we are from early 
 years by example and temperament to be neutral and moderate 
 in our language and gesture, an analogous danger may perhaps 
 be found in the tendency to nurse suppressed emotion until 
 it becomes a drain upon the mental forces or breaks out in 
 extravagant action. 
 
 In his treatment of truthfulness, 4 the virtue which comes 
 next upon his list, Plato is short and simple. Elsewhere, 5 in 
 passages where truth is identified with " what is," we find 
 him basing the obligation to truthfulness upon the desire to be 
 in harmony with fact ; here, where he is concerned primarily 
 with early education, he connects it naturally with obedience. 
 He would have the young citizens continually conscious that 
 they are living under authority, and that " to say the thing that 
 is not" 6 to their elders is as " deadly and destructive to the 
 community " as it would be for the sailor to lie to his officer or 
 
 1 387 b. 2 387 d-e. 3 388 e. 
 
 4 3. 389 b-d. 5 E.g. 6. 485 c ; 486 d. 3. 389 c.
 
 i oo THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 the patient to his doctor. Obedience too is the basis of the 
 remaining virtue of crw^pocrvvrj, 1 which in its literal sense 
 describes the man who remains " sound in mind," or, as we 
 might say, " keeps his head," under the stress of appetite and 
 passion. " To obey those who are in authority and to have 
 authority over one's-self " 2 is the fully-developed virtue of which 
 the sentiment of at'Soj? is the instinctive germ. It is this law- 
 loving spirit, whether the law be the external law of the state 
 or the voice of reason within us, which is the enemy alike of 
 forwardness and insolence, of gluttony, drunkenness, and lust, 
 of meanness and avarice. The principle of balance and con- 
 trol, which so pervades the Greek life and philosophy, comes 
 out nowhere so prominently as in the conception of this virtue. 
 It is a principle which no longer appeals strongly to the modern 
 mind, to which it tends to suggest rather the complacencies and 
 prettinesses of morality than its inward victories or struggles. 
 But to a people like the Greeks, combining such an extra- 
 ordinary sense of proportion with such an extraordinary capa- 
 city for excess, a perfect self-mastery might well seem as high 
 an ideal as the humility and purity which take its place in the 
 Christian code. 
 
 The elements of moral greatness just enumerated form the 
 second main category in the legitimate material of poetry in a 
 well-ordered state. To trace them out in the lives and actions 
 of national heroes and great men, and to give them fitting 
 expression, is the true function of the masters of language. 
 The divine and the heroic, however, are not the only subjects 
 which Plato would allow to poets. There remains the whole 
 sphere of human life and nature, to discover some principle 
 in which was the original problem of the EepuUic? How 
 then are poets to deal with this vast material ? What canons 
 can be laid down to which their imagination should con- 
 form in drawing human nature, corresponding to the canons of 
 religious and moral truth which they are not to transgress in 
 drawing the divine ? Is the world really what it is popularly 
 represented, a scene of confusion and caprice, in which the 
 
 1 3. 389 d 391 d. a 389 d-e. 
 
 3 3. 392 a, irepl avOpuirwv ri> \onrbv &v etrj.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 
 
 unjust are happy and the just miserable ? J The answer to these 
 questions is the Rcpiiblic itself. If, as Plato would have us 
 believe, justice is the health, and injustice the disease, of human 
 life, individual and social; 2 if the triumph of what is most 
 divine in the world is also the triumph of what is most human, 3 
 and man can only realise himself by living at his highest; 4 if 
 the life of the just man is in the hand of God, who orders 
 all things for good whatever the appearances may be, 5 and if, 
 when we come to look at the facts, even in the judgment of 
 the world justice more often prospers than not ; 6 if this is the 
 truth, then children must be taught it, and poets must sing 
 it, and the contrary representations of popular literature 
 are as great calumnies upon man as they are upon gods and 
 heroes. 
 
 Many reflections must be suggested to a modern reader of 
 the part of the Republic to which we have been referring, partly 
 as regards the nature and method of early education, and partly 
 also as regards the position and functions of poetry and litera- 
 ture. One of the first points which must strike him, accustomed 
 as he is to hear the methods of imparting knowledge, and the 
 kind of knowledge to be imparted, made the main subjects of 
 discussion, is the almost exclusive attention given by Plato to 
 the method of developing character, and the kind of character 
 to be developed. We are not indeed to suppose that Plato 
 intended children to be brought up in ignorance of reading, 
 writing, and arithmetic ; besides this elementary knowledge, he 
 evidently contemplated some teaching of the rudiments of such 
 science as then existed. 7 But he does not dwell upon this early 
 scientific education, except to say that it will be comparatively 
 unsystematic, 8 and that it should be made as little compulsory 
 as possible, " for the acquisition of knowledge ought not to be 
 made a slavery to any free man." 9 Thus it remains true on the 
 whole that Plato regarded the formation of character in child- 
 hood and early youth as a much more important part of educa- 
 tion than useful instruction or the training of the intellect. It 
 
 1 3. 392 b. 2 4. 444 d e. 3 9. 589 c 590 a. 
 
 4 9. 586 d-e. . 10. 612 e 613 b. 10. 613 b-e. 
 7 7. 536 d ; 537 c ; cf. 6. 498 b. 
 
 etj/, 536 d : x^v, 537 c. 7. 536 e.
 
 i o 2 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 would, however, be a mistake to suppose that because this 
 branch of education finds a comparatively small place in modern 
 theoretical discussions, it is therefore neglected in modern 
 practice; on the contrary, it is probably just because it receives 
 so much attention at home and at school, that it is thought 
 capable of taking care of itself. The successes of our public 
 school system have lain, much more than in any particular 
 stimulus that they have given to literary or scientific activity, 
 in the production of certain types of character and the prepara- 
 tion for the art of life, and in these points we naturally feel less 
 need for method or even for consistency. And yet perhaps 
 our very feeling of security should make us diffident. The 
 names of " Christian," " scholar," and " gentleman," are as much 
 in our mouths as those of the cardinal virtues were in the 
 mouths of the Greeks ; but the ideas of religion, culture, and 
 manhood, which we attach to them, are not less confused, and 
 often not less untrue, than some of those which Plato found in 
 the current literature and opinion of his day. 
 
 Our neglect of the theory of ethical education as compared 
 with Plato has also another explanation. In a small Greek 
 State, with the whole or greater part of its effective citizens 
 taking part in the conduct of affairs, the influence of per- 
 sonal character upon society and politics was more direct and 
 unmistakable than it can be in the vast organisation of a 
 modern nation, where the members at the circumference may 
 be almost unconscious of their connection with the centre. 
 Ultimately, no doubt, it is as true now as it was in the times 
 of Plato and Aristotle that the character of a people is respon- 
 sible for its social and political life, and that education is mainly 
 important because it produces or modifies that character and 
 thus affects the public interests. But the steps by which ethi- 
 cal and psychological agencies come to the surface in politics 
 are much more numerous now and much more difficult to trace, 
 and it is proportionately more easy to isolate particular aspects 
 of the national life and to treat them as if they had no connec- 
 tion with each other or the whole. And thus, while it has 
 become a commonplace that many of the evils of modern 
 society can only be cured by education, few people probably can 
 see the connection between the evil and the remedy as clearly,
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 103 
 
 and express it as simply, as Plato did when he said that the 
 encouragement of ghostly fears and superstitions tends to make 
 bad soldiers, or that changes of fashion in popular music are 
 symptoms of political revolution. 
 
 But the difference between ourselves and Plato in the rela- 
 tive importance attached to the education of character is not 
 greater than the difference in the means employed for that 
 education. In the first place, we have no really national 
 mythology which takes, or could be made to take, such a posi- 
 tion in education as did that of the Greek people. The Arthur 
 legend has indeed been recently made to yield the picture of 
 an " ideal knight," and the still more recent treatment of the 
 Scandinavian Sagas has shown that the ideas which stirred 
 our forefathers are still alive in ourselves. But the position of 
 Mr. Tennyson and Mr. Morris in this respect is very different 
 from that of the Greek dramatists. The myths with which the 
 latter worked had been handed down by a continuous tradition, 
 both literary and popular; and however freely a poet might 
 transform or modernise them, he was still sure of appealing to 
 the popular imagination, of which his material had come to 
 form an integral part. The characters of Celtic and Scandi- 
 navian mythology are no longer domesticated amongst us ; we 
 no longer regard them with either familiarity or reverence ; the 
 ties which bound them to us have been shattered beyond repair, 
 and it is only here and there that we dimly catch sight of them 
 behind the crowd of classical and Christian figures which has 
 pressed in between us and them. 
 
 The place thus left vacant in education by our want of a 
 national mythology has been partially filled by other forms of 
 literature, of which the books of the Old and New Testaments 
 are the most conspicuous, while alongside of them there has 
 grown up the miscellaneous mass of stories, romances, allegories, 
 and fairy-tales, comprised under the head of " literature for the 
 young." It is from these two sources that our early concep- 
 tions of the divine and the heroic are mainly derived. What 
 would Plato have thought of them ? He would no doubt have 
 been surprised at the hard and fast line which it is usual to 
 draw between sacred and profane literature, which robs the 
 former of much of its legitimate literary effect, and the latter
 
 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 of much of its educational power. There may seem to be a 
 certain incongruity in applying high canons of criticism to 
 the story-books of children ; and indeed their miscellaneous 
 character and rapid multiplication makes such an application 
 almost impossible. Yet it would be a fruitful work for a com- 
 petent person to make such a collection from the religious 
 books, mythologies, and popular tales of different peoples and 
 ages, as should appeal to and stimulate the best elements in a 
 child's imagination, without either spoiling its simplicity, over- 
 exciting its sensibility, or nursing its conceit. In such a 
 collection the most appropriate stories from the Bible would 
 find their natural place. The circumstances which have led to 
 the Biblical writings being treated as a single book, while 
 investing them all with the same promiscuous sanctity, have 
 greatly increased the difficulty of using them as a text-book of 
 religion and morality. There is much in the Old Testament 
 which Plato's canons would exclude from the education of the 
 young, and some of the worst expressions of Jewish fanaticism 
 have served as the watchwords of modern cruelty or cant. On 
 the other hand, the direct influence of example is much less in 
 the case of the Old Testament than it was in that of the Greek 
 poets. The heroes of Jewish history do not live in the English 
 mind as types to be imitated in the same way that the Greek 
 heroes lived in the mind of their own nation. It is to the 
 words with which their names are associated, rather than to 
 the deeds, that the influence of the former is due, and this 
 makes it all the more important that their words should be 
 purged from the baser matter which adheres to them, and fitted 
 to be in truth what they are now only in name, a revelation 
 of the divine nature to the English people. With the New 
 Testament the case is different. Here it is the story of a life 
 and a character to which, more than to anything else, the power 
 of the book has been due ; and Plato, if he might have warned 
 us gently against that literal imitation which is really no imita- 
 tion, would have found there all and more than all the ideal of 
 heroic manhood which he sought for in vain in the figures of 
 his native mythology. And yet we must see that the very 
 exaltation of that character and life makes it difficult to pre- 
 sent it to children without falsifying it, and that we are not
 
 AV THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 105 
 
 teaching them to be like Jesus, either on the one hand by 
 making him so familiar to them that they can " play at being 
 him," or on the other by introducing him to them in a buckram 
 of ecclesiastical dogma. To us, as to Plato, the problem of 
 early religious education is, How to express the highest truth in 
 the most appropriate and the least inadequate forms. But in 
 the interval of more than two thousand years which separates 
 us from him, the spiritual inheritance of Europe has been both 
 enormously enriched and enormously encumbered ; enriched 
 by the advent and expansion of new and potent religious ideas, 
 which have carried the human mind to heights scarcely dreamt 
 of by him, but encumbered also by an undergrowth of theologi- 
 cal tangle which makes it harder for us to keep in view the 
 grander outlines of the truth and the light towards which they 
 tend. 
 
 The demand of Plato that poets should be teachers, and 
 their subject-matter limited accordingly, will generally be 
 received with disgust or derision in the republic of letters. 
 This is due partly to the extreme simplicity and even crudity 
 of Plato's language, and the difficulty of translating it to suit 
 the complex conditions of our modern civilisation, partly to 
 a narrow conception of the scope of education on the one hand 
 and the responsibilities of literature on the other. Plato in 
 the Republic,} as he tells us himself, " is not making poetry, but 
 founding a commonwealth, and the founder should know the 
 outlines within which the invention of poets should be exer- 
 cised ; but it is not his business to invent himself." Hence to 
 any one who thinks of the exuberant variety of the poetic 
 activity, these " outlines " are apt to seem a Procrustes-bed, and 
 Plato's poet is pictured as a literary tailor who cuts his wares 
 to order. And this feeling is intensified by the fact that Plato 
 is much more concerned to criticise the current literature of his 
 time than to suggest fresh lines for writers to work on, thus 
 leaving the impression of an entirely hostile attitude to poetry 
 in general. Moreover, in reading proposals like his, we are 
 naturally more apt to seize upon the difficulties or mistakes in 
 them than on the essential truth which they may contain. We 
 
 1 2. 378 e-379 a.
 
 106 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 are all agreed that a public censorship of poetry would be im- 
 possible and self-destructive ; we also see that as a matter of 
 fact the greatest poets have not often been educators of their 
 people. We forget that this idea of a censorship is an accident 
 of Plato's mind and circumstances, and that the truest ideas are 
 often those which are most slowly realised in history. For 
 what is the requirement here made, if we look at it on its posi- 
 tive, not merely its negative, side ? It is that the poet should 
 take his place in the commonwealth, not as an ornamental 
 luxury, a caterer for the pleasure of intellectual epicures, 1 but as 
 an integral part of it, with a work of his own, imprinting 2 the 
 first indelible ideas upon the souls of the young, revealing 3 the 
 inscrutable nature of God in forms of imaginative truth, nerving 4 
 the heart and chastening the emotions by the power of heroic 
 examples, interpreting 5 to the fancy the language of facts, and 
 surrounding 6 the mind with an atmosphere of health and beauty. 
 This is not a position of which any poet need be ashamed. 
 Few, if any, have ever risen to it ; but not a few, and those not 
 the least, have claimed it. The abilities of the poet, says 
 Milton, " wheresoever they be found, are the inspired gift of 
 God, rarely bestowed, but yet to some though most abuse in 
 every nation : and are of power, besides the office of a pulpit, to 
 inbreed and cherish in a great people the seeds of virtue and 
 public civility ; to allay the perturbations of the mind, and set 
 the affections in right tune ; to celebrate in glorious and lofty 
 hymns the throne and equipage of God's almightiness, and what 
 he suffers to be wrought with high providence in his church ; 
 to sing victorious agonies of martyrs and saints, the deeds and 
 triumphs of just and pious nations, doing valiantly through 
 faith against the enemies of Christ; to deplore the general 
 relapses of kingdoms and states from justice and God's true 
 worship. Lastly, whatsoever in religion is holy and sublime, in 
 virtue amiable or grave, whatsoever hath passion or admira- 
 
 1 2. 373 b, where poets and artists are included in the list of "unnecessary" 
 luxuries in the rpvty&cra. 7r6\is. 
 
 * 2. 377 c. 3 2. 382 d. 4 3. 387 c ; 389 e. 
 
 6 3. 401 C, TOI>S tinpvws Svvafj^vovs Ixvevfiv rrjv TOV KO\OV re Kal evffx^ " ^ <j><bffiv, 
 andcf. 402 c, where the "images of the letters, " which "music "has got to teach 
 us to read, seem to be works of art. 6 3. 401 c.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 107 
 
 tiou in all the changes of that which is called fortune from 
 without, or the wily subtleties and refluxes of man's thoughts 
 from within ; all these things, with a solid and treatable smooth- 
 ness, to point out and describe." 
 
 High words like these will perhaps provoke a smile or a 
 sigh in those who remember the bathos of unsuccessful attempts 
 to carry them into effect ; and when to this is added the thought 
 of the pressure of modern life, so feverish and yet so mechanical, 
 so interesting and yet so unlovely, the poet himself will some- 
 times lose heart, and become,instead of "the trumpetwhich sings 
 to battle," " the idle singer of an empty day." Yet those who 
 fancy that the lamp of imagination is waning before the dawn 
 of industry and science might reflect that our scientific insight 
 into nature is scarcely more in advance of the crude fancies of 
 the Greeks than our imaginative interpretation of it is in 
 advance of their naive mythology. And if others are inclined 
 to retire to a " shadowy isle of bliss," and to leave education to 
 school boards and ministers, they should remember that the 
 "immortal garland" of poetry must be " run for, not without dust 
 and heat." They might consider too (to adapt Milton's words 
 once more), " What nation it is whereof they are, and whereof" 
 (if they knew it) " they are the governors ; a nation not slow and 
 dull, but of a quick, ingenious, and piercing spirit ; acute to 
 invent, subtile and sinewy to discourse, not beneath the reach 
 of any point that human capacity can soar to." Such a nation 
 is worthy to be educated by men who have the genius to do it. 
 
 We have heard Plato's answer to the first of the two ques- 
 tions which he raised about poets the question, What ought 
 they to say? and may now pass on to the second, How ought 
 they to say it ? What is the manner or form of poetry best 
 fitted to the functions which have been assigned to it in edu- 
 cation ? By the form of poetry Plato understands merely the 
 mode in which the poet represents the personages in his poem, 
 that is, whether he speaks in his own person and simply 
 describes what they say and do, or whether he puts himself in 
 their place and makes them speak and act for themselves. 1 The 
 first of these manners he calls " narrative," 2 the second " imita- 
 
 1 3. 392 c ff. * 3. 394 c.
 
 1 08 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 live ;" the two may of course be employed separately, or com- 
 bined in various proportions in the same work. The type of 
 the " imitative " manner is the drama, that of the " narrative " 
 certain kinds of choric hymns, while the epic introduces them 
 both. We shall, however, understand Plato better if we banish 
 from our minds this triple division of poetry, with its modern 
 associations, and fix them upon the real question which occu- 
 pied him. That question is, Whether " imitation," or, as we 
 might better say, impersonation, should be the ruling principle 
 in poetry, or whether some other principle should rule ; or, in 
 other words, Is the poet to put himself into as many and as 
 various interesting personalities and situations as he possibly 
 can, and is the greatest poet he who can do this to the greatest 
 extent, or is he to observe some principle of selection other 
 than that of the merely interesting, and is there some other 
 criterion of poetic excellence than the degree of " imita- 
 tive " power ? That this is the real issue in Plato's mind 
 appears from the following passage : " The well-regulated man, 
 when he comes in his narrative to a speech or a deed of a good 
 man, will, it seems to me, want to give it in the very person of 
 that man, and of such imitation he will not be ashamed ; he 
 will imitate the good man most of all, when he acts without 
 stumbling or folly ; to a less extent and degree when he has 
 been upset by disease, or love, or drunkenness, or any other 
 calamity. But when he comes upon a person unworthy of 
 himself, he will not like seriously to assimilate himself to his 
 inferior, unless it be on the few occasions when he does some- 
 thing good ; partly he is unpractised in imitating such people, 
 and partly, too, it goes against the grain to put himself into 
 the mould of natures worse than his own ; his mind scorns 
 to do such a thing, unless it be in fun." l On the other hand, 
 " the lower the nature of the poet, the less will he discrimi- 
 nate in what he says, or think anything unworthy of him, 
 so that he will try to imitate anything and everything, in 
 sober earnest and before a large audience, such things even as 
 thunder and wind and hail, the noises of \vheels and pulleys, the 
 tones of trumpets, flutes, pipes, and all kinds of instruments, 
 
 1 396 c-e.
 
 AY THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 109 
 
 and the voices of dogs, sheep, and birds." 1 We see that Plato is 
 here grouping together forms of imitation which would be dis- 
 tinguished by a modern writer. 'As art and literature advance, 
 the primitive delight of mere mimicry gives way to that of 
 subtler kinds of reproduction, and tends to confine ifself to the 
 less educated classes of society. But though the dramatic poet 
 stands on a different level from the actor, still more from the 
 pantomimist, they all agree in one point, that they are endowed 
 with more than ordinary capacity of losing their own person- 
 ality in that of others. It is in this common capacity that 
 Plato sees a danger, a danger both to the artist who possesses 
 it, and, in various degrees, to the audience which is able to fol- 
 low him in the exercise of it. His whole conception of the true 
 form of human society is based, as we saw, on the principle that 
 each member in it should have his work to do, and should do 
 it. 2 He is convinced of the impossibility of one man's excelling 
 in many trades or professions ; the same natural law which 
 makes every man the possible helpmate of others imposes on 
 him the necessity of accepting help from them. And if one 
 man cannot do many things well, neither can he imitate many 
 things ; and Plato (at least when he wrote the Republic) did 
 not think it possible for the same poet, or even for the same 
 actor, to excel both in tragedy and comedy. This law of the 
 limitation of human nature, which he found to hold good in 
 arts and professions, he would see observed in the greatest of 
 all arts and professions, the life of the citizen who is engaged in 
 the public service of the state. To men for whom the good of 
 the commonwealth is to be the paramount rule of conduct, 
 whose " craft " 3 is to be to maintain the liberty of their country, 
 what need is there of doing or being anything except what bears 
 upon their work ? and if not of doing and being, why of imi- 
 tating ? For imitation, bodily or mental, cannot remain mere 
 imitation ; if it begin early and continue long, it results in a 
 second nature. 4 If, then, the young are to put themselves into 
 other characters at all, let it be such characters as we wish them 
 ultimately to be, but no others, " lest from the imitation they 
 
 1 397 a. 2 3. 394 e 395 c ; cf. 2. 370 a-c. 
 
 z dtifjuovpyofc t\evdeplas TTJS iriXews irdvv aKpiftets, 3. 395 c. 4 3. 395 c-d.
 
 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 catch something of the reality." And thus the only poets who 
 will have work to do in a well-ordered State, will be those who 
 will "imitate what is right, and that only ;" 1 who will express 
 in their works the true type of character, and thereby help to 
 produce it. As for the great pantomimic genius, " the man 
 with the skill to turn himself into all kinds of people, and to 
 imitate everything," 2 he may be allowed to be " divine and 
 miraculous and delightful ;" but he will find no audience in a 
 society where " twofold and manifold men do not exist, but 
 everybody does one thing." 
 
 The mitigated attack made upon the drama in the third 
 book of the Republic, is renewed by Plato in the tenth with 
 greater vehemence and a more elaborate array of argument. 
 We need not here enter into the general theory of the nature of 
 artistic production which he there advances in order to refute 
 the extravagant claims of omniscience made for the poets by their 
 admirers ; but his account of the psychological effects of dra- 
 matic poetry may be noticed, as it develops and illustrates that 
 given in the earlier book. Plato charges dramatic writers, 
 firstly, 3 with depending mainly upon illusion for their success ; 
 and secondly, 4 with weakening character by over-stimulating 
 the emotions. The meaning of the first charge is best seen from 
 the analogy of painting by which it is illustrated. 5 Painting 
 and kindred arts produce their effects by taking advantage of 
 certain optical illusions ; the perception of the actual propor- 
 tions of objects is kept in abeyance by the mere appearance, 
 until corrected by scientific measurement. Similarly the poet 
 takes advantage of illusions of feeling ; 6 the aspects of charac- 
 ter which he likes to represent are not those where it is simple, 
 quiet, consistent, and rational, but rather its emotional aspects, 
 with their shifting lights and shadows, where the contrasts are 
 strong and the transitions rapid ; and the element in his audi- 
 ence to which he appeals, and upon which he reckons for his 
 success, is not the sober judgment which sees life in its true pro- 
 portions, but the illusory feelings of the moment which care only 
 for their immediate satisfaction. So that, judged by the worth 
 
 1 3. 397 d. 2 397 e 398 b. 3 10. 602 c 605 c. 
 
 4 605 c 606 d ; 605 b. 6 602 c-e. 6 604 d 605 e.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. in 
 
 
 both of what it represents and of what it appeals to, dramatic 
 poetry seems to condemn itself to inferiority. The second 
 charge against it is an expansion of that made in the third 
 book. Few people reflect that in putting themselves in the 
 positions of others, they catch something which becomes their 
 own. 1 Yet this is the case when, in seeing tragedy and comedy, 
 we give unrestrained way to emotions which we should be 
 ashamed to indulge in real life. We think it does not matter, 
 because we stand outside the circumstances which call them 
 forth ; but when similar circumstances arise in our own experi- 
 ence we find that our will has been weakened and our self- 
 respect undermined. 
 
 Two dominant ideas underlie all the objections urged by 
 Plato against the dramatic element in literature : the duty of 
 being true to ourselves, and the duty of being true to facts. 
 The two were in his mind closely related. As the burden of 
 his philosophy of knowledge was that we should learn to see 
 things as they are, not as they appear to us to be, so the burden 
 of his philosophy of conduct is that we should learn to be 
 what we really are, and not what our fancy makes us. And as 
 the belief in an objective world of reality, an order of existence 
 which we do not create, but which we find and must recognise, 
 pervades his logical speculation, so it is the corresponding con- 
 viction that the rational self in man is his most real self, and 
 that life in accordance with the rational order of the world is 
 his truest life, which gives nerve and consistency to his theories 
 of morality. We have already seen expressions of this convic- 
 tion in the denial of the possibility of change in the divine 
 nature, and in the condemnation of excessive indulgence of 
 emotion. Order and immutability seemed to Plato the attributes 
 of what is best and highest both in the physical and in the 
 moral world, and it is just these attributes which he missed in 
 the capricious current of feeling. The lower he went in human 
 nature or in human society, the more did he seem to find men 
 the creatures of their sentiment, and the less purpose or law 
 did he discern in their lives. 2 And art, especially dramatic art, 
 seemed to him to pander to this natural fickleness. It had 
 
 1 606 b. a 4. 431 c ; 3. 397 d ; 10. 604 e ; 608 a.
 
 1 1 2 THE THE OR Y OF ED VGA TION 
 
 no principle of selection, no law of better and worse ; l wherever 
 it could raise a laugh, or draw a sigh, or tickle an appetite, 
 there it was ready with its phantasmagoria of life. It had a 
 direct interest in "watering and nourishing" 2 the lower and 
 more trivial impulses which reason calls upon us " to dry up," 
 and it stimulated the already too great tendency in us to do 
 everybody's business except our own, to be actors instead of 
 citizens, to play at life instead of living it. The words of Bacon, 
 in which he gives the reason why poetry " was ever thought to 
 have some participation of divineness," might have been used 
 by Plato in another sense to express why it is so far from being 
 divine ; " poetry doth raise and erect the mind, by submitting 
 the shows of things to the desires of the mind, whereas reason 
 doth buckle and bow the mind unto the nature of things." 
 
 The very emphasis and fulness of Plato's polemic against 
 dramatic literature must make us feel that he was writing in a 
 different atmosphere from our own. Few modern writers on 
 education in England would reckon the stage amongst the most 
 powerful agents, whether for good or bad ; few too would regard 
 a tendency to theatricality and effusiveness as one of the most 
 serious dangers to the English character. Not the most extra- 
 vagant admirer of our dramatists would claim for them what 
 Plato heard men claim for Homer, that they have " educated 
 their country, and deserve to be read over and over again as 
 authorities on human conduct and education, and as models on 
 which men may order the whole of their lives." 3 Nor is the 
 average Englishman likely to be too " imitative " in the sense 
 which alarmed Plato. The suppleness of nature which made 
 it hard for the Athenian to be " one man and not many," is 
 generally replaced in us by a sturdiness and concentration, 
 of which consistency and self-respect, self-consciousness and 
 selfishness, are respectively the good and the bad developments. 
 Yet it must be admitted that these qualities are not incom- 
 patible with illusions and extravagances of feeling, none the 
 less dangerous because outwardly repressed ; and though we are 
 not, on the whole, a nation of theatre-goers, we are undoubtedly 
 a nation of novel-readers, and may find there the dramatic 
 
 1 605 a-c. 2 10. 606 d. s 10. 606 e.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 113 
 
 
 stimulants against which Plato protested. It must be borne in 
 mind, in comparing any ethical influence of literature in ancient 
 and modern times, that what in Greece was mainly a public of 
 spectators and listeners is now mainly a public of readers. It 
 is true that in the pulpit we have a medium of oral communi- 
 cation which they had not, but, speaking generally, it is not now 
 in the open places of the theatre, the camp, the law-courts, and 
 the marketplace, that the uttered word most circulates and 
 works ; it is rather in silence or in solitude, through the news- 
 paper on the family table, the periodical at the club, the poem 
 or novel in the bedroom, that the modern writer speaks to his 
 fellow-men. And the difference in the medium goes along with 
 a difference in the effect. Instead of the noisy publicity in 
 which contagious feeling grows as it spreads from man to man, 
 till the individual is " borne helplessly along the stream," l and 
 loses himself in an indiscriminate froth of exaggerated feeling, 
 we brood over books in the heated cells of our own imagination, 
 build castles of the fumes of our own emotions, and come forth 
 to measure the world by the mock-heroic standard of our own 
 littleness. But the craving for change and excitement, the 
 desire to escape from our own true selves with the responsi- 
 bilities which they entail, are not the less strong in us because 
 we are not born actors or mimics ; the mind can make its own 
 stage and act upon it, while the body remains immobile and 
 unexpressive. Nor does the modern demand exceed the modern 
 supply. The novel, which absorbs so much of our dramatic 
 talent, lends itself with fatal ease to the promiscuous photo- 
 graphy of situations and feelings. The increased sense of the 
 importance of human life and of the inexhaustibleness of its 
 problems supplies a ready argument to those who find anything 
 and everything "interesting;" and there are still writers of 
 whom we might say metaphorically what Plato intended 
 literally, " that there is nothing which they will not imitate, 
 thunder and wind, trumpets and whistles, dogs and sheep." 2 
 
 The same principles which guided Plato in his conception of 
 the educational function of literature guided him also in his 
 treatment of the other constituents of " musical" education, and 
 
 1 6. 492 c. * 3. 397 a.
 
 1 1 4 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 led him to conclusions still more at variance with modern 
 practice and theory. That poetry and literature, which express 
 definite ideas, should be made to serve the interests of society, 
 is an intelligible if surprising proposal ; but that music, paint- 
 ing, and sculpture should be pressed into the same service, will 
 seem to many a vague fancy, impracticable in education, and 
 destructive of art. Let us then see what Plato's idea of the use 
 of the arts in education precisely was. " Music," he says, 1 
 " involves three elements, words, harmony, rhythm," or, as we 
 may say, to bring his meaning nearer home, without pretending 
 to give it an exact modern equivalent, words, key, and time. 
 As to the words, they must conform to the same canons as the 
 words of other poetry, and the character of the two remaining 
 elements must be determined by that of the words. Those 
 "harmonies" and "rhythms" then must be employed in musical 
 composition which will express the qualities which we wish to 
 develop in the soul. What these are we already know. They 
 are the qualities which result from the right nurture of the two 
 higher psychological elements in human nature, the " spirited" 
 and the " philosophic." We must therefore have a music of 
 corresponding character, a music of war and a music of peace, 2 
 a " harmony " of violence and effort, and a " harmony " of con- 
 ciliation and calm, a "harmony" to represent the daring of the 
 soldier and the endurance of the martyr, and a " harmony" to 
 express the accents of entreaty or persuasion, of submission or 
 acquiescence. Other kinds than these, and other instruments 
 than these require, are superfluous luxuries which must be 
 " purged away" 3 in a healthy state, whose object is not to stimu- 
 late every feverish craving of its citizens, but to weave strongly 
 those vital strains of character which sustain the fabric of 
 society. The same principle will apply to the " rhythms" 4 and 
 measures of music and dance, as to the " harmonies" in which 
 they are composed ; they must not develop in lawless indepen- 
 dence, but must be such as will express " the orderly and brave 
 life." 
 
 There is then, according to Plato, a right and a wrong in the 
 musical relations of pitch and time, and this right and wrong 
 
 1 3. 398 d. 2 3. 399 a-c. 3 399 e. 4 399 e 400 c.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 115 
 
 is in some sense akin to the right and wrong in human 
 nature and conduct. Goodness and badness of form, he says, 
 follow goodness and badness of rhythm, and goodness and bad- 
 ness of rhythm follow goodness and badness of language, and 
 these again depend upon goodness and badness of character. 1 
 Nor is it only in the movements of dance and song that there 
 is this correspondence ; in all sensuous material there is a similar 
 capability of expression ; 2 it is present in the forms of painting 
 and sculpture, of weaving and embroidery, of building and 
 manufacture, of animal and vegetable life ; " in all of these 
 there is shapeliness or unshapeliness, and unshapeliness and un- 
 rhythmicalness and inharmoniousness are the kindred of badness 
 of language and badness of character, while the opposites are 
 kindred and imitations of the opposite character, the chastened 
 and the good." The poets then are not the only artists over 
 whom the state should exercise control; 3 attention must be 
 given to the whole body of craftsmen, and they must be pre- 
 vented from expressing what is vicious and unchastened, mean 
 and unshapely, whether in the figures of living things or in 
 buildings or in any other work of art. The artists who should 
 be encouraged by the state must be " those who have the 
 genius to track out the nature of what is fair and shapely " 4 and 
 to embody it anew in their works. For the young citizens must 
 not be allowed to grow up amongst images of evil, lest their 
 souls by daily contact gradually and unconsciously assimilate 
 the ugliness of their surroundings. 5 Eather they should be 
 like men living in a beautiful and healthy place; 'from every- 
 thing that they see and hear, loveliness, like a breeze, should 
 pass into their souls, and teach them without their knowing 
 it the truth of which it is a manifestation. In such an 
 atmosphere they will not only acquire a natural grace and 
 proportion of bearing and character, but an instinctive sense of 
 what is fair and what is foul in nature and in art ; and this 
 instinctive sense is a kind of anticipation of a rational under- 
 standing of the nature of good and evil; for the reason which 
 is now presented to them in forms of sense, and calls forth 
 sensuous delight, is the same reason which they will afterwards 
 
 1 3. 400 c-d. "- 401 a. 3 401 b. 4 401 c. & 401 c-d.
 
 ii 6 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 learn to know in its own form as an intelligible principle, and 
 which they will then recognise as an old friend with a new face. 1 
 
 Such is the nature and such are the limits of the education 
 of " music." It has a more intellectual and a more emotional 
 aspect. From the former point of view, it is completed when 
 we have " learned to read " 2 the world of sights and sounds 
 which is about us. That world is like a language which we 
 have got to master ; the sensible forms of good and evil pass 
 and repass before us in an infinite variety of combinations, like 
 the letters of an alphabet which combine into an infinity of 
 words, great and small. No form can be disregarded ; acts and 
 speeches which seem trivial, like the little words in a book, may 
 contain a world of meaning and be the key to a character. And 
 the true function of the artist is to help us to learn this lan- 
 guage of life ; he is the man who knows the shapes of the letters 
 and the laws of their combinations. In the " mirror " which 
 he holds up we may see reflected the images of courage, tem- 
 perance, generosity, and their opposites, and thus learn to know 
 the realities when we see them. Thus art should find its 
 fulfilment in life; and he may most truly be said to be 
 " musically " educated, whose eye and ear are trained to detect 
 what is right and wrong, not only in the creations of art, but 
 also, so far as it can be apprehended by the senses, in the actual 
 world of which art is the reflection. 
 
 If, on the other hand, we regard the emotional effects of 
 " musical " education, they may be summed up in two, that it 
 infuses a spirit of order, 3 and that it develops the " true love " 
 of beauty, 4 the former being the more passive condition of which 
 the latter is the more active expression. To Plato, most of the 
 evils of sensual passion fall under one of two heads, unregulated 
 variety or unregulated intensity. He considered passion to be 
 essentially " many-headed," and capable of indefinite multipli- 
 cation and expansion ; and one of his chief charges against the 
 art of his time was that it fostered and satisfied the indiscrimi- 
 nate craving for emotional excitement. In contrast with it, 
 
 1 3. 402 a. 2 402 a-c. 
 
 3 3. 404 e, fftoHppoffiJvqv ; 4. 424 e, fwo^ur^pov iraidias ; 425 a, evvo^iav : cf. 
 413 e. 4 3.402 d 403 c.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 117 
 
 he demanded an art which should not merely stimulate, but 
 should also discipline, the feelings ; which should not follow but 
 lead them ; which should chasten their disorder and brace their 
 indolence by making them move in the delicate lines of pro- 
 portion and beauty, and respond to the quiet emphasis of 
 harmony and rhythm. For the balance and symmetry which 
 are essential to good artistic work are also, he conceived, 
 essential to true artistic feeling. Love is the typical feeling 
 awakened by sensuous beauty, and the genuine love of genuine 
 beauty is incompatible with ungoverned emotion. The mere 
 " mad" 1 intensity of animal appetite has nothing to do with such 
 love, which is not for the body except so far as it is the expres- 
 sion of soul. " Where beauty of inward character meets with 
 beauty of outward form, each corresponding and harmonising 
 with the other, and cast in a common mould, there is the fairest 
 sight to a man who has the eyes to see it. And what is most 
 fair is also most loveable." 2 It is this perfect accord of the 
 inward and the outward which the truly " musical " man seeks 
 and delights in ; but if it cannot be realised, if one or the other 
 element must be imperfect, he will surrender the outward, and 
 while no perfection of form will atone to him for defect of 
 soul, he " will not refuse to take pleasure in " a fair soul even 
 though it appear in an " inharmonious " body. 3 
 
 Before considering the general view here given of the func- 
 tions of art in education, a word must be said about the relative 
 position which Plato assigns to the various specific arts. We are 
 at once struck by the great prominence given to music as com- 
 pared with painting, sculpture, and architecture ; and this may 
 seem the more surprising when we remember the excellence 
 attained by the Greeks in the last two and the rudimentary 
 character of their achievements in the first. It may be that 
 Plato did not see in the sculptors and architects of his time the 
 signs of degeneracy which drew his attention to the poets and 
 musicians ; but more probably he estimated the practical 
 influence of the former upon the national character as less 
 important than that of the latter. The frame of mind in which 
 pictures and statues, and still more buildings, are most appre- 
 
 1 3. 403 a. * 402 d. 402 d.
 
 1 1 8 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 ciated and enjoyed, is rather one of open and undisturbed 
 receptivity than of active emotion, and to most temperaments 
 the burning word and the stirring melody have far more effect 
 upon action than brilliancy of colouring or majesty of form. 
 But whatever may be the cause, it is a fact worthy of attention 
 that a philosophical iconoclast like Plato, in attacking the idols 
 of sensationalism both in knowledge and morality, should have 
 almost ignored the painters and sculptors, and confined his 
 assaults to the musicians and still more to the poets. Another 
 noticeable point is the simplicity and uniformity of the criteria 
 which Plato applies to the several arts. Proportion, in one 
 form or another, is the single source to which he refers all 
 artistic excellence, in the musical relations of time and tone no 
 less than in those of space in the arts of form and construction. 
 And this leads us lastly to remark how extremely rudimentary 
 must have been the music of which he was speaking. He 
 assumes throughout that music always implies words, and the 
 whole subject of harmony, in its modern sense, is absent from 
 his consideration. The truth seems to be, paradoxical as it 
 may sound, that it was the very simplicity of Greek music 
 which led Greek writers to assign to it such a direct and 
 important educational influence. As in the early days of 
 sculpture or painting, the crudeness and symbolism makes the 
 meaning of the artist more clear, when compared with the 
 subtle design and colouring of great masters, so when music 
 was chiefly limited to an accompaniment giving emphasis or 
 precision to a recitation or a dance, its effect would be more 
 strongly recognised in proportion as it was more simple. Even 
 now there are dancing and inarching melodies which exercise a 
 direct and almost physical influence on a susceptible hearer, 
 just because there is nothing but the simple act of dancing or 
 marching which they suggest ; and if music generally were 
 intimately associated with a few elementary acts and feelings, 
 its power, being more easily expressible, would be also more 
 reducible to rule and to practice, than when it has developed 
 into a vast and independent growth, speaking in its own 
 language and obeying its own laws, of which it is itself the 
 sole interpreter. 
 
 This difference, however, great as it is, and much as it in-
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLA TO. 119 
 
 creases the difficulty of applying Plato's ideas to modern music, 
 does not except it from the general scope of his theory concern- 
 ing the educational use of art, the main features of which we 
 may now proceed to consider. Of these the central and most 
 characteristic one is undoubtedly the idea that art may have, 
 and ought to have, a definite function in the development of 
 character ; and we have to ask how Plato conceived this function 
 to be exercised. " Education in music," he says, " is so telling, 
 because rhythm and harmony sink so deeply into the inward 
 part of the soul, and take hold of it so strongly, and make it 
 graceful with the grace which they bring with them." 1 And 
 again, " Gracefulness and ungracefulness go along with rhyth- 
 micalness and unrhythmicaluess, and rhythmicalness and 
 unrhythmicalness follow and resemble goodness of language, 
 or the reverse ; the style of language, again, follows the char- 
 acter of soul, and thus goodness of language, of harmony, of 
 form, and of rhythm go along with goodness of character." 2 
 " Are the gestures and accents of a brave soul in trouble the 
 same as those of a cowardly one ?" he asks in a closely analogous 
 passage of the Laws ; " surely not ; the very colours of the two 
 men are different." 3 From these few passages, which could easily 
 be multiplied, so much is clear, that Plato was in earnest with 
 the idea that there is some real connection between character 
 and artistic form, and that the common element in both is 
 found in the Tightness of proportion which is essential alike to 
 beauty in art and to goodness in conduct. We shall perhaps 
 understand him better if we reflect (what the passages above 
 will suggest) that in the early stages of civilisation the whole 
 of life tends to be more symbolical, and the connection 
 between mental states and their physical expression more 
 immediate. In such stages speech has something of the crudity 
 of a language of signs, while gesture and sound approach the 
 delicacy and articulateness of words. With the progress of 
 civilisation the symbolism of sense does not, as is sometimes 
 supposed, disappear, but it gets infinitely more complex and 
 subtle ; colours and lines, tones and measures, instead of being 
 like letters of an alphabet with fixed and uniform values, be- 
 
 1 3. 401 cl. 2 3. 400 c-e. 3 Laws, 2. 654 e.
 
 1 2 o THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 come fitful centres of multitudinous associations, so various to 
 different sensibilities, and so remote from their primitive signi- 
 ficance, that men are tempted to deny their validity or to relegate 
 them to the sphere of individual caprice. It is curious to see 
 the human mind thus refusing to recognise, or to be recognised 
 by, its own offspring as they grow up. In the infancy of art, 
 nobody doubts but that it has a meaning, that mind speaks to 
 mind in it. Only when it has ceased to lisp and to point, when 
 the simple singer has grown into a " mighty-mouthed inventor 
 of harmonies," and the sculptor's one poor thought has made 
 way for 
 
 "The thousand sounds and sights that broke 
 In on him at the chisel's stroke," 
 
 only then do men begin to question whether what they have 
 created is really their own, and to explain it away by chance, 
 by convention, by mechanics, by anything but mind. Yet this 
 is not really to be wondered at ; for as soon as we try to account 
 for any but the simplest effects of art, they escape us, the truth 
 being that " accounting for " them merely means translating one 
 medium of expression into another and less perfect one. Lan- 
 guage and music and painting are all significant, but the sig- 
 nificance of one is not convertible with that of another. We 
 cannot listen to the meaning of colour and form, we must see 
 it ; we cannot make music speak in words without its ceasing 
 to be music, any more than we can resolve a poem into sound 
 and rhythm without its poetry evaporating. And if the relation- 
 ship of the arts to one another is so difficult to express, much 
 more so is the relationship of art in general to other modes of 
 human activity. Few people, indeed, can seriously doubt that the 
 character of an imaginative man is ultimately affected by what 
 he habitually sees and hears ; or, again, that what one person ap- 
 prehends as right or expedient, another person may apprehend 
 as beautiful; or, once more, that devotion, similar in effect 
 to that of the saint for the being whom he worships, may be felt 
 by the man of science for the truth which he pursues. But 
 when we have made a few general statements such as these, we 
 are brought to a standstill by the intricacy of the subject and 
 the limitations of our analysis. The fact remains irrefragable 
 that to the vast majority of mankind art and conduct, religion
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLA TO. 121 
 
 and science, are very different things, with little or nothing in 
 common ; and that the attempt to fuse them generally results 
 in sermonising pictures, rose-water morality, and unctuous 
 sciolism. And as, at most times and for most purposes, it is of 
 more practical importance to realise proximate differences than 
 fundamental unities, the world at large instinctively looks with 
 suspicion upon those who, in trying to see through the ordinary 
 distinctions of life, appear to be removing its ordinary land- 
 marks. No one has insisted more strongly than Plato himself 
 upon the dangers of passing too hastily " from the many to the 
 one ; " but for that very reason we need not be afraid to follow 
 him, when, with the courage of his conviction that reason is 
 one in its essence, he leads us now and again to " a high rock " 
 from which we may see that it is one also in its manifestations. 
 To Plato the laws of proportion, which are the condition of 
 beauty in art, seemed to betoken the presence of the same mind 
 as is revealed in the immutable order of the universe, and more 
 imperfectly in the moral order of human life. 1 He was very 
 far from identifying or confusing artistic beauty with moral 
 goodness; but, believing, as he did, that the whole physical 
 world is " the image of its maker, God manifest to sense," 2 he 
 could not but believe that in all things sensible, and therefore 
 in the relations of figure, time, and tone, there is a right and a 
 wrong, a good and a bad, according as they do or do not express 
 and obey intelligence. And since bodily movement and sight 
 and hearing are among the most prominent and important of 
 our vital activities, especially in early life, he drew the natural 
 conclusion that it must make a difference to the growth of the 
 human soul and character, how, and upon what occasions, those 
 activities are exercised, and that it is the function of the arts to 
 provide for their exercise in the best way and upon the best 
 objects. It is, in fact, rather the real simplicity than the sup- 
 posed vagueness of Plato's ideas which makes them embarrass- 
 ing. The luxuriant development of the arts in modern times, 
 in independence both of one another and of the other elements 
 of human life, makes it difficult to apply to them conceptions 
 formed at a time when they were modest and business-like 
 
 1 Timaeus, 47 b-d. * Timaeus, 92 b.
 
 1 2 2 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 appendages of religion, war, or public amusement ; almost as 
 difficult as it -would be to transfer the lessons learnt on a school 
 drilling-ground to the evolutions of a modern army on the 
 battle-field. 
 
 Plato would have his young citizens, who are one day to 
 govern and protect the state, nerved and inspirited, soothed 
 and softened, by warlike and peaceful songs ; he would have 
 them disciplined to order by the precision of time and tune, of 
 movement and voice ; he would remind them of their duties by 
 the sculpturesque embodiments of undying types of true man- 
 hood ; he would make grace and dignity as natural to them as 
 the air which they breathe, and lead them to bear themselves 
 unconsciously as if they were in the presence of others. In all 
 this there is nothing strange. But from the austere beauty of 
 the conception of the Greek philosopher to the confused jargon 
 of modern aesthetic culture, is a bewildering and unwelcome step. 
 Our masterpieces of art are mostly foreign, and speak a lan- 
 guage unintelligible to the ordinary English mind. Even if it 
 were otherwise, they are meaninglessly arranged in galleries, cut 
 adrift from the surroundings for which they were made, but 
 which they can never recover. Our greatest artists are going 
 back to an unreal or unnational past, or "are making the 
 public their master more than necessity requires." 1 Where are 
 we to look for the " breeze of beauty and health," for the crafts- 
 men who " can track out the nature of loveliness and grace " ? 
 We may collect engravings, and photographs, and china, and 
 make ourselves learned in the history of art ; we may found 
 museums and institutes, and spread casts of Venus and Apollo 
 through the land ; we may give thousands of pounds for pieces 
 of clever vulgarity ; but we shall not make English life much 
 more beautiful or more joyous, unless we can produce art 
 which will educate the nation to see with its eyes and to hear 
 with its ears the country in which it dwells and the history 
 which it inherits. It is in music perhaps that the outlook is 
 the least discouraging. Here there is a possibility of acting 
 upon large masses with some effect ; here social distinctions are 
 less felt ; here too the English nature seems to show more apti- 
 tude and susceptibility. We can hardly hope to make our great 
 
 1 6. 493. d.
 
 AV THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 123 
 
 towns beautiful, but it is not chimerical to look forward to a 
 time when they may each have their orchestra and chorus, and 
 adequate provision for hearing them. There is no need to 
 quarrel about the precise educational effect which modern music 
 has or may have. That it has some such effect will not be denied 
 except by those who wish to keep it to themselves, or by those 
 who are irritated at the stupidity of its would-be advocates. 
 The apparent vagueness of its influence, arising from the diffi- 
 culty of formulating it, is neither a proof of its unreality nor an 
 argument against utilising it. Everybody who is at all suscep- 
 tible to music knows that he is better for having it, and worse 
 for being without it ; he also probably know-s that the composers 
 whom the world has agreed to call great are, some, or all of 
 them, those to whose music he most likes to listen ; more than 
 this he need not be able to say, for a fact is not made more of 
 a fact by being talked or written about. If it be once fully 
 recognised that music has a great emotional power over a con- 
 siderable proportion of English people, the proper application 
 of the power becomes a public duty, and it is only a question of 
 time to discover the best ways of doing it. 
 
 We have thus far considered Plato's conception of the 
 education in " music," mainly in its ethical and psychological 
 aspect, but we should represent him very imperfectly if we 
 omitted to mention the importance which he attaches to it on 
 social and political grounds. The often-quoted text, that " the 
 fashions of music are never changed without changes in the most 
 important laws of the commonwealth," 1 may serve here as a point 
 of departure. It is difficult for us to understand the concern with 
 which Plato urges the importance of permanence and continuity 
 in the system of " musical " education. " It is in music," he 
 says, 2 " that the guardians of our state must build their guard- 
 house ; for it is here that lawlessness easily creeps in unper- 
 ceived. People think that it is only play, and does no harm. 
 And what harm does it do ? Little by little it gets a footing, 
 and spreads gently and silently into the habits and arrange- 
 ments of life ; from these it passes, gathering force as it goes, 
 into the transactions of business, and from business it gets to 
 
 1 4. 424 c. "Music " is here used in its modern sense. 2 424 d-e.
 
 1 2 4 THE THE ORY OF ED UCA TION 
 
 the laws and the constitution, with licence full-grown in its 
 train, until it ends by ruining everything, both public and 
 private." On the other hand, " when the play of children is 
 good from the first, and they take in a spirit of law through 
 their music, then it has just the opposite effect, attending them 
 at every step in life, making it grow, and building it up where 
 it had fallen down." l And as in the other case the spirit of 
 lawlessness, beginning at the trifles of education, ends by over- 
 throwing law itself, so the law-loving temper, fostered from 
 childhood, is the pregnant germ of the full insight of the legisla- 
 tor and statesman. 2 If it only be started well, it will assimilate 
 nourishment and grow by its own inherent vitality. To people 
 who have thus lived in an atmosphere of order, the details of 
 legislation will offer no difficulty; with an instinctive and 
 inherited tact they will regulate their life wisely and well, 
 whether it be in the lesser matters of social behaviour and 
 usage, or in the greater ones of business, commerce, and trade. 
 
 We have had occasion before to remark on the difference 
 between the small and simple civic communities of Greece and 
 the complex masses of modern nations, in regard to the 
 directness and rapidity of the transmission of social and 
 political changes. The passage just quoted brings that differ- 
 ence again vividly before us. To Plato, with the restlessness 
 and instability of Greek political life before his eyes, the one 
 thing needful seemed to be to establish in society a permanent 
 " ethos," a traditional character, which should be able to resist 
 the shocks of party-spirit and individual caprice. And if this 
 could only be done by a system of education, which should 
 receive each citizen at birth and retain its hold upon him 
 through life, it was no mere fancy to watch with a jealous eye 
 the first symptoms of innovation in the system, even in matters 
 so apparently trivial as popular songs. To us, with our national 
 gift for forming and carrying on traditional modes of life and 
 thought, it will often seem that in education we need more 
 exhortation to adopt new ideas than to remain faithful to old 
 ones. Our great schools and universities are typical instances 
 of the way in which prejudice and tradition may uphold 
 
 1 4. 425 a. 8 424 a ; 425 a-e.
 
 AY THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 125 
 
 methods of teaching and social habits which have ceased 
 to have a reason for existence. As regards the other part of 
 Plato's opinion, that for men who are going to serve their 
 country in government and legislation the early formation of a 
 " constitutional " character is of much more importance than a 
 study of written systems or codes, we are more nearly at one 
 with him. If the Duke of Wellington could say that the 
 battle of Waterloo was won on the playing-fields at Eton, we 
 need not be surprised at Plato when he speaks of children 
 " receiving the spirit of law through their music," l or when he 
 says that " one of the greatest tests of a man's character is the 
 show which he makes in his gymnastics." 2 The distrust in 
 " technical " education for the higher spheres of public life, and 
 the belief in the efficacy of a " liberal culture," which glories in 
 having nothing directly to do with a profession, are both strong, 
 sometimes perhaps too strong, in the English mind. Even if 
 the theory itself were in no danger of being overdriven, the 
 poverty of the culture which we provide on the strength of it 
 might give us some qualms. The principle of our system, put 
 at its best, is that by taking the mind through the greatest 
 works of classical literature, we both train it to habits of 
 exactitude and observation, and cultivate the taste, imagination, 
 and judgment with the finest and wisest thought of antiquity. 
 We inherit the system from an age when the language and 
 literature of modern Europe had only just begun to exist, and 
 when great thoughts adequately expressed could only be found 
 in classical writers. The value of the intellectual discipline 
 gained in the curriculum cannot seriously be disputed; but 
 whether, as it is at present worked, even when supplemented by 
 the teaching of parts of the Bible, it supplies the best and most 
 natural food to the " philosophic " element in the English mind, 
 is extremely doubtful. It is not indeed upon this ground, of 
 inadequacy for its professed purpose, that the system is gene- 
 rally attacked ; its assailants are more often persons who are 
 crying out for " practical" education, and who, if they had their 
 way, would eliminate from the culture of the human mind the 
 study of its own greatest works. But it is just this which 
 
 1 4. 425 a. 7. 537 b.
 
 1 2 6 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 makes the question a serious one. For if the position of the 
 higher education is assailed from without by misguided or 
 mercenary ignorance, while its natural defenders are beginning 
 to doubt whether they have anything to defend, we may well 
 fear for its future. In the confusion and din which surrounds 
 the subject, nothing seems so important as to come to a clear 
 understanding of the point at issue. It should be seen that 
 convenient catch-words like " supply" and " demand," or well- 
 sounding oppositions like " words " and " things," tell us 
 absolutely nothing unless we realise first by what the "de- 
 mand" is made, and what "things" are. It should be under- 
 stood that the primary question is, not whether to refine the 
 taste, or to produce a gentleman, or to teach useful knowledge, 
 is the end of education ; but, before all, how the whole man is 
 to be made the best of ; and that whether it be nature and her 
 works, or man and his works which are studied (and neither 
 can rightly be neglected), it is ultimately mind in some form 
 or another which we have to educate, and mind in some form 
 or another through which alone it can be educated. The 
 representatives of religion, literature, and science might then join 
 hands over their common subject-matter, instead of snatching at 
 it by turns, and trying each to undo the work of his supposed 
 rival. In the meantime, until we are nearer to such a result, 
 two lesser and more practicable things may be done by the 
 teachers of language ; they may try to make classical education 
 less a matter of mere grammatical discipline or of imitative 
 ingenuity, and more a study of human thought and character ; 
 and they may try to rescue our own English literature from its 
 present neglect, to treat it in the spirit of the great men who 
 have created scholarship, not on methods combining the worst 
 features of the traditional classical curriculum, and, by making 
 it speak to the youth of the nation, give it a systematic place in 
 the development of the national character. 
 
 We may conclude Plato's representation of the political and 
 social importance of " musical " education by looking with him 
 for a moment at some of the consequences of its neglect. In 
 the eighth and ninth books of the Republic, Plato has given us 
 in a series of pictures an ideal history of the fall of the human 
 soul, both in the individual and in society. He had previously
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 127 
 
 shown us what he conceived that the life of man might be if it 
 were allowed to follow the highest law of its development ; he 
 now shows us to what lowest depths it might be supposed to 
 sink if the logical principle of degeneration were allowed to 
 work unchecked. He had followed man up to the point at 
 which he is nearest to God ; he now traces his descent to the 
 point when he is on the verge of passing into a beast. In this 
 picture of the progress of evil a strikingly prominent place is 
 assigned to the gradually increasing neglect of "music;" and 
 nowhere does Plato express more clearly his sense of the vital 
 importance, social and political, of a thing apparently so far 
 removed from society and politics as the early culture of the 
 higher side of human nature. The ideally best condition of life, 
 individual and social, had been represented by him as resulting 
 from the harmonious and normal development and operation of 
 certain psychical forces. In accordance with this view, the 
 gradual declension from such a condition is represented as a 
 continually increasing discord in the vital faculties, beginning 
 with the failure of the highest to perform their proper functions, 
 and the usurpation of their place by lower ones, and ending 
 with the complete inversion of the true psychological relations, 
 and the absolute dominion of those activities which have no 
 right even to exist in the organism. And as the ideally best 
 conditions were conceived by Plato to depend upon a right 
 system of education, maintaining and transmitting a certain 
 character, so the typical forms of evil or imperfection in the 
 world are pictured by him as resulting from the abandonment 
 or perversion of such a system, the soul being thereby deprived 
 of its proper nourishment, and left a victim to the bad influ- 
 ences of its environment and its own lower nature. 
 
 The first effect of the neglect of " music" is a certain loss 
 of elevation in the general aim of life. 1 The "philosophic" 
 faculties, deprived of their true object, find exercise in calculat- 
 ing means to lower ends, and in this unnatural service lose 
 that simplicity and directness which are alone compatible with 
 the pursuit of truth in the interests of society. The element 
 of " spirit" rises into the place thus left vacant, and makes the 
 
 1 Cf. 8. 546 e ; 548 b-c ; 549 b ; 547 d-e.
 
 1 2 8 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 desire for distinction the ruling principle of life. But the 
 falseness of its position reacts upon it ; deprived of the higher 
 inspiration which its nature requires, it sinks itself into mere 
 personal ambition, while the meaner desires, which it should 
 have joined with reason to regulate or repress, begin to lift up 
 their heads. Such is Plato's psychological diagnosis of certain 
 well-known social phenomena. When the best intellects in 
 the community begin to be suspected of being " too clever," and 
 are kept out of high places in favour of " honest and down- 
 right" men; when self-respect tends to degenerate into self- 
 will, and the desire for personal distinction becomes a passion ; 
 when moral rectitude is upheld more by fear of disgrace than 
 by inward conviction, and a chivalrous bearing in public is 
 compatible with the pursuit of money and pleasure "in the 
 dark;" 1 then we may suspect that "the Muses are beginning 
 to be neglected," 2 and that "reason tempered with music, 
 which is the only guardian-angel of virtue," 3 is being driven 
 from its natural home in the souls of men. 
 
 The continued neglect of education brings with it more 
 aggravated results. 4 As the eye of the mind grows more and 
 more unaccustomed to the vision of beauty and truth, its sight 
 gets more and more narrowed to the objects nearest to it, and 
 the " blind god " of wealth becomes the leader of the " blind " 
 soul. And the fresh downward step of the higher self is accom- 
 panied by a fresh rise in the lower ; the animal appetites, which 
 ambition had affected to despise and repress, now no longer 
 " tamed " by reason or swayed by high purpose, become noisy 
 and importunate ; and though respectability and self-interest 
 may still keep them down, " want of education " leaves them 
 free to engender a brood of " drone-like " passions, unproduc- 
 tive and inorganic, the paupers and criminals of the soul. The 
 same " want of education," operating over a wider area, pro- 
 duces analogous conditions in a state, where the neglected and 
 unnurtured children of the upper classes first sink into unpro- 
 ductive spendthrifts, and then swell the useless and dangerous 
 elements of the society which, in its blind devotion to money, 
 had helped to impoverish them. 
 
 1 Cf. 8. 547 d-e ; 549 a ; 548 a-b. 2 8. 546 d. 
 
 8 8. 549 b. 4 554, b-d ; 552 e.
 
 AV THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 129 
 
 It is a further stage in decline \vhen the comparative 
 respectability and consistency of the pursuit of wealth gives 
 way to the mere restlessness of indiscriminate impulse, and the 
 satisfaction of the passing moment is erected into a principle 
 of life. Here, again, it is the " uneducated " l soul which falls a 
 victim. A father, who believes in nothing that does not pay, 
 gives his son a cheap education. 2 The son gets into fast society ; 
 its flashiness dazzles his eyes, which have never learnt to look 
 at anything but the ground ; after a struggle perhaps he 
 temporarily recovers his hereditary steadiness, but his soul is 
 still empty and barren, and weeds, both native and exotic, have 
 full liberty to grow there. The " words of truth and beauty, 
 which are the best garrison of souls whom God loves," 3 have never 
 been allowed to hold their rightful citadel, and their vacant 
 place is gradually occupied by the "false and swaggering" 4 
 theories, which promise " initiation " into the " mysterious " 
 knowiedge of the world. 5 Their key to the mystery is simple, 
 and consists in "calling insolence good breeding, anarchy 
 freedom, prodigality magnificence, and shamelessness man- 
 hood." 6 For a soul so circumstanced, the best chance is that it 
 may stop in its career of licence before it has become the victim 
 of any one dominant passion, and arrive at a sort of equilibrium 
 in its desires, satisfying them each in turn, and living that life 
 of so-called " freedom " which consists in being the creature of 
 the moment. 7 But if circumstances are not so favourable to 
 it, 8 the trembling balance of discordant appetites is sure to be 
 overset, the irresistible impulse of passion to absorb everything 
 unless it be itself absorbed will assert itself, and the easy-going 
 "liberty and equality" of many-coloured caprice will settle 
 down into the cruel and sombre " tyranny " of lust. 
 
 These meagre fragments, from what forms perhaps the most 
 powerfully written section of the Republic, will suffice to illus- 
 trate Plato's conception of the consequences of neglecting the 
 education of the reason through the imagination and the emo- 
 tions. They will show how strongly he felt the truth which we 
 are sometimes in danger of forgetting, that the evil in human life 
 
 1 8. 559 d. 2 559 d 560 a. * 560 b. 4 560 c. 
 
 5 560 e. 6 560 e. 7 561 a-e. * 9. 572 e 573 c.
 
 130 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 is quite as much due to negative as to positive conditions ; that 
 it is the absence of healthy and bright surroundings, the want of 
 healthy and interesting employments, the abeyance of healthy 
 and inspiring emotions, which drag so many men down. We 
 cannot help seeing this in the case of the lower strata of 
 society, where the pressure of circumstances is so gross and 
 palpable ; but if we agree with Plato, we shall feel that the 
 more richly endowed and the more delicately organised human 
 nature is, the more important and also the more difficult it is to 
 educate it well, and the more fatal are the consequences, both 
 to itself and to society, of educating it badly or not at all. And 
 what is true of different natures compared with one another, is 
 true also of the different elements in the same nature. Good, 
 like evil, begins at the top and radiates downwards. If we can 
 secure that the highest faculties, intellectual and emotional, are 
 at their highest activity, the lower ones will not probably be 
 seriously disorganised ; but no amount of decent regularity in 
 the working of the lower will guarantee the vitality of the 
 higher. " When the whole soul follows the philosophic element, 
 and there is no faction in it, the justice of each separate part is 
 secured, and each does its own work and reaps its own pleasures 
 too, the best pleasures, and also up to its measure the truest. 
 But when any of the other elements dominates, it not only fails 
 to find its own pleasure itself, but it compels the other elements 
 to pursue a pleasure which is not their own nor true." 1 
 
 The evils arising from the neglect of " music" are not the 
 only evils which Plato describes in connection with it ; we have 
 already seen what he considered to be the psychological effects 
 of its excessive or exclusive study. To obviate these effects is, 
 as we also saw, the proper function of gymnastic ; and we have 
 now to complete our account of Plato's conception of that 
 branch of education. Of this, as of music, he only lays down 
 certain general " outlines" or principles, leaving the details to be 
 filled in by those who have to apply them. The most important 
 of these principles, which we have already had occasion to notice, 
 is that gymnastic, though concerned primarily with the body, 2 
 is to be considered as ultimately affecting the soul and the 
 
 1 9. 586 e. 3 3. 410 c.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 131 
 
 character, and owes to this fact its educational importance. 
 This principle at once determines the general aim of bodily 
 exercises ; they should aim " not so much at producing mere 
 strength, as at awakening the spirited element in human 
 nature." 1 It is the fault of the professional trainers that they 
 ignore the educational side of their business, and attend only to 
 developing the muscles. And their system not only fails in an 
 ethical point of view, but even where it might be expected to 
 succeed, it does not really do so. " The athletic habit of body 
 is a sleepy sort of habit, and is liable to upset the health. We 
 see how the professional athletes doze away their life, and how, 
 if they deviate a little from their prescribed diet, they get 
 serious and violent diseases." 2 A " finer kind of training " is 
 wanted for a man who is to serve his country as a soldier ; 3 he 
 must have his wits wide awake, be quick of sight and hearing, 
 and able to endure changes of food and weather without break- 
 ing down. Of the two elements in such a training, diet and 
 exercise, Plato, in the Republic, devotes much more considera- 
 tion to the former. The most characteristic point in what he 
 says of the latter is, that for a certain period physical exercise 
 should be pursued alone, to the exclusion of all serious mental 
 work. 4 This period would apparently be from two to three 
 years, 5 between the ages of seventeen and twenty. Two reasons 
 are given for this view : that " hard work and sleep are enemies 
 to study," and that " the figure which a man makes in his 
 gymnastic is one of the greatest tests of his character." 6 Every 
 one who knows anything of English school-Life will be ready to 
 indorse both these statements ; but he will not probably con- 
 sider the truth of them a reason for making two years and a 
 half of exclusive athletic exercises a necessary part of educa- 
 tion. We must remember, however, that Plato was thinking of 
 something more analogous to an incipient military service than 
 to the games of our schools. The exercises upon which so long 
 a time was to be spent would aim principally at disciplining 
 the body for the work of a soldier, and would include, if practi- 
 cable, some actual " taste of blood " on the battle-field. 7 Still, 
 
 1 3. 410 b. s 3. 404 a. * 404 a-b. 
 
 4 7. 537 b. s Cf. 7. 537 b ; 539 e. 7. 537 b. 
 
 7 5. 466 e-^67 e ; cf. 7. 537 a ; 3. 404 a-b.
 
 1 3 2 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 even with this explanation, it is curious that his belief in 
 the importance of " specialising " work should have so far over- 
 ruled his consciousness of the dangers of one-sided develop- 
 ment. 
 
 Plato has more to say on the other branch of gymnastic, the 
 system of diet and general management of the body ; for he is 
 here brought into contact with the medical practice of his day, 
 and about this he held some strong opinions. Impressed with 
 the want of principle and purpose, of simplicity and concentra- 
 tion, in all departments of Greek life, he saw in the recent 
 growth of luxury, with its attendant crop of new diseases, and 
 its new methods of medical treatment, an analogous phenomenon 
 to that which he observed in the sphere of art. While the 
 artists seemed to him to be mainly engaged in catering for a 
 morbid appetite for emotional stimulants, 1 helping to enervate 
 morality and to fill the law-courts with litigants, instead of to 
 make men a law to themselves, the doctors, he thought, were 
 pampering a luxurious valetudinarianism, and flattering the 
 whims of rich voluptuaries whose disorders were the result of 
 their own mismanagement. 2 The simplicity for which he had 
 cried aloud in art, he now demanded in living, and upon the 
 same grounds. In a well-ordered society, every man ought to 
 have his work to do ; and if he has work to do, he must make 
 himself fit to do it. 3 The spiced luxuries of a feverish civilisa- 
 tion, with its "sauces from Sicily," its " grisettes from Corinth," 
 its " Athenian confectionery," have no more place in his life 
 than they would have if he were training for a race. 4 Most of 
 the long names which recent medicine has given to diseases 
 are, in Plato's opinion, the polite inventions of doctors who will 
 not offend their rich patients by telling them the truth, that 
 they have worked too little and eaten too much. 5 A man who 
 is always wanting to see a physician, except in case of accidents 
 or epidemics, ought to be as much ashamed of himself as a man 
 who is always going into court to get justice, because he has 
 none of his own. 6 We might learn a lesson here from the de- 
 spised artisan. 7 He cannot afford to be long in bed ; his work 
 
 1 3. 404 e 405 a. 2 3. 405 c 408 b. 3 3. 406 c. 
 
 4 404 d ; cf. 2. 373 a, where erdlpat are similarly inserted between 6^/a and 
 . 6 3. 405 d. 6 3. 405 ad. ' 7 406 c d.
 
 AV THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 133 
 
 will not wait for him ; and if he cannot be cured soon, he dies. 
 But the rich man is supposed to have no work to do, abstention 
 from which would make life not worth living. 1 He is to be 
 allowed to give up his duties as a householder or a citizen, or 
 to let his brain lie fallow as long as he likes, whenever he 
 fancies that he has a sick headache. 
 
 Modern life would have supplied Plato with close analogies 
 to the evils which he saw in the gymnastics and dietetics of his 
 own day. Our public schools and universities have no lack of 
 the sleepy and brutalised athlete, who has not an idea of doing 
 anything except by force, whose perceptions are cloyed and 
 dull, whose "life moves without grace or rhythm," 2 and who 
 yet probably could not serve on a campaign or a geographical 
 expedition. Nor is the well-to-do valetudinarian an unfamiliar 
 creature amongst us, the man who " suffers torments if he 
 depart at all from his accustomed diet," and "is always in 
 labour about his body." 3 Both phenomena may be said to 
 represent the bad sides of something which is intrinsically good ; 
 the exaggerated interest taken in athletic exercises, while 
 it partly defeats its own aim by artificialising school life, and 
 making games into professions, is nevertheless the outcome of a 
 genuine desire to broaden the basis of education, and to lose no 
 chance of developing character out of strong national tendencies. 
 So, too, the attention given to diet and the less serious forms of 
 ailment, though it may sometimes result in making a man 
 "profitable neither to himself or society," 4 is a symptom of the 
 higher and more intelligent value which is set upon human life. 
 Every real advance in civilisation, along with the higher re- 
 sponsibilities and the more delicate public conscience which it 
 brings with it, entails also fresh forms of abuse and greater 
 necessity for taking trouble ; but the best modern minds will 
 not agree with Plato that it is the duty of society to let anybody 
 die who can be kept alive. If, however, we have advanced 
 upon his ideas in this point, we are still far from having 
 realised them in others. We have not yet found the best way 
 " to blend music with gymnastic and apply them proportionately 
 to the soul " of the average schoolboy ; and we have scarcely 
 
 1 3. 407 a-c. 2 3. 411 e. 3 3. 406 b and 407 c. 4 407 e.
 
 1 3 4 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 begun to entertain the idea that a man is as much bound to 
 manage his health properly as he is to manage his morals, much 
 less to diffuse the knowledge which would enable him to do it. 
 Let us now gather up briefly the main threads in Plato's 
 account of " musical " education, which, in its wider sense, as 
 implying the harmonious development of the whole nature, 
 includes " gymnastic " as well as " music." Its function is to 
 provide nurture for the soul from childhood to youth. Upon 
 the lower or " appetitive " element its action is more indirect 
 than direct ; it tames, regulates, or represses its various mani- 
 festations, by encouraging interests and emotions by which they 
 are absorbed, or with which they are incompatible, as the case 
 may require. Upon the " spirited " and " philosophic " elements 
 it acts directly, by compelling and encouraging their normal 
 activity through the bodily limbs and senses. The means 
 which it employs for the former are diet and exercise, for the 
 latter they are poetry and the arts. These last are the appro- 
 priate nurture of the " philosophic " nature, not in its entirety, 
 but in that phase of its growth in which it is mainly imagina- 
 tive and emotional, not logical and reflective. By presenting to 
 the soul the true principles of human life in the sensuous mate- 
 rial which it is able to assimilate, they prepare it unconsciously 
 for assimilating them when presented at a later stage in a more 
 rational form. They teach it how to live by telling how divine 
 beings and great men live and have lived ; they teach it what 
 to love by surrounding it with what is really loveable ; they 
 foster its acquisitive instincts by encouraging the quick and 
 accurate use of the senses ; they develop its tendency to order 
 and law by accustoming it to recognise severe symmetries of 
 sound and form; and, finally, they introduce it to manhood 
 endowed with an instinctive capacity of doing and saying the 
 right thing at the right time, and with an instinctive perception 
 of what is right and wrong in the deeds and words of others. 
 In calling the capacity and perception thus acquired " instinc- 
 tive," it is not intended that Plato conceived them to be received 
 at birth or got by natural selection. No doubt Plato did attach 
 immense importance to natural endowment; no doubt also he 
 believed that there was some natural tendency in human nature 
 towards what was good for it ; but we have abundantly seen
 
 7.V THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 135 
 
 that this belief was more than counterbalanced by a conviction 
 that mere natural endowment may be simply destructive, and 
 that a mere tendency to what is good may ultimately tend to 
 what is bad. 1 By " instinctive " then is meant that the sub- 
 stance of the education of " music " is appropriated and held by 
 the soul without real reflection ; that, in Greek phraseology, it 
 feels neither the need nor the capacity to " give an account of " 
 it ; that it is conscious of it only as part and parcel of itself, 
 not as an object which it can hold apart, look at, and criticise. 
 Such a condition of mind is not of course unreflective in the 
 sense of implying any capriciousness or instability ; on the 
 contrary, the imperceptible degrees by which it has been formed 
 guarantee its depth and fixity. And, accordingly, when Plato 
 wishes to describe finally the effects of " music " upon the 
 character, he can find no better metaphor than one taken from 
 the process of dyeing. The dyers, he says, 2 when they want to 
 dye wool a fine purple, first select white wool from amongst the 
 various colours ; then they prepare it very carefully to receive 
 the bloom, and then at last they dye it ; a dye put in in this 
 way is fast for ever, whereas if otherwise treated it washes out in 
 a ridiculous manner. " This then was what we were trying to 
 do when we selected our citizen-soldiers, and educated them by 
 music and gymnastic ; our whole object was that by obedience 
 they should take in the laws like a dye, so that their belief 
 about danger and all other things might become fast, through 
 their having both the proper nature and the proper nurture, 
 and thus the influences of pleasure, pain, fear, and appetite, 
 which are more potent than all the soaps and solvents in the 
 world, might never be able to wash it out." 
 
 The question now arises, Is education so conceived complete ? 
 Is the soul, when nurtured up to this point, full-grown as far as 
 education can make it? At one time Plato seems to have 
 thought that it was; 3 that at about twenty a man must cease 
 learning in the narrower sense of the word, and get the rest of 
 his knowledge in the practical life of a citizen, and that it 
 rested with those in authority to watch his development and 
 regulate his career accordingly. But we have also seen that 
 
 1 C. 491 b. z 4. 429 c 430 b. 3 3. 413 e 414 a.
 
 1 3 6 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 in the second section of the Republic, he clearly expresses his 
 feeling of the imperfection of the education of " music," and 
 assigns to it a subordinate and preparatory function in a more 
 elaborate system. 1 There are two main points in which Plato 
 finds it imperfect : subjectively, from the side of the soul, it 
 leaves important capacities undeveloped ; objectively, regarding 
 the matter which it imparts and the form in which it imparts 
 it, it stops short of the requirements of knowledge. On the 
 one hand, it teaches the " philosophic " nature to love what is 
 beautiful, but not to understand what is true ; 2 it makes it 
 quick to recognise the forms of goodness presented to sense or 
 imagination, but not to see with the mind's eye the essential 
 principles which those forms imperfectly express ; 3 it infuses 
 into it indelible beliefs and convictions, attaching to the parti- 
 cular characters and actions which have come before it in the 
 course of education, but it does not satisfy the desire to know 
 the laws to which those beliefs can be referred.* On the other 
 hand, if we regard the matter which it teaches, this consists 
 mainly of ideas embodied in sensible forms; the characters 
 and deeds of individual men are described in poetry or sug- 
 gested in music or pictured in painting and sculpture, with the 
 view of stimulating imitation and educating the sense for the 
 corresponding realities in life. The ideas thus imparted carry 
 conviction to the soul, not through their logical consistency and 
 irrefragability, but through their familiarity; they are appre- 
 hended, not in the systematic form of science in which each 
 part is seen to be connected with every other, but as a multi- 
 tude of isolated instances, each complete in itself, and contain- 
 ing its own justification. 5 A person in this mental condition 
 does not satisfy the requirements of what Plato understands by 
 knowledge; and here few thoughtful people would disagree 
 with him ; where he differs from most of the world is in think- 
 ing that the further mental progress, instead of being left to the 
 circumstances and choice of the individual, should be systemati- 
 cally provided for by a continued education. He seems to have 
 been led to this idea by reflecting upon the consequences which 
 
 1 7. 522 a ; 6. 503 e ff. 2 Cf. 3. 402 d and 403 c, with 5. 475 d-e. 
 8 Cf. 3. 402 b-c with 5. 476 a-d. 4 Cf. 3. 412 d^!4 a with 6. 503 a-e. 
 5 See the account of 56$a and its objects, 4. 477 a 480 a.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 137 
 
 seemed to him to follow from the neglect of it. He was per- 
 suaded that the evils of human life had their root in ignorance, 
 and that if men could once realise what their true interests 
 required them to do, they would do it. He did not expect that 
 mankind at large should ever have such a keen and profound 
 perception of the truth, but it seemed to him not impossible 
 that a few exceptional persons might arrive at it, and that 
 society might allow itself to be governed by them ; at any rate 
 he was convinced that this sovereignty of true knowledge was 
 the ideal to be aimed at, convinced that there is an intelligible 
 principle pervading and connecting not only the life of men but 
 the life of the whole universe, convinced that to discern this 
 principle and to conform to it is the highest achievement of 
 knowledge and of conduct, and that to " rise by stepping-stones" 
 towards this height is the true education both of the individual 
 and of the human race. Of such a principle the education of 
 "music" had nothing to tell ; l it showed examples and types of 
 courage, temperance, justice, but it did not show "wherein they 
 are good," 2 what is the end to which they all converge, and 
 which gives unity and meaning to their variety ; and without 
 some such perception how can we be said to " know " justice, or 
 even to possess it ? We may know it in one form, but we might 
 mistake it in another ; we may think we have got hold of it at 
 one moment, in one place, under one set of circumstances, but 
 it may escape us when we have changed our point of view. 
 This is why the results of the first education are " sketchy " 
 and " inexact," and require " filling up " and completing by a 
 further education. 3 
 
 But there was another consideration which led Plato to the 
 same conclusion. It has already been shown how the concep- 
 tion of what he called the " philosophic " nature grows under 
 his hands in the Republic, and how from being a complemen- 
 tary psychological element it comes ultimately to be represented 
 as the germ of complete manhood. Though, however, it has 
 in it this inherent capability, like other germs it depends for 
 its development upon its environment, and Plato is the first 
 
 1 7. 522 a. 2 6. 506 a. 
 
 1 6. 504 b, d/cpt/3eias t\\iirrj ; ib. d, inroypaQ-qv . . . airepya<ria.v, K.T.\.
 
 1 3 8 THE THE ORY OF ED UCA TION 
 
 to admit, and even to insist upon, the fact, that this richly- 
 endowed " philosophic " nature, which might be the cause of 
 the greatest good to mankind, is generally the cause of the 
 greatest evils. 1 The reason of this strange phenomenon is 
 found, partly in the very gifts of the nature itself, partly in the 
 external advantages, so called, which it usually commands. 2 
 Driven by the native force of genius, it cannot rest in the 
 narrow conventionalities of common opinion. 3 But its un- 
 quenchable thirst for what is real, its far-reaching vision, its 
 magnificent aspirations, find no true satisfaction or guidance. 
 The atmosphere in which it lives is public opinion, speaking 
 through its hired mouth-pieces, who think themselves its 
 leaders ; loud, exaggerated, irresistible, intolerant of principles, 
 and confident in facts, which are really nothing but the dictates 
 of its own caprice. 4 What can save a great nature in such an 
 atmosphere, especially if his force of mind be supplemented by 
 beauty and strength, wealth and connections ? His power is 
 flattered by venal servility,his ambition spoiled by easy triumphs; 
 he feels the world within his grasp. And if some wiser man 
 whisper in his ear the hard truth that he is living the life 
 of a fool, how should he listen ? Or if his better genius chance 
 to make him listen, how should he escape the clutches of the 
 parasites, who had looked forward to living upon his success ? 
 So it is that the philosophic nature is corrupted, and sinks to a 
 life unworthy of itself, while philosophy, deserted by her true 
 kinsmen, falls a victim to any jackanapes who can afford to de- 
 spise his own profession, and bears in this enforced and unnatural 
 union the wretched bastards who go about the world bearing 
 her name, and bringing shame upon their mother. 5 Only here 
 and there, by some exceptional circumstance, ill-health perhaps, 
 or banishment, or pride, or possibly an inward and inexplicable 
 monition, a man of the true stuff is kept back from public life 
 and saved for philosophy ; and those poor few can do nothing 
 better than stand aside out of the storm of the world, happy if 
 they can live without sin and die in hope. 6 Such is Plato's 
 
 1 6. 487 e. 2 6. 491 b-c. 
 
 3 6. 490 a, OVK eiri^vot, iirl TO?S Sofafo/tt^ots elvai TroXXots ^/cdaTots. 
 
 4 C. 491 d 495 c. 6 6. 495 c 496 a. 6 6. 496 a 497 a.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 139 
 
 indictment against the society in which he was living. " No 
 one of the forms of constitution now existing is worthy of 
 the philosophic nature. Therefore it is changed and distorted, 
 and as a seed sown in a strange soil will lose its virtue and 
 become a victim to the influences amongst which it lives, so 
 in the present state of things this kind of soul does not keep its 
 force, but falls away to a nature not its own. But if it can 
 find a form of society good enough for it, then men will see that 
 it was always really divine, and that all else in their nature 
 and ways of life is human only." 1 
 
 It is then in the interests of society, whether we regard 
 them as endangered by want of real knowledge, or by the 
 neglect and corruption of its noblest natures, that Plato finds 
 a further education to be necessary ; and the question is, 
 firstly, How did he conceive of the higher kind of appre- 
 hension which he called knowledge and the higher form of 
 object which he called truth, and by what means did he think 
 that the mind might be educated to the knowledge of such 
 truth ? and secondly, How did he hope to avoid the dangers 
 attendant on the philosophic nature, and to make it an instru- 
 ment of salvation instead of destruction to society? These two 
 questions were to Plato really one ; for in his view the dominant 
 impulse of the philosophic nature is the impulse to know the 
 truth, and to know the truth of things is to know the reason of 
 them, and to know their reason completely would be to see 
 them as convergent parts in a whole governed by a single end, 
 or, in Platonic language, a single " good ;" so that ultimately to 
 know the truth of the world would be to know " the good" of 
 the world, or the " reason why " of its existence, and to under- 
 stand human life thoroughly would be to see the end or pur- 
 pose which governs it in the light of that larger end or purpose 
 which makes the whole universe luminous and intelligible. 
 Thus the true interests of society coincide with those of its 
 highest natures ; for the study of what the good of man is and 
 requires, is the best way of satisfying the best impulse of those 
 natures, and the same process which develops the philosophic 
 mind to its highest pitch, and makes a man a true philosopher, 
 
 1 6. 497 b-c.
 
 140 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 will bring it also to the knowledge of the principles which 
 should guide human conduct, and will make a man a true 
 statesman. Thus the question with Plato comes to be, What 
 is the education by which the human mind may be brought 
 nearer to that truth which is at once the keystone of know- 
 ledge and the pole-star of conduct ? And this question is most 
 instructively treated under three heads, firstly, What is the 
 nature of intellectual progress ? the answer to which will give 
 us a scale of knowledge and truth up which education should 
 lead the mind ; secondly, What is the nature and cause of 
 human ignorance, which keeps the mind from thus advancing ? 
 and thirdly, What are the specific means by which this 
 ignorance may be removed, and the inherent capacity of the 
 mind developed and regulated ? The last only of these ques- 
 tions concerns education directly ; but just as in the case of the 
 earlier education of character it was impossible to understand 
 Plato without considering the constituent elements out of 
 which the character had to be formed, so in order to make 
 intelligible his account of the later education of reason, it is 
 indispensable to consider in a general way how he conceived 
 the activity and sphere of reason, in other words, knowledge 
 arid truth. And further, as Plato's manner of developing a 
 view by antagonism to an existing state of things is nowhere 
 more forcibly illustrated than in his treatment of this part of 
 his subject, we should be throwing away the half of our infor- 
 mation if, in examining the ideal of knowledge at which he 
 aimed, we neglected his picture of the ignorance from which he 
 wished to escape. 
 
 At the end of the sixth book of the Republic 1 Plato gives 
 us, under the figure of a line divided into four parts, a series of 
 the objects of mental apprehension, and of the mental operations 
 which correspond to them, arranged in an ascending order of 
 clearness and truth. At the bottom of the scale of objects he 
 places what he calls " images," and at the bottom of the scale 
 of mental activities the " perception of images." By " images " 
 he understands primarily shadows and reflections, but he seems 
 also to include under the term any perceivable object which 
 
 '6. 509 d 511 e.
 
 IN THE RE TUB LIC OE PLATO. 141 
 
 reproduces or suggests another in the same kind of way that 
 shadows and reflections suggest and reproduce the things which 
 occasion them. Thus all works of art may be called, more or 
 less appropriately, " images," for it is common to them all to 
 represent how things appear, or what they suggest to sense or 
 imagination, by means of words, sounds, colour, or form, which, 
 however directly related to the things, cannot be identified 
 with them. 1 This is of course far from being a full account of 
 what the arts do ; but they all do at least this, and Plato, for 
 reasons which we shall presently see, chose to emphasise this 
 characteristic of artistic representation, and to class together 
 indiscriminately all objects of perception to which it is common. 
 Judged then by the standard of clearness and truth, the lowest 
 kind of perception is that which perceives merely shadows, 
 reflections, or analogous images, of things, whatever the 
 medium through which the image is conveyed. The Greek 
 substantive (el/cacrla) used by Plato to describe this " perception 
 of images," means literally the act of making one thing like 
 another. The corresponding verb, besides the corresponding 
 sense of copying or imitating, is commonly used in the sense of 
 "conjecturing," apparently because one of the most obvious 
 forms of conjecture is an inference drawn from comparing, that 
 is, mentally " making like," one thing to another. No doubt 
 this double association of the verb recommended the substan- 
 tive to Plato's use; for it enabled him conveniently to 
 characterise the lowest stage of perception, not merely as a 
 perception of "images," but also as having only a "conjectural" 
 certitude. 2 It is obvious that if we compare the knowledge 
 about an object or an event derived from a picture or a descrip- 
 tion, with the knowledge of a person who has seen the object 
 or been present at the event, the former is not only more 
 indirect and superficial than the latter, but the certainty which 
 we are justified in feeling about it is also less. 
 
 It would seem to be in relation to the last-mentioned sense 
 
 1 Cf. 10. 599 a ; 605 c ; 3. 402 b-c ; 7. 517 d, where the "shadows of 
 images " would be, e.g., the representation or misrepresentation of the existing 
 laws (themselves only " images " of justice) by a rhetorician or pleader. 
 
 2 See 7. 516 c-d, for an application of elKaala in the sense of " conjecture."
 
 1 4 2 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 of eltcaa-id that Plato calls the next stage in the scale of know- 
 ledge 7T/crTi9, " belief " or " conviction." Here, as in the former 
 case, when the word has so many associations, it is important 
 to seize the particular one which Plato apparently intended to 
 convey. The objects of " belief," he says, are the things of 
 which the images of the first stage are resemblances, in other 
 words, what are ordinarily understood by " real things." The 
 differences in the mental state of a man whose knowledge con- 
 sists in " images " and that of one whose knowledge is derived 
 from personal contact are many, but the one which is 
 emphasised by Plato for his present purpose is that the latter, 
 besides being more clear and true, is also more certain. 1 
 
 The two kinds of mental objects and operations just described, 
 while they differ from one another in important respects, have 
 certain other important points in common when both compared 
 with a higher stage of knowledge ; and they are accordingly 
 comprised by Plato under the single generic name of Soa, or, 
 as it is usually translated, " opinion." 2 Neither the Greek word 
 nor its English equivalent, in their ordinary usage, gives any 
 indication of the special meaning which Plato here intended 
 to express. The characteristic marks of what he chooses to 
 call " opinion " are the following : subjectively, it is a state of 
 mind which carries with it no guarantee either of truth or per- 
 manence; it may be either true or false 3 (whereas what we 
 understand by " knowledge " must be true), and it is liable to 
 be changed or lost 4 (whereas when we really know a truth once 
 we know it always) ; objectively, it relates to a matter which is 
 given in forms of sense, and which is manifold, particular, and 
 relative. 5 An illustration will best explain Plato's meaning. 
 A man has " opinion " about justice or beauty or weight or 
 size; that is, he "thinks" that certain things are just or beauti- 
 ful, heavy or large. His thought may be more or less positive 
 according to his nature and circumstances, but however posi- 
 tive he may feel, he cannot use " thinking " as equivalent to 
 "knowing." If asked, What is justice? What is heaviness? 
 he will probably answer by pointing to this or that instance of 
 
 1 Cf . 10. 601 e 602 b. 2 7. 534 a. 3 5. 477 e ; cf. Theaetetus, 187 b. 
 
 * 3. 412 e ; cf. 6. 508 d ; and Meno, 97 e 98 a. 5 5. 476 a 480 a.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 143 
 
 what he means ; justice perhaps will be to him bound up with 
 certain particular laws, actions, or persons, heaviness with 
 certain particular materials. The respective aggregates of these 
 particular instances will make up his conceptions ; justice is to 
 him this aggregate, and nothing more. But now, suppose the 
 actions or institutions in which his conception of justice was 
 embodied to be done under different circumstances or worked 
 under different conditions, they may very likely appear to be 
 unjust instead of just. And similarly the materials with which 
 alone he associated heaviness will seem light and not heavy 
 when put alongside of materials which are heavier. The matter 
 of " opinion," then, whether it be moral or aesthetic, mathemati- 
 cal or physical (for in this respect there is no difference), is, 
 firstly, " manifold," consisting of a number of sensible or 
 imaginable objects ; and secondly, it is " particular " and 
 " relative," for each of its constituents depends for its character 
 upon its own particular position, and changes its character as 
 its relative position changes. And it is clear that these charac- 
 teristics belong equally to the matter in question, whether it be 
 apprehended directly in actual sensible experience, or indirectly 
 through an artistic or other medium. The condition of mind 
 thus characterised is that of the majority of people on most 
 subjects, and of all people on many subjects. 1 What we com- 
 monly call our knowledge, except where we may have made a 
 special study in a special direction, is either derived from the 
 representation of other men, or from our own casual and limited 
 observation of the particular objects with which we happen to 
 have come in contact. On the other hand, though the mind 
 is for the most part content to remain in this condition, there 
 are occasions on which it is conscious of its unsatisfactoriness. 
 This must be the case, for instance, as soon as it begins to see 
 that the sensible qualities of things, which it supposed to be 
 fixed and absolute, are after all variable and relative, and that 
 the same thing seems to have opposite attributes according 
 as its position is changed. This relativity, which is inherent 
 in the matter of sensation, whether in the physical or moral 
 world, is one of the first difficulties which stimulates thought or 
 
 1 5. 479 d, rd. ruv iro\\wv TroAXd, v6/M(M.. ]
 
 144 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 reflection. 1 The same thing seems to be both light and heavy, 
 both just and unjust ; how can this be ? Are then light- 
 ness and heaviness, justice and injustice, one and the same ? 
 To suppose this is to give the lie to one's own consciousness. 
 The dilemma forces the mind to advance and to analyse further 
 this perplexing matter of sensation, which, instead of the clear and 
 permanent thing which it seemed to be, has become a " confused" 
 centre of contradictory and fluctuating attributes. 2 To detect 
 distinctions in this confusion, to ask, What then really is weight ? 
 What then really is justice? and to distinguish finally the 
 object of sense, with its capacity of developing contradictions 
 and of " playing double," 3 from the object of thought which can 
 be fixed and defined, these are the further steps which reflection 
 takes, and with these we have left the domain of " opinion" and 
 entered upon that of science. And this brings us to the next 
 stage in the Platonic scale of mental objects and activities. 
 
 When we reflect upon the meaning of "knowledge" or 
 " science " (for the Greek word is the same for both), it seems 
 incongruous to apply it to a state of mind which is liable to 
 error, or to an object-matter which is liable to change. We 
 cannot say that we "know" what justice is, if the embodiments 
 of our conception may become unjust by a change of relations, 
 any more than we could say that we " knew " what a triangle 
 was, supposing that we found that the properties of triangles as 
 such varied with the size, colour, or position of the particular 
 figures of which we demonstrated them. This, however, is just 
 what we do not find ; we conceive that a triangle is always and 
 everywhere a triangle, that once known it is always known : 
 and in this belief we speak of geometrical science or knowledge, 
 which we distinguish from our ordinary state of mind on ordinary 
 subjects. What we only "think" or "believe" is scattered 
 about in a number of separate objects ; what we " know " is one, 
 and only one, however many may be the instances in which we 
 perceive its truth. What we only " think," depends for its 
 character or validity upon its particular form or environment, 
 and changes with them ; what we " know " is independent of 
 its particular presentation, and remains true under all apparent 
 
 1 7. 523 a 524 d. 2 ffvyKfxv^vov n, 524 c. 8 fira^orepl^eiv, 5. 479 c.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 145 
 
 changes. The state of mind thus distinguished from " opinion" 
 is what is commonly understood by " scientific/' and as the 
 only sciences which could be said to exist in Plato's time were 
 mathematical, he took mathematics as the type of the third 
 stage in his scale of knowledge, though his characterisation of 
 them would equally apply to all sciences ordinarily so called. 
 The geometrician, Plato says, 1 uses sensible figures in his reason- 
 ing, but does not really think of them. What he really has in 
 his thought is not the particular triangle which he draws on 
 paper, but the " triangle itself," which the one on paper " is like" 
 or " is an image of." Similarly we might say of the botanist 
 or political economist, that in proportion as their subject-matter 
 has reached a scientific stage, they ignore the particular modifi- 
 cations under which it is presented to them, and see through 
 these to the essential forms or laws of which they are symbols. 
 In doing this they have no more doubt than has the geometri- 
 cian, that they are nearer to the truth than if they allowed 
 themselves to attend to nothing but the particular circum- 
 stances of the place or the moment. Whatever popular pre- 
 judices may be violated by the scientific mode of thought, and 
 whatever metaphysical difficulties may be raised by the assump- 
 tion of degrees of reality, the best minds are practically, if 
 not theoretically, convinced that there is a difference between 
 " thinking " and " knowing," and that in the latter they are 
 more in conformity with what is real than in the former. 
 
 The word ^avoia, which Plato 2 appropriated to the form of 
 mental activity just described, had no more fixed connotation 
 in ordinary Greek usage than such English words as " thought," 
 " intellect," " understanding." We have seen what was the par- 
 ticular meaning which he wished to convey by it, namely, that 
 the next step in the scale of clearness and truth above the mere 
 certainty of opinion, is that in which the mind, while employing 
 sensible objects, is really occupied with something of which 
 they are only symbols or images. It is necessary to dwell at a 
 little more length upon Plato's conception of the distinction 
 here involved, which plays such a vital part in his theory of 
 education and knowledge. The opposition between sense and 
 
 1 6. 510 cl-e. 2 6. 511 d ; 7. 534 a.
 
 146 THE THEOR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 thought in various forms had attracted the attention of Greek 
 thinkers from the earliest times. The apparent arbitrariness 
 and fluctuation, both of our physical sensations and of our moral 
 ideas, were continually contrasting themselves with the fixity 
 and substantiality which the simplest conception of knowledge 
 and the most rudimentary moral distinctions alike seem to 
 presuppose. The necessity for immutable principles, if the 
 world of -nature and human life is to be explained, impressed 
 itself upon Plato with all the greater force that he seems to 
 have realised with peculiar vividness the mutability of much 
 which ordinary experience pronounces permanent. To the 
 element of reality which his mind discovered or surmised 
 everywhere behind the appearance and change which sensation 
 shows us, he gave the name of " form." It is a curious instance 
 of the changes of fortune in the life of language, that the Greek 
 word " idea," which Plato chose to express what is most pro- 
 foundly real, and least dependent on the human mind for its 
 reality, should have come to be used for a mere mental creation 
 or fiction, and that its English equivalent " form " is now mainly 
 suggestive of what is superficial and unsubstantial. The his- 
 tory of the word in Greek speculation before its employment 
 by Plato is very slight ; we can only conjecture that to a Greek, 
 peculiarly organised for the perception of shape, and accus- 
 tomed to find significant and typical lines in all that he saw, it 
 was a natural transition from what is outwardly and visibly 
 characteristic to what is inwardly and theoretically essential. 
 Every people, like every individual thinker, has its favourite 
 metaphors for expressing ultimate philosophical conceptions. 
 In the phraseology of Greek philosophy there is no pheno- 
 menon of which we are more constantly reminded than that 
 of vision, and the use of the word " form " by Plato is only the 
 most pregnant and far-reaching instance of a metaphor which, 
 in the way of analogy, simile, or suggestion, pervades his 
 speculation. We have here only to indicate in the briefest and 
 most general way the meaning of the Platonic conception of 
 " form," so far as it enters into the theory of knowledge and 
 education. It may be said to combine elements of all the 
 modern conceptions of essence, law, and ideal. Those qualities 
 or characteristics in a thing which most make it what it is, and
 
 AV THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 147 
 
 which contrast with others that are casual and separable, are 
 the " form " which characterises and individualises the thing. 
 That principle which gives consistency and continuity to 
 changing manifestations of activity, is the " form " which works 
 itself out in a plastic material. And once more : the aim or 
 mark to which the various steps in a process converge is the 
 " form " to which the agent in the process looks, and which he- 
 strives to attain. So that alike in art, in science, in morality, 
 it is the " form " which is essential and important, the " form " 
 which the imagination discerns through the chaos of sense- 
 impressions, the " form " which the reason separates from the 
 accidental conditions of time and place, and the " form " in 
 which the moral consciousness finds rest and guidance amidst 
 the distractions and contradictions of experience. 
 
 Plato has various ways of expressing the mode in which the 
 " form " exists, and is apprehended. It is that which really 
 " is," as opposed to that which " seems ; " that which is " one," 
 as opposed to that which is " many ; " that which is self- 
 identical and permanent, as opposed to that which is always 
 becoming something else. Or, again, the sensible world is only 
 the " appearance " of the intelligible ; the things which we see 
 and hear are " images," that only " resemble " and suggest some- 
 thing which we cannot see or hear ; and each of these images 
 or resemblances only " participates in," but does not adequately 
 embody, the reality which is grasped in and over it. The vivid 
 and sometimes crude manner in which Plato represents the 
 relationship between what is and what is not "form," has 
 given rise to much misunderstanding of him as well as to many 
 real difficulties, and has left a doubt whether he had himself 
 clearly apprehended what he was endeavouring to express. 
 The truth seems to be that no great genius, "stung by 
 the splendour of a sudden thought," can ever work out or even 
 conceive his idea with the coolness and completeness which are 
 necessary to make it consistently intelligible and to guard it 
 from misinterpretation. But we are here concerned, not with 
 the exaggerations and confusions, real or supposed, to which 
 Plato fell a victim, but with the central truth which he saw 
 clearly, and to which he held tenaciously. 
 
 Returning now to the scale of knowledge, we see that
 
 148 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 whether we regard the sense of unsatisfactoriness which impels 
 the mind to advance upon sensible opinion, or the intellectual 
 condition in which that impulse results, it is what Plato 
 understands by " forms," for which the mind is looking, and in 
 which it rests. The mathematical sciences, which spring from, 
 and are the answer to, questions raised by the mathematical pro- 
 perties of sensible objects, take account, not of the particular 
 figures to which they refer, but of the "objects themselves," 
 of which those figures are only the "images;" these "objects 
 themselves" are clearly what we have learnt to know as "forms." 
 Though, however, it is about the " form " of the triangle or of 
 unity that the geometrician and arithmetician really reason, not 
 about the figures on the paper, they cannot dispense with those 
 figures. They exercise intelligence, but intelligence which still 
 has an appendage of sense, and is not therefore perfectly 
 intelligent. And along with this imperfection in the know- 
 ledge of which mathematics are a type, goes another one which 
 Plato expresses by saying that such knowledge is "assump- 
 tive " or " hypothetical." " Geometricians, arithmeticians, and 
 the like, assume the odd, the even, the figures, the three kinds 
 of angle, and other similar things, according to the particular 
 branch of the science with which they are dealing ; these they 
 assume themselves to know, and make them hypotheses, and 
 do not think themselves bound to give any further account of 
 them either to themselves or others ; they suppose every one to 
 see the truth of them. From these hypotheses they start, and 
 when they have got this start they go on through the remain- 
 ing steps, and arrive conclusively at the result which was the 
 original object of their inquiry." l Such a procedure does not 
 satisfy the full conception of knowledge or science ; for " when 
 the starting-point of the argument is something assumed and 
 not known, and the end and intermediate steps depend for 
 their connection upon this unknown starting-point, how can 
 such a conclusion possibly constitute knowledge ? " 2 By 
 "hypotheses," then, Plato understands, not assumptions tem- 
 porarily made for certain definite purposes, but truths which, 
 while really depending for their validity upon their connection 
 
 1 6. 510 c-d; 511 d. a 7. 533 c.
 
 IN THE RE 'PUBLIC OF PLATO. 149 
 
 with higher truths, are treated as if they were independent of 
 that connection, and self-proven. In this sense, each one of 
 the " forms " of existence with which the special sciences are 
 concerned, number, figure, motion, etc., is a "hypothesis;" 
 the special sciences are scientific so far as they follow logically 
 from these " hypotheses " which form their principles, but so 
 far as those principles themselves are not, strictly speaking, 
 " known," they do not satisfy the ideal requirements of science. 
 For science to Plato means explanation and intelligibility ; we 
 "know" a truth when we can "give account of" it, and the 
 way in which we give account of it is by showing its necessary 
 connection with wider and more independent truths. Progress 
 in science is progress from isolated to connected thought ; and 
 if we try to imagine such a progress consummated, we are led 
 to the conception of a universal science, in which every part is 
 seen in its relation to every other part, and of which the whole 
 forms a perfect orb of truth, beginning and ending in itself. 
 Of such a science, as it might be if the speculative impulse of the 
 human mind were fully satisfied, Plato has given us a picture, 1 
 though he is conscious that it is only a picture, and that to 
 realise what he is imagining is " a flight above " 2 both himself 
 and his readers. The whole matter of knowledge is imaged as 
 a perfectly graduated scale of the essential " forms " of exist- 
 ence ; each " form " is seen to be, not an ultimate truth, but a 
 " hypothesis," depending for its truth upon one above it ; the 
 mind mounts from " form " to " form," using each as a " point 
 of departure " to the next, until it reaches the topmost " un- 
 hypothetical principle," upon which the whole chain hangs, and 
 from which it can descend again securely down the ladder of 
 intelligible reality. In such a perfect system of knowledge, as 
 there would be nothing " hypothetical " or unproven, so there 
 would be no element of sense or unintelligibility. The 
 symbolism of sensible appearances, which suggest imperfectly 
 something which they are not, and blur the intellectual vision 
 with an unexplained residuum, would melt into the perfect 
 transparency of reason, when mind met mind face to face. 
 We have thus reached the highest stage in the Platonic 
 
 1 6. 511 b-c. 2 6. 506 e ; cf. 7. 532 e 533 a.
 
 1 5 o THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 scale of mental development, that stage to which he applies 
 emphatically the name of '' knowledge," and the object-matter 
 of which is the essential " forms " of existence without 
 admixture of hypothesis or sense. Like the preceding stage, 
 it represents an inherent impulse in the mind ; but, unlike it, 
 it leaves the impulse in the main unfulfilled. The different 
 specific sciences owe their existence to the dissatisfaction occa- 
 sioned to the mind by reflection upon its sensible experience. 
 This dissatisfaction they remove by revealing permanent and 
 consistent " forms " in what before seemed a fluctuating chaos ; 
 but it still survives in the sense of incompleteness and limita- 
 tion which the mind feels, when it finds that each science rests 
 upon an unproven basis and points beyond itself for the 
 ultimate establishment of its conclusions. The force or 
 faculty in virtue of which the mind is perpetually trying to 
 rid itself of this dissatisfaction, to get out of the region of 
 " hypotheses," and to see truth as a whole of parts, is called 
 by Plato the " dialectical " faculty, 1 and the ideal science which 
 the completed exercise of that faculty might be conceived to 
 create, is the " science of dialectic," the only form of science 
 or knowledge which seemed to him strictly to deserve the 
 name. 2 The term " dialectic," which plays almost as con- 
 spicuous a part in the Platonic philosophy as " form," means 
 originally nothing more than the process of oral discussion by 
 question and answer. Naturally a prominent and familiar 
 word among a people where ideas were communicated so 
 much more by talking than by reading, and specially con- 
 secrated to Plato by the example of his master Socrates, it was 
 adopted by him to describe the process by which the mind 
 endeavours to arrive at true conceptions, whether by actual 
 verbal discussion or by inward " dialogue with itself." And as 
 Plato conceived that the truth exists in a certain form or order, 
 and that the human mind in learning and apprehending it 
 must conform to that order, he naturally used " dialectic " for 
 that particular mode of manipulating language and thought 
 which seemed to him most consonant with truth, and most 
 fitted to lead to its discovery. What that mode must be we 
 
 1 7. 533 a ; cf. ib. c, and 532 a. 2 7. 533 c-e.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 151 
 
 have already had some indication. If the only conception of 
 reality which satisfied Plato was that of a cosmos which is 
 neither a vacant unity nor a crowded chaos, but a reasonable 
 system of interrelated elements, the only true logic or method of 
 knowledge must seem to him to be that which obeys the two- 
 fold requirement arising from such a conception, a method which 
 unifies without confounding, which specifies without separating, 
 a method which does not " break the limbs " of truth, 1 but 
 follows and reveals the natural articulations of its subject- 
 matter till it has reached the perception of its organic unity. 
 Such a method is the true " dialectic," the only true method of 
 learning, teaching, and investigating, because the only method 
 which is in agreement with the inherent constitution of the 
 real world. And if the method be supposed to have been 
 carried through to the utmost verge of truth, the moving 
 process passes into a completed result, and dialectic, instead of a 
 logic of discovery and definition, becomes the living expression 
 of the truth itself, the embodied logic of reality. Plato has 
 nowhere filled up the outline of his conception of " dialectic ; " 
 but the greater part of his dialogues are practical illustrations 
 of the principle, and the suggestions of a theory which are 
 scattered up and down them are often more instructive as well 
 as more stimulating than the finished systems of other men. 
 
 We have now seen how Plato conceived the natural order 
 in the ascent of the mind towards truth. It begins by seeing 
 things " darkly," through the uncertain " glass " of fancy ; it 
 goes on to the certainty of direct sensible experience ; from the 
 objects of sense and opinion, with their local and temporal 
 limitations, it advances to the perception of essential " forms " 
 and principles, which those objects symbolise or suggest ; and 
 from the understanding of isolated principles and their conse- 
 quences it passes to the apprehension of them as steps in a 
 connected scale of existence. We have next to ask, How far 
 does the human mind actually obey this principle of progress ? 
 What is the actual state and opinion of mankind as regards its 
 " education," in the fuller sense in which we have now come to 
 use the word ? Plato has expressed his views upon this sub- 
 
 1 Pkaedrus, 265 e.
 
 152 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 ject in the famous allegory of the cave, with which the seventh 
 book of the Republic opens. The allegory to be understood 
 and appreciated must be studied in its entirety. A few only 
 of its main features need be dwelt upon here. Mankind in 
 general, Plato gives us to understand, so far from advancing up 
 the road which leads to truth and light, remain for the most 
 part during their whole life in the state of mind which is only 
 fit for children. They are like men sitting bound at the bottom 
 of a cave, lit by a fire to which their backs are turned, able 
 only to look straight before them at the wall of their prison. 
 The living world of nature and man lies behind them, and all 
 that they know of it are its shadows and echoes, the hazy, 
 unsubstantial, artificial reproductions of the minds of other 
 men. At this moving world of phantasms they stare, and 
 in its reality they believe, with all the fixity and fervour of 
 men who have done a thing from their childhood. They watch 
 its vain shows as they pass and repass, observe the order of 
 their succession, and formulate a conjectural science which is 
 to enable them to predict the future. From this condition 
 there is for most men no escape, for they do not know, and 
 therefore cannot desire, any other sort of existence. Only now 
 and then, by some force of nature or circumstances, a prisoner 
 is set free from his chains, made to stand on his feet and look 
 round, to see with his own eyes, and hear with his own ears, 
 and step by step, perhaps, to make his way to the upper air 
 and the sunlight of knowledge. But each stage in the process 
 is grievous to him ; the first experience of actual life confuses 
 him, and makes him wish for his old world of fancy again, and 
 the sudden revelation of scientific truth dazzles his mind, 
 which is only used to empirical certitude. Only by slow 
 degrees he gets an insight into the principles which really 
 govern the world, and the supreme principle upon which they 
 all depend ; and if in compassion for the ignorance of man- 
 kind he tries to teach them his new knowledge, he is received 
 with ridicule and opposition, which in the end may cost him 
 his life. 
 
 Philosophy, like religion, has often begun by calling upon 
 men to get rid of their prejudices and illusions. It is custo- 
 mary, indeed, to look upon the two as antagonistic, and to con-
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 153 
 
 trast the humility required by the Gospel with the supposed 
 arrogance and self-sufficiency of the philosophic spirit. Yet 
 if we take men so different, and so representative in their 
 differences, as Plato, Bacon, and Spinoza, we find them all 
 agreeing, not in a glorification of the human mind, but in the 
 imperative demand that it should shake off its " chains " and 
 turn to receive the light, that it should surrender its " idols " 
 and " become as a little child," that it should look at things 
 " under the form of eternity," not through the vague confusion 
 of its own imagination. To all alike, however different their 
 phraseology and their motive, the conviction is common, that 
 there is an order of existence or of nature which man does not 
 make but finds, which he must wait upon and not forestall, if 
 he would attain to the wellbeiug, the power, or the freedom, 
 of which he is capable. 
 
 Passing from these common features to the details of Plato's 
 conception of human ignorance, we do not find him, like Bacon, 
 giving any classification of the false " shadows and images," but 
 we can gather many hints as to their nature. Primarily they 
 are the dim, exaggerated, and shallow representations of things 
 through the medium of art, literature, and rhetoric. 1 In ex- 
 plaining Plato's antipathy to dramatic representation, we have 
 already had occasion to notice some of his attacks upon art in 
 general. Those attacks seem to be valid if, and so far as, 
 artistic representation produces actual illusion, and substitutes 
 appearance for reality. To a mind which is really fitted by 
 nature and education to receive art in the spirit of art, illusion, so 
 far from being a necessary element in aesthetic enjoyment, is a 
 distinct bar to it. A person who looks at a play exactly as if 
 it were real life may be vehemently moved for a moment, but 
 will eventually find the spectacle either so exciting or so 
 wearisome that he will wish to interrupt it or to go away. It 
 is essential to the perfect reception of artistic effect that the 
 impulse to action should be in abeyance, and the theoretic 
 faculties at their fullest activity. The after-effect may issue in 
 acts, but at the moment of seeing, or hearing, or reading, the 
 work of art, considered as such, demands that " wise passive- 
 
 1 Cf. 7. 517 d-e ; 10. 600 e 602 b ; 605 c.
 
 1 5 4 THE THE OR Y OF ED I 'CA 7 ION 
 
 ness " which is only the other side of theoretic energy. But 
 there are comparatively few imaginative persons in whom the 
 double power of self-control and self-surrender, of entering in 
 and yet of standing outside, is so strong that they " cannot 
 choose but " hear or see. To most of us the message of art 
 awakens a cross echo in our own selves, and we go away with 
 the flattering feeling that the vapours or the rhetoric of egoism 
 are the universal types or tones of genius and truth. Then it is 
 that the artist, often without knowing it, and against his will, 
 becomes "a mimic and a juggler" to the public; 1 the spirit 
 distilled in the crucible of imagination gets cloyed with the 
 lees of prejudice or sentiment ; and the " impassioned expres- 
 sion, which is in the countenance of all science," stiffens into a 
 masquerade which can " deceive children and fools." 2 
 
 The " shadows and echoes " amongst which Plato's prisoners 
 live are not, however, only the illusions, intentional or un- 
 intentional, produced by art and literature ; they are also the 
 illusions of our own passions. It would be a great mistake to 
 regard the darkness of the cave as a mere darkness of intellec- 
 tual ignorance, or the escape from it as a mere intellectual 
 enlightenment. In the mind of Plato, reason is never for long 
 dissociated from emotion, or knowledge from purpose; the 
 highest impulse to him is the impulse towards truth, and the 
 highest knowledge is knowledge of the end of action. Thus 
 the great reason why the spark of "divine" 3 intelligence is so 
 nearly smothered in man is not primarily the difficulty of 
 learning or the mysteriousness of nature ; the fetters which 
 bind the men in the cave are those " leaden weights which the 
 pleasures of gluttony and the like gather round them, and 
 which turn the eye of the soul to the earth." 4 The " impulse " 
 which, if it had sway, 5 would carry the soul out of the " sea " 
 of earthly life, to union with " the divine, immortal, and 
 eternal " to which it is " akin," is checked and thwarted by no 
 irresistible necessity or power of evil, but by the " shells and 
 stones and tangle" with which the "delights of the table" 
 gradually incrust it. The " painted images of true pleasure," 6 
 
 1 10. 598 d. 2 10. 598 c. 3 7. 518 e. 
 
 4 7. 519 b. 10. 611 c 612 a. 6 9. 586 a c.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 155 
 
 with which men choose to dwell, are the offspring of their own 
 nature, which leads them about " like cattle, with their heads 
 down and eyes fixed upon their dinners, feeding and breeding, 
 and kicking and butting one another because they cannot get 
 enough." It is not the thought of " this unsubstantial pageant " 
 which leads Plato like Shakespeare to call human life a 
 ' dream ;" l rather it is the same feeling as that of Lucretius 
 when he cries to man, 
 
 " Qui somno partera majorem conteris aevi, 
 Et vigilans stertis nee somnia cernere cessas." 
 
 It is because men will not rouse themselves to the reality 
 which is there if they had the eyes to see it, because they 
 mistake the passing shows of sense for the eternal essence of 
 which they are the mere outside, because they " fight about 
 shadows " of power and clutch after " phantoms of good," that 
 " before they are well awake in this world they find themselves 
 in the other, sleeping the heavy sleep of death." 2 
 
 " How then " (and this is the third and last part of our 
 question) " are men to be led up to the light, as some are said 
 to have gone up from Hades to dwell with the gods in heaven ?" 3 
 Or, as we may also put it (for it is upon progress in knowledge 
 that the good of mankind depends), " what kind of studies and 
 practice will produce the men who are to save society ? " * Or, 
 once more (for the interest of society is ultimately identical 
 with that of its noblest natures), " how is the commonwealth 
 to handle philosophy so as not to be destroyed by it ?" 5 Clearly 
 it is important that society should look to it ; that her greatest 
 sons, instead of being criminals or outcasts, who owe their 
 mother nothing for their bringing up, should be bound to her 
 by ties of mutual obligation. 6 The principle of justice which 
 regulates other spheres of life ought to hold good here too ; 
 the man who has the philosophic faculty should not be allowed 
 to do what he likes with it ; 7 he should be induced to contribute 
 his share to the common good, and to help in " binding the 
 commonwealth together," while his fellows should do for him 
 
 1 7. 520 c ; 5. 476 c-tl ; cf. Timaeus, 52 b-c. 
 
 2 7. 534 c-d. 3 7. 521 c. 4 6. 502 d. 
 
 6 6. 497 d. 6 7. 520 b. ' 7. 519 e 520 a.
 
 1 5 6 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 what he cannot do for himself, provide him with the neces- 
 sary material of life and supply his soul with the nurture which 
 it demands. The general character, then, of the duty of society 
 is clear : it has to find a way for doing methodically and with 
 the greatest possible ease what now takes place exceptionally 
 by the force of circumstances and under almost insuperable 
 obstacles. Arid the general character of the education which 
 shall do this is also clear : it must be an education which will 
 help the soul to " see " the truth, to penetrate the darkness 
 which fancy and appetite spread between it and facts, to follow 
 its own " divine impulse," and to shake off the fetters of its 
 own forging. Some " professors of education," l indeed, talk as 
 if the soul were like a blind eye and teaching were " putting 
 sight into it." But the truth is that the " eye of the soul," the 
 " organ with which it learns and understands," is not like the 
 eye of the body. The latter is more or less independent of the 
 rest of the organism, and can be moved without it ; but the 
 former can only be " turned to the light " if the whole soul be 
 turned with it. The soul is not in pieces, but continuous; 
 knowledge in the highest sense is not an independent act of a 
 part of the self, but that union of the whole witfrtruth, in which 
 the lower parts are taken up into the higher according to their 
 capacities. 2 It is not possible to be habitually living the life of 
 the lower elements, and to keep the higher at their greatest 
 efficiency. Evil is the " disease " of the soul, 3 and to be or do 
 evil and still expect to exercise the highest psychical activity is 
 as reasonable as it would be, if body cured body by contact, to 
 expect the most diseased body to be the best healer. It is 
 from this point of view that Plato denies the possibility of 
 getting to know the real nature of evil by personally experienc- 
 ing it ; the very experience which is to be the object of know- 
 ledge spoils the instrument by which it is to be known. The 
 "whole" soul then must be turned to the light, for the " eye of 
 the soul " is the highest element in it, and carries with it the 
 other elements. 
 
 In another respect also the mental is unlike the bodily 
 vision. The bodily eye may lose its power of sight and have it 
 
 1 7. 518 b-c. 2 9. 586 e. 3 4. 444 e 445 b ; 3. 409 a-e.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 157 
 
 restored to it again, but the analogous faculty in the mind can 
 neither be created nor destroyed ; " the other virtues of the 
 soul, as they are called, seem to be nearly akin to those of the 
 body, for they are not originally in existence, but are an after 
 product of habit and practice ; but the virtue of intelligence 
 seems to belong to something altogether more divine, something 
 which never loses its force, but is made serviceable or unser- 
 viceable, helpful or harmful, according as it is turned to the 
 light or not." l The power of mental insight still remains active 
 in the warped soul of the clever scoundrel ; it is the divine and 
 immortal part in the soul, that which makes it "capable of 
 bearing all good things," 2 but capable also of bearing " all evil 
 things ;" it may be " buried in the mud" of ignorance or over- 
 grown with the " incrustations " of passion, but it is never so 
 lost that it cannot be lifted up, purged, and re-illumined, or so 
 negative that anything else can be substituted for it. 
 
 The general principle, then, of the higher education is ex- 
 pressed in the term " conversion." 3 How is this to be effected ? 
 Clearly the educational process must follow the true and natural 
 order of mental development. If the scale of knowledge and 
 truth is what it has been represented to be, education must be a 
 method for leading the soul from the lowest stage, where it ap- 
 prehends nothing but " images," through that of direct sensible 
 experience, to the region of essential " forms " of existence, and 
 so finally to that perception of the systematic unity of truth 
 which is the ideal of science. The first two steps are provided . 
 for if the education in "music" be successfully carried through. 
 Its function was precisely to obviate the possible perversion of 
 the imagination and emotions, by training them rightly ; to pre- 
 vent people from being still children when they ought to be 
 men, by making childhood the real precursor of manhood ; to 
 train the imagination so that it should not lead to an idolatry 
 of sensible forms which the mind can only leave with pain and 
 difficulty, but that " when reason comes" she may be " welcome" 
 to the soul which has already learnt to know her unconsciously ; 
 to form habits which may not be mere habits, but the basis 
 for fresh acquisitions of character, and convictions which shall 
 
 1 7. 518 d 519 a. 2 10. 621 c. 3 7. 518 d ; 521 c.
 
 1 5 8 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 not be merely fixed, but shall offer a ready material for receiv- 
 ing the form of principles. In a soul thus trained, with its 
 imagination filled with fair sights and sounds, its emotions 
 instinctively responsive to what is really loveable, its beliefs 
 " dyed fast " with truth, the new structure of knowledge has to 
 be reared. The steadfastness of opinion has to be translated 
 into logical consistency ; the quickness and exactness of per- 
 ception and fancy into the power of abstraction and reasoning ; 
 the love of things and persons into the devotion to principles 
 and ideas. What the first step in the new " conversion " will 
 be we already know by anticipation. The mathematical 
 sciences, which are at once the product and the type of the 
 third stage in the scale of mental activity, are clearly marked 
 out to be the instruments for stimulating and training that 
 activity. Those sciences, as we saw, owe their existence to the 
 difficulties which the soul experiences when it reflects upon 
 the matter of sensuous opinion. It is in meeting those diffi- 
 culties, in obedience to an inherent speculative impulse, that 
 the soul passes from the supposed clearness and consistency 
 of local and temporal truth to the more transparent clearness 
 and the more rigorous consistency of a truth which is not 
 sensible but intelligible. If, then, we could make the soul per- 
 form methodically and under guidance the process which it is 
 its nature to perform imperfectly and at random, if the sciences 
 could be utilised for training its scientific faculties as the arts 
 were utilised for training its artistic faculties, we should be 
 helping in the most effective, because the most natural, way 
 to " make the work of conversion easy." 
 
 Plato complains 1 that the true educational function of the 
 sciences has been ignored or neglected. Arithmetic has been 
 studied so far as is useful for trade and commerce, geometry 
 for the purposes of measurement, astronomy for its value in 
 navigation, harmonics in the interest of the professional musi- 
 cian ; but it is hard to make people believe the truth that each 
 of these sciences may be made a means for "purging and 
 rekindling an organ of the soul which would otherwise be 
 spoiled and blinded, an organ more worth saving than ten 
 
 1 7. 525 c ; 527 a-b, d-e ; 531 a.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 159 
 
 thousand eyes, for by it alone the truth is seen." He does not 
 of course deny the importance of such practical applications in 
 their proper sphere ; on the contrary, he himself emphasises 
 the practical utility of arithmetic and geometry to a man who 
 is to be a soldier and tactician. 1 But he points out that for 
 such practical purposes a very slight amount of science is 
 necessary, and that the methods of study which serve for such 
 purposes are not the methods which serve for education. 2 The 
 mere empirical observation of objects, which is all that is 
 necessary for immediate utility, does not "lead the soul to 
 look upwards," 3 whereas the study of the same objects in the 
 scientific spirit is just what is wanted to make " the natural 
 intelligence useful instead of useless." 4 For, as we have already 
 been told, the really scientific man, though he employs sensible 
 objects in his reasoning, does not " think of them." The num- 
 bers of the arithmetician are such as " can only be manipulated 
 by thought;" 5 and if we point out to him that the visible or 
 tangible object which represents his unit is not " one " at all, 
 but is divisible into infinite multiplicity, he will only laugh at 
 our simplicity, and will adhere to his assertion that one is one, 
 and never anything else, invariable and indivisible. Geometry, 
 too, so far as it is scientifically treated, relates to "what is 
 invisible and eternal," 6 and not to the sensible figures which are 
 " becoming " something else at the very moment that we speak 
 of them. Nor will Plato admit that the case is really different 
 when we come to astronomy. Here indeed the splendour and 
 beauty of the visible objects with which the science is con- 
 cerned, easily deceive us into thinking that this merely sensible 
 nature is in itself important and interesting. But gazing up 
 at the stars in open-mouthed wonderment will no more give us 
 knowledge than gazing at a very excellently constructed dia- 
 gram. 7 The whole celestial universe, so far as it " has body and 
 is visible," is subject to the same conditions as other material 
 things. It does not " admit of knowledge " in the strict sense ; 
 it is a symbol, but not the truth symbolised. The material 
 heavenly bodies, as such, do not realise the relations of figure 
 
 1 7. 522 e ; 526 d. 2 7. 526 d. 8 7. 529 a-b. 4 7. 530 c. 
 6 7. 526 a. 6 7. 527 b. 7 529 c-e.
 
 1 60 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 and motion which they suggest; 1 those relations "cannot be 
 apprehended by sight, but by thought only;" and it is as figures 
 and diagrams for the discovery and analysis of these intelligible 
 relations that the visible bodies ought to be used, if we are 
 really to study astronomy and thereby to educate the human 
 intelligence. The methods adopted in harmonics, or the science 
 of sound, admit of a similar reform ; it too may be made to 
 help in the work of "conversion" by revealing the abstract 
 numerical conditions upon which musical harmony depends. 
 But this is not understood either by the professional musicians 
 who fight over the " smallest audible interval " and " set their 
 ears before their minds," 2 or even by the Pythagorean philo- 
 sophers who, 3 though they appreciate the true interest of the 
 subject, confine their investigations to what they can hear, and 
 do not go on to ask what relations of number produce harmony 
 and what do not, and what is the cause of each. 
 
 Plato's conception, then, of the educational function of the 
 sciences is, primarily, that they may be used to teach men to 
 think. This they do by presenting to the mind sensible objects, 
 and at the same time compelling it to ignore or abstract from the 
 particularity and limitation incident to sense-presentation, to fix 
 its attention solely upon the essential and universal " forms " 
 which are confusedly " imaged " to sense, and to deduce con- 
 sistently the consequences which follow from them. The diffi- 
 culties or misunderstandings to which he has given occasion in 
 expressing this conception, seem mainly due to the embarrass- 
 ing combination of an extremely limited and simple scientific 
 experience with an almost prophetic power of advancing upon 
 it, or divining its possibilities. In the childlike confidence 
 inspired by the still fresh perception of the nature of arith- 
 metical and geometrical truth, he leaps the barrier which 
 modern thought has erected between deductive and experi- 
 mental science, and boldly surmises a state of human know- 
 ledge in which the whole web of cosmic conditions should be 
 as rigorously intelligible as the simplest relations of number 
 and figure. He sees how the senses confuse the reason in its 
 early reflections upon units and triangles, and how the reason 
 
 1 530 a-c. 2 531 a-b. 3 531 c.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 161 
 
 sets the senses at defiance and goes on its own way securely, and 
 at a stroke he pictures to himself the whole phenomenal world 
 seen as the symbol of an intelligible order. He knows by 
 experience how the study of mathematics quickens the mind 
 and compels the practice of abstract thinking, and there seems 
 to him to be no reason why the whole of human science should 
 not be pressed into the same high service, the education of the 
 human race. 
 
 We have however mentioned only one, and the lesser one, 
 of the motives which led Plato to advocate the study of the 
 sciences. The ten years between twenty and thirty, over 
 which he would continue that study, would be a very long 
 time to spend in the mere practice of logical thinking. But 
 the study has to him a real as well as a formal significance. 
 It serves not only as a mental gymnastic, helping the soul to 
 reach the place where the truth is to be found, 1 but also as an 
 actual introduction to the truth for which it is looking. That 
 this is Plato's conception appears both from his enumeration 
 of the sciences themselves, and, still more, from the principle 
 upon which he directs that they should be studied. In his 
 series of sciences, arithmetic, geometry, stereometry, astronomy, 
 and harmonics, he is clearly following an order of progression 
 in their respective subject-matters, 2 number, planes, cubes, 
 motion of cubes, motion of audible bodies. We need not 
 suppose the series to be intended to be complete, even in the 
 then condition of knowledge ; we are expressly told that there 
 are many other forms of motion which might be mentioned ; 3 
 still it would seem that Plato meant to co-ordinate, in outline at 
 least, those portions of the knowledge of his time which could 
 pretend to the name of science. This appears more clearly 
 from the passage in which he indicates the method upon 
 which they should be studied. "If the pursuit of all these 
 subjects which we have enumerated be carried on to the point 
 where they communicate with and are related to one another, 
 and their natural affinities be inferred, I think it is of some 
 use for our present purpose, and not labour spent in vain, as it 
 otherwise is." 4 And again, 5 when the age of twenty is reached, 
 
 1 7. 526 e. * See, e.g. 1. 528 b. 
 
 3 530 c-d. 4 531 c-d. 6 537 c. 
 
 L
 
 1 6 2 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA T10N 
 
 the branches of knowledge which have been placed before the 
 student in boyhood " promiscuously," to be picked up without 
 system or constraint, " are to be brought together, so that he 
 may have a comprehensive view of their relationship to one 
 another, and to the nature of being." From these passages we 
 see that Plato regarded the sciences which he had enumerated, 
 not as arbitrary and isolated pieces of knowledge, still less as 
 merely formal constructions, but as directly related to the sum 
 of being or reality, of which each one of them expresses a 
 particular aspect, and in which they all find a common meet- 
 ing-point. Number, extension, motion, are primary " forms " 
 of being ; the first especially 1 is involved in the simplest acts of 
 thought, and underlies the processes of all the arts and sciences. 
 In learning to deal with them we are not only preparing our- 
 selves for dealing with more important subjects, but we are 
 actually setting our foot upon that " ladder " of existence, the 
 ascent of which would be the summit of scientific attainment. 
 And here we are reminded of the language in which Plato 
 explains what he considers to be the imperfection or inadequacy 
 of the knowledge of which mathematics are a type. That 
 knowledge, we were told, is "hypothetical," that is, it rests 
 upon principles which are unproven, because they have not 
 yet been apprehended in all their relations to other principles. 
 In requiring, then, that the study of the sciences should be 
 constantly directed to the perception of their mutual relation- 
 ships, Plato is clearly intending to remedy this characteristic 
 defect by pointing the way from the region of the "hypo- 
 thetical " to that of a self-demonstrated system of knowledge. 
 To such a system Plato, as we saw, gave the name of " dialectic," 
 and the impulse which leads, and the rules which guide, the 
 mind in the endeavour to realise it, are the " dialectical " faculty 
 and method. Accordingly we find, as we might expect, that 
 in the power of perceiving the mutual relationships of the 
 particular sciences, Plato finds " the greatest test of the pre- 
 sence or absence of a dialectical nature," for "the man who 
 can see things together is a dialectician, and he who cannot is 
 not." 2 And as to " see things together," or in their natural and 
 
 * 7. 522 c. * 537 c.
 
 JN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 163 
 
 necessary connection, is the same thing as to understand, ex- 
 plain, or account for them, the " dialectician " is also naturally 
 described as the man who " can give account both to himself 
 and others of the essential nature of any given thing." l 
 
 The sciences, then, "ordinarily so called," 2 are the " prelude " 3 
 or the "propaedeutic" 4 to "dialectical" science. The study of 
 them, as usually conducted, is far from making a man a 
 " dialectician," for it generally leaves him incapable of " giving 
 any account of" his knowledge, 5 and knowledge thus un- 
 accounted for is neither an intelligent nor a permanent acqui- 
 sition. But if studied on the principles above suggested, they 
 not only " purge and rekindle " 6 the mental vision, they are 
 not only " fellow-labourers in the work of conversion," 7 but they 
 also directly prepare the way for a higher study, partly by 
 discovering and developing the requisite faculty for it, partly 
 by introducing the mind to the elementary basis in that struc- 
 ture of knowledge of which " dialectic " is " the coping-stone." 8 
 
 The study of the sciences during the ten years between 
 twenty and thirty is not, in Plato's plan, to claim the whole 
 time and energy of the citizen who is admitted to it. He is 
 to be at the same time serving his apprenticeship in military 
 service, and testing the courage of his moral convictions under 
 the various trials of pleasure and pain, fear and persuasion, 
 which meet him in the course of his public duties. 9 The study 
 of " dialectic," on the other hand, which is to go on from thirty 
 to about thirty-five, is to concentrate the entire faculties of 
 the student while it lasts. 10 Of the form and substance of this 
 " dialectical " science we can only collect hints from Plato. And, 
 firstly, as to its form. If we conceive " dialectic " as a body of 
 scientific truth, it would be nothing less than a system of 
 universal knowledge, in which not only the "hypothetical" 
 principles of the mathematical and physical sciences, but those 
 of all other branches of human inquiry, found their place and 
 justification, and were seen to depend upon a single " unhypo- 
 thetical principle." Plato was as conscious as we are that no 
 
 1 7. 533 b ; 534 b. * 533 d. 531 d. 4 536 d. 
 531 e. 527 d. 7 533 d. 534 e. 
 
 * Cf. 6. 503 e ; 3. 412 e 413 e ; 7. 537 d ; 535 c. M 539 d.
 
 THE THEORY OF EDUCATION 
 
 such universal science was in existence, but perhaps he felt 
 more strongly than we do the importance of insisting upon its 
 theoretical necessity, and of keeping the outlines of it before 
 the mind. If, on the other hand, we think of the study of 
 " dialectic " as an educational study of the true method or logic 
 of thinking, the simplest account of it is that it is " that educa- 
 tion which will enable the student to question and answer in 
 the most scientific way." 1 This may seem to be a great fall 
 from the height to which we are carried by the conception of 
 a universal science, but this is mainly because we use oral 
 discussion so comparatively little as a means for arriving at 
 truth, and because our ideas of science and speculation are 
 associated with printed books and systems, rather than with 
 the living processes of thought which produce them. If we 
 substitute for " the man who can question and answer in the 
 most scientific way," "the man who can elicit, whether from 
 his own mind or that of others, the truest thought on every 
 subject which comes before him," we shall have a more adequate 
 notion of what Plato meant. For if, as he conceived, truth is 
 a system in which no part can be fully known until its con- 
 nection with all other parts has been apprehended, it follows 
 that in proportion as a man can " give and take account of " 
 any subject, or part of a subject, he must have the system 
 before his mind. We can therefore understand how Plato can 
 say that "no other procedure can undertake to give a com- 
 plete and methodical grasp of the essential nature of any given 
 thing." 2 For what is the case in what is commonly called dis- 
 cussion ? Generally we go no further with it than to produce 
 a certain comfortable persuasion in our own minds or that of 
 others; we appeal to no higher standard than the current 
 opinions and desires of the public which we address ; 3 we are 
 satisfied when we have turned a smart phrase or won a verbal 
 victory. 4 Even reasoning which aspires to be " philosophical " 
 is often only an artificial arrangement of skilfully adjusted 
 words, which seem to have admirable coherence, but bear no 
 relation to facts. 5 But let us suppose a mind to which debate, 
 
 1 7. 534 e. 2 533 b. 3 533 b. 
 
 4 6. 499 a. 5 6. 498 e.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 165 
 
 whether outward or inward, has no other object than the 
 attainment of truth ; l a mind bent upon arriving at and im- 
 parting conviction, and feeling that a lifetime is but a frag- 
 ment in the eternity which such a work demands; 2 suppose it 
 filled with an insatiate desire for reality, 3 which no fragment is 
 so insignificant as to escape, 4 no objections so formidable as to 
 deter, 5 no complexity so great as to confuse, 6 no hypothesis so 
 ultimate as to satisfy ; 7 suppose too that such a mind had been 
 trained by many years' practice in the power of abstracting 
 itself from the immediate presentations of time and place, so 
 that it was able to " let go eyes and other senses, and make 
 its way to the real truth;" 8 and suppose that there is present 
 in it, not only the general desire for truth and the belief in the 
 possibility of arriving at it, but also a conception, in outline 
 only, but not therefore the less firm or definite, of the form in 
 which the truth exists and in which it must be apprehended 
 by the inind, a conception leading us to look everywhere for 
 unity in multiplicity and differentiation in unity, so that 
 while no piece of truth can be confounded with any other, no 
 piece can be isolated from any other ; and suppose, lastly, that 
 this conception of the constitution of truth had borne fruit in 
 an approximate systematisation of the existing sum of know- 
 ledge, a logic of truth as complete as the state of the human 
 mind at the time admits, and that this logic had been studied 
 and practised unremittingly for years : then we shall perhaps 
 have some idea of what Plato intended by the true " dialec- 
 tical " nature and the true " dialectical " education. 
 
 "We shall probably feel that such an education must depend 
 for its success more upon the spirit in which it is imparted and 
 received than upon its particular form and matter. And cer- 
 tainly no one can be further than Plato from the idea that 
 " dialectic" is a ready-made system of formulas to be swallowed 
 whole by the mind. He is never tired of insisting upon the 
 importance of choosing the right natures for the study of the 
 
 1 6. 499 a. * 498 d. 8 5. 475 b-c. * 6. 485 b. 
 
 6 tiffirep tv (J-dxy 3ti irdvruv, K.T.\., 7. 534 c. 
 
 6 d-7r6 TWV AXXdif TrdvTuv a<pe\uv, K.T.\, 534 b. 7 7. 533 C. 
 
 8 7. 537 d.
 
 1 6 6 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 sciences, and still more for that of " dialectic." They must 
 be, not " bastards," but " genuine " children of philosophy ; l 
 " sound in limb and sound in mind," well grown and developed, 
 not one-sided "cripples." 2 They must not only be quick to 
 learn, but must have also the qualities of intellectual retentive- 
 ness and endurance and love of work, " for hard study makes 
 a craven of the soul much more than gymnastic ; the work 
 comes more home to it, for the soul has it all to itself, and does 
 not share it with the body." 3 Above all, they should be of the 
 proper age, and should have been " dyed " indelibly with the 
 spirit of law and order, so that they may combine, what it is 
 hard to find in combination, constancy and steadiness of char- 
 acter with speculative activity and aspiration. 4 Otherwise the 
 study of dialectic will continue to bring upon philosophy the 
 charge which is so often made against it, that it unsettles the 
 mind and undermines morality. 5 For, as we have already 
 heard, 6 philosophy is a double-edged instrument ; the specula- 
 tive spirit which demands to have its beliefs justified and its 
 experience accounted for, may by a turn of the hand become 
 the spirit of revolution, denying the validity of all beliefs and 
 the reasonableness of any experience; and the same logical 
 method which, when rightly handled, guides us through the 
 maze of opinion and reveals the essential forms of truth, may 
 be applied by the intellectual gladiator to show that one thing 
 is no more true than another, and to confound real distinctions 
 in a mist of words. The danger lies in the transition from 
 the atmosphere of " opinion " to that of " knowledge." In the 
 former we seem to be surrounded by a world of solid and per- 
 manent objects, each with a definite position and character 
 of its own, with which our ideas are inseparably bound up. 
 Our principles are materialised in particular persons and things, 
 and these in their turn are invested with the sanctity of prin- 
 ciples. Of the possible incongruity between an idea and its 
 local and temporal embodiment we are as yet unconscious. 
 But the mind has an inherent and a justifiable impulse to 
 advance upon this state ; for, as a matter of fact, truth is not 
 
 1 7. 535 c-d. * 536 b. * 535 b. 
 
 4 6. 503 c-e ; cf. 7. 535 a ; 539 d. 7. 537 e 539 d. 6. 497 d.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 167 
 
 merely local or temporal, and however necessary it may be that 
 our experience of it should be so, it will be continually, so to 
 say, giving the lie to that experience and breaking the limita- 
 tions imposed upon it. And in this capacity which the mind 
 possesses of rising above itself, 1 asking itself questions, feeling- 
 dissatisfaction with its own results, lies the real condition and 
 source of progress, intellectual and moral. But the difficulty 
 is to regulate the capacity rightly, to aw r aken it at the right 
 moment, and to exercise it in the right method. The power of 
 logical manipulation in clever people is often far in advance of 
 the strength of their character. The first sense of command 
 over logical formulas, not unlike that of command over literary 
 expression, is apt to upset the balance of the mind, which feels 
 as if it had the world at its command, because it can set it up 
 and knock it dow r n again in syllogisms. Many of us must 
 have observed, as Plato had done, " that schoolboys, w r hen they 
 get their first taste of logic, make free with it as if it were a 
 game ; they are for ever using it to contradict people, and in 
 imitation of those who confute them they go and confute others, 
 as pleased as puppies to worry and tear every one who comes 
 in their way." 2 But there is a more serious danger than that 
 arising from the mere delight in the exercise of a new accom- 
 plishment. The " flattering " 3 voice of pleasure is always 
 encouraging the intellect to find a flaw in the beliefs and insti- 
 tutions in which we have been brought up. The " question- 
 ing spirit" 4 comes to us and asks " What is honour?" "What 
 is justice ? " We answer by pointing to this and that belief, 
 this and that course of action, according to what we have been 
 taught. But logic has no difficulty in confuting us, in showing 
 that this particular belief or action is in itself " no more right 
 than wrong ; " 5 for the particularity of the belief or the act is 
 just what is unessential to their moral quality, as the particular 
 colour or size is unessential to the mathematical quality of a 
 triangle. It is only as " partaking in " or " imaging " some- 
 thing which cannot be apprehended in the limits of sensible 
 experience, that the particular phenomenon has a moral value. 
 
 1 7. 524 a-b. a 7. 539 b. 7. 538 d. 
 
 < 538 d. 6 538 e ; cf. 5. 479 a-b ; 7. 524 a.
 
 1 6 8 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TJON 
 
 But if the mind has not yet realised this, 1 if it has only 
 realised the relativity of the particular form of presentation, it 
 will probably identify the unessential and phenomenal con- 
 ditions with this essential reality, and in ceasing to believe in 
 them will cease to believe in anything at all. Against such a 
 tragic result, which brings discredit on philosophy and turns 
 into enemies of society men capable of being its saviours, 
 Plato would guard by putting off real philosophical study till 
 thirty, restricting it as far as possible to those characters which 
 combine the requisite moral constancy with the requisite specu- 
 lative interest and ability, and preparing for it by a long and 
 severe discipline both in intellectual and practical work. In 
 other words, he would not have " the question " asked until the 
 mind is already on the way to answer it, or the " reason why " 
 given until it merely means the throwing of a stronger light 
 upon truth already seen. " Dialectic " should " destroy hypo- 
 theses," 2 but only " in order to establish them ;" it should lead 
 the mind to see through empirical facts, but not into a dark- 
 ness or vacuum, only into a wider vista of clearer truth. 3 
 
 A systematic study of philosophy, in the spirit and under 
 the conditions suggested by Plato, is as remote from the modern 
 theory and practice of education as a systematic employment 
 of the arts. His account of what actually took place in his 
 time might be applied with slight modifications to our own : 
 " those who study philosophy at all, do it in this way : when 
 they are just emerged from boyhood, in the intervals of business 
 and money-making, they go into the most difficult part of the 
 subject, I mean logic, and then they leave it ; I am speaking of 
 those who become the greatest proficients ; and in after years, 
 if they ever accept an invitation to listen to 'a philosophical 
 discussion, they are quite proud of themselves, for they look 
 upon it as a mere pastime ; and as they draw towards old age, 
 their light goes out, all but that of a very few, and is never 
 kindled again." 4 Philosophy in modern England has not even 
 the advantage, a dubious advantage perhaps, of that conven- 
 tional glory which attached to the word in the society of Plato's 
 day, when a " philosopher " seems to have combined in himself 
 
 1 rd re dXi?^ (J.T) evpiffK-rj, 7. 539 a. 2 7. 533 c. 
 
 8 Of. 7. 520 c, and 532 a. " 6. 497 e 498 a.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 169 
 
 the lofty associations of the " savant " with the social prestige of 
 the " man of culture." It would hardly now be said of philosophy 
 that it is "a place full of fair names and shows/' 1 into which 
 the " escaped convicts " of other professions " are glad to take a 
 leap." In the popular estimation, it is a cold and comfortless 
 region, haunted mainly by the fancies of dreamers, the sneers 
 of sceptics, and the formulas of pedants. Not, indeed, that it 
 is looked upon with less suspicion on that account. The cry is 
 as loud now as it was in Plato's time, that speculation unsettles 
 and corrupts the mind of the young. And if we may retort with 
 him that the so-called theories upon which society is so hard 
 are often nothing but its own opinions articulately expressed, 2 
 and though we may not attach so much importance as he did 
 to the love of speculative truth and the dangers of its perversion, 
 we cannot deny that the forcible or adroit expression of what 
 many men are dumbly feeling has in itself an incalculable 
 power, and that not only are many honest minds needlessly 
 perplexed by speculative writing and discussion, but that much 
 real force of intellect and character is spoiled or frittered away 
 by the want of method and management in the higher branches 
 of our education. But though we may still feel the reality and 
 presence of Plato's difficulties, we are as far as he could be from 
 any prospect of applying his remedies. If the idea of concen- 
 trating the efforts of literary and artistic genius upon education 
 seemed chimerical, what are we to think of the proposal that 
 our best and ablest men should combine a severe course of 
 scientific study with the first ten years of active life, and 
 then give exclusive attention to logic and metaphysics for 
 five years more ? Or, even if the proposal itself were more 
 likely to find favour or attention, where is that co-ordination 
 of the sciences, and, still more, where is that science of logic, 
 which could, with any confidence, be set before an aspiring 
 mind ? In the case of this, as of others of the most valuable 
 ideas in the Republic, we are reduced to content ourselves with 
 the crumbs which fall from the " feast of reason." In the way 
 of its literal execution we can do hardly anything ; but we 
 might do a little towards carrying out some of its spirit. We 
 
 1 6. 495 c d. * 6. 493 a.
 
 1 7 o THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 might introduce more continuity into the curriculum of our 
 schools and universities, trying to give the mind its natural 
 food at the right times, and not letting it be still sprawling on 
 the ground when it ought to be able to walk, nor asking it to 
 climb a mountain before it can rind its way about the house. 
 The writers and supporters of our periodical literature might 
 have more sense of the responsibility of their calling, and 
 realise more fully that they spread truth or falsehood, as well as 
 provide excitement or relaxation. Above all, we might con- 
 vince ourselves that speculation, when it deserves the name, 
 does not mean spinning cobwebs or playing with fireworks, but 
 the finding of clews in the chaos of fact, and the letting in the 
 daylight through the mist of prejudice ; and that the specula- 
 tive spirit, though it may have many counterfeits, is a real 
 element in human nature, and an element to which it owes both 
 its most splendid achievements and its most disastrous failures. 
 To discuss the details of any educational system, actual or 
 possible, would be far beyond the scope of an essay, and would 
 be especially fruitless when the position of the natural sciences 
 in education and their relation to philosophy is still a subject 
 of so much dispute. As long as the advocates of scientific 
 education suppose themselves, or are supposed, to be in essen- 
 tial antagonism to those of a literary education, and as long as 
 metaphysics is understood to mean a mass of exploded fancies, 
 there can be no common ground between ourselves and Plato. 
 His whole theory hangs upon the principle that the study of 
 the sciences should be complementary to a previous training 
 through literature and art, and should itself be supplemented 
 in turn by a study of those universal logical principles to which 
 it points, and in which its problems find solution. Amongst 
 ourselves the educational use of science, apart from its teaching 
 for practical application, can only be said to have just begun, 
 and is still mostly confined to the popularisation of certain 
 elementary truths with a view of stimulating early habits of 
 observation and an interest in external nature. The idea of a sys- 
 tematic exhibition of the leading principles of the sciences, such 
 as should not only train the inind to think, but should awaken 
 its perception of the real nature of the world in which it lives, 
 and " draw it gently out of the outlandish slough " in which it
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 171 
 
 is half buried, is still only an idea. Nor can the existing teach- 
 ing of philosophy be said to satisfy Plato's requirements any 
 better than that of science. A not very profound knowledge of 
 small portions of Plato and Aristotle, a smattering of the history 
 of philosophy mainly derived from second-rate handbooks, or a 
 familiarity with some generalised theory of evolution, represent 
 the chief part of what we can point to as the results in this 
 branch of education. Meantime the air teems with speculation 
 and discussion ; questions are raised and answered in newspapers 
 and periodicals which could hardly have been printed twenty 
 years ago without raising an uproar; and there is no lack of 
 those " young men of talent, able to skim the surface of every- 
 thing that is said, and to draw inferences from it as to the best 
 way of leading their lives," 1 of whom Plato anxiously asked, 
 " What are we to suppose that they will do ?" In the dearth 
 of really original contemporary speculation, we seem to be 
 driven back upon a work only less difficult than that of crea- 
 tion, the work of interpreting the past. The task of editing 
 philosophical books for educational purposes requires, as much 
 as any task, real editorial genius, and as yet it has scarcely 
 been attempted ; nor have we any adequate collection of the 
 most valuable parts of great philosophical waitings, such as can 
 be put into the hands of students. Perhaps, if the present 
 interest in elementary education is ever followed by an equal 
 interest in its higher grades, the expenditure of industry and 
 ability upon primers and handbooks will be paralleled by an 
 effort to make accessible to the more advanced minds of the 
 community some of the original works which are now being 
 made meat for the babes. We cannot expect to revive the 
 days when truth was communicated by question and answer, 
 though we may adopt some of their method on a humble scale ; 
 but it is all the more important that the few men in each 
 generation who might once have discussed philosophy in the 
 streets of Athens or the gardens of the Academy should make 
 the works of the great thinkers of the world not a dead letter, 
 but a living voice, by entering into their spirit, interpreting 
 their speech, and carrying on their thought. 
 
 1 2. 365 a.
 
 1 7 2 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 We have been thus far considering the Platonic education in 
 science and "dialectic" mainly in its formal aspect, and we have 
 found in it a method for leading the soul from the stage in which 
 its knowledge is held in the form of opinion and imagination to 
 that in which it is held in the form of an intelligible system. 
 But we have heard scarcely anything of the matter or substance 
 of the education : much about the way in which it is to teach 
 the mind to think, little of what it is to teach. And the ques- 
 tion which now remains to be asked, and the answer to which 
 puts the coping-stone to Plato's theory of education, is, What 
 is the ultimate lesson which the human mind has got to learn, 
 and for the sake of which all this elaborate apparatus has been 
 put together ? In the language of Plato's allegory, Where is the 
 upper air to which the prisoners have to ascend, and what is 
 the sun to which their eyes have to be turned ? Or, in his 
 technical phraseology, What is that unhypothetical first prin- 
 ciple upon which the whole structure of truth depends, and to 
 grasp which is the crowning act of knowledge? We have 
 already seen (p. 137) briefly and by anticipation what is Plato's 
 answer to these questions. It is " the form of the good " which 
 is "the greatest of all studies;" 1 it is this which "comes last 
 in the world of knowledge;" 2 it is this which is the end of the 
 " dialectical " process, 3 the ultimate principle to which all the 
 " hypotheses " of knowledge are to be referred. 
 
 The word " good " has so many meanings and associations 
 in English, that it is important to be clear as to the particular 
 sense in which its Greek equivalent was used by Plato. That 
 sense is perhaps most simply and most clearly illustrated in the 
 familiar expressions, "What is the good of a thing?" and 
 " What is a thing good for ?" The answers to both these ques- 
 tions will give us the use, purpose, or end, which the thing in 
 question serves, and when we say a given thing is " good " in 
 this sense, we can generally paraphrase the expression into " it 
 does its work, or serves its purpose, well." From this sense is 
 to be distinguished what would commonly be called the more 
 " moral " sense of " good." It is indeed difficult to say how far 
 the two uses have modified one another ; but in the minds of 
 
 1 6. 505 a. 2 7. 517 b. 3 Of. 6. 511 b-c, and 7. 532 a-b.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 173 
 
 most people there is a tolerably marked distinction "between the 
 sense in which they speak of " a good man " and that in which 
 they speak of " a good horse " or " a good plough." In the 
 former case they think primarily of a certain state of mind or 
 character, secondarily of the end which it fulfils, or the work in 
 which it is manifested ; in the latter, the work which the horse 
 or plough does is the first consideration, the conditions of their 
 doing it come second. We shall understand, not only Plato, 
 but the whole of Greek moral philosophy, better, if we bear the 
 second use of " good " in mind ; if we accustom ourselves to 
 think of man as having a specific work to do, of morality as his 
 doing that work well, of virtue or " goodness " as the quality 
 which makes him do it well, and of " the good " as that which 
 the work serves or realises, and in serving and realising which 
 it is itself " good." Unfortunately the modern associations with 
 the word " good " in this sense are somewhat narrow and mis- 
 leading. When we ask, What is the " good " of a thing ? we are 
 apt to think of the " good " in question as a purpose or end out- 
 side the thing itself, to which it is made or supposed (perhaps 
 only by ourselves) to contribute ; and it is to this perversion of a 
 true idea that the doctrine of final causes owes much of its de- 
 served disrepute. To conceive of a thing as good for something, 
 or having some good, is, in the truest sense of the words, nothing 
 more than to conceive of it as having a meaning or being intel- 
 ligible ; for, strictly speaking, a thing of which the elements 
 exist side by side in no connection or order whatever, or a thing 
 which itself exists by the side of other things without standing 
 in any expressible relation to them, is to our intelligence an 
 inconceivable nonentity. And the moment that we mentally 
 interpret a thing, or, in other words, understand it, we give it a 
 reason for existing, whether that reason be a form which it 
 assumes, a purpose which it serves, a function which it per- 
 forms, or a substance which it is. We may protest as vigorously 
 as we can against the utilitarian or pietistic applications of such 
 a conception ; we may warn students of science against the 
 dangerous tendency to anticipate nature, and to translate facts 
 into the formulas of their own wish or fancy ; but such protests 
 and warnings touch only the abuse, not the essence, of the 
 conception, that the world is not an unmeaning chaos, but a
 
 1 7 4 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 something of which, however slowly and with however many 
 mistakes, we are discovering, and not merely inventing, the 
 significance. 
 
 It seemed necessary to make these few preliminary remarks 
 in order to get a point of departure for considering Plato's 
 account of " the good " in the Republic. That account may be 
 treated conveniently under three heads, according as "the good" 
 is regarded from an ethical, a logical, or a metaphysical and 
 religious point of view. And firstly, " the good " is " that which 
 every soul pursues, and for the sake of which it does all that it 
 does j" 1 it is the object in life which all men more or less feel 
 themselves to have, but which very few clearly conceive or 
 could clearly express ; it is that which makes everything which 
 we do seem worth doing, and everything which we possess 
 worth possessing ; 2 that about which no one would willingly 
 deceive himself, but of which every one says or thinks, " this at 
 least is something real, and this is what I really live for." 3 
 Theories of life apparently the most opposite imply the exist- 
 ence of this conception ; the man who lives for pleasure does 
 not really live for pleasure pure and simple ; 4 he admits the dis- 
 tinction of " good " and " bad " pleasures, and he chooses the 
 good ones, in other words, those which fall in with his general 
 scheme of life, however fragmentary or dim that scheme may 
 be. So, too, with those who live for knowledge ; 5 it is not 
 mere intellectual insight which is their aim, but insight into 
 something " good," something which they think worth knowing 
 or having ; for what is all knowledge worth unless it have some 
 relation to our life, unless it show us what is the good in our 
 life, and in the world where it is lived? And yet, though 
 every one has, more or less consciously, some such ultimate 
 object, something about which he would wish to be sure, some- 
 thing which makes things worth doing and having, it is here 
 more than in any other point that the ignorance of mankind is 
 most conspicuous. Most people " have no one mark in life at 
 which to aim in all that they do," 6 and are more sure about any- 
 thing almost than about the real object of their desire. The 
 
 1 6. 505 e. 2 505 b. 3 505 d. 
 
 4 505 c. 505 b. s 7. 519 c.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PL A TO. 175 
 
 immediate steps which they take, the present means which they 
 employ, seem to them much more clear than the ultimate goal 
 to which they aspire. And this uncertainty of aim reacts upon 
 the rest of their life ; the proximate advantages which they 
 grasp at elude them and turn out profitless, just because they 
 have no connection, no pervading purpose, no whole in which 
 they find a place. 1 It is the same want of unity and consist- 
 ency which makes most of our moral ideas and character so 
 vague and insecure. We talk of our principles of justice and 
 honour, but how can we be said to understand, or even to 
 possess, a principle or a virtue, unless we see " wherein they are 
 good," 2 unless we know what it is which gives them their value, 
 unless they are not isolated fragments in a vague " sketch " 3 of 
 life, but connected parts in a fully wrought design ? How can 
 a man order his own life or that of others, if he has " no clear 
 pattern in his soul" 4 to the ideal truth of which he can look for 
 guidance ? How can he maintain existing laws or institutions, 
 or reform them when they need it, if his acquaintance with 
 them is the merely empirical familiarity which a blind man 
 might have with things which he had often touched, or with a 
 road along which he had learnt to walk straight ? 5 Such a man 
 is only half awake ; 6 the good things which he supposes him- 
 self to secure are only images and shadows of the truth ; his 
 mental grasp of them is conventional and unintelligent, 7 and 
 is liable to be loosened by every logical objection. He can 
 "give no account" of them to himself or others, can see no 
 single " form " underlying their variety, but confuses what is 
 essential in them with what is unessential, the fragment with 
 the whole, the resemblance with the reality. 
 
 It is the perception of " the good," then, which is required to 
 complete morality, to do away with the vagueness, the aimless- 
 ness, the blindness, the fragmentariness, of life, and to give it 
 unity, completeness, and decision. But Plato sees in it the 
 condition, not only of conduct, but of knowledge also. What 
 the sun is in the world of visible objects, that he conceived " the 
 
 1 6. 505 e ; cf. 7. 534 c, otfre <*XXo dyaObv ovdtv. 
 
 2 6. 506 a. 8 6. 504 d, inroypa^v . . . TeXewrdr^v direpyacrtav. 
 4 6. 484 c. * 6. 484 c-d ; 506 c ; cf. 493 b, x/x 
 
 6 5. 476 c-d. 7 7. 534 c.
 
 1 7 6 THE THE ORY OF ED UCA TION 
 
 good " to be in the sphere of intelligence. 1 To the complete 
 fact of sight there are, in Plato's view, four factors necessary, 
 an eye capable of seeing, an object capable of being seen, light 
 in the eye and the object, and the sun of which the light is an 
 " effluence." The fact of knowledge may be analogously ana- 
 lysed : there must be a subject capable of knowing and an ob- 
 ject capable of being known, there must be intelligence present 
 in both making the one intelligent and the other intelligible, and 
 there must be a source of intelligence from which it is diffused 
 through the twin world of subject and object, soul and being. 
 Such a source is " the good," which " supplies truth to the 
 object of knowledge, and gives to the subject the power of 
 knowing." 2 Nor is this all : as the sun is the condition not only 
 of vision and visibility, but also of birth, growth, and nurture 
 to visible things, so the objects of knowledge owe to " the 
 good," not only their truth, but also their very being and 
 essence. 3 And lastly, like the sun in the allegory of the cave, 
 " the good " is the crowning vision in the upward progress of 
 the soul from darkness to light ; or, speaking without metaphor, 
 if the soul, in the strength of the dialectical impulse, penetrates 
 right through the imagery of sense, and traverses the whole 
 chain of intelligible relations, the " end of the intelligible " 4 at 
 which it arrives, the " unhypothetical first principle," upon 
 which it sees the whole structure of knowledge to depend, is 
 again "the good." In Plato's mind then, the conception of 
 knowledge and truth, the conception of objective reality or 
 essence, and the conception of a systematic order or cosmos, 
 alike implied the conception of a " good," which cannot be 
 identified with any of them, but is the condition or logical 
 prius of them all. 5 Things are known and understood so far as 
 they are seen as elements in a rational order ; knowledge is the 
 perception of them as such, and things so perceived are truly 
 perceived. Again, a thing is what it is in virtue of its position 
 in such an order. As in the physical organism the character 
 of each organ depends upon its relation to the whole, and has 
 no existence apart from that relation ; 6 as in the larger whole 
 
 1 6. 507 b 509 b. 2 508 e. 3 509 b. 4 7. 532 a-b. 
 
 * irpeajSetq. Kcd 8w<i/xet i'7re/>^x oj ' TOJ > 6. 509 b. 6 4. 420 d.
 
 AY THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 177 
 
 of the state each member only preserves his true individuality 
 so long as he takes his proper place in the organisation of 
 labour, and loses it when he ceases to do so ; l so in the universal 
 order of existence, each constituent not only is understood, but 
 subsists, only so far as it remains true to its place in the order, 
 and as that place is determined by the ruling principle, end, or 
 " good," of the order, it is to this ultimately that it owes what 
 it is. Lastly, as a life without purpose is blind, as qualities 
 without unity and connection are sketchy and incomplete, so 
 a system of truth without an unconditioned principle to depend 
 on is baseless and " dreamy ;" and such an unconditioned prin- 
 ciple Plato could only conceive in the form of an absolute end, 
 which casts a light backward through the whole system of 
 existence, but is itself above and beyond it. It thus becomes 
 intelligible how he could speak of sciences so abstract as the 
 mathematical as leading up to " the good," 2 of geometry as 
 " making us see the form of the good more easily," 3 and of the 
 study of harmony as "useful for the investigation of the 
 beautiful and the good." 4 For, if each science deals with a par- 
 ticular " form " of universal being, and each " form " points to 
 and connects with the "form" above it, and ultimately the 
 highest " form," then even in the simple relations of number, 
 figure, and sound, we may expect to hear the faint "prelude" 5 
 to the far-off " strain " of that fuller intelligence " whose voice 
 is the harmony of the world." 
 
 From this conception of a logically implied condition or 
 postulate of the world of knowledge, it was to Plato an easy 
 step to the conception of a creative cause of the universe, 
 both material and intelligible, and we are not surprised to hear 
 the sun spoken of, not only as the "analogue," but as the 
 " begotten child," 6 of the good. Plato seems here to have com- 
 bined the metaphysical conception which he expresses in the 
 Phaedo with the more mythological ideas of the Timaeus. In 
 the former dialogue, 7 the " choice of the good and the best" is 
 represented as the essential characteristic of intelligence, and 
 
 1 4. 420 e^21 a ; cf. 3. 417 b ; 5. 466 b. * 7. 532 b-c. 
 
 3 7. 526 e. 4 7. 531 c. * 7. 531 d. 
 
 6 6. 508 c ; 7. 517 c. 7 Phaedo, 99 a-c. 
 
 M
 
 1 7 8 THE THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION 
 
 any one who holds that the universe is really the work of 
 intelligence is bound to show that "it is the good and right 
 which binds and holds it together;" for it is folly to think that 
 we shall ever find " an Atlas " to support it " more mighty and 
 more immortal and more sustaining" than this. In the 
 Timaeus?- " the maker and father of the universe," whom " it is 
 hard to find out and impossible to declare to every one," being 
 himself good, and therefore incapable of envy, creates the sen- 
 sible world in all things as good, that is as like himself, as the 
 conditions of sensible existence allow. The whole material 
 universe is thus the " image " 2 or expression to sense of an 
 intelligible system, and though this intelligible system is some- 
 times spoken of as the "pattern" 3 upon which the Creator 
 made the world, it seems to be practically absorbed in the 
 Creator himself when, at the end of the work, 4 the visible 
 cosmos is said to be " the image of its maker, God manifest to 
 sense." In the light of these passages we may interpret the 
 account of the good in the Republic. It is the final cause of 
 the world ; not that 
 
 " far-off divine event 
 To which the whole creation moves," 
 
 but the immanent reason in things, in virtue of which each, 
 realises its own end in realising that of the whole. It is also 
 the eternally creative power which sustains existence ; which 
 imagination represents in 5 " picture-language " as a person 
 making all things good, and which reason apprehends as the 
 " unhypothetical principle" which all truth and goodness lead up 
 to and imply. Art, morality, and science have each something to 
 tell of it, for it is " in a manner the cause of all that we know," 6 
 whether in a more or a less perfect form. It is foreshadowed 
 in the child's story of the God who is perfectly good and 
 unchangeable, 7 in the poem which presents the 8 " image of the 
 good character " in its simplicity and integrity, in the beauty 
 of line and melody which speak of " that beauty in which all 
 things work and move." 9 Or again, it is the divine beneficence 
 
 1 Timaeus, 28 c 29 c. 2 Ib. 30 c-d. 3 Ib. 28 c 29 a. 
 
 * Ib. 92 b. 5 Ib. 29 b-d, e^raj \6yovs. G 7. 516 c. 
 
 7 2. 380 b 383 a. 8 3. 397 d ; 401 b. 9 Timaeus, 47 b-d.
 
 IN THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO. 179 
 
 which does no evil, the moral perfection in which our frag- 
 mentary virtues find their "filling up," 1 the spirit of a world 
 where injustice is neither done nor suffered, 2 and which we may 
 look at until w T e become like it. Or, once more, 3 the sciences 
 put us on the ascent which leads to it, and surrender their 
 hypotheses to receive them from it again connected and estab- 
 lished ; philosophy teaches us to find the outlines and articula- 
 tions of its presence under the motley confusion of appearances; 4 
 and the working life of mature and educated manhood supplies 
 the rough material in which those who have mastered their 
 lesson in theory may learn to understand and work it out in 
 practice. For we must not forget that the fifteen years of 
 training in sciences and dialectic are to be followed, in Plato's 
 scheme, by fifteen more years of public service, " in order that 
 the citizen may not be behind the rest in experience;" 5 and 
 during all this time he is to be tested in the strength of his 
 mind and character, " whether he will stand being pulled about 
 this way and that, or will blench at all." Not till he has 
 " passed through this trial and shown himself foremost both in 
 action and in knowledge," is he to be made " to turn the eye 
 of his soul upward and look at the very good itself, which is 
 the universal source of light." 6 Then at last the world will lie 
 open before his mind, ordered and intelligible, connected and 
 pervaded by a single principle which he can trace in many 
 forms and combinations, 7 but can distinguish from them all. 
 Then the shadows and images of everyday life will acquire 
 their true meaning, for he will see through and over them to 
 the realities which they reflect. 8 The isolated and self-con- 
 tradictory maxims of popular morality will interpret themselves 
 into fragments of a single perfection, which human life suggests 
 though it does not realise it. 9 The separate sciences will cease 
 to talk " in dreams," 10 and will point beyond themselves to the 
 waking vision of an absolute being. Philosophy will be, not a 
 cunning device of words or an occupation for a listless hour, 
 
 1 G. 504 d. 2 6. 500 c. 3 7. 533 c-d ; 517 b. 
 
 4 7. 534 b-c. 5 7. 539 e. 7. 540 a. 
 7 7. 534 c.; cf. 5. 476 a. "7. 520 c. 
 
 9 6. 501 b. 7. 533 c.
 
 1 80 THE OR Y OF ED UCA TION. 
 
 but the articulate language of truth which a lifetime is too 
 short for learning. Only eternity can interpret that language 
 fully, 1 but to understand it is the nearest approach to heaven 
 upon earth, and to study it is true education. 2 
 
 II. L. X. 
 
 1 6. 498 c-d. 
 
 2 7. 519 c, TOI)J fv Traideiy eu/j.^i>ovs oia.Tpipfii> . . . fjyov/j.ei'OL ev JJ.O.KO.JMV
 
 
 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION OF 
 THE STATE. 
 
 ARISTOTLE'S work on Politics has a twofold interest historical 
 and theoretical. If it does not add very materially to our 
 knowledge of facts and events, it throws more light than any 
 other writing, ancient or modern, on the constitutional forms 
 and struggles of the Greek States. It is the result of the politi- 
 cal experience of a people, reflected in the mind of one of its 
 wisest men and reduced to theory. Aristotle wrote of a life 
 that was going on around him, and the freshness of personal 
 knowledge enlivens his coldest analysis. Thus, in spite of the 
 scientific character of his theory, it is national. He does not 
 write as though Greek civilisation were in his eyes something 
 transitory, or a single stage in history. Though he had been tutor 
 to Alexander, he seems unaware that the day of autonomous 
 republics was passing, and that in the Macedonian monarchy a 
 kind of government was arising hitherto unknown in the develop- 
 ment of his race. On the other hand, the very fact that he stood 
 on the confines of change gives him a peculiar advantage. His 
 position is not midway in a political development, where the 
 character of institutions and the meaning of movements is 
 obscure. The strength and weakness of Greek society and of 
 Greek civic virtue, the political structure which had protected 
 that virtue and been upheld by it, the gradual decline of 
 public spirit, the corruption of military aristocracy into an 
 oligarchy of wealth at Sparta, of active free government into 
 impotent ochlocracy at Athens, the war of classes which sprang 
 from a social question and became a political one, all this lay 
 behind him. The prime of Greek life was nearly past when he 
 wrote. What we miss in his work, what would have been of such 
 great interest now, a description of military monarchy and of 
 federal government, would not have touched the life which rises
 
 1 82 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 before our minds when we hear of Greek history. And what 
 he does describe is fully developed, and therefore capable of 
 adequate analysis. 
 
 But it is not merely our desire to understand the past which 
 is satisfied by a treatise like the Politics. That which is true 
 of the art and literature of the Greeks is only less true of their 
 political creations. Their most intensely national products are 
 at the same time " purely human." To apply to modern affairs 
 conclusions drawn from Greek history is indeed hazardous, and 
 such reasonings are often as futile theoretically as the imita- 
 tions of Roman virtue in the French Eevolution were practically 
 hollow. The fate of Athenian democracy will not disclose to us 
 the future of the American Republic, for the circumstances are 
 radically different. But in spite of change there are permanent 
 characteristics of social forces and of forms of government, of 
 commerce and agriculture, wealth and poverty, true and false 
 aristocracy, oligarchy and democracy. Not only this : among the 
 subjects of which the Politics treats there is something even more 
 permanent and universal, and that is the simple fact of political 
 society. Let a State be the organisation of a nation or a city, it is 
 still a State ; and what is true of its nature and objects in one 
 case will, up to a certain point, be true of them in another and 
 in every case. It is in the discovery of these truths and the 
 investigation of such ideas as those of justice and right, that the 
 primary business of philosophy in its application to politics 
 consists ; and Aristotle is before all things a philosopher. These 
 facts and ideas are so familiar to us that we take little account 
 of them ; they seem to us self-evident, and we prefer to deal with 
 more concrete difficulties. But to philosophers the self-evident 
 ceases to be so, and their effort is to know what everybody seemed 
 to know before. Thus Aristotle makes these preliminary 
 problems the basis of all further discussion. It would have 
 seemed absurd to him to attempt the settlement of complex 
 problems, when the elementary conceptions on which they 
 depend have been subjected to no analysis ; to blame the State 
 perhaps for overstepping its limits, when we do not know what 
 the State is, and therefore cannot possibly tell what its limits 
 are ; or to assert a right to share in government when we can 
 attach no intelligible meaning to the word " right." The fault
 
 OF THE STATE. 183 
 
 of reasoning on insufficient data has never been charged on 
 Aristotle's Politics ; every one knows that he founded his theory 
 on researches into more than a hundred and fifty Greek consti- 
 tutions, and that he even made a collection of the social and poli- 
 tical usages of foreign tribes. But he is equally free from other 
 defects more easily forgiven : he does not use criteria the value of 
 which he has never questioned, nor try to account for one set of 
 human phenomena in total isolation from the theory of all the 
 rest. To him political science is founded on ethics, and ethics 
 on psychology ; and all these rest upon metaphysic and its 
 application to nature. 
 
 In the following pages I propose to give a sketch of the views 
 which Aristotle held on a few of these preliminary questions. 
 In the nature of things, these questions are less affected than 
 any others by historical changes ; and an attempt to show their 
 vital meaning through the forms of Greek thought may have an 
 interest, although it can offer nothing to professed students of 
 antiquity. But the differences which exist between Greek poli- 
 tical conditions and those of our own time, and between the ideas 
 associated with each, are so marked that they appear even in 
 the most abstract discussions ; and there are some of such 
 importance that, unless they are constantly kept in sight, it is 
 impossible rightly to appreciate Aristotle's views, or to separate 
 what is essential in them from what is merely temporary. In 
 spite of their familiarity, therefore, it will be as well to begin 
 by recalling some of these points of difference to mind, and 
 examining Aristotle's position in regard to them. 
 
 First of all, the Greek State was a city, not a nation. If we 
 think of an English county with a single city and its surround- 
 ing territory, and imagine it to be independent and sovereign, 
 we shall have more idea of one of the largest Greek States than 
 if we compare it with a modern nation. Political life was con- 
 centrated in the capital to such an extent that the same word 
 stands for city and State. In such a community public affairs 
 were as much matters of every day as the municipal politics of 
 an English town, and yet they had all the dignity of national 
 decisions. The citizen, in a State like Athens, took part in 
 politics personally, not through a representative ; not once in 
 four or five years, but habitually. His convictions or his catch-
 
 1 84 ARISTOTLE S CONCEPTION 
 
 words were won not through the dull medium of the press, but 
 from the mouths of practised orators. The statesmen of his time 
 were familiar figures in his daily life. The opposite party to 
 his own was not a vague collective name to him, but he rubbed 
 shoulders with it in the streets. Thus political life was his occu- 
 pation and acquired the intensity of a personal interest. The 
 country and its welfare had a vivid meaning to him ; he felt 
 himself responsible for its action and directly involved in its 
 good or evil fortune. Under these conditions, the rise and fall 
 of a State visibly depended on the character of its citizens ; its 
 greatness was nothing but the outward sign of their energy and 
 devotion ; the failure of virtue in them acted immediately on it. 
 Thus the bonds of reciprocal influence, which we can only 
 believe in now, were palpable facts then ; and the more direct 
 danger of foreign attack or of civil war was seldom far distant. 
 Hence the vital interest taken by the State in the character of 
 its members and their education. Hence also an amount of 
 governmental inspection and control of private affairs which, 
 even if it suited modern ideas, would be scarcely possible in a 
 nation. Such "interference with liberty" was then not felt to be 
 an interference. In the best days of Greece, to participate in this 
 rapid and ennobling public life was enough for the Greek citizen. 
 If his country was independent and himself an active member of 
 it, this community satisfied him too completely for him to think 
 of " using his private house as a state" 1 or a castle. " To live as 
 one likes," this is the idea of liberty which Aristotle connects 
 first with the most primitive barbarism (Eth. 10. 9. 13), and then 
 with that degraded ochlocracy which marked the decay of the 
 free governments of Greece (179. 20 ; 185. 9 ; 216. 16). 
 
 The effects of this one difference on a political theory are 
 incalculable. And Aristotle not only adopts the Greek idea of 
 the State, and consequently thinks of it as a city, but he has 
 expressly raised the question of its proper size. The discussion 
 of this point in the account of the ideal State (101. 14 ff.) con- 
 tains one or two chance remarks which throw a strong light on 
 the Greek idea and its results. Aristotle mentions an opinion 
 
 1 73. 16. Here and throughout this Essay, where mere figures are given, 
 they indicate the pages and lines of Bekker's small edition of the Politics 
 (Berlin, 1855).
 
 OF THE STATE. 185 
 
 that the State or city should be large ; and, while he admits 
 that largeness is an advantage so long as it involves no 
 diminution of that real energy of the State which makes it 
 great and not simply big, he insists that this proviso sets 
 definite limits to the increase of size or population. It is 
 essential that the State should be " easily overseen " (evavvoTr- 
 TO?, 103. 11). Just as a boat can no more be two furlongs 
 long than a span long, so a State can no more have 100,000 
 citizens than ten (Eth. 9. 10. 3). Such a number is possible 
 for a mere tribe (e6vo<$), but not for a political community. 
 And why not ? The answer is in the highest degree charac- 
 teristic. The State implies government ; and the function of 
 the governor is to issue orders and to judge. " But if just 
 legal decisions are to be given, and if office is to be apportioned 
 to men according to merit, it is necessary for the citizens to 
 have a knowledge of each other's characters, since, where this 
 is not the case, things must needs go wrong with the appointment 
 of officials and the administration of the law; but it is not right to 
 act off-hand in either of these matters, and that is plainly w r hat 
 happens where the population is over-large." In such a case, 
 again, it is impossible to prevent strangers from quietly obtain- 
 ing the rights of citizens. And finally, who could be the one 
 general of such a multitude, and who, unless he had the voice 
 of Stentor, their one herald ? l 
 
 A second fundamental distinction is to be found in the 
 social organisation of the Greek State. The political life of 
 Sparta or Athens rested on the basis of Slavery. The citizen- 
 body might trace its descent to a conquering race which had 
 reduced the original possessors of the country to a position of 
 more or less complete subjection, and lived upon their agricul- 
 tural labour, as in the one case; or the slaves might be 
 procured through war and a slave-trade, as in the other. But 
 in both instances the bulk of the necessary work was per- 
 formed by an unfree population, far outnumbering the select 
 aristocracy of free citizens. This institution and the contempt 
 even for free labour are the most striking proofs that the 
 
 1 102. 15 ff. In 62. 10 the size of Babylon is said to fit it for an 
 rather thau a irbXis ; of. 33. 30.
 
 1 86 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 Hellenic solution of social problems was inadequate ; modern 
 writers find in them the " dark side " of Greek life, or even the 
 " blot upon their civilisation." But the latter expression at 
 least is misleading, since it implies that such defects had no 
 organic connection with the strength and beauty of this 
 civilisation ; whereas, in fact, the life of " leisure," devoted to 
 politics and culture or to war, would have been impossible 
 without them, and general conclusions drawn from Greek 
 history which do not take them into account are inevitably 
 vitiated. 
 
 On this point Aristotle shares the view common to his 
 countrymen. He recommends that slaves should be kindly 
 treated, and that good conduct on their part should be rewarded 
 by their liberation. He does not admit that the slavery of men 
 born to be free is justifiable, since, in his view, it is a viola- 
 tion of nature. But he definitely holds that there are men 
 (apparently as a rule " barbarians ") whose right and natural 
 destination is servitude ; and he adopts the institution in his 
 ideal state. Into his analysis of slavery and his partial 
 justification of it it is unnecessary to enter. Its chief interest 
 is that he attempts to put the question on a moral ground, and 
 therefore in his attempt to defend a bad cause falls into con- 
 tradictions. He does not base slavery on political utility, nor 
 fortunately has he Biblical arguments at hand which he can 
 call religious. Its morality and that to him was the deciding 
 question depends on the fact that some men are destitute of 
 reason in the highest sense of the word ; " those men who 
 differ from others as widely as the body does from the soul, 
 or a beast from a man (and men stand in such a relation 
 when the use of their bodies is their function and the best 
 thing that can be got out of them), are by nature slaves" (7. 15); 
 and for them servitude is not merely a painful necessity, but 
 their good. The problem is, then, to find men whose nature is 
 of this kind, and who at the same time are capable of obeying 
 and even anticipating orders (5. 21), of receiving rational in- 
 struction (22. 9), and of standing in the relation of friendship 
 to their masters (Etli. 8. 10. 6). And this is a contradiction 
 which cannot exist. The weakness of the position is brought 
 out in the words which Aristotle adds to his assertion that
 
 OF THE STATE. 187 
 
 friendship is possible between master and slave "not as a 
 slave, but as a man." In other words, to treat a man as a 
 slave is to treat him as though he were not a man. 
 
 Another distinction which calls for some remark concerns 
 religion. It would be superfluous to compare the doctrine 
 and spirit of Christianity and Greek religion: superfluous, and 
 perhaps misleading. For the vital differences which really 
 exist between them are liable to be exaggerated by a statement 
 of opposing principles, especially when it is assumed that the 
 "ideal" morality which we describe as Christian is that by 
 which modern Christians, for the most part, really live. But 
 though the actual religious motives and practice of Greeks and 
 Englishmen may be nearer to one another than we are apt to 
 suppose, in the position of religion in the community there is 
 a striking dissimilarity. Greek religion knew no recognised 
 orthodox doctrine and no recognised expositor of that doctrine. 
 A Greek had no church. Consequently one of the most fruit- 
 ful sources of conflict in modern nations had no existence in 
 Hellas. There is nothing in Greek history even analogous to 
 the struggles of Church and Empire and Church and State, to 
 the religious wars of Germany and France, or even to the semi- 
 theological Great Rebellion, and in Aristotle's list of the causes 
 of <rracT49 or civil discord religion is hardly mentioned. A 
 second consequence is this, that the Greek knew little, either 
 for good or evil, of the modern idea that the State is " profane." 
 His religious feelings attached themselves to it. It was not 
 merely the guardian of his property, but the source of right 
 and goodness to him, the director of his worship and guarded 
 by the gods he worshipped. He might not insult its gods, 
 although within certain limits he was left to think and speak 
 of them as he thought right. In the absence of a powerful 
 priesthood, the natural development of the religious ideas of 
 the people was unhampered and could pass easily into corre- 
 sponding action ; a vote of the Legislature might adopt a new 
 deity into the number of those already recognised. Thus, but 
 for the occasional influence of the Delphic oracle, we may say 
 that to the Greek citizen his State was the moral and religious 
 law in one. 
 
 It is easy for us to realise the defects of such a relation
 
 1 88 ARISTOTLE S CONCEPTION 
 
 and the want of truth in the religious ideas connected with 
 it. But it had also a greatness of its own ; and this we do not 
 feel so readily. It fostered the social and political virtue of the 
 citizen ; and in his devotion to his State, his perception of its 
 greatness and dignity, and the fusion of his reverence for it 
 with that which he felt for his gods, he possessed a spiritual 
 good which the modern world has known only in the scantiest 
 measure, and that only since the Eeformation. It is this spirit 
 . which breathes throughout the Politics, the spirit which is 
 x willing to be guided by the highest authority it knows; which 
 emphasises its duties to the community, and has not even a 
 word to signify its "rights" against it; which describes the 
 possession of property and the begetting of children not as the 
 ^private affair of individuals but as services to the State ; l and 
 which finds in the law, not a restraint but the supremacy of 
 the divine element in human nature, " reason without desire." 
 For the rest, there is nothing specially noticeable in Aristotle's 
 remarks on the religious services of his ideal city. He seems 
 to place this social function first in importance (108. 4). It 
 is provided for from the proceeds of the state-lands (111. 28), 
 and performed by the oldest citizens, who are freed from the 
 duties of war and public life (109. 28). It cannot be said 
 that Aristotle attributes to religion anything like the import- 
 ance it has for us. It is characteristic of him that though 
 he certainly did not believe the popular mythology, uses the 
 plainest language respecting it, and even thought that some of 
 it had been deliberately invented by rulers for political ends, 2 
 he proposes no kind of change in the public worship, and 
 contents himself with trying to guard against the moral 
 dangers connected with the celebrations of some deities (128. 
 29). What he would have thought of the use of this 
 mythology in education we can do DO more than guess, for 
 the book which treats of that subject breaks off long before it 
 can be supposed to be complete. But that his attitude was 
 not due to moral indifference is quite certain. He probabty 
 considered the common people incapable of any such exalted 
 
 1 \etTovpyeIv TT? w6\fi, 126. 21, and 152. 10. So also of government, 152. 11. 
 
 2 Met. 1074 a 38.
 
 OF THE STATE. 189 
 
 monotheism as his own, and thought that their own creed had 
 the sanctity for them that in all cases belongs to the highest 
 form in which the truth is attainable. 
 
 It will be already apparent, lastly, that if Aristotle's views 
 represent Greek opinion, we must not expect to find in him our 
 own ideas of the individual. Eoman law, with its presumption 
 that every one is a person and capable of being the subject of 
 rights ; Christianity, which asserts an identification of the 
 human and divine spirit capable of becoming actual in 
 the soul of the believer, and giving his existence an absolute 
 value ; the more popular caricature of this doctrine, which 
 places the end of this individual soul in the attainment of 
 perpetual private pleasure ; the romantic preference of personal 
 honour and loyalty to public spirit, and of purity and humility 
 to the social virtues ; the principles of the French Eevolution 
 and of English liberalism, all this lies between us and 
 Aristotle. It is natural to us to base our political theories on 
 individual liberty and rights. We look upon man as having a 
 nature of his own and objects of his own, independently of 
 society. We look upon the State as a contrivance for securing 
 to him the enjoyment of his liberty and the opportunity of 
 pursuing his ends, a contrivance which involves some limitation 
 of his rights and ought to involve as little as possible. Even 
 when reflection has shown us that there is something theoreti- 
 cally wrong with these ideas, we remain convinced that a 
 happiness or a morality which is imposed on us from without 
 loses half its value, and that there are spheres of our life and parts 
 of our inward experience into which no one ought to intrude. 
 And if we feel strongly our unity with others, and are willing 
 to admit that social and political institutions have a positive 
 object and not the merely negative one of protection, we 
 emphasise the fact that the character or happiness they are to 
 promote are those of individuals, and are often in danger of 
 falsifying our position by regarding the community and its 
 institutions as something separable from this individual welfare, 
 and a mere means to it. When we read Plato or Aristotle every- 
 thing seems to be changed. The State is regarded not as a con- 
 trivance for making possible the objects of individuals, but as 
 a sun on which the lesser bodies of its system are absolutely
 
 i 9 o ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 dependent, or rather as this system itself. It does not limit 
 private existence; private existence derives its being, its welfare, 
 and its rights from it. The community and even its institu- 
 tions seem to be regarded as an end in which personal happiness 
 has no necessary place, and to which the existence of any num- 
 ber of individuals is a mere means. We soon discover that the 
 Greek philosophers held no such absurdity as this, that they 
 regarded personal welfare in the highest sense as the sole object 
 of the State, and that they were in far less danger than ourselves 
 of seeking it in conquest or in wealth. But after this has been 
 taken into account, and after we have realised that the modern 
 citizen's patriotism and reverence for law seem to answer more 
 to Greek ideas than to our own theories, there remains a decided 
 difference both in fact and in feeling, a difference which appears 
 again and again in political questions. 
 
 For a century or more before the Politics was written, the 
 traditional Greek view had been called in question, and ideas 
 had been opposed to it which strike us at once by their modern 
 air. What is the State ? Is it something inevitably produced 
 in the development of human nature, or an invention ? Is it a 
 whole, the source of all freedom and morality to its members, 
 or a contrivance of individuals, deriving its authority simply 
 from their agreement and from enactment ? Is its object 
 something common and equivalent to the end of human life, or 
 is it a mere means to the attainment of the private objects of 
 the individuals who combined to form it ? In some such way 
 we may make explicit the questions which decide the character 
 of Aristotle's theory. And they may be summed up in the 
 single inquiry, started by the Sophists, Is the State natural 
 or conventional ? a If, with some of them, we hold that it is 
 the latter, that it rests upon custom and enactment, the result 
 seems at first sight to be that the reverence and devotion which 
 it claims from the citizen are misplaced, and that its identifica- 
 
 1 fpfoei or v6fj.y. It is impossible to render i/6/xos by a single word, as it 
 means both enactment and custom. The Gorgias and the first two books of 
 the Republic contain full illustrations of the Sophistic views referred to.
 
 OF THE STATE. 191 
 
 tion with the moral law is absurd. Yet it is clearly dependent 
 on man's will and intelligence, and neither fixed nor natural 
 as the stars are. If then it is still to be regarded as an absolute 
 moral power, and not the product of fear or force, we must find 
 some way of reconciling this absoluteness with a recognition of 
 the action of man's will in low or custom. Thus we shall find 
 that Aristotle's position towards the question practically 
 amounts to a denial of the antithesis between vcn<$ and vofjios, 
 and an assertion that the State is at once due to man's will and 
 the necessary or " natural " expression of his progress. This 
 result Aristotle reaches not by a refutation of opposing theories, 
 but by his own analysis and interpretation of facts. And the 
 first question, on which all others depend, is : What does the 
 fact of political community mean ? What is the State ? l 
 
 " Since all communities or associations are formed for the 
 sake of some good, this must be especially true of that com- 
 munity which is the highest and includes all the rest, and it 
 
 1 We use the word State in at least two different senses, and to prevent 
 misapprehension it may be as well to define shortly the meaning attached to 
 it in these pages. By State we seem to mean (1) such a community as pos- 
 sesses not only a social but also a political organisation, or, in the widest 
 sense, a government. As a State the body politic is not merely a collection 
 of individuals or classes, but is itself an individual or person ; as is especially 
 evident in its relations with other States, and in the existence of a monarch 
 or president. In the case of modern States, most of which are already 
 founded upon nationality, the word "nation" expresses this idea; and 
 language which may seem overstrained when applied to the State sounds more 
 natural if we substitute "nation." That word, however, is inappropriate 
 to Greek politics ; and even if it were not it does not express clearly the fact 
 that society has a political organisation : it is sometimes true to say "the 
 nation does or wills " this or that, when it would not be true to say this of 
 the State. It is in this first sense that I commonly use the expression 
 State. But (2) as this expression lays stress on the organisation of the com- 
 munity in government, we come to use it as equivalent to government. Thus 
 a single function of the State gets the name of the whole, and acquires a false 
 isolation. Accordingly when language used of the State is understood to apply 
 to the government, it becomes absurd, unless indeed the government is regarded 
 as representing the State and, for the time being, equivalent to it. In such 
 discussions as those on the end of the State, then, it is important to bear in 
 mind that the State is distinct, on the one hand, from government, since it 
 is the unity of which government is a single function, and that it is distinct, 
 on the other hand, from society, because it is this unity as it expresses itself 
 in political organisation and, through the fact of this organisation, acts as a 
 person.
 
 1 92 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 will clearly have for its object the highest and most command- 
 ing good. This community is the State." With some such 
 words the treatise opens. Their simplicity conceals the extent 
 to which they define Aristotle's position, yet when they are 
 admitted some of the most vexed questions are settled before- 
 hand. In accordance with his fundamental idea that every- 
 thing is defined by the end it is destined to attain, they lay it 
 down that there is a definite object for which the State exists ; 
 that this object is not something accidental, suggested by the 
 chance desires of individuals ; and that it is not the merely 
 relative end of making possible the attainment of other ends ; 
 but that the State is the highest of human associations, 
 and, instead of being one among others, includes in itself all 
 other associations ; and that, as the good at which it aims in- 
 cludes the subordinate objects of desire arrived at by the sub- 
 ordinate communities, this good is nothing short of the final 
 object of human life, the end which alone gives value to all 
 lesser ends and has no end beyond it. 
 
 Whatever this chief good which makes life worth living 
 may be, it is the end of man and not of an abstraction such as 
 the State is sometimes thought to be. In other words, it is the 
 end of the citizens who compose the community; for the good 
 of the State and that of the individual are, according to 
 Aristotle, precisely the same, although, when we regard this 
 good in the first way, it has a greater perfection and grandeur 
 (Eth. 1. 2. 8 ; cf. 93-96). But many men pursue a false end ; 
 they give their lives to objects unworthy of a man, such as 
 mere pleasure, or to objects like wealth, which, though they are 
 really desirable, are so only as means to a good beyond them. 
 In the same way there are States which pursue unworthy aims, 
 and Aristotle finds opinions prevalent which either tacitly or 
 openly assign to the State ends which are really beneath it. 
 His opposition to these views brings out his own more dis- 
 tinctly. 
 
 There are, for example, certain oligarchic and democratic 
 arguments which assume that the possession of wealth and free 
 birth, respectively, forms such a contribution to the purposes of 
 the State as ought in justice to be rewarded by political privi- 
 leges. But these arguments, as Aristotle points out, really pre-
 
 OF THE STATE. 193 
 
 suppose that the end of the State is wealth or free birth, positions 
 which lie cannot for a moment admit. Not that these elements 
 of life are without importance for the political community ; they 
 may even be means necessary to its welfare, but they do not on 
 that account constitute its essence or end. The same is true 
 of other necessary conditions. The State is not a defensive 
 alliance, concluded by individuals who wish to pursue their 
 various objects in security from hostile attacks. Nor is it a 
 device they have adopted for facilitating trade with one another, 
 and insuring themselves against force or fraud. If it were, its 
 object would be (to borrow modern language) merely the pro- 
 tection of person and property ; " the law," in Aristotle's own 
 language, " would be a contract and, as Lycophron the Sophist 
 says, a pledge of lawful dealing between man and man ; " and 
 two different nations which had formed a defensive alliance, 
 and whose citizens, when their trading led to disputes, could 
 sue and be sued in the courts of either State alike, would only 
 be considered separate States because their territories happened 
 to be distinct. But even if this difficulty were overcome, and 
 to communion in all these points were added the right of legal 
 intermarriage and the existence of societies for holding common 
 festivals and joining in common amusements, the resulting 
 association would still fall short of being " political." " All this 
 must be there, if there is to be a State ; but even if all this is 
 there, there is not yet a State." For the members of the society 
 would not only lack the single government which is essential 
 to a State, but they would not necessarily have any share in 
 that which alone gives a value to these subordinate bonds of 
 union, the final end of human life (72. 4 74. 7). 
 
 What, then, is this final end or chief good, the pursuit of 
 which and a common share in which is the essence of the State? 
 What additional bond would make this imaginary society poli- 
 tical ? Aristotle has answered this question in the concrete in 
 the passage before us. This society is a community in mere 
 " living ;" and a State is a community in " good living." These 
 associates do not trouble themselves about each other's moral 
 character or wellbeing; and the State aims at nothing short 
 of that. The law to them is a mere contract, protecting their 
 persons and property ; but the real law, the law of the State, 
 
 N
 
 i 9 4 ARISTOTLE 'S CONCEPTION 
 
 aims at making the citizens good and just men. " Good living" 
 (3. 9; 72. 14), " noble actions" (74. 1), a " perfect and self-sufficing 
 life," 1 " well-being " or happiness, these are all various names 
 for the chief good of man. The full discussion of it is the 
 subject of the Ethics ; and we have to do with it here only so far 
 as is necessary to bring out the positive character of the end at. 
 which the State is said to aim. It is the full and harmonious 
 development of human nature in the citizen, or, in other words, 
 the unimpeded activity of his moral and intellectual " excel- 
 lence" or virtue. In the freedom of this activity from 
 hindrances is implied a certain amount of "prosperity" or of 
 " external goods." But the goods of fortune are not goods at 
 all except to the man who can use them aright, and therefore 
 the essence of his wellbeing lies in the activity itself, or in his 
 character, not in what he has, but in what he is. The virtues 
 or excellences in which his true nature is developed are naturally 
 manifold ; but in Aristotle's view they fall into two main 
 groups. The soul feels and desires ; it thinks and it rules its 
 emotions. In so far as its desires are moulded by reason into 
 harmonious and controlled activities, the soul attains the 
 " moral" virtues in the narrower sense of the word ; in the 
 employment of reason itself it reaches \vhat Aristotle calls the 
 intellectual virtues. In both it feels that pleasure which 
 accompanies the free exercise of a function. That all these 
 functions are equally ends in themselves, Aristotle, of course, 
 no more believes than any one else : there is a higher and lower 
 in them, and a greater and less desirability in men's lives, 
 according as they develop one kind of excellence or another. 
 It is when the care and the necessary incompleteness of the 
 active citizen life are laid aside, and a man attains to speculative 
 
 1 73. 25 S. fto7?s reXe/as cat avrdpicovs. One idea connected with the latter 
 word is that of completeness. The chief good must lie in a life which leaves no 
 want of man unsatisfied, whether these wants be external or spiritual, a life in 
 which man's self (avrbs) is fully realised, and which therefore attains his final 
 end (rAos). " Self-sufficience " has already a meaning of its own in English, 
 and in many ways "freedom" seems to answer best to avrapKeia : freedom 
 not in a merely negative sense, but in that in which it is said that the truth 
 makes men free ; or, as by Carlyle, that the object of all religion is to make 
 man free ; or, as by Hegel, that the idea of mind and the end of history is 
 freedom.
 
 OF THE STATE. 195 
 
 insight into the reason of the world, that the divine element in 
 him approaches nearest to its source, and he touches that 
 highest blessedness which all great philosophers, as well as 
 religious men, have found in union with God. That a whole 
 life of such activity and joy is more than human, and that it can 
 be known only in moments, is no reason for falling back on 
 Philistinism. " We ought not to listen to those who tell us that, 
 since we are men, our thoughts should be those of men, and 
 since we are mortal they should be mortal ; but, so far as in us 
 lies, we ought to rid ourselves of our mortality and do all we 
 can to live in accord with that which is noblest in us ; for 
 though in bulk it be a little thing, in power and preciousness 
 it far surpasses all things" (Etli. 10. 7. 8). A life of such happy 
 moral excellence and active " contemplation " is what Aristotle 
 calls " good living." To attain and further this is the end of 
 the State. This itself, community in this, is the State. 
 
 An inseparable connection of this kind between political 
 society and man's chief good leaves only one possible answer to 
 the question, Is the State natural or conventional ? It is man's 
 destination, that in which and through which his end is 
 realised. It is therefore "natural" in Aristotle's use of the 
 word, at least in so far as man is concerned ; and if man's end 
 is also an end in the system of the world, the State will be 
 natural in a still further sense. The meaning of these ideas will 
 be clearer if we first consider the steps by which man reaches 
 the stage of political society, and thereby advances towards the 
 goal of his progress. Aristotle's account of the origin of the 
 State (2. 1 3. 9) sounds very meagre at the present time; but, 
 besides its historical interest, it contains a further refutation of 
 the view that the relations which connect men with each other 
 are accidental bonds of their own contriving. It destroys before- 
 hand the various theories which found society on an explicit or 
 implicit agreement. 
 
 The beginnings of the State, the final community, are to be 
 sought in the most primitive forms of association. These are 
 the unions, Aristotle tells us, of those " who cannot exist with- 
 out one another;" man and woman, master and slave. Man 
 and woman come together not from any rational resolve, but 
 because in them, as in the other animals and in plants, there is
 
 196 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 a natural desire to reproduce themselves. Master and slave are 
 united by the desire for security ; the master being one whose 
 superior intelligence enables him to foresee the future and fits 
 him for rule, whereas the slave is naturally adapted for simple 
 obedience, because he is only capable of carrying out the orders 
 given him. Thus, we may say, he is a body of which his 
 master is the soul ; and owing to this natural division of func- 
 tions the relation of slavery is for the interest of both parties. 1 
 It is of these two associations that the household or family con- 
 sists ; and Hesiod's verse, " first of all a house and a wife and 
 an ox to plough " is true, since to the poor man the ox stands in 
 stead of a servant. Thus the origin of the State is to be looked 
 for in the Family. But there is an intermediate step between 
 them the. stage of the milage. The village consists of several 
 families. Whether it is formed by the aggregation of indepen- 
 dent households or by the expansion of a single one, Aristotle 
 does not tell us ; but the latter view seems to be favoured by 
 the words, " it seems most naturally to be an offshoot or colony 
 (d7roiKia) of the family (oifcia), and its members, being the sons 
 and sons' sons [of the family], are called men of the same milk 
 (6fjioyd\aKTef)." In these first beginnings Aristotle finds the 
 explanation of two interesting facts. They show us why the 
 earliest form of political government, like the government of 
 tribes not yet political, is monarchical; for the village from 
 which the State springs is governed by its oldest member. 
 And this explains why the same form of government is attri- 
 buted to the gods ; " for men imagine in their own likeness not 
 only the shapes, but also the mode of life of the gods." Beyond 
 this scanty notice, we have hardly any reference to the village 
 in Aristotle's work. We do not know whether he connected it 
 as a stage in the growth of society with the formation of the 
 761/09 or clan, though the passage quoted above seems to make 
 this probable ; and there is a further one in which he speaks of 
 the State first as a " a community of families and clans," and 
 immediately afterwards as a " community of clans and villages " 
 (73. 24 ff.). However this may be, and in whatever way he 
 
 1 Later on (68. 20), though it is reiterated that " in reality the interests of 
 the natural master and slave are identical, " we are told that the master seeks 
 properly his own good, and only accidentally that of the slave.
 
 OF THE STATE. 197 
 
 may have imagined the transition from village to city, he men- 
 tions no further stage between them. With the union of 
 several villages we have the State. 
 
 Thus the individuals who became citizens of a State had 
 already been members in two previous forms of community, 
 each of which involved a definite organisation, and, what is more, 
 a relation of government. And in the same way the son of a 
 citizen has his individuality circumscribed or developed by his 
 position not only in the city, but also in these subordinate 
 spheres, which both preceded the State and continue to exist 
 in it. 1 But this is not all. If we look closer, we shall see a 
 deeper connection between the various stages. Each is a pre- 
 paration for the next ; each is produced by the effort of human 
 nature to realise itself ; it is because of the failure of each to 
 satisfy this desire fully that a new form is created. And this 
 process cannot cease until that kind of association is reached 
 which gives man the attainment of his true end. Thus the two 
 relations which compose the family are due to the necessity of 
 mere existence ; they are formed by those who simply cannot 
 do without each other ; and it is obvious that neither propaga- 
 tion nor mere preservation, which are their ends, is any complete 
 realisation of human nature. Again, the end for which the 
 family exists is defined as the satisfaction of daily wants. With 
 the village a further advance is made ; the needs which it aims 
 at providing for are more than those of the day. But it is only in 
 the State that the " limit of perfect self-sufficiency" is attained. 2 
 And if in this passage the imperfection of the lower stages is 
 placed mainly in their failure to reach avrapiceia, and we are 
 inclined to regard this avrapicela as equivalent merely to a com- 
 plete satisfaction of merely external wants, Aristotle makes his 
 
 1 It should be noticed, accordingly, that what is said of the family, as a 
 community preceding the State, is not intended to be a satisfactory account 
 of it as a part of the State. When the State has come into being, its 
 nature and object must affect its constituent elements ; and therefore Aristotle 
 postpones the full discussion of the family until he has examined the political 
 whole with reference to which its relations and education must be arranged 
 (22, 12. ff.). 
 
 2 In Eth. 8. 9. 5 the State is distinguished from other communities by its 
 aiming at good " for the whole of life," which makes the series of the Politics 
 complete.
 
 198 ARISTOTLE S CONCEPTION 
 
 meaning clear by at once adding " and though the State comes 
 into existence for the sake of mere life, it exists for the sake of 
 good life." For man's end is not reached until his " wellbeing" 
 or "good life" is reached; and it is this which drives him on 
 from stage to stage, and is both the aim and the cause of the 
 whole process of his development. 
 
 This process, therefore, and most of all its completion, the 
 State, is natural. To say that the State secures or is the end 
 of man is with Aristotle not a proof that it is natural : it is 
 simply equivalent to describing it as his nature. For the 
 realisation of the nature of anything is its end : that which a 
 thing is when its process of growth is complete, is its nature 
 (3. 11). It is this that defines a thing, or is its formal cause or 
 essence. It is this also that causes its existence, developing it 
 from a merely potential* condition to its full actuality. Thus 
 if Aristotle's is a doctrine of final causes, it is not so in the 
 ordinary sense. The final cause is not one imposed on the 
 object from without, an end to which the object is a mere 
 means ; it consists in the completed nature of the object itself. 
 In so far as the given tiling is " actual," it is equivalent to its 
 final cause; in so far as it is only partially realised, its final cause 
 or end is immanent in it and moves it to its perfection. Thus 
 the final cause of man is realised when his "nature," in the sense 
 of his mere potentiality, is developed into his " nature," in the 
 sense of his end or good. His final cause is to be himself. As 
 a child he is only potentially what he should be or is destined to 
 be ; and therefore he grows. And so, as a master, a husband, a 
 father, a member of a village, his possibilities are still in various 
 degrees latent, only partially brought into life. It is only in 
 the State that they come into full play, and therefore the State 
 is " natural " to him. 
 
 And this, which is the law of man's being, is the law of the 
 whole world. Throughout the universe this process of the 
 realisation of ends is going on ; and, what is more, these ends 
 or " natures " are not all of equal value, but form a series of 
 grades of excellence. Thus a lower stage of existence is not 
 merely " for its own sake," but it is also a step to the next 
 highest ; and in this sense it is " for the sake of " another, and 
 a means to it. Thus, we may say, to Aristotle all nature is a
 
 OF THE STATE. 199 
 
 striving towards its highest form, and what we have seen in the 
 development of man is true on this wider field. One principle, 
 in its impulse to realise itself, produces those lower forms 
 which are the necessary foundation for the higher, and passes 
 beyond them to a less inadequate development, approaching 
 more and more nearly to the divine actuality in which no im- 
 perfection remains. That man attains only for moments to 
 some likeness of this divine perfection we have already seen ; 
 but that he does so even for moments, and for a longer time 
 can produce those activities of the moral life which are the 
 victory of the divine element in him over his lower nature, is 
 enough to place him at the head of earthly things. In him 
 not as a vegetable nor as an animal, but in so far as his true 
 nature, his better self, is active the highest existence of 
 which the earth is capable is brought into being. In this sense 
 the whole inorganic, vegetable, and animal kingdoms may be 
 said to exist for his sake. And in this final and highest sense 
 the State is natural, and man by nature a " political animal." 
 
 Such, in the barest outline, is Aristotle's answer to the 
 Sophistic question. In substance it might almost be expressed 
 by that startling formula of a modern philosopher, that the 
 object of history is the State. This is not the place to criticise 
 it; but, in common with most other metaphysical theories of 
 politics, it is easily misapprehended. Such theories are often 
 accused of annihilating man's will before a spiritual fatality. 
 It is true that Aristotle's ideas lose all their meaning if we 
 suppose that human action is perfectly capricious, or that it is 
 destitute of an " end," or that this end stands in no relation to 
 the order of things. But they are not inconsistent with any 
 sober notion of freedom. When Aristotle said that the State 
 was by nature, he was not denying that it is due to human 
 thoughts and resolutions, any more than Mr. Carlyle, when he 
 speaks of an improvement in human affairs as an approach to 
 obeying Nature, means that man would be perfect if he were 
 law-abiding like a stone. To hold that there is within certain 
 limits of deviation a fixed development of human nature and 
 is not so 'much as this implied in our calling one change a 
 development or progress, and another the opposite ? is not to 
 hold that this development takes place in as involuntary a
 
 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 manner as does a flower's. And it is those very actions which 
 most further this definite progress that are most free ; since that 
 which acts in them is in the fullest sense ourself, and not a 
 distorted fraction of it. But just because they are not asser- 
 tions of our separate existence, we are apt to speak of such actions 
 as least our own. The same apparent contradiction meets us 
 elsewhere. In the creations of art, or in the experience of 
 religion, that which is the most perfect realisation of man's 
 higher self abolishes this separate feeling ; and so it is with 
 moral action and its concrete products. Thus when we wish 
 to express the freedom of such creations or experiences from 
 our lower selves, or to contrast their absoluteness with the 
 results of our shifting desires, we are apt to use language 
 which takes no notice of the share our will has had in them. 
 It is not the poet who creates, but an inspiration of which he 
 is the mere vehicle; it is not I who act but Christ that 
 dwelleth in me ; and the State or justice are due to nature and 
 not to enactment. When language of this kind is used, there 
 is a temptation to fall under its influence, and to separate 
 what we know to be really identical. It is such a separation 
 that is expressed in the antithesis of </>ucrt9 and I/O/AO?, or in the 
 modern opposition of moral necessity to free-will. But the 
 Greek rose superior to that antithesis ; though he might be 
 puzzled when it was put clearly before Mm, he felt no incom- 
 patibility between the origin of the law of his State in the 
 human will and its absolute validity. And Aristotle is only 
 giving a theoretical justification of the position which he could 
 not justify for himself. 1 
 
 It is perhaps hardly necessary to notice another possible 
 misconception. If Aristotle is not abolishing man's will 
 before the moral order of the world, still less does he mean by 
 the " nature " which produces the State what we mean when 
 we contrast the natural and the spiritual. It is true that he 
 not unfrequently uses " nature " in this lower sense, as in the 
 Ethics, where he is showing that virtue does not come by 
 nature but through a discipline of the will (Efk. 2. 1). In this 
 
 1 On the conception of Law compare K. F. Hermann, Ueber Ge.se.tz Gesetz- 
 ijebung und gesetzgeben.de Gewalt im yriechischen Alterthume.
 
 OF THE STATE. 201 
 
 sense those elements of man's being which he shares Avith the 
 other animals are more natural than his reason and rational 
 desires. In this sense, again, man is by nature " rather a pair- 
 ing animal than a political one" (Etli. 8. 12. 7). And the double 
 use of the word may be charged with some of Aristotle's pre- 
 judices in questions of political economy. But in the doctrine 
 before us nature has exactly the opposite meaning, and that 
 which is most natural in the lower sense is furthest removed 
 from that nature which is man's end. On the other hand, 
 there is an essential connection between the two ; and that 
 connection is teleological. To Aristotle the higher is not so 
 much the result of the lower, as the lower is a preparation and 
 material for the higher. It would be misleading, on his view, 
 to say that man produced the State because he wished to satisfy 
 certain primary needs ; those primary needs and instincts are 
 the stirring in him of that immanent end or idea which is ex- 
 pressed in the State. " The impulse to political society exists by 
 nature in all men" (4. 10); but the Aristotelian view is not 
 that man invents the State to satisfy the impulse ; he has the 
 impulse because his destination is the State. Thus when it is 
 said that Aristotle's is the first " scientific " view of politics, 
 this assertion may be either true or false. If it means that he 
 considered the laws and productions of human nature to be 
 identical with those of physical nature, it possesses no founda- 
 tion. It was not in that sense he asserted the unity of the 
 world, for he never held the strange belief that we are to form 
 
 * o 
 
 an idea of nature in abstraction from her highest product, and 
 then to expect no difference between that highest stage and 
 this truncated " nature." If those who propose to treat the 
 State exactly like the objects of physical science are to find an 
 ally in Aristotle, they must adopt the unity of nature in his 
 sense ; they must admit not merely that man and his works are 
 the result of her lower stages, but that the lower stages are (not 
 in a metaphor, but really) the " potency " of man, and that the 
 evolution is determined by its end. When this is admitted, it 
 will be found that Aristotle is by no means averse to recognis- 
 ing the forms or laws common to man and the lower stages of 
 existence, and that he has little sympathy with that idea of a 
 total breach between the two, in the maintenance of which
 
 202 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 our spiritual interests have often been supposed to be in- 
 volved. 
 
 Putting metaphysical questions aside, we have now to ask, 
 What is Aristotle's ground for regarding the State as man's 
 destination and good ? " Man is by nature a political animal," 
 he tells us ; " and he who, owing to his nature and not to ill 
 fortune, has no State, is either morally bad or something more 
 than a man " (3. 16). And again : " He who cannot form one of 
 a community, or who does not need to do so because he is already 
 sufficient to himself, is no part of a State, and is therefore either 
 a brute beast or a god" (4. 8). Here we have two characteristics 
 of the State noticed, both of which we have met before ; it alone 
 can supply avrapiceta, and in it alone is morality possible. The 
 reason why it is necessary for morality lies in the imperfection 
 of man, and in the fact that the State has might. " As man in 
 his perfection is the best of animals, so when he is separated 
 from law and justice he is the worst of all," the " unholiest, the 
 most savage, and the most abandoned to gluttony and lust. 
 And justice belongs to political society " (4. 12). At the end 
 of the Ethics, again, Aristotle has explained how the State is 
 directly involved in the attainment of morality. There are 
 three ways, he tells us, in which men attain virtue. One of 
 these, our natural endowment, is out of our power. Another, 
 intellectual teaching, has little or no effect except on young 
 men of a generous temper, or those who have been schooled in 
 experience. For those who live by their feelings, obeying the 
 dictates of pleasure and pain, it is useless. It is only by the 
 third means, by habituation, that the impulses which lead 
 away from virtue can be trained, and that men can by degrees 
 acquire that love of the good and hatred of the bad without 
 which mere instruction avails little. For the purpose of this 
 habituation, especially if, as is necessary, it is to be exercised 
 throughout the whole of life, we need an authority which 
 must unite two requisites. It must itself be an expression 
 of reason; and it must have the fullest powers to compel 
 and punish. And this union of right and might Aristotle 
 finds only in the State. But it is not only by its direct action, 
 by its compulsory education and its moral guardianship, that 
 the State contributes to " good living." If we examine those
 
 OF THE STATE. 203 
 
 virtues in the exercise of which this good living consists, we 
 shall find that they all imply social relations or life in com- 
 munity, and one of the most important, that practical wisdom 
 the possession of which implies the presence of the rest (Etli. 
 6. 13. G), has its sphere not only in private life, but also in the 
 ordering of State-affairs : and the Politics adds that the virtue 
 of the best man, the perfect virtue, is equivalent to the virtue 
 of the ruler (119. 22). Thus we find that the individual who 
 realises his chief good or happiness is necessarily a citizen. 
 And the strongest expression which Aristotle has given to this 
 view is to be found in his statement that the individual is 
 posterior to the State, and a part of it. 
 
 To say that the State is prior to the individual means 
 primarily no more than that his end is realised in it. By 
 " prior" Aristotle often means not anterior in time, but prior 
 in idea or, as he sometimes says, in nature. Thus in idea or 
 in nature the end is prior to the means, and the actuality to 
 the potentiality. But in the order of time, or again relatively 
 to our knowledge, the means may, and often do, precede the 
 end, and the potential existence is prior to the actual. In one 
 sense of the word, then, the family may be said to be earlier 
 than the State, and in another sense the opposite is true ; and 
 in this latter meaning Aristotle might say that the individual 
 is " later" than political society. In the present case, however, 
 this dictum has a further meaning. The State is said to precede 
 the individual not merely as the actual precedes the potential, 
 but as a whole precedes its parts. The part is itself only in 
 relation to the whole, has no existence outside it, and is 
 intelligible only in reference to it. It is therefore said to be 
 posterior to it ; for, to take the instance of a living body, " if 
 the whole is destroyed, there will no longer be a foot or a hand, 
 except in name, and as one may call a stone foot a foot ; for 
 everything is defined by its function " (4. 1), and with the 
 dissolution of the body the functions of its members have 
 disappeared. Such is the relation of the individual to the 
 State. 
 
 Language like this at once recalls the current phrase, " the 
 body politic," and the theories which have attempted to make 
 it more than a phrase. Aristotle has nowhere called the State
 
 204 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 an organism, and doubtless he did not explicitly connect that 
 idea with it. But, apart from the present passage, there is a 
 close connection between this idea and his view that political 
 society is natural, and he not unfrequently employs in his 
 consideration of it criteria gained from the study of living 
 beings. The use of such criteria no doubt requires caution, 
 and we are sometimes told that the conception of an organism 
 belongs only to the physical world and becomes a mere meta- 
 phor when applied to human society. But most of the ideas 
 we use in describing spiritual things are derived from the 
 world outside us, and it is not clear that the categories " thing," 
 " collection," " mechanism," and the like, are any less meta- 
 phorically used of a State than the category of life. On 
 the other hand, reasons are not wanting for the view that the 
 latter idea is at least less inadequate than the others ; and, if 
 this is the case, what w^e have to do is only to distinguish 
 in what respects the conception of an organism must differ 
 when it is applied to the animal body and to the political 
 body. It may be interesting, considering the present promi- 
 nence of this conception in English philosophy, to notice some 
 passages in which Aristotle seems implicitly to regard the 
 State as an organism, and then to ask whether his doctrine 
 recognises those characteristics in which it differs from living 
 things. 
 
 That the State, in the sense of the political community, is a 
 totality or composition (avvOea-ts:), admits of no question. Its 
 unity is formed of a multiplicity of parts ; it is a number of 
 citizens (58. 31). But there is more than one kind of compo- 
 sition. For example, a heap of cannon-balls is a whole made 
 up of parts. But here the whole is made up by the mere 
 addition of unit to unit : it is a collection. In such a totality 
 the part does not get its existence or character from its rela- 
 tion to the other parts and to the whole ; it is the same thing 
 in the pile that it was out of it, and has merely had a relation 
 added to it. If the State were a collection of individuals of 
 this kind it would be absurd to say of it that it was prior to 
 its parts ; it would be absurd to compare one of these parts 
 with the hand or foot, which have no existence or function 
 apart from the body to which they belong. A composite body
 
 OF THE STATE. 205 
 
 of which this can be said is not formed by the addition of 
 units, and not even the category of whole and parts is in strict- 
 ness applicable to it. Its " parts " are members ; it is a unity 
 which expresses itself in diverse members, functions and 
 organs, and the connection between these members is not 
 mechanical but organic. Apart from the decisive language 
 already quoted, Aristotle insists in more than one place on the 
 diversity of the parts of the State. He is especially emphatic 
 on this head, because he considers that Plato had neglected it 
 and, in his desire to attain a complete unity of the whole body, 
 had disregarded the necessary " differentiation " of its parts. 
 He had wished to see the principle of the whole clearly realised 
 in every member, and, in Aristotle's view, had failed to per- 
 ceive that this result cannot be obtained by making all the 
 members alike. " The State does not consist simply of a 
 number of men, but of men specifically different from one 
 another ;" these are Aristotle's words, 1 and he at once illus- 
 trates his meaning by referring to the distinction between a 
 State and an alliance. 2 In the latter the mere addition of a 
 quantity of men of the same sort is a direct good ; but in the 
 State, a community in the functions of good life, the unity to 
 be attained must issue from diversity. It is not true, he in- 
 sists, that mere unity is its object : if it were, the State would 
 not exist. For the family is, in this sense, more one than the 
 State, and the individual than the family. 
 
 In other passages the dissimilar parts of the State are re- 
 garded as classes of society, not as mere individuals. These 
 classes are formed of groups of men performing separate " func- 
 tions," or " works," in the whole. In the description of the ideal 
 constitution these works are enumerated as the agricultural food- 
 providing function, the technical or mechanical, the military, 
 the religious, the function of property, and that of government 
 in its two main branches, according as the decisions arrived at 
 
 1 24. 4. The same law which prevents a commercial KOIVUVICL between two 
 men of the same trade (Eth. 5. 5. 9) is active in the political Koivuvia. 
 
 a It will be remembered that Aristotle, in discussing the end of the State, 
 distinguished it from an alliance on the ground that an alliance has no com- 
 mon end, and its law is a mere contract. In other words, an alliance is a 
 collection of homogeneous units, not a unity in diversity.
 
 206 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 concern the common interest or the administration of justice 
 (107 and 108). In another passage (150-152) the list is 
 repeated with some enlargements, and it is pointed out that 
 the reason why different species and sub-species of constitution 
 arise is that, though all these functions or social elements are 
 necessary to a State, the particular forms which each of them 
 takes may vary, and, further, the varieties of each may be com- 
 bined with those of the rest in different ways. To illustrate 
 his meaning Aristotle refers to the manner in which the various 
 kinds of animals are distinguished. There too we find certain 
 functions which are necessary to animal life, such as those of 
 sense, nutrition and motion ; and there are special organs ap- 
 propriated to them. These appear in various forms, and the 
 varieties of one may be found 'in combination with those of 
 another. There are different shapes of the mouth, for example, 
 and various developments of the organs of motion ; and not 
 only these varieties, but the different combinations in which 
 they are found to coexist, may be made the ground for dis- 
 tinguishing species and sub-species of animals. 
 
 From this differentiation of functions it immediately follows 
 that inequality among the parts of the State is regarded not as 
 an imperfection, still less as an injustice, but as natural and 
 necessary. And not merely inequality, but a relation of 
 government ; " for wherever a single common whole is formed 
 out of a number of elements, a ruler and a ruled is to be found, 
 whether these elements are continuous," as in a physical 
 organism, " or discrete," as in the relation of master to slave, or 
 in a political organism ; and an analogue to this relation may 
 be found even in "compositions" not organic (6. 21). But 
 there is a still closer correspondence between the living body 
 and the State in this point. We soon find in reading the 
 Politics that all the " parts " or members of the State are not of 
 equal importance ; that some of them, as for example the agri- 
 cultural and industrial functions, are mere means or necessary 
 conditions to others ; and that only those which are ends are 
 properly called " parts " at all. Such are obviously those which 
 really share in the life of the whole, or realise its end ; in other 
 words, those which are organs of " good living." Accordingly 
 the real parts of the State are, to Aristotle, the citizens alone,
 
 OF THE STATE. 207 
 
 who exercise the functions of government and religion, defend 
 the State and possess its landed property. The rest of the 
 population are mere means, or sine qv.ilus non. If we turn 
 to the account of the animal body, we come upon a precisely 
 similar distinction. There too the whole body and each of its 
 organs exists for the sake of a certain function or "action" 
 (Trpdfys), but only certain parts of the body are regarded as 
 ends. These are distinguished as the specially " organic " 
 parts, and among them are counted the hand and foot, to 
 which at the beginning of the Politics Aristotle compares the 
 citizen of the State. To these organic or heterogeneous parts 
 the rest, which are homogeneous, such as the blood, flesh, 
 fat, bones, and sinews merely serve as constituents or means. 
 " The living body is composed of both, but the homogeneous 
 are for the sake of the heterogeneous." 1 And so the State is 
 composed both of citizens and of a labouring population ; but 
 the one is for the sake of the other. 
 
 In Aristotle's treatment of the State as something which 
 has laws of its growth and health, not reversible by man's will 
 except within certain limits, w r e may trace a further likeness 
 to the conception of an organism. This point of view is 
 especially evident in his remarks, already referred to, on the 
 magnitude of the city. It does not depend simply on the 
 arrangements which the citizens choose to make, how large 
 their State is to be. As a natural existence the State has a 
 definite function, and this function can only be exercised if a 
 certain limit of size is preserved. It is as much subject 
 to this law as other things, animals, plants, or lifeless in- 
 struments (102. 13). A departure from the ideal standard in 
 either direction weakens its power to perform its function, 
 and therefore lessens its] existence. 2 A still further departure 
 destroys its nature altogether, so that it ceases to be a State. If 
 it has too small a population, it ceases to be "self-sufficing;" 
 and if it has too large a one, it no longer admits of order. 
 But self-sufficience (avrapfceia) is its essence ; and order (ra|^<?) 
 is implied in its very existence as a work of nature. 
 
 1 Part. an. ii. 1 ; cf., in particular, 646 b 10. 
 
 2 Hence, to Aristotle, a great State does not mean a large one, but one 
 which vigorously exercises its function.
 
 2o8 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 The same point of view is apparent where Aristotle is 
 treating of the necessary equilibrium of the various elements of 
 society. It is only within certain bounds that this equilibrium 
 will bear disturbance. The disproportionate development of 
 one social function is hostile to the wellbeing of the whole, 
 and may destroy the constitution (212. 1 ff . ; 201. 2). The 
 illustration is again taken from the living body. " A body is 
 composed of parts, and they ought to grow proportionally, that 
 its symmetry may be preserved; otherwise it perishes;" as it 
 certainly would, if " the foot were six feet long and the rest of 
 the body only two spans." So it is with the State. And as 
 again a certain kind of disproportionate growth may result in 
 one animal form actually passing into another, so one consti- 
 tution may from the same cause pass into another, and the 
 whole nature of the State be therefore changed (197. 30). 
 The same idea lies at the root of Aristotle's advice to those 
 who wish to preserve either of the two principal " perverted " 
 forms of government, oligarchy or democracy. It is the 
 essence of these constitutions that they represent the pre- 
 ponderance of one social element in the State, whether it be 
 that of the few rich or the many poor, and that this class rules 
 not for the common good but in its own interest. Even so 
 perverted a State has a vital principle of its own. But this 
 principle will not bear straining too far ; and Aristotle points 
 out that the worst friends of such constitutions are those who 
 wish to develop their characteristics to the uttermost. " Many 
 of those things that are counted democratic destroy demo- 
 cracies ;" and the same is true of oligarchies. The governing 
 class cannot really get on without the opposite element which 
 it strives to suppress, and therefore the pursuance of its main 
 principle beyond a certain point ends in its self-annihilation. 
 "A nose," as Aristotle drily tells us, "may depart from the 
 ideal straightness and tend to be either aquiline or snub, and 
 yet it may still be beautiful and have a charm for the eyes ; 
 but if an artist were to push the deviation to excess, first of all 
 the feature would lose its due measure of size, and at last it 
 would not look like a nose at all" (214. 26). The principle of 
 measure or the mean (TO peaov) rules the State, as it does the 
 moral character of the individual.
 
 OF THE STATE. 209 
 
 ~\Ve may thus reach an important conclusion. That end of 
 the State which is described as good living or happiness is also 
 described as the common interest or good (TO Koivfi crv^epov, 
 68. 9), that noble living (/caXw? ffiv) in which each shares 
 according to his ability. In any whole that is " prior " to its 
 parts, in any organism, there is an identity between the general 
 welfare and the particular welfare of each part. It is in the 
 healthy and harmonious development of its organs or functions 
 that the health of the whole body lies, and the interest of the 
 State is nothing but that of its citizens. And conversely, there 
 is no part which really has a separate interest ; for its essence 
 and good lie in its function, and this is a function of the 
 whole body. Thus if it appears to have a private interest 
 which is thwarted by its membership in a system and sacri- 
 ficed to that system, this appearance must be considered a 
 delusion. The disproportionate growth of a single organ, for 
 example, is its real misfortune ; for its true nature is not 
 developed, and it injures the whole on which its own health 
 depends. And in the same way we may say that the depend- 
 ence of one member on the rest is not a sign of bondage but 
 its real liberty, if liberty means " self-sufficiency ;" and the 
 growing independence of the parts is equivalent to the loosen- 
 ing of that bond which is the life of the organism and only 
 disappears in its decay. 
 
 Such are some of the points in which Aristotle seems to 
 find the characteristics of animal life in the body politic. It 
 is clear that they would not justify us in calling his conception 
 of it organic; but perhaps they amount to something more 
 than analogies, and they give a fuller meaning to his descrip- 
 tion of the State as a natural existence with laws of its own. 
 If, however, we are to retain this idea at all, it is essential to 
 realise how vitally a political organism differs from a merely 
 physical one ; and a few words will suffice to show that 
 Aristotle's view does not obscure the distinction between the 
 two. 1 
 
 1 In Mot. an. 703 a 29 there is an interesting comparison of the animal 
 body to a State, and the fact that the "order" of the latter is due to the 
 human will is pointed out. But it is doubtful whether this treatise is 
 genuine. 
 

 
 210 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 " That man is a political animal in a higher sense than the 
 bee or any other gregarious creature, is clear. For nature, as 
 we say, makes nothing in vain ; and man is the only living 
 thing that possesses rational speech (\6yos). A mere voice 
 (<$>u>vri) serves to signify pleasure and pain, and therefore it is 
 possessed by the other animals as well as by man ; for their 
 nature goes so far that they feel pain and pleasure, and signify 
 these feelings to each other. But language has for its office to 
 express what is helpful and hurtful, and therefore also what is 
 right and wrong (TO Bi/caiov teal TO aSt/cov). For this is peculiar 
 to man, as compared with the other animals, that he alone has a 
 perception of good and evil and of right and wrong. And it is 
 community in good and right that constitutes a family and a 
 State" (3. 20). Thus, in modern language, the State is more 
 than an organism ; it is a moral organism. The soul of man is 
 not a mere principle of growth and nutrition, like that of 
 plants. Its activity is not confined to sense and the desires 
 which depend on sense, like that of the lower animals. It is 
 intelligence and rational will. And therefore man not only 
 has a law of his life, but is capable of knowing the law of his 
 life : lie not only knows it, but is capable of living by it. In 
 him therefore appears the separation of what is and what 
 might be, of good and evil, of right and wrong; in a word, 
 morality. And this morality is not something which belongs 
 to each man's private life. It is community in it which con- 
 stitutes the State or political organism. But the consciousness 
 of this organism, and therefore its morality, can exist nowhere 
 but in its members. The principle of the whole is present 
 in the parts. Its reason and morality are theirs ; its end is 
 theirs ; it is in them that it feels, suffers and enjoys. And if 
 the converse is not true, if the end of any particular member 
 seems to be something else than the end of the whole, it is 
 because this single function attempts to deny the relation in 
 which it stands, and must stand, to the whole. 
 
 From what has been already said, it will be evident that 
 Aristotle is in no danger of obliterating these distinctions. 
 The citizen is related to the State as the hand is to the whole 
 body. But the end of the State is happiness or noble action ; 
 the State itself is community in this good life, or in the right
 
 OF THE STATE. 211 
 
 which language only can express. If the whole then is 
 rational and moral, its highest functions must be rational and 
 moral. But these highest functions are those of its mem- 
 bers ; and for that very reason those of its parts which fulfil 
 no such function are not, properly speaking, members of it, 
 but merely necessary conditions of its life. For the same 
 reason, however, its true " parts " necessarily attain their 
 own ends in attaining the end of the whole. " Happiness is 
 not a conception like that of evenness in number. That may 
 be predicated of the whole number" (say 10) "without being 
 predicated of its component parts " (say 3 and 7) ; " but this 
 is impossible with happiness" (32. 27). On the other hand, 
 the welfare of the citizen is not merely bound up with that 
 of the whole, but he is capable of realising this, and of either 
 devoting himself to the State or making his supposed private 
 advantage his end. His relation to the State is not, like that of 
 the hand to the body, one simply of fact, but also one of duty. 
 " No citizen ought to think that he is his own, but all that 
 they are the State's" (130. 15). And Aristotle does not sup- 
 pose that, left to himself, a man is likely to identify his good 
 with that of the whole organism in the manner of a healthy 
 animal organ. It is just because he is a 
 
 ' ' fool whose sense 
 No more can feel but his own wringing," 
 
 that the education of the State and the arm of the law are 
 required, to convert him from a life " according to passion " to 
 one of true citizenship and participation in happiness. 
 
 The functions of the body politic, then, are moral functions ; 
 and the members which exercise these functions are conse- 
 quently moral agents. It must be remembered, lastly, that the 
 virtue or happiness which is the end of State and citizen alike, 
 is not something distinct from the direct duties of citizenship, 
 but that these duties themselves play a large part in it. A 
 man is not a good citizen in order that he may gain something 
 by it. Happiness is the exercise of "virtue." In being brave 
 and self-controlled and liberal a man is attaining happiness, 
 and at the same time showing the virtues of citizenship. But 
 there are excellencies of a more commanding kind than these.
 
 212 ARISTOTLE 'S CONCEPTION 
 
 As we have already seen, the crowning talent of moral wisdom, 
 with the possession of which all the virtues are given, has its 
 sphere no less in affairs of State than in a man's own house- 
 hold. It is the virtue of government, the possession of which 
 makes a " good citizen " and a " good man " equivalent terms, 
 while the citizen-virtues of obedience would by themselves not 
 amount to perfect goodness. The citizen must be free 
 from the mere wants of life that he may have time for 
 politics no less than for philosophy ; for those are the two 
 main forms of happiness. So far then from the growth or 
 action of the political organism being merely natural, they 
 are to be consciously guided by the most developed char- 
 acter and wisdom. It is as though a plant should be 
 aware of the conditions on which its perfect growth depends, 
 and, making this perfect growth its object, should consciously 
 attempt to realise those conditions. Whether this conscious 
 guidance is a characteristic of the State which renders the con- 
 ception of an organism radically inapplicable to it, we need not 
 stop to dispute. It certainly is at first sight more in accord- 
 ance with our common view of government as a mechanism ; 
 and to Aristotle it suggests the metaphor of the "ship of State" 
 rather than that of the " body politic." He compares the 
 citizens to sailors (63. 9), and (by implication) the citizen as 
 ruler to the steersman (68. 31). And there is a psychological 
 fitness in the comparison. For reason, which acts in govern- 
 ment, is not in his view connected with the human organism 
 in the same way as the inferior " faculties ;" and in the case of 
 this psychical " part," he would have answered in the affirmative 
 the question raised in de Anima (2. 1. 11), whether the soul is 
 related to the body as " a sailor to his boat." 
 
 In any great political theory the comprehension of one 
 main idea makes the rest comparatively obvious. The remain- 
 ing conclusions on which our space allows us to touch, follow 
 naturally from the general ideas already sketched, and will 
 serve to give them a more substantial shape. With this 
 purpose we may rapidly review Aristotle's teaching on the 
 subjects of citizenship, State- education, the various forms of
 
 OF THE STATE. 213 
 
 government, the meaning of political justice and political 
 rights. 
 
 Aristotle's view of the nature of citizenship has been 
 already indicated ; but it can hardly fail to be misunderstood 
 unless we take into account his judgment as to the political 
 position of the labouring classes. From the conception of the 
 State two main results directly follow : first, that citizenship can 
 mean nothing less than the right or duty of exercising political 
 functions ; and, secondly, that this exercise is, in the true 
 State, the activity of those higher virtues which make the good 
 citizen identical with the good man. For practical purposes it 
 may be, though it is not always, true to say that a citizen is 
 one whose father and mother were both citizens. But this is a 
 mere external mark, and does not tell us in what citizenship 
 consists. In what does it consist ? JSTot in the mere posses- 
 sion of civil rights. Just as the State is not merely a com- 
 munity in territory or in the legal protection of person and 
 property, so a citizen does not mean one who resides in a 
 certain city and can be sued in its law-courts. These are not 
 functions of the State, and do not involve participation in its 
 end. If the citizen is to be really a part of the State, he must 
 live its life ; and that in the concrete means that he must 
 govern. Thus citizenship may be defined as " ruling and being 
 ruled," and a citizen as one who shares, or has the right to 
 share, in government, deliberative, executive and judicial. In 
 so doing he uses not only the virtues of obedience, not only 
 the common moral virtues, but also the excellencies of moral 
 wisdom and command. His life is pre-eminently one of 
 apery. 
 
 But the brain cannot think unless the heart beats ; and 
 society cannot exert its highest powers when its lowest needs 
 are unsatisfied. The whole must exist before it can exist well ; 
 and it cannot exist well if the organs whose office is to think 
 have to attend to mere living. A life of culture and political 
 aperr) implies freedom in him who lives it from the necessity of 
 looking after these lower wants (66. 22). It implies what Aris- 
 totle calls "leisure," and this leisure must be supported on 
 some one's labour. The life of labour is a mere means to the 
 higher life. It is not a participation in the State-life, but a con-
 
 214 ARISTOTLE S CONCEPTION 
 
 dition of it, a sine qua non. It does not do what is noble, but 
 provides what is necessary. It might produce a joint-stock 
 company, but not a State. It creates mere material prosperity, 
 and " no class has a share in the State which is not a producer 
 of virtue" (100. 21). 
 
 The result of this hard and fast distinction is obvious. So 
 far as aperrj is concerned, it makes no great difference whether 
 the labourer is a slave or a free man. " Those who provide 
 necessaries for an individual are slaves, and those who provide 
 them for society are handicraftsmen and day-labourers" (66. 24 ; 
 cf. 21. 32). And the labouring class includes not only peasants, 
 but all fidvavaoi, a designation w T hich covers artisans, professional 
 singers and artists, and no doubt all persons engaged in trade. 
 It is against fiavava-ia that the reproach of ignobleness is 
 especially directed ; and the word, like our " mechanical," has 
 an ethical significance. " That," says Aristotle, " must be con- 
 sidered a mechanical practice or art or subject of study, which 
 makes the body or the soul or the intellect of free men useless 
 for the activities of virtue" (131. 7). Bavava-la deforms the 
 body (18. 8), and renders it unfit for military and political duties 
 (140. 15). It accustoms a man's mind to low ideas, and absorbs 
 him in the pursuit of the mere means of life. The (3dvavcros 
 seeks the satisfaction of other people's wishes, and not the im- 
 provement of his own character; and this is the mark of slavery. 
 It is for this reason that the occupation of the professional 
 musician is considered unworthy of a man (136. 18). He treats 
 his art " technically " or professionally, practises " amazing and 
 brilliant pieces" (140. 19), has to gratify an audience often of 
 vulgar tastes, and therefore practises a kind of day-labour 
 (141. 25). 1 If citizenship then means essentially the practice of 
 
 x lt will be remembered that in Greece not only professional performers 
 but even original artists were considered ' ' mechanical. " It is inconceivable 
 that Aristotle, with his high view of art, should have considered his account 
 of fiavavaia. applicable to Phidias ; but probably the following typically antique 
 passage would not have sounded so strange to him as it does to modern ears : 
 "If a man applies himself to servile or mechanical employments, his industry 
 in those things is a proof of his inattention to nobler studies. No young man 
 of noble birth or liberal sentiments, from seeing the Jupiter at Pisa, would 
 desire to be Phidias, or, from the sight of the Juno at Argos, to be Poly- 
 cletus ; orAnacreon, or Philemon, or Archilochus, though delighted with their 
 poems." Plutarch's Life of Pericles (Langhorne's translation).
 
 OF THE STATE. 215 
 
 dperi], there can be no question for Aristotle as to the admission 
 of the ftdvava-oi to political rights. In such perverted constitu- 
 tions as " democracy " they might find a place, as they actually 
 did; for the principle of that constitution is not the true principle 
 of the State. And in an oligarchy, the " perversion " which sub- 
 stitutes wealth for political virtue, though a day-labourer could 
 hardly attain the property- qualification necessary for citizen- 
 ship, a ftdvavaos might (07. 2). Accordingly at Thebes, we are 
 told, a law was in force that a man could not take part in 
 government until ten years after his retirement from the market. 
 But in any true State, in any constitution in which " the honours 
 of office go by excellence or merit," it is impossible that the 
 ftdvavcros should be a citizen. For his life is " ignoble and 
 opposed to dperij" (66. 31 ; 108. 32). 
 
 Aristotle's view is only the reproduction of current Greek 
 ideas. At first sight it is so repulsive to us that we are tempted 
 to condemn it wholesale. But it should be observed that it is 
 due not only to a contempt of labour connected with the institu- 
 tion of slavery, but also to the height of the ideal with which 
 the labouring life is compared. In this point it contrasts 
 favourably with the modern upper-class sentiment which it 
 seems at first to resemble. And it is worth while to ask where 
 its falsity lies. 
 
 If we grant Aristotle's premises, no fault can be found with 
 his exclusion of the labouring classes from political rights : their 
 admission would have been a mere inconsistency. It is simply 
 true that, as a body, they could not have possessed the qualities 
 he demands in the citizen, even if they had found the leisure 
 for military, political, and judicial duties. We have given up 
 the idea of professedly apportioning shares in government 
 according to merit, virtue, or culture (words which Aristotle 
 uses interchangeably in this connection) ; all that we hope for is 
 that, through a political machinery which assigns no superior 
 rights to these qualities, they may yet find their way to the 
 helm. But if we did accept Aristotle's principle in the matter, 
 we should certainly arrive at his conclusion, and should wish to 
 exclude from the suffrage the great majority of those who possess 
 it. Nor again is the idea that this culture depends upon lower 
 labour false. It is a fact which, however painful, cannot be too
 
 216 ARISTOTLE 'S CONCEPTION 
 
 clearly recognised, that the existence of those excellencies in 
 which Aristotle finds the end of life and the virtues of the 
 citizen, rests upon a mass of mere work as its necessary con- 
 dition. And is there any modern society which can plume 
 itself on the advances it has made in uniting these two elements, 
 the end and the means, in the same persons or classes ? If no.t, 
 we must admit that, so far, Aristotle's view is not open to 
 reproach. Nor, lastly, will any honest observer deny that there 
 is a moral ftavava-ta which besets some of the occupations 
 included under that term. 
 
 What is disputable in Aristotle's view is the too exalted 
 idea of citizenship, an idea which, with the increase in the size 
 of States, has ceased to be even plausible. What is psychologi- 
 cally untrue is the pre-eminence given to intellect in the con- 
 ception of man's end, and the hard and fast line drawn between 
 the virtues of government and those of obedience. What is 
 morally repulsive is the consequent identification of the end 
 and means of life with two separate portions of the community, 
 and the feeling that moral lowness has anything to do with 
 labour, as such, or with a professional occupation. Modern 
 civilisation, in its best aspects, tends to unite what is here 
 separated. The intellectual excellencies themselves have be- 
 come the basis of professions. Payment for performing the 
 duties of government, in Greek democracy the symptom of 
 decay, is the recognised rule of modern States, so far as adminis- 
 tration is concerned. Clergymen, artists, poets, authors, philo- 
 sophers receive, or may receive, wages for their work, and it is 
 not supposed that they necessarily work with a view to their 
 wages. We anxiously avoid even the semblance of contempt 
 for the labouring classes ; not only out of deference to their 
 political power, but from a conviction that there is no shame in 
 labour. It is felt that work, be it what it will, may be done in 
 such a spirit that moral character may be developed by it ; and 
 that in this character, in family affection, and in religion a 
 happiness is attainable which contradicts the idea that in the 
 mechanical life there can be no production of " virtue," and 
 therefore nothing to make life worth having. Some of our 
 language would even imply that mere labour was the end of life, 
 and not a means to something beyond itself; but this piece of
 
 OF THE STATE. 217 
 
 cant is implicitly contradicted by efforts to educate the classes 
 engaged in manual work, and to put suitable " occupations of 
 leisure " within their power. 
 
 But it is easy to make too much of these differences, and to 
 imagine a correspondence between the facts of modern society 
 and its best tendencies which does not really exist. Prejudices, 
 resting on old custom and containing half a truth, repose com- 
 fortably in our minds side by side with ideas which, if we were 
 thoroughly awake, would destroy them. Aristotle himself has 
 laid down with the greatest clearness that even the most menial 
 services need not be ignoble, and that the slavishness of a pur- 
 suit lies not in the things that are done, but in the spirit in 
 which they are done, and in their object. And for this reason 
 he would have some of such services performed by the youthful 
 citizens (119. 17; 131. 16). And yet he seems hardly to ask 
 himself whether work which is rewarded in money may not be 
 done for its own sake ; and, with ideas of art hardly less exalted 
 than Plato's, he utters no word of protest against the identifica- 
 tion of the artist with the fidvavaos. Nor, again, can it be said 
 that these old prejudices are wanting in vitality at the present 
 day. If a good many " yomig men of liberal sentiments" would 
 so far differ from Plutarch that they would desire rather to be 
 Shakespeare than Pericles, most of their relations, and perhaps 
 all their mothers, would take quite another view ; and they 
 themselves might not all persist in an ambition which would 
 involve their ceasing to be " gentlemen " and becoming common 
 actors. One of the wisest of Englishmen, when he heard a 
 compliment to the Queen, which Garrick had introduced into a 
 play, characterised as " mean and gross flattery," asked " (rising 
 into warmth) : How is it mean in a player a showman, a 
 fellow who exhibits himself for a shilling, to flatter his Queen ? " l 
 Yet Garrick was the greatest actor of the day, and Johnson's per- 
 sonal friend. Again, what does the respectable father of a family 
 think of the boy who turns painter or musician ? What does the 
 respectable man of learning think of him ? If we do not know 
 from experience how " society " looks upon artists, Thackeray 
 will tell us ; what it thinks of " persons in trade," not to speak 
 
 1 Boswell's Life of Johnson, vol. ii. p. 215 (edition of 1824 in 4 vols.).
 
 218 ARISTOTLE S CONCEPTION 
 
 of the "lower orders," no one can help knowing. But there 
 is a difference between this sentiment and Aristotle's. If he 
 shares our prejudice, he does not share our ideal. The leisure 
 which he thought indispensable for a citizen was not leisure to 
 be stupid, idle, or busy only in amusement. The notion that 
 that was the end to which a thousand lives of toil were a mere 
 means would have seemed an astounding one to him. The 
 strenuous exercise of the highest powers of body and mind in 
 defending and governing the State, and in striving to quicken 
 the divine reason in the soul, this is the kind of " high life " 
 with which fiavava-ia is contrasted, and the citizenship of which 
 it is declared incapable. 
 
 If this life is man's personal ideal, there can be little ques- 
 tion of the mode in which it is to be approached. Without 
 the gifts of nature not much can be done, and Aristotle hardly 
 seems to find the happy mixture of spirit and intelligence in any 
 race except the Greek (105. 25). But, given the good material, 
 the rest is the work of Education. And Aristotle uses this 
 word in its strict sense. The natural effects of climate, air, 
 water, and the like, are important (112. 23 ff.). The unconscious 
 influence of a moral atmosphere can do much. The direct 
 action of the Legislature in arranging institutions has its effect. 
 But it is not communism which will cure the moral diseases 
 of society, but education (30. 30 ; 38. 6) : and when he is 
 describing the ideal city Aristotle's interest in outward arrange- 
 ments soon flags. He turns abruptly to the question, How 
 shall we make our citizens good men ? and answers, By 
 education. 
 
 From the very beginning the child must be definitely 
 trained and guided ; and this training has to follow its natural 
 development. Care can be taken of the body before the mind 
 is active, and the desires are in full energy long before the intel- 
 lect. It is in this early time that the habituation, on which 
 Aristotle lays so much stress, is possible. Pleasure and pain 
 rule the first years of the soul, and the problem of education is 
 to attach these feelings to the right objects; not to teach the 
 reasons of good and evil, but to nurture a love of the one and a 
 hatred of the other. If this has not been done, the cultivation
 
 OF THE STATE. 219 
 
 of the intellect will have little moral result ; and, if it lias been 
 done, reason will afterwards appeal not to a chaos of passions, 
 but to emotions which have taken her own order and colour, 
 and to habits which form a body pliant to her will. A nature 
 which has gone through such a training has a chance of reach- 
 ing that energy of the soul which is the main constituent of 
 happiness. 
 
 To Aristotle then the fundamental problem of politics is one 
 of education. And to him the practical conclusions are in- 
 evitable. Education must ~be public and compulsory. Aristotle 
 is riot blind to the advantages of private instruction, the system 
 followed in most of the Greek States (129. 26). It has the 
 same advantages which government by a person possesses over 
 government by a fixed law ; it can adapt itself to individual 
 differences. But he cannot admit that the State should give 
 up the training of its citizens. That it attended to it, in how- 
 ever narrow a spirit, at Sparta and Crete, was one of the chief 
 claims of those communities to honour. Not only does the 
 State possess a conception of the end which training is to 
 attain, but it, and it alone, has power to enforce this training 
 on unwilling subjects ; and, owing to its impersonal character 
 the compulsion it exercises is comparatively inoffensive (Eth. 10. 
 9. 12). Nor, even if it were possible, would it be right for the 
 State to leave this duty to that private enterprise which means 
 private opinion. It has an end and a moral character exactly 
 as an individual has, and its responsibility is like his (130. 19). 
 If the object it sets before it is not realised in the persons of 
 its citizens, it is not realised at all. And this object is not 
 something indefinite, but a fixed type of character, or ^#09. 
 The failure to produce it is the failure of the State, and may be 
 its danger ; for the rjdos is that living spirit which keeps the 
 political body healthy and united. " The greatest of all securi- 
 ties for the permanence of constitutions is what all men now 
 neglect, an education in accordance with trie constitution," 
 and the best laws in the world are of no avail if men are 
 not educated in the spirit of the State (215. 27; cf. 78. 7; 
 146.17). 
 
 And this is not all. The same reasoning leads Aristotle to 
 the further conclusion that education must be uniform and
 
 220 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 universal. The end of the whole State is one (130. 10), and 
 its spirit must be one. Some of the imperfect constitutions 
 might, and naturally would, depart from this rule ; for in them 
 the rulers and the ruled form two distinct classes, and would 
 consequently require a different training. But in the true 
 State every citizen at some period of his life takes part in 
 government, and a common culture is the ideal to be sought. 
 Whatever departure from this uniformity might be admitted 
 would be due to that insistance on the absolute universality of 
 education which is one of the most striking features of Aristotle's 
 doctrine. The State is not to content itself with the training 
 of its active citizens. That of its women is hardly less im- 
 portant. It was a fatal error in the Spartan constitution that 
 it educated its men and left its women uncared for, a negli- 
 gence which bitterly avenged itself in the effect they produced 
 on the moral character of the whole State (45. 11). For the 
 women "form half the free population" (22. 23), and where 
 their condition is not what it should be, " half the State 
 must be considered uucared for by the law." Doubtless, 
 if Aristotle's promise to deal with this subject were fulfilled in 
 the book, as we possess it, we should find that he gave very 
 different regulations for the training of the two sexes ; but 
 the same law of conformity to the constitution is insisted on 
 for both. 
 
 Nor can the State afford to relax its care with the manhood 
 of its pupil. Its education, in the wider sense of the word, 
 ought to last through life (Eth. 10. 9. 9; cf. 115. 11 ff. ; 128. 
 22). For the mass of men, at least in ordinary States, can 
 hardly be expected to live by the light of their own reason. 
 Under the inferior forms of government it is of so great im- 
 portance that men should live in accordance with the estab- 
 lished constitution, that special officials ought to watch and 
 control the lives of disaffected persons (212. 10) ; and the best 
 of existing governments, we are told, have functionaries to 
 guard the conduct of women (174. 21). If we turn from the 
 adult years of the citizen to his very birth, we find the same 
 point of view. If the contribution of nature to man's good 
 lies in part beyond our power, it is only in part that it does so. 
 And with a view to the production of the best material for
 
 OF THE STATE. 
 
 education the whole arrangements of marriage are placed under 
 the absolute control of government. It is at such points as 
 these that we feel farthest removed from Greek ideas, and are 
 surest of our progress. But there is at least nothing unworthy 
 in the spirit which dictates such interferences with private life. 
 We feel all the moral intensity as well as all the harshness of 
 the ideal statesman (Etli. 1. 13. 2) in the rebuke with which 
 Aristotle meets those who wish to live " after their own heart's 
 desire." " But this is base : for one ought not to think it 
 slavery to live in the spirit of the constitution" (216. 18) ; and, 
 " No man ought to think that he is his own, but all that they 
 are the State's" (130. 15). 
 
 Of the education which seemed to Aristotle ideal we have 
 only a fragmentary sketch. Its spirit may be conjectured from 
 the end at which it aims, but any account of it would lead us 
 beyond our immediate subject. If we turn now to the perfect 
 city for which this education is intended, a glance at the very 
 scanty account of its political organisation will enable us to 
 understand the imperfections of the other forms of govern- 
 ment. 
 
 All the citizens of the ideal State have received the same 
 education ; they are " free and equal." Their education was 
 designed to fit them not only for obedience, but also for govern- 
 ment, and for the second by means of the first. Of the virtue 
 implied in this function there is one indispensable condition, 
 freedom from the necessity of providing the means of life. 
 Accordingly the property of the community is in the hands of 
 the citizens ; and though they ought to some extent to permit 
 a common use of it, they hold it as their own, and not in 
 common. 1 Under these conditions what distribution of public 
 rights or duties does justice demand ? In virtue of the 
 equality of the citizens, it demands that all shall share in 
 civic rights. Of these functions there are two main classes, 
 
 1 One is tempted to suppose that by "property" is meant landed pro- 
 perty ; since the fidvawoi, who are not citizens, might possess wealth of 
 another kind. But it is possible that Aristotle, who dislikes trade and 
 manufactures, may have intended his State to be almost entirely agricultural. 
 And the agricultural labourers would not be free men (112. 13).
 
 ARISTOTLE S CONCEPTION 
 
 military and political; and accordingly every one has to take 
 part in each. But the equality of the citizens is not identity ; 
 they are unlike as well as like ; and in the necessary distinc- 
 tion which nature makes between them Aristotle finds the 
 ground for a difference in rights or duties. Various functions 
 demand various capacities, and these capacities belong roughly 
 to separate periods of man's life. Energy or force (SzW/u?) is 
 the gift of youth, and wisdom (<f)p6vna-is) of riper years. In 
 the ideal State, then, the citizen in his earlier manhood will 
 perform the military duties, and will only take part in govern- 
 ment when they are completed. The remaining function of 
 citizenship, the care of religious worship, is assigned to those 
 advanced years which relieve men from more active services. 
 We shall see that, as in this distribution of work, so in other 
 respects the ideal State is the image of that perfect justice 
 which in Aristotle goes by a name afterwards applied to a very 
 different conception natural right. 
 
 That every constitution existing in Aristotle's time answered 
 to his idea of the State no one could suppose. Not one fully 
 corresponded to it, and the majority fell far short of it. In 
 this, as in every other work of nature, there are variations and 
 defects. Nature, as Aristotle mythologically says, aims at the 
 best, but she cannot always attain it (cf. 7. 27 ; 9. 18). Her 
 creation is arrested at some point, or it develops itself awry. 
 Thus men do not always reach the stage of political society, 
 and when they do they often form imperfect or even " perverted " 
 States. They mistake the true end, or else they do not take the 
 right means to reach it (116. 8). Yet the mere beginnings, or 
 the deformed growths, are better than nothing. " Man is by 
 nature so political an animal that, even when men need no 
 assistance from each other, they none the less desire to live 
 together ;" and though the common good of a noble life is in 
 the highest degree their end, yet " they come together for the 
 sake of mere life, and form political communities even for it 
 alone. For perhaps it has something of the noble iait " (68. 7). 
 Thus subordinate ends which fall short of man's true develop- 
 ment are raised into ultimate ones, and form the bases or 
 fundamental principles (vTrotfecret?) of imperfect constitutions. 
 On the "hypothesis" of we"alth arises what Aristotle calls
 
 OF THE STATE. 223 
 
 oligarchy, on that of mere freedom what he calls democracy. 
 As we have seen, neither wealth nor freedom is the end for 
 which the State exists ; but both are necessary to that end. 
 Hence at once the existence and the weakness of such forms of 
 government. They are States, and so far good ; and of neither 
 of them does Aristotle use the language he applies to tyranny, 
 which takes the pleasure of the tyrant for its object. On the 
 other hand, in common with tyranny, they are perversions of 
 the true idea, and therefore contrary to nature (92. 1). Each 
 of them, if it pursues its " hypothesis " to the legitimate conclu- 
 sion, destroys itself, whereas the true end cannot be pursued to 
 excess. With every step in its development the chance of 
 permanence for the constitution decreases ; the extreme forms 
 live a hazardous life, and, like diseased organisms, perish of 
 trifling ailments (187. 25). The reason is that they diverge 
 from the idea of the State so far, they realise it so little, 
 as hardly to be States at all. And we shall find that this is 
 equivalent to saying that they pursue a false end, that they 
 pervert justice, and that their government is selfish arid not 
 public. 
 
 When Aristotle thus distinguishes between an ideal State 
 and various perversions of it, he is far from supposing that the 
 existence of bad forms of government is avoidable. He does 
 not dream of framing an ideal scheme of government, the 
 adoption of which would turn a misshapen State into the image 
 of his idea. To him the constitution (troXtreia, a word which 
 has a wider sense than its English equivalent) is inseparable 
 from the nature of the people who live under it as inseparable 
 as any organisation is from the matter organised in it. It is the 
 " order " of the citizens (rat9, 58. 28). It is the " form " of the 
 State, and constitutes its identity (62. 22 ff.) : and it is often 
 spoken of as the State itself. But it is possible, and even 
 necessary for our purpose, to draw a distinction between the 
 two. To ask why an imperfect State exists is to enter at once 
 on a metaphysical question, and comes at last to the problem 
 of the existence of evil. But there is a more obvious meaning 
 in the inquiry why an imperfect constitution exists, although 
 this inquiry must ultimately merge in the other. It exists 
 because it is the natural outcome of a given social condition.
 
 224 ARISTOTLES CONCEPTION 
 
 Given a certain material, a population of a certain kind and in 
 a definite degree of civilisation, and there is a form or order 
 naturally fitted for it ; and no other order, however superior 
 it would be in better circumstances, is better for it. This 
 fact Aristotle clearly recognises. There are populations, he tells 
 us, naturally adapted to monarchy, aristocracy, and a constitu- 
 tional republic (91. 31 ff.) ; and though he adds that all the 
 perversions are unnatural, he does not mean by this that they 
 do not naturally arise under the appropriate social conditions : 
 on the contrary, this is true not only of oligarchy or democracy, 
 but of the various sub-species of those forms (166. 14 ff. ; 178. 
 22 ff.). Accordingly, when he is describing his own ideal State, 
 Aristotle does not confine himself to the arrangements of 
 government. He realises that, if his sketch is to have any 
 verisimilitude, he must imagine also the population for which 
 the constitution is intended, and even the physical conditions 
 under which it lives. In other words, he describes an ideal 
 State, and not merely an ideal constitution. In the same way 
 he recognises that the approaches which can be made to the 
 constitution of this ideal are very various in degree, and that it 
 is essential for a political theorist to consider all of them. 
 False simplicity he regards as the besetting sin of such theorists. 
 Some of them investigate nothing but the one best constitution, 
 in which things we wish for, and cannot insure, play so large a 
 part ; others eulogise a single existing form, like the Spartan, 
 and sweep all the rest out of sight. But it is necessary, 
 Aristotle points out, not only to know what we wish for and to 
 take care not to want impossibilities (34. 1), but also to find out 
 what constitution suits any given population ; what is the best 
 constitution that can be framed on a given " hypothesis ; " what 
 form is the highest attainable by an average State ; and, instead 
 of supposing that there is one oligarchy and one democracy, to 
 study all the varieties of each (145 and 146). On the other 
 hand, from the fact that for any given people that constitution 
 is best which is fit for it, Aristotle does not draw the hasty 
 inference that all constitutions stand on a level. If we consider 
 that people which is fitted for free institutions more civilised 
 than that which is fitted for despotism, we implicitly assert that 
 one form of government is also superior to the other. This is
 
 OF THE STATE. 225 
 
 the language which Aristotle commonly adopts : nor is there 
 any objection to it, so long as we bear in mind, as he invariably 
 does, that the constitution is the form of the State, and, con- 
 sidered apart from the State, is an abstraction. 
 
 Aristotle's main division of the forms of government is into 
 six (69. 19 ff.). Of these three are good or right, and of each 
 of the three there is a perverted form (vrape/c/iJacri?). The first 
 set consists of Kingdom, Aristocracy, and Republic (iro\i,Teia) ; 
 the second of Tyranny, Oligarchy, and Democracy. And, accord- 
 ing to some passages, the first three are placed in a descending 
 order of goodness, and the second three in a descending order 
 of badness, so that the corruption of the best (kingdom) is 
 the worst (tyranny). But this division, probably suggested by 
 Plato's Statesman, undergoes serious modifications in the course 
 of the work. The historical forms of kingdom and aristocracy 
 receive slight attention, mainly because in Aristotle's time they 
 were of little importance. On the other hand, an ideal State, 
 not identical with any of these historical forms, but regarded 
 indifferently as either a kingdom or an aristocracy, though 
 commonly as the latter, becomes a main subject of discussion. 
 In accordance with this point of view, the main division into 
 good and bad States loses its sharpness. The Republic or 
 Politeia 1 is always regarded as markedly inferior to its two 
 companions (cf. 70. 7; 92. 16; 158. 20), and is once roundly 
 called a Trape/cftac-is (149. 15). And there is another important 
 change. The three constitutions in each set are at first distin- 
 guished according to the number of the government, which may 
 consist of one man, a few or many. But Aristotle has no sooner 
 adopted this principle than he points out that the distinction is 
 in some cases illusory. The number of the governing body is 
 a mere accident of oligarchy or democracy, which are really 
 distinguished by the wealth or poverty of the ruling class 
 (71. 8) ; and though in the later books Aristotle again modifies 
 his new principle, he never deserts it. In the same way in 
 
 1 This form of government is, as the reader will see, called simply Consti- 
 tution. In English we have nothing that is even an apparent equivalent. So 
 far as any Greek State can be called a republic, the Politeia may be called 
 a republic of the middle classes. But there is no single case in all the six in 
 which the use of the designations given to modern States is not misleading. 
 
 P
 
 226 ARISTOTLE 'S CONCEPTION 
 
 various passages various causes are assigned for the existence 
 of different forms of government ; and the truth is that there is 
 no one principle of division in the Politics. This wavering 
 procedure seems to be due in part to the recurrence, at various 
 times, of two distinct points of view, and an indifference to their 
 relation to each other. After what has been said, it will be 
 obvious what these points of view are. At one time Aristotle's 
 endeavour is to fix clearly in what the goodness or badness of 
 a State consists ; to discover the fundamental principle of each 
 main form of government, and, by a comparison of it with the 
 standard of the ideal State, to determine its value. At other 
 times the fact that every actual constitution is the expression of 
 a certain social order becomes prominent ; and it is found that, 
 though the previous distinction may determine the general 
 goodness or badness of such a constitution, it does not really 
 explain its concrete character. It will be best, without enter- 
 ing into any critical discussion, to separate these methods from 
 each other, and to ask, first, what is the main external 
 difference of constitutions, and afterwards to analyse those 
 characteristics which distinguish any good government from 
 any bad one. 
 
 The question what social condition is appropriate to each 
 constitution lies beyond the scope of this Essay. Still less can 
 we reproduce Aristotle's sketch of the order in which the main 
 forms of government appeared (88. 8 ff.), or his explanation of 
 the fact that some of them had ceased to answer to the needs 
 of the time. 1 The doctrine which we have to notice is that the 
 constitution is not merely in general the result of social con- 
 ditions, but that it expresses the relative power of the different 
 elements or sections of society. Every political community 
 contains a variety of parts, elements, or functions. Translating 
 this into the concrete, we may say that every society is divided 
 into classes, although it does not necessarily happen, and, 
 according to Aristotle, had better not happen, that every func- 
 tion is allotted to a single class. Each of these elements or 
 
 1 See, for example, on the disappearance of the kingly form of monarchy, 
 223. 3 ff. ; and on the connection of democracy with the increased size of 
 States, 88. 25 ; 188. 3 ; 186. 4.
 
 OF THE STATE. 
 
 classes which are variously enumerated in different passages 
 contributes something to the State, and so has a certain claim to 
 share in its life, or constitution, 1 or political rights. And, apart 
 from the justice of these claims, as a matter of fact the relative 
 strength of these elements determines the question where the 
 supreme power or sovereignty lies in the community, and there- 
 fore settles what the constitution of the State shall be (e.g. 80. 
 20 ff.). Thus Aristotle tells us more than once that the variety 
 of constitutions is due to the various vTrepo-^al, or preponderances 
 of the social parts (148. 7 ; 149. 1 ; 152. 29) ; and this must be 
 regarded as his settled view of the existing States, although he 
 does not admit the complete justice of the claim of any class to 
 exclusive power (e.g. 81. 12). Thus again the true difference 
 between oligarchy and democracy, the commonest actual forms 
 of government, consists in this, that in the one the element of 
 wealth, which naturally falls into a few hands, is supreme 
 (fcvpiov} among the social elements, whereas in democracy the 
 poor multitude has got the mastery. And in the same way the 
 superiority of the Politeia to these two constitutions is that in 
 it neither of these extremes has overpowered the other, but the 
 middle class possesses a social force which results in political 
 supremacy. 
 
 These distinctions of fact, however, are only the signs of a 
 difference in moral value. The transition from one point of 
 view to the other is facilitated by the haphazard way in which 
 Aristotle uses abstract and concrete expressions. He speaks of 
 a social element indifferently as wealth or the wealthy, freedom 
 or the free, virtue or the good. Accordingly, instead of saying 
 that one of the classes of society, say the wealthy, predominates 
 in a State, he defines the constitution of that State as one which 
 takes a single social element, wealth, for its standard (0/909). 
 Thus, he tells us, of the qualifications which can claim to 
 be such a standard there are on the whole three free birth, 
 wealth, and virtue (since a fourth, nobility, means ancestral 
 wealth and virtue); and these are the standards respectively of 
 democracy, oligarchy, and aristocracy (159. 15). From the 
 notion of a standard to that of an end the step, especially in 
 
 1 rj yap iroXireia /3t'os ris i<m 7r6Xews. 163. 3.
 
 228 ARISTOTLE S CONCEPTION 
 
 Greek, is a short one. Accordingly, we are not surprised to find 
 Aristotle distinguishing constitutions by the ends they pursue. 
 And again, since the end or standard determines the rights 
 which are thought to belong in justice to the citizen, we are 
 told that the existence of certain constitutions is due to the 
 fact that men have not a right idea of justice (193. 28 ft'.). But 
 when we come to divide States according to the ends they 
 pursue and the justice they realise, we have left the ground of 
 a mere analysis of social forces, and have entered the region of 
 moral judgment. If we add to these criteria the question what 
 kind of rule is exercised in a given State, we shall have found 
 the three tests by which the goodness or badness of a con- 
 stitution may be tried. 
 
 The first of these criteria is obvious. The very definition 
 of the State places its whole nature in its end. To pursue a 
 false end is to be a bad State, or even (so far) to fail of being a 
 State at all. The true end, as we know, is that noble life which 
 is identical with happiness or the exercise of complete virtue. 
 But there are various subordinate constituents or various 
 necessary conditions of this end, which may be mistaken for 
 it. And just as a man may take as the object of his life 
 not real happiness, but wealth or pleasure, so may a State. 
 Thus the end of the good State is, as we may suppose, the true 
 end. That of the ideal State is this end in its perfection, so that, 
 in the aristocratic form of it which is really Aristotle's ideal, 
 the virtue of the good citizen is, as such, identical with the 
 virtue of the good man. In the same way the fact that the 
 Politeia is counted among the good States, must mean that its 
 end is virtue ; but the virtue at which it aims is that imper- 
 fect aperrj of which a large number of men is capable, the 
 virtue of the citizen-soldier (70. 15). 1 On the other hand, the 
 
 1 In this instance we have an example of the way in which the real con- 
 ditions of a society are connected with the moral qualities of the constitution. 
 The possibility of attaining the true end depends on a limitation of the 
 number of the body which governs ; even in the ideal States only some of the 
 citizens actually rule. If a large number are to govern, the end must be 
 lowered, and with it the standard for political rights. Thus the qualification 
 in the Politeia is the possession of arms, or (what comes to the same thing in 
 a Greek State) such a property-qualification as admits only the upper and 
 middle classes to power.
 
 OF THE STATE. 229 
 
 ends which define the perverted forms are not merely imperfect 
 degrees of apery, but something subordinate to it. Thus 
 we shall expect to find the object of oligarchy in wealth, and 
 this is implicitly asserted by Aristotle (e.g. 218. 9). That of 
 democracy must be freedom, since the other characteristics of 
 that form, poverty, numbers, and low birth, are obviously in- 
 capable of being ends (159. 15; 179. 7; 180. 17). That of 
 tyranny again is not the noble life on which pleasure necessarily 
 follows, but pleasure itself and, with a view to pleasure, wealth 
 (218. 4). 
 
 In the perversions, then, the government does not seek the 
 good. But, secondly, it does not seek the common good (TO 
 Koivfj a-v^epov, 68. 5). It pursues the end for itself, and not 
 for the whole State. Its rule therefore is not political but 
 despotic ; that is, a kind of rule applicable to the relation of 
 master and slave, but not to the relation of citizens to each 
 other. The welfare of the ruled is, like the slave's, only 
 accidentally involved in that of the ruler, in the sense 
 (apparently) that more than a certain amount of ill-treatment 
 destroys the living material or instruments by which the master 
 or tyrant obtains his own objects. Thus the subject, like the 
 slave, is the means to another man's end; whereas it is the 
 essence of political society to be a community of free men. In 
 this sense democracy, oligarchy, and tyranny are alike despotic 
 (69. 1 7). In other words, they are so far not States at all ; they 
 are insecure ; their vital principle is self-destructive ; and their 
 safety lies in suppressing the full development of this principle, 
 or in adopting for a bad end measures which, as a matter of 
 fact, tend to the common good. 
 
 Each of these two moral characteristics is indispensable. To 
 seek an end which is common to all the citizens will not make 
 a government correct, if the end is false ; and to seek the true 
 end will not do so either, if this end is not sought for all. And 
 Aristotle combines the two characteristics when he defines the 
 common good as the share of noble life which falls to each 
 citizen (68. 10). But beyond this mere assertion of their 
 union he does not go ; he does not attempt to prove that 
 the pursuit of the true end is necessarily unselfish, whereas 
 that of a false one is not. We may gather such a result
 
 2 3 o ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 from his denial that a mere society of traders would con- 
 stitute a State. The ground of this denial is, that such a 
 society has not a really " political " end ; it seeks nothing more 
 than protection for the endeavour of each man to attain his 
 private end of wealth, an endeavour in which the welfare, and 
 even the wealth, of his fellows is involved, if at all, only 
 accidentally. And to this is opposed the interest of the citizen 
 in the moral character of others, that is, in the attainment of 
 the end of the State by others as well as himself. Or again, we 
 may infer that the true end of the State is necessarily a common 
 good, from the account of justice in Ethics v. 1. In that pas- 
 sage justice is identified with virtue, when virtue is regarded 
 in its relation to other men ; and the virtue of the citizen is, 
 as we know, the end of the State. But to seek this justice must 
 be to seek the good of all the citizens ; for, owing to its rela- 
 tion to others, it may be defined, Aristotle says, as the " good 
 of others" (a\\oTpiov aryaOov), and not merely of the just man 
 himself. But we have to find such indications for ourselves. 
 The antithesis of selfishness and disinterested action, which 
 suggests the difficulty, had no such prominence in Greek Ethics 
 as it possesses for good and evil now. Aristotle never ex- 
 plicitly raises the question, so obvious to us, in what relation 
 a man's happiness stands to the realisation of the same end in 
 others, and whether it is possible for one to be attained with- 
 out the other, and, therefore, to be preferred or sacrificed to 
 the other. And in the same way here, there is no attempt to 
 show that the pursuit of the real end is in its nature public- 
 spirited, and that of wealth or mere freedom or pleasure neces- 
 sarily the subordination of the public good to a private or class 
 interest. 
 
 We have to ask, thirdly, in what way is the State a realisa- 
 tion of justice or right. 1 It is so, first of all, in this general 
 sense, that it produces in its citizens that virtue for which, 
 as we have seen, justice is another name. But there is also 
 a more special principle of right in political society. This is 
 
 1 On this subject H. A. Fechner's tract, Ueber den Gerechtigkeitsbegriff des 
 Aristoteles may be compared. The corresponding passages in the Politics and 
 Ethics are fully pointed out in the notes to Mr. H. Jackson's edition of the 
 fifth book of the Ethics.
 
 OF THE STATE. 231 
 
 what Aristotle calls distributive justice ; and its law is that 
 public honours, advantages, or rights, are distributed among 
 the citizens, not arbitrarily, but in proportion to their contribu- 
 tion to the end of the State, or, in other words, according to 
 their worth (a%ia). Thus this justice maybe defined in modern 
 language as the correspondence of rights and duties. A right 
 given, which does not answer, and answer proportionately, to 
 a duty done, is a violation of justice. A duty done, a contribu- 
 tion to the State, which does not meet with its proportionate 
 return in the shape of a right, is equally a violation of justice. 
 Or, again, this justice may be represented as a geometrical pro- 
 portion. If A and B are two citizens whose worths differ, the 
 rights , which go to A, ought to differ in amount from the 
 rights &, which go to B, proportionately to the difference in 
 worth between A and B ; or, A : B : : A-f a : B + &. In the same 
 way Aristotle calls political justice a principle of equality. And 
 by this he means not absolute equality, but equality of ratios. 
 Thus if A gets the amount of rights which answer to his 
 worth, and B does the same, they are treated justly ; and, 
 although they receive unequal rights, they are treated equally. 
 To give equal rights to unequal worths, or unequal rights 
 to equal worths, is to violate equality. In so far then as a 
 State applies this law of proportion, it realises distributive 
 justice. On the other hand, although it fairly distributes 
 rights according to worth, it may in reality violate justice by 
 using a false or one-sided standard of worth. Instead of rating 
 the citizen by his capacity of exercising true citizen functions, 
 it may adopt a criterion answering to its own false end. In 
 this case, among others, the justice of the State will, in a 
 higher sense, be unjust. And it is only when this positive 
 justice corresponds to, or expresses, natural justice, that the 
 State can be said to be a full realisation of right. 
 
 This is not the case with the perverted States. Plainly, 
 none of them is likely to produce justice in its citizens. None 
 of them, again, fully satisfies distributive justice. Though all 
 except, we may suppose, the tyrant admit that justice 
 means proportionate equality (193. 29; 195. 14), in no State 
 except the ideal is political right wholly coincident with 
 natural (Eth. 5. 7. 5). The departure from natural justice in
 
 2 3 2 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 oligarchy and democracy is represented by Aristotle in two 
 different ways. A partial equality or inequality is taken as 
 absolute, and a false standard of worth is adopted. Thus in 
 the oligarchy an inequality in one respect is considered a just 
 ground for the exclusive possession of power ; and political 
 rights are restricted to those who are superior to their fellow- 
 citizens in one particular, viz., wealth. Here is already an in- 
 justice ; but it is heightened by the fact that the measure of 
 worth is itself a false one. "What is a man worth?" means 
 in an oligarchy not " What is his merit, his contribution to the 
 true end of the State ?" but " How much money is he worth ? " 
 The injustice of democracy, though it leads to very different 
 outward results, is in principle the same. Grasping the fact 
 that in one point, freedom, all its citizens are on a level, it 
 takes this partial equality for an absolute one, and gives equal 
 rights to everybody. In other words, it gives equals to un- 
 equals, and thereby violates justice. And again, though 
 according to the standard of worth it has adopted it may 
 apportion fairly, this standard is not merit but the imperfect 
 one of free birth. Hence Aristotle can at one time insist that 
 equality is justice, and at another condemn democracy on 
 account of its passion for equality, since the equality it realises 
 is not proportionate but absolute or numerical. 1 So it comes 
 about that there is an " oligarchical right " and a " democratic 
 right." They are not, in the highest sense, right at all. But 
 to a certain extent they are so ; partly because the agio, which 
 they take as the qualification for political power, although not 
 the true one, still has a subordinate importance for the State ; 
 and partly because, on the basis of this standard, they do dis- 
 tribute public advantages and honours according to a fixed law. 
 Thus, though Aristotle does not trace the gradual decline of 
 justice in the various stages of these Trape/cfidaeis, it is not an 
 accident that those extreme forms of oligarchy and democracy, 
 which are furthest removed from right and almost on a level 
 with tyranny, are characterised in his view by contempt of the 
 
 1 Hence also Aristotle sometimes says (e.fj. 188. 4) that democracy is opposed 
 to "justice according to worth (<ita)." Its standard of worth is mere free- 
 dom, and, therefore, scarcely a standard at all.
 
 OF THE STATE. 233 
 
 law, and the substitution for it of the mere will of " dynastic " 
 plutocrats (157. 16) and the momentary decrees of the despot 
 mob (154. 15). 
 
 Aristotle's application of these ideas to the various grounds 
 on which political power may be claimed is, in the main, very 
 simple. The nearest approach to our modern notion of a " right" 
 is to be found in his discussion of this subject ; and, like him, 
 we seem to use this word, as well as "justice," in a double sense. 
 Let us take, as an example of political rights, the suffrage. The 
 poor man, then, claims this privilege as his right ; and he bases 
 his claim on the ground that he is equal to, or as good as, those 
 who possess it. The rich man claims a greater or unequal 
 share of power, on the ground that he is superior or unequal 
 to his poorer fellow-citizens. The idea underlying each 
 argument is that of distributive justice, and it is a sound one. 
 If the poor man is equal to the rich, he has a right to equal 
 powers ; and if not, not. But the real question is, What does 
 the equality or inequality of men mean in this connection ? 
 In what are they equal or unequal? (78. 19 ff.) It is evident 
 that equality or inequality in any quality whatever which we 
 choose to take will not give a right to equal or unequal 
 political power. If it did, a man might claim the suffrage 
 because he was the same colour or the same size as those who 
 possess it. An illustration from, another field will guide us to 
 the true conclusion. Suppose we had certain flutes to distribute. 
 We should scarcely give the best of them to those players who 
 happened to be of the highest birth ; " for they will not play 
 better than other people on that account." And even if the 
 superiority of one man to another in wealth or birth far 
 exceeded his inferiority to him in flute-playing, we should still 
 give the best flute to the poor and low-born proficient. " For 
 it is to the function or work in question that the superiority 
 in birth or wealth ought to contribute ; and it contributes 
 nothing." The same principle will apply to politics ; and it 
 will not justify either of the claims in question. It is not un- 
 just that a real inequality, a superior contribution to the end 
 of the State, should be rewarded by a superior share in the 
 function. But against the favour shown to irrelevant in- 
 equalities the democrat rightly protests. On the other hand,
 
 234 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 the point in which he is equal to every other citizen is 
 not that which ought to settle his political u^ta. The 
 end of the State is no more free birth than wealth ; and 
 absolute justice belongs in reality only to claims based on the 
 equal or superior possession of intelligence and moral character. 
 Suppose, however, that a given State pursues a false end, and 
 accordingly adopts a false standard of worth. In this case, 
 whatever the standard may be, he who contributes to it equally 
 with other men may truly be said to have an equal right to 
 political power with other men, although his right would in an 
 ideal State be none. So, again, in an oligarchy a wealthy man 
 has a right to greater privileges than others ; and his superior in 
 aperr), or the real capacity for government, might be legally 
 treated as inferior to him. In such a case, in one sense the 
 poor man of ability would have no right to the power refused 
 to him, and yet, in another sense, he might be said to have an 
 absolute right to it. Obvious as these distinctions appear, any 
 controversy on the suffrage will show how easily they may 
 still be confused, and that the twofold idea of " rights " is 
 still current. When we say that a man has a right to the 
 franchise, what do we mean ? We may mean that according 
 to the constitution, the English political BUaiov, he can claim 
 it, because he satisfies the conditions laid down by the law as 
 necessary to the possession of it. But when the franchise is 
 claimed as a right by those who do not satisfy these conditions, 
 this cannot be the meaning. They really affirm that the 
 actual law, the English SUaiov, is not properly or absolutely 
 just, and does not express " natural right ; " that, according to 
 real justice, they ought to have the suffrage, and that, if they had 
 it, the State would be less of a Trape/cySao-t? and nearer to the 
 ideal. And if the further question were asked, why true justice 
 demands the change, would not the answer (unless it were a 
 piece of mere clap-trap) involve the notion that equal rights 
 ought in justice to follow equal duties to the State, and the 
 assertion that those who claim the suffrage contribute equally 
 to the State with those who already possess it ? 
 
 The result of these principles for Aristotle would seem to 
 be clear ; and to a certain extent it is so. That the only true 
 standard of worth for distributive justice is merit, or virtue, or
 
 OF THE STATE. 235 
 
 education (TraiSeia, " culture "), is obvious. But in the imme- 
 diate application of this doctrine uncertainties arise. First of 
 all, there is one limitation on all governments, a limitation 
 which has, fortunately for us, become almost too obvious to be 
 worth mentioning. The rule of those who possess any 
 superiority, even that of virtue, is to be considered inferior to 
 the rule of law. It is only because the law is too general to 
 meet all the particular cases that arise, that a government is 
 necessary to supplement as well as execute it ; and therefore, 
 with one exception to be noticed later, the rule that all govern- 
 ments ought to be subject to it is absolute (e.g. 77. 30). 
 Secondly, an element of doubt is introduced by the true per- 
 ception that, though wealth or free birth are not direct contri- 
 butions to the end of the State, they yet constitute elements 
 necessary to its existence (79. 22). There is consequently a 
 certain amount of justice in the demand that the possession of 
 them should be followed by some share in public rights. But 
 what share this should be, and in what rights it should be a 
 share, are questions which Aristotle does not discuss. Lastly, 
 his view of the claims of individuals to political power receive 
 an important modification in the account of the imperfect 
 States. Aristotle tells us (166. 6 ff.) that we have to consider 
 not only quality, but quantity; that is, not only the element or 
 quality on which a claim to rule is based, but also the number 
 of those who possess it. It is the comparative power of these 
 factors which settles the constitution of a State. Thus 
 oligarchy means the preponderance of the quality of wealth 
 over the superior quantity of the poor, and democracy 1 the 
 opposite. It is the tendency of either government to push its 
 principle to an extreme. Oligarchy heightens the amount of 
 the "quality" of wealth necessary for political rights, and 
 thereby increases the numbers opposed to it. Democracy 
 
 1 Obviously, according to Aristotle, democracy is absolute government of 
 a quality, viz. free birth, and the oligarchs make up a quantity of men. 
 But then free birth is common to rich and poor, the noble by* nature and the 
 noble by birth alike. Accordingly he sometimes speaks as if the essence of 
 democracy were mere number, i.e. mere quantity, or this united with 
 poverty and low birth, i.e. the absence of certain qualities. In the same 
 way, as we saw, he speaks as though democracy recognised no dta, because 
 its cl|ia is so slight a one.
 
 2*6 ARISTOTLE 'S CONCEPTION 
 
 extends the franchise more and more, and with its increase of 
 quantity loses more and more all distinctive quality. The 
 further this development goes, and the further these factors 
 are separated, the worse the State becomes, and the nearer it 
 approaches to an internecine struggle between them. Accord- 
 ingly, it is the characteristic of the Politeia, which is dis- 
 tinguished for its stability, that it combines these elements ; 
 and it is in this connection that Aristotle's celebrated eulogium 
 on the middle classes occurs. But it is clear that the applica- 
 tion of this idea to the question of political rights will make 
 our previous results uncertain. For those results are based 
 simply on an inquiry into the quality which any individual 
 can allege as a claim to power : this doctrine, on the contrary, 
 touches the rights not of an individual, as such, but of a 
 number, or possibly a class, and it expressly admits that their 
 quantity must be considered. 
 
 A consideration not quite identical with this, but closely 
 allied to it, is applied even to the good States ; and it has a 
 special interest, because it leads Aristotle to discuss the rights 
 of the mass or people (TTA/^O?, the whole body of citizens). 
 Let us assume, so we may state his results (75. 6 77. 30), 
 that wealth is the standard by which rights are apportioned. 
 Still, it will not follow that " the rich " should rule. The mass 
 might justly dispute their claim; for although the wealth of any 
 rich man might far exceed that of any poor one, yet the col- 
 lective wealth of the people might exceed that of the wealthy 
 class. Again, even if we admit that the true standard of 
 justice is apery, it is not certain that the best and ablest man 
 in the State, nor the few best and ablest men, have a right to 
 hold the reins of government. It is possible that the 
 aggregate aperr) of the people might outweigh that of this 
 individual or class ; and then the very arguments on which the 
 latter claim to govern might be turned against them. The 
 man of distinguished aperrj, we might say, is like the ideal 
 portrait. In it are united the various beauties which in life 
 are distributed among different men, and it is therefore more 
 beautiful than the average man. Yet if we take a crowd, we 
 may find in it here a mouth, and there eyes, and there again 
 another feature, still more beautiful than are the features of the
 
 OF THE STATE. 237 
 
 portrait. And so, although each individual of the 7rA,?}#o<? may 
 be far inferior in political merit to the aristocrat, yet if we 
 take the whole mass, it may contain an aggregate of merit 
 exceeding his. Each member of it brings a contribution to the 
 one vast man, who has many feet and hands and senses. In 
 the same way we find that the judgment of the mass on poetry 
 and music is better than that of a single critic ; for one man 
 appreciates one excellence, and another another, whereas the 
 taste of an individual is necessarily one-sided. And again, as 
 a large quantity of water is less easily defiled than a small, so 
 it is harder to corrupt a whole people than an individual ; and 
 " it is not easy for them all to be enraged or mistaken at once." 
 For these reasons it may be just to give such powers as those 
 of election and the scrutiny of official actions to the whole 
 people. And if the objection be raised that, if they are not 
 fit to hold office themselves, they cannot be fit to choose 
 officials and judge their conduct, the answer is that in many 
 cases it is not necessary to know how a thing is made in order to 
 judge of it. The head of a household, who could not have built 
 the house, is a better judge of the product than the builder, the 
 man who eats a dinner than the cook who prepared it. 
 
 This is Aristotle's version of "the sovereignty of the 
 people;" and his arguments, whether wholly sound or not, 
 have a permanent value. But it is important to recognise 
 clearly on what basis they rest, and to what conclusion they 
 are supposed to lead. We have to remember, first, that the 
 " people," here as everywhere, is not equivalent to the whole 
 male population, and does not include the enormous body of 
 slaves and aliens. Nor does Aristotle suppose that his 
 arguments will apply to any and every mass ; for, " by heaven, 
 in some cases this is clearly impossible." And, further, the 
 sovereignty of the people to whom they do apply is doubly 
 limited. It is subject to the ultimate supremacy of the law ; 
 and even under the law it is not complete. The very reasons 
 which establish it restrict it to those cases in which the people 
 can act en masse, and not individually. In other words, the 
 functions of government in which the 7r\fj6o<; can claim a share 
 are the general ones of deliberation and decision, which con- 
 stitute the definition of citizenship, and not the highest
 
 238 ARISTOTLE $ CONCEPTION 
 
 executive offices, for which special ability is required. Lastly, 
 it will be observed that the ground on which these claims are 
 based by Aristotle is not that of simple quantity as opposed 
 to quality. It is a claim based on the superior quantity of a 
 quality. It is not because "all government rests on the 
 consent of the governed," nor because one man is as good as 
 another, nor because the people is a majority, that it has a 
 right to rule; but because, in the case of a high level of 
 civilisation, its rule is more likely to realise the government 
 of intelligence and character than any other arrangement. 
 Number stands on no higher level, or even on a lower level, 
 than money or birth. Whatever rights belong to it, belong to 
 it as the sign of something beyond itself. 
 
 Partly on account of this discussion, partly through the mis- 
 interpretation of various passages in the Politics, some readers 
 of the work have identified the Politeia with Aristotle's ideal 
 State. But it is quite impossible to maintain this view. It is 
 true that in both the suffrage is widely extended. But the 
 Politeia is only the practical ideal. It is the constitution 
 adapted to an average good State. It is a government of aperr), 
 but of imperfect aperrj. The whole people does not rule ; there 
 is a strict qualification for political rights, and, with a view to 
 obtaining a rule of fair aperr), the qualification fixed is one of 
 moderate wealth. The ideal State, on the other hand, is the 
 true aristocracy ; a government of complete dperr), a government 
 of the best men (apta-Toi) for the best end (apia-Tois), (70. 1). 
 In the form which Aristotle has given to it the whole body 
 of citizens bears rule. But then he is constructing a State 
 according to his wishes ; he supposes all the citizens to be men 
 of high excellence ; and even then he does not give the actual 
 functions of government to them until they have reached a 
 certain age. If his "wish" should not be fulfilled, justice 
 would demand a different constitution. A population, in which 
 a small band of men were distinguished to such a degree that 
 
 their aperr; surpassed that of the remaining TrXrjQos, w r ould, on 
 Aristotle's principle, be governed by that select few. And a 
 still stranger case is not inconceivable to him. It might 
 happen that a man appeared in the State, gifted with a great- 
 ness of soul which raised him far above all his fellows. In
 
 OF THE STATE. 239 
 
 such an event no love of his own ideal will deter Aristotle 
 from the consistent result of his principles. If the great man 
 really has a spirit so exalted in energy and virtue that these 
 gifts exceed in quantity those of the whole body of his fellow- 
 countrymen, justice demands that he should be held for what 
 he is, "a god among men" (82. G). The conditions of common 
 political life cease to be applicable. He is not an equal among 
 equals, to be bound by equal rules. In this single case even 
 the supremacy of law must be abandoned. He is to be recog- 
 nised as of right an absolute king, governing for the common 
 good. That Aristotle considered such an occurrence extremely 
 improbable is obvious. But that it was conceivable is the 
 reason why he describes the ideal State as either monarchy 
 or aristocracy (147. 1). And as in the Ethics (8. 10. 2), so in 
 the Politics he has even given the first place to the former 
 (147. 10). 1 
 
 The true State may take various forms ; but, whatever form 
 it takes, these two requirements are absolute : it must strive 
 to realise perfect justice by giving power to the natural 
 sovereignty of intelligence and virtue, and it must seek the 
 common good. The Greek constitutions have no more than a 
 historical interest for us now. Our monarchy, our feudal 
 aristocracy, our representative government, were things unknown 
 to them, and the most democratic of their democracies we 
 should call an oligarchy. But these principles remain. The 
 first of them modern States attempt to carry out in various 
 ways. From the very force of circumstances we are even less 
 tempted than the Greeks to translate the truth that reason 
 alone has a " divine right " to rule, into the dictum that philo- 
 sophers should be kings ; but it is still possible to forget that 
 wealth and numbers have no political value except as symbols, 
 and that political machinery is very far from being an end in 
 
 1 The absolute kingship described above is of course the exact opposite of 
 tyranny. It has been supposed that, in speaking of it, Aristotle was thinking 
 of Alexander, and the enthusiasm of his language is certainly striking. But 
 it is almost incredible that such an opinion of the new military monarchy 
 should have left so little trace on the structure of his whole political theory. 
 And it should be observed that the comparison of the rule of law and of 
 an absolute king has throughout a reference to Plato's Statesman, and that 
 Aristotle makes use even of Plato's illustrations.
 
 240 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 itself. The second of these principles may be thought, fortu- 
 nately for us, to have lost the pressing importance it had to 
 Aristotle. For him the ruin of the Greek States was the 
 witness of its violation. 1 The organisation of the State, in- 
 stead of representing the common good and standing above 
 the strife of social parties, had become in many cases the prize 
 for which they fought, and a means which the victorious party 
 used for its own exclusive advantage. Cities were divided 
 into two hostile camps of the rich and poor. In this immediate 
 dependence of the State on society we have one of the most 
 marked characteristics of Greek politics. In modern nations 
 the struggle of classes for political power does not, as a rule, rise 
 prominently to the surface; and, though a change in social 
 conditions such as the decay of a landed aristocracy, or the 
 rise of the commercial or the labouring classes, inevitably 
 expresses itself in politics, it commonly does so slowly and, so to 
 speak, unintentionally. The State has a fixity and power such 
 as the Greeks in spite of the far greater part played by govern- 
 ment in their lives never knew ; and, where the opposition of 
 classes begins to pass from the social sphere and to take an 
 openly political form, we recognise a peril to the national 
 welfare and morality which to the Greek, instead of being a 
 rarity, was ever at the doors. But it is impossible to say how 
 far this supremacy of the State is connected with the modern 
 institution of monarchy, and to what extent more popular 
 forms of government, by whatever name they go, may be able 
 to preserve it. That it needs no preservation, that great 
 nations can do without it, and can subsist on nothing but the 
 natural competition of interests modified by public opinion, is 
 a hope which underlies some forms of the democratic faith, and 
 seems to be implicitly adopted by many who have no theoretic 
 convictions on the subject. Yet it seems too probable that, in 
 more than one European country, the irruption of an exaspe- 
 rated social strife into the political arena would follow any 
 weakening of the central power ; and it would be a poor change 
 which freed men from the burden of that power only to bring 
 
 1 Cf. L. v. Stein in the Zeilschrift fur die gesammte Staatswissenschaft for 
 1853, pp. 115-182.
 
 OF THE STATE. 241 
 
 it back in its least beneficent and progressive form, that of 
 military force. Nor is it possible to confine these doubts to 
 the great continental States. In more than one of the English 
 colonies, unless they are maligned, the interest of a class is 
 predominant in politics, and is susceptible of scarcely any 
 check from above. And if representative institutions are not 
 in other cases to be misused for the same " despotic " purposes, 
 if they are not to produce, instead of the public good and the 
 rule of dperrj, class-government and the supremacy of the dema- 
 gogue and the wire-puller, it may be that the sluggish action 
 of public opinion will need to be reinforced by some strengthen- 
 ing of the State and some counterpoise to those tendencies 
 which characterised the extreme democracy described by Aris- 
 totle, the gradual weakening of the executive and the grasping 
 of all the powers of government by the popular assembly 
 (154. 26; 170. 12; 174. 16; 179. 25180. 11). 
 
 There is no fear that modern civilisation will abandon the 
 ideas which mark its progress. Unless some gigantic calamity 
 were to overtake it, men who have once conceived of God as 
 identical with the inmost spirit of humanity and bound by no 
 limits of race or nation, who have realised that the breath of 
 morality is freedom, and that voluntary association may be 
 almost as powerful a force as the State, are never likely to find 
 their ideal in the Greek city. The dangers are still on the 
 other side. The process through which those ideas gained 
 strength involved serious losses, and the false antitheses to 
 which it gave rise have not yet ceased to rule our thoughts. 
 To them the spirit of Aristotle's conception may still serve as 
 a corrective. With every step in the moralising of politics and 
 the socialising of morals, something of Greek excellence is won 
 back. That goodness is not abstinence but action ; that egoism, 
 to however future a life it postpones its satisfaction, is still 
 nothing but selfishness ; that a man does not belong to himself, 
 but to the State and to mankind ; that to be free is not merely 
 to do what one likes, but to like what one ought ; and that 
 blindness to the glory of " the world," and irreverence towards 
 its spiritual forces, are the worst of passports to any " church " 
 worthy of the name, every new conviction of such truths is an 
 advance towards filling up the gulf between religion and reality,
 
 2 42 ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPTION 
 
 and restoring, in a higher shape, that unity of life which the 
 Greeks knew. 
 
 So far as opinions have weight, there are not many which 
 more retard this advance than the idea that the State is a mere 
 organ of "secular" force. That it is so seems to be the theoretical, 
 though not the practical, belief of most Englishmen ; and 
 Aristotle's fundamental position, that its object is nothing short 
 of " noble living," seems to separate his view decisively from 
 ours. The partial truths that the law takes no account of moral 
 character, and that Government ought not to enforce morality 
 or interfere with private life, seem to be the main expressions 
 of this apparent separation. But, to say nothing of the fact 
 that legal punishments do in some cases habitually consider a 
 man's moral guilt as well as his illegal act, it is forgotten that 
 the reason why this is not the rule is itself a moral reason, and 
 that if, by making it the rule, the good life of the community 
 were likely to be furthered, it would be made the rule. And 
 in the same way the reason why the State does not to any 
 large extent aim at a directly moral result, is not that morality 
 is something indifferent to it, but that it believes it will 
 help morality most by not trying to enforce it. If we hold to 
 Aristotle's definition, it does not follow that we are to pass 
 sumptuary laws and force men to say their prayers. Every 
 argument that is brought against the action of Government may 
 (so far as it does not rest on a supposed right of the individual) 
 be applied, with whatever truth it possesses, under that defini- 
 tion ; and if, in the pursuit of its final object, the State, with a 
 view to that final object, refrains from directly seeking that 
 final object, that does not show that the immediate ends which 
 it pursues are its ultimate and only end. But, apart from this, 
 it is not true that in our own day the State has ceased actively 
 to aim at a positive good, and has restricted itself to the duty 
 of protecting men's lives and property. If the theory that its 
 duty should be so restricted were carried out, it would lead to 
 strange results and would abolish public laws and acts which 
 few would be willing to surrender. We need go for a proof no 
 further than our own country, where the action of Government 
 is certainly not overvalued. A State which, in however slight 
 a degree, supports science, art, learning, and religion ; which
 
 OF THE STATE. 243 
 
 enforces education, and compels the well-to-do to maintain the 
 helpless ; which, for the good of the poor and weak, interferes 
 with the " natural " relations of employer and employed, and 
 regulates, only too laxly, a traffic which joins gigantic evil to 
 its somewhat scanty good ; a State which forbids or punishes 
 suicide, self-maiming, the voluntary dissolution of marriage, 
 cruelty to animals, offences against decency, and sexual crimes 
 which, if any act could be so, are the private affair of the 
 persons who commit them, a State which does all this and 
 much more of the same kind, cannot, without an unnatural 
 straining of language, be denied to exercise, in the broad sense, 
 a moral function. It still seeks not merely " life," but " good 
 life." It is still, within the sphere appropriate to force, a 
 spiritual power, not only the guardian of the peace and a 
 security for the free pursuit of private ends, but the armed 
 conscience of the community. 
 
 A. C. B.
 
 EPICURUS. 
 
 IN the year 1752, certain workmen, who were excavating 
 the soil of the modern Portici, which covers the ancient 
 Herculaneum, struck upon a small chamber or cell belonging 
 apparently to a country house which in former times looked 
 over the sea. Eound the walls of this little chamber were 
 arranged, on a pavement of mosaic, chests and cupboards of 
 marqueterie, and standing on one of these, in the middle of 
 the room, were seen busts of Demosthenes, Epicurus, Zeno, 
 and Hermarchus. It was almost the first discovery of real 
 importance which had rewarded the patience of the explorers. 1 
 Some ancient statues had indeed been unearthed in 1713, 
 during the excavations carried on by the Prince d'Elbosuf, 
 and again in 1737 under the orders of Charles in.: but the 
 discovery of Pompeii in 1748, and the superior facility with 
 which excavations could be carried on in the "passamonte" 
 (light cinders) which covered the ruins of the sister town, had 
 diverted attention for a while from Herculaneum. Yet the 
 soil beneath Portici and Resina offered relics of far greater 
 value. On the shelves of the cupboards found in the room of 
 the buried villa lay little rolls, about two or three inches in 
 diameter and a palm in length, the appearance of which gave 
 
 1 Perhaps the Emperor Titus was anxious to restore the city, which had 
 been ruined in A.D. 79 ; cf. Suetonius, Tit. 8 : "Bona oppressorum in Vesevo, 
 quorum heredes non exstabant, restitution! afflictarum civitatum attribuit. " 
 Winckelmann is supposed to be wrong in saying ( Werke, ii. p. 23), on the 
 strength of an inscription containing the words ' ' signa translata ex abditis 
 locis," that the Romans carried on excavations.
 
 EPICURUS. 245 
 
 the workmen the notion that they were in the shop of a 
 charcoal or coal merchant. An accidental fall revealed the 
 tact that they were covered with decipherable letters, that in 
 reality the charcoal-rolls were nothing but rolls of papyrus, 
 charred with the action of fire. 1 
 
 So startling a discovery was not long in engaging the atten- 
 tion of savants. A certain Camillo Paderni, who was superin- 
 tending the excavations in 1752, was the first to make an 
 attempt to open the volumes. Despairing of success in other 
 ways, he adopted the barbarous plan of cutting the volume 
 in half longitudinally, and was quite satisfied, if the result of 
 his labours revealed the language in which the manuscripts 
 were written. By this means, no less than 337 Greek volumes 
 and eighteen Latin were destroyed in a few months. Fortunately 
 his successors in inquiry were neither so impatient nor so 
 unfortunate, and something was done to repair his ravages as 
 well as to carry on his original object. A series of investigators 
 since 1752 have worked with admirable devotion to recover 
 the manuscripts, amongst whom the important names are those 
 of Piaggio in 1754, Mazocchi, Lapira in 1786, Hayter at the 
 commencement of the nineteenth century, Sickler in 1814, and 
 Davy in 1819 and 1820. Every kind of plan has been tried, 
 fumigation, exposure under glass to the sun, and different 
 modes of chemical treatment; but it has had in the long-run 
 to be confessed that the plan which Piaggio invented is on the 
 whole the most successful. It is an infinitely slow and laborious 
 
 1 What this villa was, and to whom it belonged, forms an interesting matter 
 for speculation. According to Prof. Comparetti, whose name is honourably 
 known in connection with explorations at Herculaneum, the villa belonged to 
 Calpurnius Piso, the colleague of Gabinius in the consulship (58 B.C.) The 
 majority of the charred scrolls found there are the works of Philodemus, a 
 late Epicurean, of no particular merits as a philosopher. Philodemus was 
 unlikely to have a villa of such pretensions belonging to himself ; and he 
 might have been a sort of superior secretary and philosophical instructor to 
 Piso. Comparetti further supposes that two bronze busts, which have been 
 sometimes called Seneca and Berenice, represent in reality Piso and Gabinius, 
 the latter of whom Cicero calls effeminate. See the essay furnished by Com- 
 paretti to the volume of articles published on the occasion of the eighteen- 
 hundredth anniversary of the destruction of Pompeii and Herculaneum. 
 ("La inlla del Pisoni in Ercolano e la sua Biblioteca," published in " Pompei e 
 la fiec/ione sotterata dal Vesuvio nelV anno LXXIX." Napoli ; Giannini,1879.
 
 246 EPICURUS. 
 
 process. The first task is to discover the margin of the paper, 
 which is by no means always easy. Then the roll is hung on 
 two ribbons and rests on wool, spread on a piece of card. This 
 card is held on leather supports, which can be raised or lowered 
 by a screw. After all this preliminary work, the real process 
 begins. Small portions of goldbeaters' skin are glued to the 
 paper by means of isinglass, and, when the back of the paper 
 is thus strengthened, threads of silk are attached to it, fas- 
 tened to a cylinder. The cylinder is slowly turned, while 
 other workmen open out the leaf with the point of a needle ; 
 and in this manner, in the course of four or five hours, 
 a single inch is unrolled. The portions thus opened are laid 
 on linen, copied and engraved, and the engravings form 
 the collection now known as the "Volurnina Herculanen- 
 sia," brought out under the authority of the Academia Erco- 
 lanese. 1 
 
 Such is a brief history of the discovery which will in time 
 give us, in all probability, a fuller acquaintance with the Epicu- 
 rean philosophy. For of the unearthed fragments, the great 
 majority belong either to Epicurus himself, or to Philodemus, 
 an Epicurean contemporary of Cicero. Hitherto we have learnt 
 much of Epicureanism from the mouths of its adversaries : 
 from the professed sceptic, Sextus Empiricus from Plutarch, 
 who wrote against an influential Epicurean named Colotes 
 from Seneca, who was a Stoic from Cicero, above all, in most 
 cases a most unfriendly and even contemptuous critic of Epicu- 
 reanism. Of the positive tenets of Epicurus we learn most 
 from the tenth book of Diogenes Laertius, to whose recital we 
 must, of course, add the testimony of the eloquent Epicurean 
 poet Lucretius. Of all the 300 rolls of Epicurus's own writ- 
 ings, the scant remains we possess are his will, a few epistles 
 and letters, and a philosophical epitome, entitled icvpiai So|at, 
 preserved by Diogenes: some individual expressions which 
 we find in Seneca, Plutarch, and others : and fragments of 
 Books ii. and xi., and portions of a few other books of his large 
 
 1 See the account given by Dr. J. C. G. Boot in his Notice sur les manu- 
 scrits trouves a Herculanum (Amsterdam, 1841), and also the report of Mr. 
 Hayter, who was sent by the Prince Regent to Naples.
 
 EPICURUS. 247 
 
 work " on Nature," which form part of the Volumina Hercu- 
 lanensia. 1 
 
 To recast for ourselves, however, the society of Epicurus 
 in its main features is no difficult task. There is hardly any 
 other ancient philosopher whose personality comes before us 
 with such strikingly clear and definite traits. His was essen- 
 tially a simple character, with none of the profundity of the 
 student, or the exclusiveness which marks the expounder of a 
 singular and isolated system. It was indeed the adaptability 
 of his doctrines to general life to the ordinary pursuits of 
 ordinary people which gave them such an unique charm in 
 the eyes of his contemporaries, and made his school flourish' 
 from the third century before Christ to the third or fourth 
 century after. 2 Nor were the characteristics essentially changed 
 in this long life of 700 years, for there was no school which 
 was more careful to preserve the actual words of the founder. 
 Epicurus had not the obtrusive idiosyncrasy of the Cynic, nor 
 the severe and strict austerity of the Stoic. Philosophy with 
 him did not mean speculation, nor yet an isolated seclusion : 
 neither was its effect to be seen in the outward clothing, or 
 want of clothing, of a Diogenes. Philosophy was " a daily 
 business of speech and thought, to secure a happy life," evepyeia 
 
 1 The following, according to Professor Gomperz, is a table of fragments 
 belonging to Epicurus from Herculaneum : 
 
 n [ ire pi <pv<rews . Bk. ii. 
 
 3. ) Bk. xi. 
 
 4.1 Bk. xi. 
 
 5. Bk. xiv. 
 
 6. Bk. xv. 
 
 7. Bk. xxviii. On Causes of Error. 
 
 8. ) ? ( Fragments on the Freedom of 
 
 9. J ? j the Will. 
 
 10. ? On Error. 
 
 11. ? On Life after Death. 
 
 12. ? 
 
 The treatise was originally in thirty-seven books. Facsimiles of 1 and 3-10 are 
 preserved in the Bodleian Library at Oxford. In 2 occurs a curious word, 
 tl;WffTiK6s. Is this the right reading of the word in Diog. L. x. 143, which 
 usually stands ^opicrriK-fj (al. ^epurriKfj, ta.iptTiKrj) ? 
 
 2 Epicurus was born in the year 342 or 341 B.C. Came to Athens in 306 
 B.C. (Diog. x. 2). Died 270 B.C. (Diog. x. 15). That the school lasted to at 
 least the third century after Christ is proved by what Diogenes says ( 9), 
 writing in the first half of the third century, according to Zeller.
 
 248 EPICURUS. 
 
 KOI Slavery tcrfAois rov ev8ai/j,ova ftiov TrepiTroiovaa. It was 
 not necessary to have read deeply or thought profoundly : 
 indeed, literature and education were often more of a hindrance 
 than otherwise. " My good sirs, leave all culture alone" (irai^eiav 
 Traaav, fiafcdpioi, favyeTe) writes Epicurus in his letter to 
 Pythocles. 1 It need not trouble any one, says Metrodorus, his 
 pupil, if he had never read a line of Homer, and did not 
 know whether Hector was a Trojan or a Greek. And Cicero - 
 adds his testimony, " nihil opus esse eum, philosoplms qui 
 futurus sit, scire literas." One study, however, for a philosopher 
 was absolutely necessary, the study of nature, and that for 
 the reason that a man cannot be happy unless he discard 
 superstition. "A man cannot be released from his fear on 
 matters of highest import, unless he knows the nature of the 
 universe and discards mythical superstition, so that without 
 physical science our very pleasures are tainted " (coo-re OVK rjv 
 avev <f)vcrio\,oylas dxepaia$ ra<$ rjSovas d7ro\an/3dveiv). s For the 
 rest, a simple life without ostentation, without meanness, not 
 pharisaically temperate, nor yet too liberally self-indulgent, 
 was the ideal of Epicurus. " For myself, I can be pleased 
 with bread and water," he says, " yet send me a little cheese, 
 in order that when I want to be extravagant, I may be." 4 
 This was the man, Diogenes pithily adds, whose doctrine was 
 that pleasure was the end of life. 
 
 Not less clearly stand out the personal kindliness, the sym- 
 pathy, the generosity, the sweetness of Epicurus's character. 
 In the little circle which surrounded the philosopher in his 
 famous gardens were Polyaenus, Hermarchus his future suc- 
 cessor, Colotes, possibly Leonteus and his wife Themista, 
 Leontion, and a beloved disciple, Metrodorus. Metrodorus, 
 who from the time of his first acquaintance with Epicurus 
 only left his side for six months, died before his master, 
 leaving two children. For these Epicurus seems to have 
 had an especial tenderness, leaving many injunctions about 
 them in his will. " Let my heirs watch over the daughter of 
 Metrodorus," he writes, " and when she grows up, let them 
 
 1 Diog. x. 6 ; cf . 121 : "The wise man lives poems, and does not make 
 them" iroirifj.a.T<i re tvepye'iv, OVK &v iroirjffai. Also 87. 
 
 2 Cic. de Fin. ii. 4. 12. s Diog. x. 143. 4 Ibid, 11.
 
 EPICURUS. 249 
 
 give her in marriage to whomsoever Hermarchus shall choose, 
 if she be modest and obedient." Among the Herculanean 
 remains there is a letter of Epicurus to a little child, who may 
 possibly be this daughter of Metrodorus. The letter runs 
 thus : " We came to Lampsacus, Pythocles, Hermarchus, 
 Ctesippus and myself, and we are quite well. We found there 
 Themista and our other friends, and they are quite well. I 
 hope you are well too, and your mamma, and that you obey her 
 and papa and Matron in everything, as you used to do. For 
 you know quite well, my pet, that I and all the others love 
 you very much, because you are obedient to them in every- 
 thing." 1 The use of the very w r ords of childhood (" papa " and 
 " mamma "), the tender little expression, vairia (though why 
 Doric in form it is hard to say), the travelling with a sort of 
 retinue, all seem to mark this letter as genuine. But if so, 
 what an admirable comment it forms on the encomiums in the 
 9th and 10th sections of Diogenes's history ! on the man who 
 could keep about him, " held prisoners by the siren-charms of 
 his teaching" (rals So^/xart/cai? avrov cretprjcri TrpoKaracr^eOevre^), 
 such a host of followers " that whole cities could not contain 
 them," who counted in his school men and women alike, and 
 could enlist in the number of his disciples even his slaves, one 
 of whom, named Mus, attained some celebrity as a philosopher ! 
 And in this context we may perhaps read his dying words to 
 
 1 Of. Gomperz's " Em brief Epikurs an ein kind " in Hermes, vol. v. (1871) 
 pp. 386-395. 
 
 According to the arrangement of Gomperz the fragment is as follows : 
 
 d<f>elyfjL0a et's Aauif/aKov v- 
 
 yiaivovres, ^yu> Kal Hv6o- 
 
 K\ijs Kal "Epuapxos Kal KTT}- 
 
 ertTTTros, Kal e/ce? KaTei\rj<f>a- 
 
 fjifv vyiaivovras 0e/u/<r- 
 
 TO.V Kal TOVS \Oi7TOi)s $('\Ol/S. 
 
 e3 Sf Troieis Kal el cri> vyi- 
 alvfis, Kal T] fj.dfj.fj.7i, (cai^T?; (?) 
 Kal irdira Kal Mdr/jwyt TTO.V- 
 ra TrfiOfi, ucnrfp Kal Z/j.- 
 irpoffBev' eD yap i<T0i, vairla, 
 Sri Kal tytj} Kal ol XoiTroi 
 Trdvres ae jj.lya QiXovfiev 
 Sri TOVTOIS ireiBif)(i) irdfTa.
 
 250 EPICURUS. 
 
 Idomeneus, 1 wliich though they contain possibly a note of 
 exaggerated rhetoric, yet bear a last testimony to the quiet 
 happy life among friends, which his philosophy recommended. 
 " On this last, yet blessed, day of my life, I write to you. Pains 
 and tortures of body I have to the full, but there is set over 
 against these the joy of my heart at the memory of our happy 
 conversations in the past. Do you, if you would be worthy of 
 your devotion to me and philosophy, take care of the children 
 of Metrodorus." ' ETn^eXov rwv -TralSwv Mrjrpo&copov were the 
 last words he wrote. 
 
 If this is not the ordinary notion which is held about 
 Epicurus, the reason is that his philosophy is more studied 
 than his life, and there are many points of view from which his 
 philosophy seems to invite criticism and disparagement. AVith 
 some critics, the fundamental idea of Epicurus the value of 
 human happiness is not one which enlists their sympathies ; 
 by others an unconscious comparison is drawn between Epicu- 
 reanism and the magnificent systems which preceded it very 
 much of course to the detriment of the former ; by others, again, 
 that notorious dislike of culture, which the founder of the 
 school not only felt but was proud of, is considered fatal to his 
 philosophic fame. And in these ways Epicureanism is un- 
 doubtedly open to blame ; to which must also be added a 
 certain logical weakness and inconsistency of thought which is 
 not surprising in one who thought so lightly of logic as a study. 
 The poverty of the theory of knowledge and truth, the incon- 
 sistency between a systematic incuriousness about astronomy, 2 
 and the acknowledgment of the necessity of physics, the flat 
 contradiction between the reign of Law in Nature and the 
 Freedom of Will in Man, the difficulty of understanding how a 
 purely selfish theory of life could not only extol disinterested 
 friendship, but even worship gods from whom nothing could 
 be obtained, all these points, and many others beside, must 
 tend to lower our admiration for Epicurus as a philosopher, 
 
 1 Diog. x. 22. The power and influence of Epicurus over his disciples is 
 acknowledged by Lucian : Alex. Pseud, caps. 17, 25, and 61 (Jacobitz). 
 
 2 Of. the astonishing assertions in Diog. x. 91, 92 ff., Epicurus thought that 
 the sun was about the same size as it appears to be, etc. etc.
 
 EPICURUS. 251 
 
 however attractive a character may belong to Epicurus as 
 a man. 
 
 But the historical circumstances of the time, which perhaps 
 promoted individual virtues, were fatal to the elaboration of a 
 systematic philosophy. It was a time of weariness and exhaus- 
 tion a weariness of metaphysical abstraction, a weariness of 
 sophistical ingenuity and rhetoric, a weariness of political 
 activity. At the time when Epicurus was living at Athens, at 
 the close of the fourth century B.C., the Grecian world had seen 
 the downfall of Thebes, the exile of Demosthenes, the ship- 
 wreck of the Hellenic state-system. The death of Alexander 
 at Babylon had led to the fruitless struggle for independence 
 in the Lamian war ; the conquest of Antipater had crushed out 
 the last efforts of Greek spirit. Aristotle, accused of atheism, 
 had left the city of Socrates and Plato, and had died at 
 Chalcis. In the misery and repression of the time, men did 
 not want far-reaching theory or elaborate system, but some- 
 thing definite, precise, concrete : some ideal of existence which 
 would suit those who had given up politics and had become 
 isolated and self-centred, a theory of individual life, not a com- 
 pendium of cosmical knowledge. The philosophy of Epicurus 
 was the most effectual answer to the needs of the age. While 
 Stoicism preached heroic fortitude, and had to be transformed 
 in a century and a half, Epicureanism in the fourth century 
 after Christ remained essentially the same system which had 
 been promulgated by the son of Neocles. 
 
 " The aim and end of all action," says Epicurus, " is that we 
 may neither suffer nor fear," rovrov jap xdptv aTravra irpar- 
 roftev OTTOJ? fiijre dA/yeo/iez/ //.^re rapySco/iey * " when once 
 this end is realised, all the tempest of the soul subsides, for 
 animal nature has then no need to satisfy, nothing is wanting 
 to the full completion of good, whether of body or soul. For 
 we want pleasure when we feel pain at its absence ; when we 
 feel no pain, we want no pleasure. It is for this reason that 
 we say that pleasure is the beginning and end of a happy life." 
 Here at least there is a concrete and definite answer to men's 
 demands. " Who will show us any good ? " was the pressing 
 
 1 Diog. x. 128.
 
 2 5 2 EPICURUS. 
 
 question asked amid the ruins of Hellenism. The good 
 is pleasure, and pleasure is the good, is the ans\\ 7 er of Epi- 
 curus. Xor will he have any mistake as to his meaning. 
 " I can conceive of no good remaining," he says, " if you 
 take from me the pleasures of taste, the pleasures of love, 
 and the pleasures of ear and eye." 1 And Metrodorus, the 
 disciple, exaggerating, as is the -wont of disciples, the teaching 
 of his master, says boldly : " It is in the belly that the natural 
 reason of man finds the chief object of his care." 2 The brother 
 of Metrodorus, a certain Timocrates, who was a renegade from 
 Epicurus's school, found in this and other texts plenty of matter 
 for scandal. He had had hard work, he said, to get away from 
 his nightly revels and all his mystic confraternity. As to 
 Epicurus 819 rrjs rjfiepas ep,eiv VTTO rpv<>rjs' crvvelvai re amm re 
 fcal MrjTpoSwpa) eraipas Kal aXXa?' Map/j,dpiov Kal 'HSeiav /ecu 
 'Epcortov Kal Ni/clSiov? "Notum inter accolas odium," and 
 Epicurus's name was the subject of many attributes, of which 
 Ktvai$o\o<y6<> was by no means the worst. 
 
 But Epicurus was not such a tiro in pleasures as to sup- 
 pose that a life of sensual enjoyment was a life of happiness. 
 A man of fierce, sensual nature like Aristippus, with the hot 
 blood of Africa in his veins, might indeed think so, and make 
 moments of pleasurable emotion (^ovo'xpovo^ rj^ovrj) the motto 
 of his school. But a man who lived no tempestuous life like 
 the Cyrenaic, but taught in his garden at Athens, who expressly 
 recommended his pupils to live in the country, 4 was not likely 
 to be a libertine and a voluptuary. Does pleasure only consist 
 in motion and restlessness ? Can indiscriminate indulgence in 
 pleasures secure happiness, not only for the present, but for 
 life ? Do pleasures differ only in quantity and not in kind ? 
 and is not the pleasure of the mind higher than the pleasure of 
 the body ? Does not man, as rational, look before and after, 
 and is not therefore the future and the past, as well as the 
 present, matter of concern for him ? Such were the questions 
 which naturally presented themselves to Epicurus, and mate- 
 
 1 Diog. x. 6. 
 
 * Ap. Athen. vii. ii. , irepl yaffr^pa 6 Kara (frvtnv padlfav \6yos TTJV awaffav ^x fl 
 ffirovd7]v. Cf. Eur. Cyclops, 335 (Paley), Kal rfj ^cyta-Ty yacrrpi ryde dai/j.6vuv. 
 s Diog. x. 6, 7. * [rbv a(><t>ov} cf>t\ayprifffiv.Ibid. 120.
 
 EPICURUS. 253 
 
 rially qualified his views on pleasure. "We do not choose 
 every pleasure : there are times when we relinquish many 
 pleasures, when the consequent inconveniences are greater, 
 and we hold many pains to be more choiceworthy than 
 pleasures, when, after much endurance of pain, we are re- 
 warded by a higher pleasure. Every pleasure is in its essential 
 nature a good, but not every pleasure is choiceworthy, just as 
 every pain is an evil, but is not therefore always to be avoided." 1 
 And again, very explicitly : " When we say that pleasure is 
 the end, we do not mean the pleasures of the libertine and 
 the pleasures of mere enjoyment, as some critics, either igno- 
 rant, or antagonistic, or unfriendly, suppose ; but the absence 
 of pain in the body and trouble in the mind." 2 Hence the 
 necessity of prudence and self-control in the direction of life 
 a prudence which is only to be taught by philosophy. " For 
 it is not drinkings and revellings, nor the pleasures of love, 
 nor tables loaded with dainties, which beget the happy life, 
 but sober reasoning (yr)$wv Xoyto-yLio?), to discover what must 
 be sought or avoided, and why, and to banish the fancies which 
 have most power to distract men's souls. Philosophy has no 
 more priceless element than prudence, from which all the 
 other virtues flow, teaching us that it is not possible to live 
 pleasantly without also living sensibly, honourably, and justly : 
 nor yet to live sensibly, honourably, and justly without living 
 pleasantly." 3 Therefore says Epicurus, " Let not the young man 
 delay to learn philosophy, neither let the old man weary ot 
 philosophy : for no one is either under age or over age to secure 
 his soul's health." 4 In point of fact, the end of a wise man's 
 life is not pleasure in the ordinary sense, but health, ease, 
 serenity (ir/leia, airovia, aTapa^la). 5 
 
 To the realisation of this serenity many things appear as 
 obstacles. Nature seems against a man, fate crushes him in 
 its grasp, the gods are not always his friends, death comes at 
 the last to end all his hopes and energies. Epicurus saw 
 
 1 Diog. 129. 2 Ibid. x. 131. 3 Ibid. 132. 4 Ibid. 122. 
 
 5 Cf. Lucian, Bis accusatus, cap. 22. Parasitus, ch. 11. The former 
 passage is a dialogue between the 2ro<f and Epicurus himself ; the latter is 
 concerned with the Epicurean idea of felicity.
 
 EPICURUS. 
 
 clearly enough that these impediments must be removed out of 
 the path of men's happiness, although, unfortunately, in nearly 
 each case, the removal is effected at the expense of his logic. 
 The whole of the superstructure which he builds on the founda- 
 tions of Hedonism and Sensationalism is an interesting attempt 
 to go beyond his ground-plan, to find room for the complexity 
 and the many-sidedness of life on the narrow platform of what 
 is called Individualism. Most of the miseries of life are caused 
 by superstition, and the first effort of the wise man must con- 
 sequently be to oppose science to religion, a knowledge of 
 nature to an imaginative mythology. Science, says Epicurus, 
 is freedom; mental serenity means enfranchisement from all 
 mythical opinions, and the constant memory of the main facts 
 of nature. " For if we study those events whence arise our 
 anxiety and fear, we shall find their true causes and be free." 1 
 Here is the first breach made in that theory of unintellectual- 
 ism with which Epicurus started. It is all very w r ell to tell 
 men to eschew culture and be happy ; but it is impossible at 
 the same time to tell them to be sages. However much it may 
 be true in some given point that ignorance is bliss, it is not a 
 good maxim for a life which aims at being continuously happy. 
 The theory breaks down at the outset, directly it is discovered 
 that happiness means at least freedom from fear, and that fear- 
 lessness is not attainable without knowledge. Some of the 
 elements of culture may indeed be abandoned ; a man need 
 not know literature, he may "act poems and not make them ;" a 
 Polyaenus may, on his entrance to the Epicurean ranks, abjure 
 the higher mathematics which made him famous ; and Epicurus 
 himself might declare the knowledge of celestial phenomena to 
 be either useless or unattainable a few years before Archimedes 
 and Hipparchus measured the volume of the earth and the 
 approximate distance of the moon; 2 but yet a certain amount 
 of science is indispensable, so as to make head against foolish 
 superstition. Almost the chief endowment of the Epicurean 
 sage must be a knowledge of nature, for "without physical 
 
 1 Diog. x. 82. 
 
 z Cf. M. Guyau's La Morale (PEpicure, p. 185. He there compares 
 Epicurus's incuriousness with that of Auguste Comte. Cf. too Cic. Acad. ii. 
 33. 106 ; Fin. i. 6. 20.
 
 EPICURUS. 
 
 255 
 
 knowledge our very pleasures are tainted." Religion lias been, 
 as Lucretius afterwards said, the chief cause of the greatest 
 evils ; and it is only possible to checkmate religion by science. 
 What then is to be our view of natural operations ? what 
 is the character of this saving and enfranchising physics ? 
 Epicurus's scheme is a strictly materialistic one, for the details 
 of which he is mainly indebted to Democritus. All life is 
 material, some form of body being at the base of all existence. 
 The ultimate elements of nature are not the so-called elements 
 which Empedocles made his o-roi-^eta. Fire, earth, air, and 
 water are, in fact, not simple bodies at all, but complex aggre- 
 gates, which can be divided into something more primordial 
 and original. At the base of things scientific analvsis reveals 
 
 o / 
 
 two elements, atoms and void, both of which are infinite ; and 
 the beginnings of creation are due to the infinite atoms fallino- 
 
 O t 
 
 through infinite space, collecting and aggregating themselves 
 here and there and forming worlds, life meaning the collection 
 of atoms, death their dispersion. 1 Even the soul is really 
 material, formed out of atoms which are indeed finer and rarer 
 than those which go to the creation of other substances, but 
 still essentially material in their structure. 2 Atoms have only 
 primary qualities, shape, size, and weight ; other qualities of 
 taste or colour are only subjective and secondary. 3 
 
 But before we get so far as this, the question naturally occurs 
 as to the capacities of the human mind for ascertaining the 
 truth about nature. What is the criterion of truth ? Sensation, 
 aiadrja-ts, is the answer of Epicurus. In that part of his 
 philosophy which answers to Logic, and which in his termino- 
 logy is TO /cavoviKov, he is very explicit on this matter. " The 
 criteria of Truth are sensations : There is nothing which can 
 convict sensations of error; neither a similar sensation, for 
 similar sensations have an equal value ; nor yet different 
 sensations, for they refer to different objects ; nor yet reason, 
 for reason itself is constructed out of, depends upon, sense (mi? 
 <yap Xo7o<? OTTO TWV alcrQrfcrecav ijpTrjTai)." 4 How then does 
 error arise, for it is obvious that hallucinations, for instance, 
 and dreams, are real ? It arises, not in the sensation itself, but 
 
 1 Diog. x. 39, 40, 41. 2 Ibid. 63. 3 Ibid. 44. * Ibid. 31, 32.
 
 256 EPICURUS. 
 
 in our inference from the sensation. The actual sensation of a 
 ghost which a nervous man sees is real and indubitable ; the 
 mistake arises when he draws the inference that what he sees 
 has a real existence outside him. Yet go beyond mere sensa- 
 tion we must ; for how else are we even to attempt to interpret 
 for ourselves the constitution of nature ? Epicurus feels the 
 necessity, but is not very scientific in his theory of the pro- 
 cesses founded on sensation. There are 7rpo\rf\lret,<>, he says, 
 which are notions founded on repeated sensations, and 6at, 
 which are opinions, and \6yos, which is ratiocination. The 
 whole process seems to go on naturally, without any idea of 
 the activity of mental construction. Every body throws out 
 ei^wXa, images of itself, and these images may come differently 
 to different men not that the thing itself changes, but that 
 the images, which men see of it, are different. Hence, as 
 Protagoras said, what seems to a man to be true is true for him, 
 and yet there is a real objective truth, as well as subjective 
 opinions. But how in any given case are we to know that we 
 have got hold of the true image ? Here Epicurus fails us ; 
 whether he falls back upon the Democritean dogma that there 
 is a true knowledge of the intelligence, as well as a false know- 
 ledge of mere sense-impression, or whether he cuts the knot by 
 the assertion that the images of the wise man are always true. 
 In each case the solution is more than unsatisfactory ; and in 
 this failure, the whole theory of nature, so far transcending the 
 mere impressions of sense, is involved in uncertainty and 
 doubt. 
 
 But this is after all a logical or metaphysical difficulty, 
 antecedent to the study of nature. There is, however, another 
 of a more practical nature which the Epicurean system of 
 physics has to meet. If everything in nature goes by fixed 
 and unalterable laws, is not man too bound in the links of an 
 iron fate ? For man is, according to the materialistic position, 
 part of nature, his body formed of the grosser atoms and his 
 soul of the finer. And if so, what becomes of human happiness 
 before the rigid laws of Necessity ? For Fate, too, as well as 
 superstition, is a stern schoolmaster, driving us in ways which 
 do not make for our peace. How can man's freedom, on 
 which his happiness seems to depend, be secured side by side
 
 EPICURUS. 257 
 
 with that regularity of natural law which is to banish super- 
 stition ? Here Epicurus's theory, judged by a modern standard, 
 becomes almost puerile. The atoms, according to him, have a 
 certain wilful spontaneity of their own ; they do not descend 
 in parallel lines : they swerve aside, self-moved, and in this 
 power of the atoms to deviate from the perpendicular, Epicurus 
 finds the origin of human free-will. 1 This is the celebrated 
 doctrine of the " clinamen," which Lucretius expounds at 
 length, and which Cicero covers with ridicule. 2 It may be, 
 of course, that we have not as yet got the theory in its true 
 outlines. Recent fragments from Herculaneum throw, accord- 
 ing to Professor Gomperz of Vienna, clearer light upon this 
 much-vexed question. " From these fragments there arises a 
 series of deductions which, it seems to me, are indubitable. 
 Epicurus was not, as has been hitherto supposed, an Indeter- 
 minist : he was an opponent of Fatalism, not of Determinism : 
 he did not believe in the causelessness of human acts of will ; 
 for, like Voltaire and others, he believed that man to be morally 
 free whose actions were determined by his own opinions : he 
 avoided, like the best thinkers of our day (like Mill, Grote, or 
 Bain), the use of the word Necessity in the processes of the 
 will, as a misleading expression. Like these philosophers, he 
 held that it was unsuitable to denote the efficacy of irresistible 
 causes, and the efficacy of all causes generally by one and the 
 same expression. Finally, his theory of the will was coloured 
 by that doctrine of knowledge which was peculiar to him and 
 to Democritus. The problem evidently culminates with him 
 in the question How can an act of will through an image 
 (el8a)\.ov) from without (the antecedent of every perception 
 and mental representation) be excited and determined by the 
 collection of our convictions, i.e. (in his sense) our whole 
 personality." 3 Whatever may be the exact opinions of Epicurus 
 on this matter, two things are clear First, that he declared (as 
 against the Stoics) that such a thing as Fate did not exist (7-771; 
 
 1 Plutarch, de Solert. Anim. 7, STTWS rb ^<' -qfjuv /UTJ air6\riTcu. 
 
 2 M. Guyau, in his La Morale. (V Epicure, defends the doctrine. See pp. 
 71-103. 
 
 3 Nuiie Bruchstiicke Epikur's insbesondere uber die Willenxfragc, von Th. 
 Gomperz (Wien, 1876), pp. 9-11. The fragments in question are those marked 
 
 K
 
 258 EPICURUS. 
 
 VTTO TWU>V Bea'TroTii' elcrayo^evrjv TTCIVTWV fj,rj 
 secondly, that freewill in man was necessary to insure the 
 validity of moral distinctions (TO Be Trap JHJ.WV d&eo-Trorov &> KCU 
 TO fiefiTTTOv Kal TO evcLVTiov 7rapaKO\ov6elv 7re<pvfcev). 1 
 
 Eyen though a man should disbelieye in Fate, he yet may 
 belieye in the influence of the Divinity upon human affairs, and 
 the Divine influence may chance to be malevolent. In the 
 thoughts of many of the Greeks, the godhead was not free from 
 envy ; and human happiness, if prolonged for many years, was 
 sure to bring down the gods' displeasure. Even though sucli 
 definite maleficent purpose were wanting, yet in the action of 
 the godhead there was something at once irresponsible and 
 incalculable, which would make the Epicurean " serenity " 
 difficult to realise. What then does Epicurus bid his followers 
 think about the gods ? " In the first place," he says in the 
 letter to Menoeceus, " you must think the god to be a being 
 incorruptible and blessed, according to ordinary notions on the 
 subject : attribute to him nothing which is inconsistent with 
 his incorruptibility, or inappropriate to his blessedness, but 
 think about him everything which is true to that union of 
 happiness and immortality which he enjoys. For gods there 
 veritably are, because our idea of them is clear. But they 
 are not what most people think them to be ; and the atheist 
 is not he who destroys the gods of the people, but he who 
 attributes the fancies of the people to gods." 2 And again : 
 
 8 and 9 in the list given above. [Pap. 1056 ; Coll. prior x. 697 ; Coll. alt. 
 vi. 55 seq.] Here is a fragment tolerably easy to follow, as restored 
 by Professor Gomperz : 
 
 ov (d d7r)oXeforet TO. irdOr] rov ylv(e'cr0at) vov0e(r)\ elv 
 
 re a\\rj\ovs Kal (/J,)dx(fff)9ai. Kal /jxTapvB/jLi^eiv (sic) 
 
 (!K %x oVTa 'S K l *" ea(v)Tdis rrjv al(r)La.v KCU oi>xl 
 
 Iv rfj e dpxys f^vov ffvffrdfffi KCU Iv rfj rov 
 
 7re/3(^%ovros Kal eireurt6vTos Kara TO afn-6narov 
 
 dvdyKi)(i). el yap ns Kal Tip vovdeTeiv Kal T^J 
 
 vovOere'icrOai TTJV /caret Tb av(r6) fJ.a(T)ov dvdyK-r)v 
 
 irp(ocr}v(t l j.oi'). Pap. 1056, 21, and Pap. 697, D, 1. 
 
 Cf. too Die Ueberreste eines Buches von Epikur irepi <f>v<rews (Gomperz, Wien, 
 1879), which adds to the foregoing. Also Fr. Bahnsch (Philolog. Anzeiger 
 1878, Nr. 5, Art. 73.) 
 
 1 Diog. x. 133. 
 
 2 Ibid. 123, dcre/Srjs 8t, oi/x 6 TOUS TWV TTO\\UV Oeovs dvaipuv, dXX' 6 rds r&v 
 
 Oeols
 
 EPICURUS. 259 
 
 " The blessed and immortal deity neither feels trouble nor 
 causes trouble : he feels no anger, nor is he moved by flattery : 
 for all such feelings indicate weakness " (ev do-Oevel jap irav TO 
 Toiovrov). 1 On the one hand, then, if the gods are really 
 happy, they can have nothing to do with the troubles of the 
 world; on the other hand, if they have nothing to do with 
 human affairs, men need not be afraid of their interference. 
 Thus the very condition of happiness in the gods secures the 
 inviolability of human happiness. The gods, infinite in num- 
 ber, live in happy ease in the intervals which separate the 
 infinite worlds. 2 They are in stature like men, composed of 
 very fine atoms ; they eat food, and thus repair the ravages of 
 time ; they are male and female ; and Philodemus, according to 
 a Herculanean fragment, has the hardihood to assert that they 
 speak something like the Greek language. 
 
 It is at the least doubtful how far Epicurus himself would 
 assent to all these predications about the godhead which were 
 certainly rife in his school. It would savour too much of that 
 " attributing of the fancies of the people to gods," which, in his 
 own fine phrase, constituted the character of the real atheist. 
 But, whatever may be the mental reservations or nuances of 
 thought involved, Epicurus undoubtedly asserted that the gods 
 exist, for the notions we have of them (based on sensations) are 
 clear, and clearness is to him, as well as to Descartes, the test 
 of truth. Perhaps the images of them which are found in 
 men's minds are due, as Deinocritus thought, to the fact that 
 while all objects, distant as well as near, send off eiBco\a of 
 themselves, the intervening medium of air distorts and magnifies 
 the images received by the senses. Perhaps they were mere ideals 
 of human life and happiness, for Epicurus in one passage declares 
 that they were only to be apprehended by reason \6ym Oewpr)- 
 Tot/9 elvai? Perhaps Epicurus was after all, in this respect, 
 somewhat of a hypocrite, according to the judgment of Posi- 
 donius. This much at least is certain, that, whatever the gods 
 were, they were not to be allowed to interfere either with the 
 reign of law in the natural world, or with the happiness of the 
 
 1 Diog. x. 139. 3 TO. /j.eraK&cr/jua, intermundia. 
 
 3 Diog. x. 139. Lucian makes Epicurus an atheist ; cf. the Jila accusatits, 
 Z< a* Tra/joedus, 22, and Jcaromenippus, 32.
 
 260 EPICURUS. 
 
 Epicurean wise man. The Epicureans might worship at the 
 temples, and a Diocles might feel the grandeur of Zeus himself 
 increased by the sight of an Epicurus on his knees ; l but Zeus 
 was no longer to be the cloud-compeller, the lord of heaven and 
 earth : he might retain his majesty, but he must lose his 
 terrors. 
 
 Yet, even so, the possibility of worshipping such gods 
 demands greater self-forgetfuluess in the wise man than Epi- 
 curus allows him. It is a remark of Seneca, that although 
 Epicurus banished disinterestedness from morality, he yet 
 allowed it a place in the worship of the gods. 2 What reason 
 could induce a man who was persuaded that his own pleasure 
 was his only object in life, to worship gods who had nothing to 
 do with the course of the world? What good could he get 
 from them ? what evil could he avert by his bended knees ? 
 And if nothing could be gained from such an act, what induce- 
 ment was there for a man to perform it ? The same difficulty 
 occurs in the Epicurean theory of friendship. Friendship, like 
 every other external relation, must in such a system be ulti- 
 mately based on its advantages. 'H (j)i\ia Sia T<Z<? %peia<?, says 
 Epicurus, although he adds that a great part of the resulting 
 advantage is the sense of community in enjoyment. Yet, how- 
 ever selfish in origin, friendship appears eventually to figure as 
 a highly disinterested virtue Epicurus in this view of the 
 subject resembling the ordinary modern Utilitarian. Hardly 
 any friendships, moreover, were more celebrated than the Epi- 
 curean, as Cicero remarks ; and hardly any words were too 
 strong to recommend it. "Of all the things which wisdom 
 provides for the happiness of a lifetime by far the greatest is 
 friendship." 3 And so high a view has Epicurus of the society 
 of friends, that he expressly discountenances the Pythagorean 
 formula of friendly communism. A professed communism 
 argues distrust, and distrust is the ruin of friendship. 4 When 
 
 1 Ace. to M. Guyau, La Morale d 1 Epicure, p. 178. 
 
 2 Senec. de Benef. iv. xix. 
 
 3 Cic. Fin. i. 20, 65 ; ibid. ii. 25, 80. 
 
 4 T(>V re ''EjriKovpov /J.TJ a^iovv efc rb KOIVOV KarariOeffOai TO.S ovcrias, Ka.0a.wep rbv 
 Tlvdayopav, KOIVO, TCI. rQ>v tfiiXuv \yoi>TO. - airicrTovvTuv yap flvai rb TOIOVTOV' el d' 
 airiaTUv, ovdt <pi\ui>. Diog. x. 11 ; cf. ibid. 148.
 
 EPICURUS. 261 
 
 we consider the selfish origin of friendship, it is not surprising 
 to learn that the later Epicureans were much exercised with 
 regard to the proper interpretation of the phenomenon. 
 
 One more obstacle to happiness remains, the most difficult 
 yet the most necessary to remove. The awful shadow of death 
 lies across men's lives, quenching not only enthusiasm but 
 serenity in the fear of impending pain and perfect annihilation. 
 How is a man to bear up against so inevitable a future ? How 
 is the delicate plant of human happiness to thrive in such an 
 undermined soil ? Some of Epicurus's best sayings have refer- 
 ence to death. " Accustom yourself," he tells Menoeceus, " to 
 think that death has nothing to do with us, since every good 
 and every evil depends on sensation, and death is the absence 
 of sensation. Whence it comes that the true knowledge that 
 death has nothing to do with us makes what is mortal in life 
 really enjoyable, not because it adds to life immortality, but 
 because it takes away our longing for immortality. For there 
 is nothing which can terrify a man in life, when he is assured 
 that there is nothing terrible in the absence of life. So that he 
 is a fool who tells us to fear death, not because its presence 
 will torment us, but that its anticipation torments us. For 
 that which troubles us not when it is come, has but vain 
 terrors when it is looked forward to. Death, then, the most 
 awful of ills, is nothing in our eyes ; for when we are, death is 
 not, and when death is, we are not." 1 But fear is not to be 
 exorcised by sophisms, and the question still presses for an 
 answer, Are not our pleasures ruined by the prospect of death ? 
 No, answers Epicurus, for pleasure is not made pleasure by 
 continuance, it is whole and entire in every pleasurable 
 moment. Pleasure is still pleasure, happiness is yet happiness, 
 even though it be doomed to an inevitable death. "Time, 
 whether limited or unlimited, involves an equal amount of 
 pleasure, if a man measures it by reason." 2 Can this con- 
 sideration, then, help the Epicurean, that pleasure is pleasure, 
 whether it is fleeting or permanent, whether it comes once or 
 lasts a lifetime ? Yet, when we remember that it was only by 
 means of the idea of continuance that Epicurus overcame the 
 
 1 Diog. x. 124. * Ibid. 145.
 
 262 EPICURUS. 
 
 ^ovrj of the Cyrenaics, that the pleasure he recom- 
 mended was precisely not the pleasure of any given moment, 
 but that pleasure which could last and become a permanent 
 possession, even this consolation breaks down. Here once 
 more, in the case of death, as in the case of fate, freewill, and 
 the gods, the higher philosophy of Epicurus is found too wide 
 for his foundation, and mental serenity, the Epicurean ideal of 
 life, can only be gained at the expense of Epicurean logic. 
 
 After all, one has to turn away from the system, in order to 
 reconstitute one's notion of the man. We think rather of the 
 kindly and genial teacher, realising the " rus in urbe " in his 
 Athenian garden, and surrounded by his friends, the faithful 
 Metrodorus, Polyaenus the converted mathematician, Hermar- 
 chus the future successor, above all, the little Epicurus and his 
 sister, Metrodorus's children. There are no asperities about 
 Epicurus, no angular points of chagrin or disappointment or 
 baffled hopes. He is as much above his professed opinions as 
 the ordinary man is below them. His system may require a 
 selfish account of friendship, yet he can say, " It is more blessed 
 to give than to receive." 1 His theoretic view of death forces 
 him to deny it any terrors ; yet he knows the full value of life, 
 and can administer a stern rebuke to the pessimist (perhaps 
 Hegesias, 6 TreicnOdvaTos) of his own day. " He who admonishes 
 a youth to live well, and an old man to die well, is a fool ; but 
 far worse is the man who says, ' It is well not to have been 
 born, and, when born, it is best to die.' For if he means what 
 he says, why not die at once ? It is quite open to him to do 
 so. But if he is jesting at us, he is frivolous on subjects which 
 do not admit of jest." 2 Epicurus might despise superstition, 
 yet he felt that fatalism was more morally ruinous. " It were 
 better to follow the myths about the gods than be a slave to the 
 fate of the physicists." 3 Seneca, who felt all the attractions of 
 the Epicurean system, has preserved for us another saying of 
 
 1 rb eZ iroielv ijSiov ecrrt TOV ir6.<rx f <- v - Plut. N on posse suav. viv. 15. 4. 
 
 2 Diog. x. 126, 127 ; cf. Soph. (Ed. Col. 1225. 
 
 3 Ibid. 134. So again a man's happiness is not to be imperilled by a belief in 
 luck and chance. ' ' Little indeed is the power which fortune has over a wise 
 man, for the main interests of life have been, are, and will be ordered by 
 Reason" (c. 144). And again : " Chance does not give us good and ill, but 
 only the beginnings whence good or ill may come" (c. 134).
 
 EPICURUS. 263 
 
 Epicurus, which has quite a modern sound : " Initium salutis 
 est notitia peccati "-the knowledge of sin is the first step in 
 reform. 1 Indeed, there is much modern quality in Epicurus. 
 Besides that doctrine of Utilitarianism, which fathers so much 
 modern philosophical thought, there is his belief in progress and 
 the slow results of Time. " We must admit," he says, " that the 
 nature of man is in many respects forced and schooled (StSa^- 
 Ofjvai, re teal avafyKacrdrjvai) by circumstances. Reasoning after- 
 wards perfects nature's lessons, and adds thereto new discoveries, 
 sometimes quickly, sometimes slowly, sometimes in long periods 
 of time, practically infinite." 2 It is difficult to find in any 
 other Greek writer so explicit a statement as this of the effects 
 of Time on human development. Or again, there is his theory 
 of justice, which anticipates Hobbes and Locke and Rousseau : 
 " Justice is nothing in itself, apart from human societies : 
 Justice is the token of a common interest, a contract not to 
 wrong or to be wronged." 3 Or, once more, there is the natural 
 origin attributed to Language (by no means the ordinary Greek 
 idea), which is said to be neither a divine creation nor an 
 artificial product, but which both Epicurus and Lucretius 
 explain as due to the natural emission of sounds expressive of 
 sensations and ideas. 4 
 
 But Epicurus's chief merit is undoubtedly found in the 
 simple, practical, and unaffected morality which he inculcated 
 both by precept and example. As a summary of the philo- 
 sophy of life the following maxims are not unworthy to be 
 reckoned with the thoughts of greater men than the Gargettian 
 sage : " The injuries which come to men either through hatred 
 or envy or pride, the wise man will conquer by reason. He 
 will acknowledge the power of feelings and passions, but will 
 not thereby be hindered in his wisdom. Even though he be 
 tortured, he is yet happy, albeit that at times in his torture he 
 will moan and groan. 6 It is the wise man only who can feel 
 
 1 Senec. Ep. 28, 9. 
 
 2 Diog. x. 75 ; cf. Lucret. v. 1452 : 
 
 Usus et impigrae simul experientia mentis 
 Paulatim docuit pedetemtim progredientes. 
 
 3 Diog. x. 150. 4 Diog. x. 75 ; Lucret. v. 1027. 
 6 As against the Stoical endurance of pain.
 
 264 EPICURUS. 
 
 affection for his friends, whether present or absent. He will 
 not punish his servants, but will be compassionate, and pardon 
 those who are worthy. Xo wise man will fall in love, nor 
 believe that Eros is heaven-sent. Xor will he be a good 
 orator. At times a sage will marry and beget children ; at 
 times, if circumstances be adverse, he will not marry, and will 
 try to dissuade others. He will neither cherish wrath in drunk- 
 enness, nor will he engage in politics, nor become a tyrant, nor 
 yet flatter. Neither will he beg. Even though bereft of eyes, 
 the wise man will still have a hold on life. He will feel grief : 
 he will think about property, he will provide for the future. 
 He will be fond of a country life, and bear a stout front against 
 fortune. Only so far will he think of repute amongst men, 
 that he be not contemned. More than others he will feel 
 delight at the theatre. It is only the wise man who will have 
 a right opinion on music and poetry ; yet the sage lives poems, 
 and does not make them. Money he will make, yet only in 
 wisdom, if he be in w r ant. He will court a monarch at the 
 proper moment; he will humour a man, in order to correct 
 him. He will found a school, but not to gain crowds of 
 scholars. He will give his opinion freely, and never be at a 
 loss; in his dreams he will be true to himself. And some- 
 times he will die for his friend." 1 
 
 Epicurus has had many resurrections ; his spirit has' lived 
 again in Gassendi, in La Eochefoucauld, in Saint-Evremond, in 
 Helvetius, and in Jeremy Bentham. Perhaps this fragment 
 from Saint-Evremoud may be most fitly compared with the 
 summary of virtue just quoted from Epicurus : 
 
 " He is a philosopher who keeps aloof alike from superstition 
 and from impiety ; an Epicurean, whose distaste for debauchery 
 is as strong as his appetite for pleasure ; a man who has never 
 known want, but at the same time has never enjoyed affluence. 
 He lives in a manner which is despised by those who have 
 everything, envied by those who have nothing, appreciated by 
 those who make their happiness and their reason agree. In his 
 youth he hated waste, being persuaded that property was 
 necessary to make a long life comfortable. In his age he cares 
 
 1 Diog. x. 117-121.
 
 EPICURUS. 265 
 
 not for economy, feeling that want is little to be feared, when 
 one has but a little time left to want in. He is grateful for 
 the gifts of nature, and finds no fault with those of fortune ; 
 he hates crime, endures error, and pities misfortune. He does 
 not try to find out the bad points of men in order to decry 
 them, but he looks for their foibles in order to give himself 
 amusement ; is secretly rejoiced at the knowledge of these 
 foibles, and would be still more pleased to make them known 
 to others, did not his discretion forbid. Life is to his mind too 
 short to read all sorts of books, and to load one's memory with 
 all sorts of things at the risk of one's judgment. He devotes 
 himself not to the most learned writings, so as to acquire 
 knowledge, but to the most sensible, so as to strengthen his 
 understanding. At one time he seeks the most elegant to 
 refine his taste, at another the most amusing to refresh his 
 spirits. As for friendship, he has more constancy than might 
 be expected from a philosopher, and more heartiness than could 
 be looked for even in a younger and less experienced man. As 
 for religion, he thinks justice, charity, and trust in the good- 
 ness of God of more importance than sorrow for past offences." 1 
 Such too was the Epicurean sage ; not a hero, not a statesman, 
 not even a philosopher, but a quiet, humane, and prudent man, 
 "a hero," as Seneca says, "disguised as a woman." Epi- 
 cureanism was undoubtedly not a speculative success, but as a 
 practical code of life it suited the world far more than its rival, 
 Stoicism, and lasted longer. It could not produce martyrs, 2 or 
 satisfy the highest aspirations of mankind, but it made men 
 fall back on themselves, and find contentment and serenity in 
 a life at once natural and controlled. AaOe fiiooa-as, Live in 
 secret, was the Epicurean watchword. " Keep my words," said 
 Epicurus, " and meditate on them day and night, by yourself 
 or with your friend, and you shall live as a god amongst men. 
 For there is nothing mortal about a man who lives in the 
 midst of immortal good." W. L. C. 
 
 1 Quoted in George Saintsbury's article on Saint-Evremond, Fortnightly 
 Review, July 1879. 
 
 * M. Guyau, however, says that Vanini, who had his tongue cut out, and 
 was burnt at Toulouse in 1619, was a martyr for the sake of Epicureanism. 
 La Morale d' 'Epicure, p. 192. He is usually called a Peripatetic.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF 
 THUCYDIDES. 1 
 
 1. THE famous phrase in which Thucydides claims a 
 lasting value for his work has had the fate of many striking 
 expressions : it is often quoted apart from the words which 
 explain it. " A possession for ever," not " the rhetorical 
 triumph of an hour:" taken by itself this has a ring of exul- 
 tation, noble perhaps, yet personal, as if the grave self-mastery 
 of the historian had permitted this one utterance in the tone of 
 the Eoman poet's confident retrospect or the English poet's 
 loftier hope, speaking of a monument more enduring than brass, 
 of things so written that men should not willingly let them die. 
 It is the context that reduces the meaning to a passionless pre- 
 cision. " The absence of fable in the History," he says, " will 
 perhaps make it less attractive to hearers ; but it will be enough 
 if it is found profitable by those who desire an exact knowledge 
 of the past as a key to the future, which in all human probability 
 will repeat or resemble the past. The work is meant to be a 
 possession for ever, not the rhetorical triumph of an hour." 2 
 That the intention of Thucydides has been fulfilled in his own 
 sense is due largely to the speeches which form between a 
 fourth and fifth of the whole work. It is chiefly by these that 
 the facts of the Peloponnesian war are transformed into typical 
 examples of universal laws and illuminated with a practical 
 significance for the students of politics in every age and country. 
 
 1 A table of the Speeches will be found at page 322. 
 
 2 i. 22. The re after KTij/ua. in the original marks the connection of the 
 thought: "and so. " Cp. i. 4, Mlvus . . . (Kpdrriffe . . . r6 re \yffTiKbv, 
 tl)s ek6s, Kadypfi : so 5, TO re ffid'rjpo^opfiffdai : 6, ^yv/j.vudrjffdv re : 9, 'A7<x- 
 
 re.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 267 
 
 The scope of the speeches is seen best if we consider what the 
 History would be without them. The narrative would remain, 
 with a few brief comments on great characters or events, and 
 those two passages in which Thucydides describes the moral 
 effects of pestilence and of party-strife. But there would be little 
 or no light on the inner workings of the Greek political mind, 
 on the courses of reasoning which determined the action, on 
 the whole play of feeling and opinion which lay behind the 
 facts. 
 
 2. The introduction of speeches became a regular part 
 of ancient historiography, and came in again at the revival of 
 literature, not quite going out, in Italy and France at least, till 
 the end of the last century. But the followers of Thucydides 
 were obeying an established tradition ; he was the writer who 
 had done most to establish it ; indeed, he might properly be 
 called its founder. The place of the speeches in his design was 
 due to special influences of the age as well as to the peculiar 
 bent of his mind ; we have to consider what had been done 
 before him, and the plan on which he went to work. 
 
 At the beginning of the Peloponnesian war a Greek prose 
 literature scarcely yet existed. The Ionian prose-writers before 
 Herodotus, or contemporary with him, are known to us only 
 from scanty fragments. But the Augustan age possessed all, 
 or nearly all, their writings ; and Dionysius of Halicarnassus 
 has described their general characteristics, comparing them 
 collectively with Herodotus and Thucydides. 1 These Ionian 
 writers, he says, treat the annals of cities and people sepa- 
 rately, 2 not combining them into a large picture, as Hero- 
 dotus does. Their common object was to diffuse a knowledge 
 
 1 Dionys. de Thuc. c. 5. Dionysius concedes the more dignified name of 
 ffvyypafais to the Ionian logographers. He names, (1 ) as anterior to the age of 
 Thucydides, Eugaeon of Samos, Deiochos of Proconnesos, Eudemos of Paros, 
 Democles of Phigaleia, Hecat'aeus of Miletus, Acusilaus of Argos, Charon of 
 Lampsacus, Amelesagoras of Chalcedon ; (2) as elder contemporaries of 
 Thucydides, Hellanicus of Lesbos, Damastes of Sigeion, Xenomedes of Chios, 
 Xanthos of Lydia. His words imply that these, " and many more " (dXXoi 
 ffvxvoi), were then extant. 
 
 lh. ov ffwaTTTOvres dXX^Xaiy (ras i<rropias), d\Xd /car' HOvri Kal Kara. TnSXets 
 ditupovvTfs : whereas Herodotus is said TroXXdj Kal 5ia<p6povs 7r/>dets ^s /j.iav 
 Trepiypa<j>T]i> IT pay pare Las ayaytlv.
 
 268 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 of the legends which lived in oral tradition (oaai 
 fAvr]jj,ai), and of the written records (ypa^ai) preserved in 
 temples or state- archives ; and to publish these " such as 
 they received them," without adding anything, and on the 
 other hand without omitting " myths " and ' theatrical epi- 
 sodes" which appear childish to a more critical age. 1 As 
 to style, it is much the same for all of them, plain, 
 concise, " strictly to the point," 2 without artificial display ; 
 but with a certain freshness, he adds, and some degree of 
 charm, which has been the secret of their survival. The 
 meagre fragments which remain, such as those of Xanthus 
 and Charon, Hecataeus and Hellanicus, consist chiefly of short, 
 jerky sentences, strung together in the baldest possible fashion. 3 
 If these Ionian writers introduced dialogues or speeches as 
 the example of the epic poets might have led them to do it may 
 be conjectured that these were of the simplest kind. There is 
 one, indeed, who has left proof that he could write dialogue 
 with the ease and grace of Herodotus himself. 4 But Ion 
 of Chios was a poet as well as a chronicler; he knew the 
 
 1 Dionys. de Thuc. c. 5, ev otj /cal /j.i)0oL rives evijffav virb TOV iro\\ov 
 ireiria'Tfii/j.evoi j(j>l)vov (cp. Thuc. i. 21, of the stories told by the logographers, 
 virb xpoi/ou . . . eirl TO /jivdwdes eKveviKTjKora) /ecu OearpiKai rives irepnreTfiai, 
 iroXi) rb rf\L0Lov ?x fiv T0 ^ s v ^ v SoKovffai. 
 
 s Ib. TOLS Trpay/Aaai Trpoff<pvrj. In Herodotus (i. 27, etc. ) irpoutpvews \eyeiv 
 is simply ' ' to speak pertinently. " But the phrase of Dionysius seems to 
 mean, not merely "adapted to the subject," but closely adhering to the 
 facts of the story (whether mythical or not), without attempt at verbal 
 embellishment. It is illustrated by the dry and absolutely matter-of-fact 
 style of the extant fragments. 
 
 3 Muller, Fraym. Histor. Graec. i. 1-68. The longest fragment of Heca- 
 taeus may serve as a specimen : " Orestheus, son of Deucalion, arrived in 
 Aetolia in search of a kingdom ; and a dog produced him a green plant ; 
 and he ordered the dog to be buried in the earth ; and from it sprang a 
 vine fertile in grapes. Wherefore he called his son Phytius. Now the 
 son of Phytius was Oeneus, so named after the vine-plant ; for the ancient 
 Greeks called the vine Oena : and the son of Oeneus was Aetolus. " (Frag. 
 341, p. 26.) 
 
 4 The story of the poet Sophocles defending the phrase M irop<j>vpeoM 
 Trapyaiv against the criticisms of a learned guest at a supper-party in 
 Chios. (Muller, Fraym. Hist. vol. ii. p. 46. ) The 'Eiridr]/j.tai, in which it 
 occurred, seem to have been Ion's account of his own "visits" to Athens 
 and other cities. (Ibid. p. 45.)
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 269 
 
 Athens of Pericles ; and his memoirs, with their sprightly 
 gossip, must have been very unlike the normal type of Ionian 
 chronicle. 
 
 Herodotus is distinguished from his predecessors, first of 
 all, by an epic unity of plan. It is hard to say exactly how 
 far he was superior to them in his method of verifying facts 
 his diligence and his honesty are both unquestionable, and we 
 know that he attempted not very scientifically, perhaps to 
 decide between conflicting versions of the same story. But in 
 the dramatic element of his narrative he shows the true free- 
 dom of an epic poet. In his History, as in the Iliad and the 
 Odyssey, the author seldom speaks when there is a fair pretext 
 for making the characters speak. The habitual use of " direct 
 speech," or easy dialogue, is evidently a different thing from 
 the insertion of set speeches : there is nothing necessarily 
 rhetorical about it. It is merely the vivid way of describing 
 thought and motive, the way natural to a simple age ; and in 
 the case of a work meant to be heard rather than to be read, 
 like the early Greek prose works, it has the obvious recom- 
 mendation of helping to keep the attention alive. Even the 
 longer speeches in Herodotus have usually the conversational 
 tone rather than the rhetorical. 1 On the other hand, there are 
 a few which may be considered as properly rhetorical, that is, 
 as efforts by Herodotus to work up a vague tradition in the 
 most effective form. The debate in the Persian cabinet on the 
 invasion of Greece 2 is a case in point. The speeches of 
 
 1 E.g. the speech in which Aristagoras of Miletus appeals for aid to 
 Cleomenes, king of Sparta (Herod, v. 49), and that of Sosicles at Sparta 
 (v. 92), which is simply a plain sketch of the Corinthian tyrannies, put 
 into the mouth of a Corinthian speaker. 
 
 a Her. vii. 8-11. The council is called fftiXXoyos ^TT/K-XIJTOS Hepafav ru>v 
 dptffruv : as in viii. 101 Xerxes tfiovXevfro &/j.a Ilfpfftwv roicrt. tiriKXrfroiffi : i.e. 
 with his "privy-councillors." Later writers went at least as far as Hero- 
 dotus in reporting speeches made on occasions which presuppose privacy ; 
 as when Dionysius, Livy, and Plutarch give the expostulations of Veturia 
 (or Volumnia) with Coriolanus, when Sallust is present in imagination 
 at a debate of Catiline's conspirators, or when Livy transcribes the 
 brilliant, but domestic, remonstrances of Pacuvius Calavius with his son 
 Perolla, offered with a view of dissuading the young man from murdering 
 Hannibal at Capua. Thucydides never violates dramatic probability in 
 this particular way.
 
 270 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 Xerxes, Mardonius, and Artabanus have been carefully elabor- 
 ated, and have the elementary dramatic merit of expressing 
 views which Persian speakers could conceivably have taken. 
 Another example is the debate of the Persian conspirators 
 after the death of the false Smerdis. Otanes argues for 
 democracy, Megabyzus for oligarchy, Darius for monarchy ; 
 but here the points of view seem purely Hellenic. 1 Herodotus 
 prefaces his report of the discussion by saying, " Speeches 
 were made which some of the Greeks refuse to credit ; but 
 made they were :" 2 and elsewhere 3 he remarks with triumph 
 that " those Greeks who do not believe " in Otanes having 
 advocated democracy will be surprised to hear that Mardonius 
 established democracies in the Ionian cities. The ground of 
 this dramatic episode, then, was a story current among the 
 Greeks of Ionia, but rejected by some of them, as manifestly 
 inconsistent with Persian ideas. The spirit of rhetorical 
 dialectic may be traced again very clearly in the conver- 
 sation between Solon and Croesus, where Solon refines on 
 the distinction between wealth, good fortune, and happi- 
 ness. 4 Still, it cannot be said that Herodotus had much 
 love for set rhetorical display : his taste was for conversa- 
 tion lively, ingenious, argumentative it might be, but still 
 mainly in the colloquial key. 5 A good instance of the 
 
 1 Her. iii. 80-82. Similarly in Her. iii. 36 the Lydian Croesus utters 
 Hellenic thoughts. 
 
 2 Her. iii. 80, e\'xfl'n ffa - v ^0701 S.TTICTTOI /JLV tvioicri 'EXX^rwc, ^\^6-rj(rav ft 1 Siv. 
 
 3 Her. vi. 43, tvdavra. ^yicrrov 6uv/j.a tptu roiffi /J.TJ a.Tro5eKo/j.tvoicn 'EXX^wy 
 Hepcrtwv Toiffi fTTTCL 'Ordvfo. yvwfj.riv dirod^aaOai, ws xpe&v eii) drj/uLOKpar^effOai 
 Tltpffas : where yurj d7ro5e/co / it&'oi<rt implies more than //TJ iriffTevovvt would have 
 implied, viz. that the statement was offered for acceptance, not simply 
 by Herodotus himself, but by a widely-spread rumour. 
 
 4 Her. i. 32. The question of Croesus to Solon had been rlva rfdrj irdvruv 
 elSes oXjSiciro.Toi' ; Solon answers, in effect, that irXoOroj is certainly an 
 element of 6X/3os, but that complete 8\pos requires evrvxia also, and that 
 a man's life cannot be called curias unreservedly until we have seen it 
 to the end. Dean Blakesley observes (on Her. i. 32), that this "might 
 have proceeded from the mouth of Protagoras, or Hippias, or any other 
 of the fjLepifivrjral \6ywv alluded to by Euripides" (in. Medea 1225 f.). If it 
 has not the matured subtlety of the rhetorical dialectic, it may certainly 
 be said to anticipate its spirit. 
 
 5 Dionysius says most truly of Herodotus that he has almost all the 
 excellences of style except the eva.-yuvi.oi dperai the combative excellences,
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 271 
 
 way in which he passes by an opportunity for oratory is his 
 brief notice of the speech made by Themistocles just before the 
 battle of Salamis : l "His theme was the contrast between all 
 that is worthy and all that is base. He exhorted them to 
 choose the better part in all that men's nature and condition 
 permit ; and then, having wound up his discourse, he ordered 
 them to embark." The true rhetorician would have developed 
 the topic which Herodotus barely indicates. 2 It may be 
 noticed, too, that the ornament of the speeches in Herodotus is 
 sometimes distinctly Homeric illustrating his nearer affinity 
 to epos than to rhetoric. Thus the Corinthian Sosicles, in 
 the debate at Sparta, begins with truly epic force : " Verily 
 now the sky shall be under the earth, and the earth shall 
 hang above the sky, men shall have their pastures in the 
 sea, and fish upon land," if Spartans become the friends of 
 tyranny. 3 
 
 3. Thucydides has stated the general principles on which 
 he composed the speeches in his History. The precise interpreta- 
 tion of that statement depends, however, partly on the question 
 How far is it probable that Thucydides is there instituting 
 a tacit comparison between his own method and that of Hero- 
 dotus ? So far as we know, the work of Herodotus was the 
 only prose work in which Thucydides could have found a pre- 
 
 such as were afterwards developed by strenuous controversy, political or 
 forensic. ovd yap drj/jnjyoptais iroXXdis 6 dvijp ov5' evayuviois KexP 7 l Tal \6yois, ovS' 
 fv T iraOaiveiv Kal deivoiroielv rd Trpdyfiara TTJV d\KT]v % (de Thuc. c. 23). 
 
 1 Her. viii. 83, TO. d Hirea Ijv irdv-ra Kpeaau TOICTI eayoffi avririOefieva. Sera 
 8 tv dvdp&irov <t>vo~i Kal KaraaTacri eyyiverai, wapatveffas 5?j TOVTUV rd Kpeaau 
 alptevOai Kal /cara7rX^as TTJV pTJcnv eafiaiveiv eK.e\eve es ras vrjas. 
 
 ? Cp. Plato, Hippias Major, p. 286, where the sophist Hippias tells 
 Socrates that he has composed "an admirable discourse" on the theme of a 
 question supposed to be put by Neoptolemus to Nestor after the taking of 
 Troy What are /caXd 1-jrir'rjde^/jLara ? The phrase of Herodotus, /carairX^^ay 
 TTJV prjcriv, reminds us of the tone in which the speakers of Thucydides some- 
 times decline to develop commonplaces. 
 
 3 Her. v. 92, ^ di] & re ovpavbs tcrrai ZvepBe rrjs yrjs Kal ij yrj fj-ertupos virtp rov 
 otipavov Kal ol avBpuvoi vofJibv ev Oa\dffffr] efcovffi Kal o't /%#yes rbv irporepov avGpwiroi, 
 Sre ye vpets, & AaKedaiu6viOi, IfroKparias Kara\vovTes rvpavvidas s rds 7r6Xty Kard- 
 yeiv wapa(TKevde(r9e. Compare the epic phrase which closes the spirited 
 oration of Dareius in the debate of the conspirators ov yap afj.ei.vov (Her. iii. 
 83 ; Iliad xxiv. 52, ov /J.TJV ol TO ye KO\\IOV ovde r 1 &/j.fivov, etc.).
 
 272 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 cedent for dramatic treatment applied to history. If Thucy- 
 dides knew that work, it would naturally be present to his 
 mind at the moment when he was stating the rules of his own 
 practice. It can be shown almost certainly that a period of at 
 least twenty years must have elapsed between the time at 
 which Herodotus ceased to write and the time at which 
 the History of Thucydides received the form in which it has 
 come down to us. 1 It was possible, then, for Thucydides 
 
 1 Herodotus alludes to no event later than 425 B.C., the latest mark of 
 time being a doubtful reference to the death of Artaxerxes in 425 (vi. 98). 
 And there are instances in which his silence affords presumptive proof that 
 later events were unknown to him. (1) In 437 B.C. Athenian colonists 
 founded a city on the spot formerly called Ennea Hodoi, and their leader 
 Hagnon named it Amphipolis, because the Strymon flowed on both sides of it. 
 Herodotus mentions Ennea Hodoi (vii. 114), but nowhere speaks of Amphi- 
 polis. Had he been writing after the new colony had become important, he 
 would naturally have mentioned it in this connection ; he could scarcely 
 have failed to do so after the battle of Amphipolis in 422 B.C. had made the 
 place famous. (2) Demaratus tells Xerxes that Spartans never yield : it is 
 their fixed law to conquer or die (Her. vii. 104 ; cf. 209). This passage would 
 have been singularly infelicitous if it had been written after the surrender of 
 the Lacedaemonians at Pylos in 425 B.C., when 120 Spartan prisoners were 
 brought to Athens ; an event which, as Thucydides expressly says (iv. 40), 
 astounded the Greeks, precisely because their belief had been that which 
 Herodotus expresses. (3) Demaratus advises Xerxes to detach 200 ships 
 from his fleet, for the purpose of occupying the island of Cythera, and quotes 
 the saying of Cheilon, that it would be well for Sparta if Cythera were sunk 
 in the sea (Her. vii. 235), Xerxes neglected the advice. But in 424 B.C. 
 the Athenians actually occupied Cythera, and the damage thence inflicted on 
 Laconia was one of the causes which disposed the Spartans to conclude 
 peace. Herodotus would not have omitted, if he had known, so forcible an 
 illustration of Cheilon's saying. And there are indications that Herodotus 
 did not live to give the last touches to his work : thus a promise made in 
 vii. 213 is left unfulfilled. [The revolt of the Medes "from Dareius " (Her. 
 i. 130), which Dahlmann identified with the revolt of 408 B.C. (Xen. H. i. 2. 
 19), has been shown by the Behistun inscription to belong to the reign of 
 Dareius Hystaspes.] 
 
 F. W. Ullrich (Beitraqe zur Erklcirung des Thukydides ; Hamburg, 1846) 
 has ingeniously argued that Thucydides composed his first three Books, and 
 Book iv. as far as ch. 48, in exile (about 421-413 B.C.) ; and the rest of the 
 work, as a continuation, after the final close of the war. This view rests 
 mainly on the alleged existence of passages in Books i. iv. 48 which imply 
 ignorance of later events. Classen has examined these passages in detail 
 (Einleitung, xxxii. liv.), and has, I think, shown that they are insufficient to 
 support the theory built upon them. My opinion has not been altered by read- 
 ing a learned essay in favour of Ullrich's hypothesis, which has appeared
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 273 
 
 to know the work of Herodotus ; that he actually knew it, and 
 that he pointedly alludes to it in several places, cannot be 
 doubted by any one who weighs the whole evidence. 1 
 
 In the view of Thucydides there had hitherto been two 
 classes of writers concerned with the recording of events. 
 First, there were the poets, especially the epic poets, of whom 
 Homer is the type, whose characteristic tendency, in the eyes 
 of Thucydides, is to exaggerate the greatness or splendour of 
 
 since Classen's Introduction was published (Ueber die successive Entstehung 
 des Thucydideischen Geschichtswerkes, by Julius Helmbold ; Colmar, 1876). 
 But for the present purpose it is enough to assume, what even the supporters 
 of Ullrich's view would allow, viz. that the whole work was at least revised 
 by Thucydides after the end of the war. (See Thuc. i. 13. IS ; ii. 65.) The 
 probable influence of Herodotus is here being estimated in relation to those 
 parts of the work of Thucydides which would have been the last to receive 
 his finishing touches the speeches. 
 
 1 That Thucydides knew the work of Herodotus is assumed by Lucian (de 
 cons. hist. 42), Marcellinus (vit. Thuc. 54), Suidas (s.v. opydv), Photius 
 (cod. 60), and the Scholiast on Thuc. i. 22, etc. In modern times it has been 
 denied or questioned by F. C. Dahlmann (Herodot. p. 214), K. 0. Miiller 
 (Hist. Gk. Lit. c. xxxiv. 2, and Dorians, ii. 98, 2), by J. C. F. Bahr (in 
 his edition of Herodotus), and in an essay De plurlmis Thuc. Herodotique locis, 
 by H. Fiitterer (Heiligenstadt, 1843). The proofs that Thucydides knew the 
 works of Herodotus have been brought together by Mure (Hist. Gk. Lit. Bk. 
 iv. ch. 8), and more recently by H. Lemcke, in an essay entitled Hat Thuc. 
 das Werk des Herod, gekannt 'f (Stettin, 1873.) The crucial texts are (1.) 
 Thuc. i. 20, on the common errors regarding the vote of the Spartan kings 
 and the Pitanate company, compared with Her. vi. 57 and ix. 53 ; (2.) Thuc. 
 ii. 97, on the Thracians and Scythians tacitly correcting what Herodotus 
 says of the Thracians (v. 3) and of the Scythians (iv. 46) ; (3.) Thuc. i. 126, 
 on Cylon's conspiracy, compared with Her. v. 71 ; Thuc. vi. 4 on Zankle 
 (Messene) compared with Her. vi. 23 ; Thuc. ii. 8, on the earthquake at Delos 
 (cf. i. 23) compared with Her. vi. 98. In view of all these passages, it seems 
 impossible to doubt that in i. 97 Thucydides includes or specially designates 
 Herodotus among those who ^ ret irpb T&V 'M.ijdiKwv 'E\\rjviK& ^werldeaav i) 
 avra TO. Mr?5t/cd. 
 
 I must add a word on the vexed interpretation of Her. vi. 57, TOI)S fj.d\iffrd 
 ff<j>i TUV jfpbvTwv TrpoffT/iKovras <=~)(eiv TO. rCiv /3a<ri\ewv ytpea, dtio ^0ous ride^vovs, 
 rplr-qv 8 TT\V ewvr&v. The question is, Does Herodotus mean riOe^vovs dtio 
 ij/ri<povs (Kdrepov, TpiTtjv 8t TTJV ewvrov ? Shilleto (Thuc. i. 20) thinks that this is 
 not certain, suggesting that roi)s irpoff-fiKovras might mean rbv dei Trpoff-fiKovra, and 
 comparing Her. iv. 62, T0icr5e = ry ev e/cdory dpx^'V, but ne sees the difficulty 
 of supposing the same person to be nearest of kin to both kings. Failing this 
 resource, we must surely allow that Herodotus means 5tfo ^TJC^OVS fKartpov, for 
 Isu how could he possibly have written Tpiri^v 8 rty euvruiv ? Would he 
 not have written dtVT^pas St rds fwvrwv ? 
 
 S
 
 274 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYD1DES. 
 
 things past. 1 Secondly, there were the prose writers whom he 
 calls chroniclers (\oyoypd(j)oi) ; and these he characterises by 
 saying that they " compiled " 2 their works with a view to 
 attracting audiences at a recitation, rather than to truth ; deal- 
 ing largely, as they did, with traditions which could no longer be 
 verified, but had passed into the region of myth. Now with 
 such chroniclers Herodotus was undoubtedly classed by Thucy- 
 dides. The traits common to Herodotus and the other chro- 
 niclers, as Thucydides viewed them, were (1) the omission of 
 really accurate research the tendency to take what lay ready 
 to the writer's hand (TO, erolfjua, i. 20) ; (2) the mixture of a 
 fabulous element with history ; (3) the pursuit of effect in the 
 first place, and of truth only in the second. Probably Thucy- 
 dides would have said that Herodotus was more critically 
 painstaking and less indiscriminately tolerant of fable than 
 most of the other chroniclers, but that his study of effect was 
 more systematic and more ambitious. The imaginary dialogues 
 and speeches in Herodotus would be the most conspicuous 
 illustrations of this desire for effect. If they were not absolute 
 novelties in the chronicler's art, at least we may be sure that 
 they had never before been used in such large measure, or 
 with such success. 
 
 The first aim of Thucydides in his introduction is to show 
 that the Peloponnesian war is more important than any event 
 of which the Greeks have record. He then states the principles 
 on which his History of the War has been composed. " As to 
 the various speeches made on the eve of the war, or in its 
 course, I have found it difficult to retain a memory of the 
 precise words which I had heard spoken ; and so it was with 
 those who brought me reports. But I have made the persons 
 say what it seemed to me most opportune for them to say in 
 view of each situation ; at the same time, I have adhered as 
 closely as possible to the general sense of what was actually 
 said. As to the deeds done in the war, I have not thought 
 myself at liberty to record them on hearsay from the first in- 
 
 1 Thuc. i. 10, et'/cis eirl rb /J,eiov [itv Troii)Tj]v 6vra Ko<rfj.fj<ra.i : 21, ws TroiTjral 
 VfU^lictUTU> tirl TO p,ei^ov Ko<r/j.ovvTes. 
 
 3 Thuc. i. 21, ^vvtBeaav, as again 97, ^vverLOfaav, implying a process more 
 external and mechanical than ^v
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 275 
 
 formant, or on arbitrary conjecture. My account rests either 
 on personal knowledge, or on the closest possible scrutiny of 
 each statement made by others. The process of research was 
 laborious, because conflicting accounts were given by those who 
 had witnessed the several events, as partiality swayed or 
 memory served them." 1 
 
 The phenomena of the war, then, as materials for history 
 are classed by Thucydides under two heads \6yoi,, things said, 
 and epya, things done. These are the two elements of human 
 agency. 2 As regards the epya, the deeds, he is evidently con- 
 trasting his ow r n practice with that of the chroniclers generally. 
 He has not taken his facts, as they did, without careful sifting 
 he had formed a higher conception of his task 
 In regard to the words, the \6yot, he is tacitly con- 
 trasting his own practice with that of Herodotus, the only 
 conspicuous example in this department. If his statement 
 were developed in this light, it might be paraphrased thus : 
 Thucydides says : (1) I have not introduced a speech except 
 when I had reason to know that a speech was actually made : 
 unlike Herodotus, when he reports the conversation between 
 Croesus and Solon, the debate of the Persian conspirators, the 
 discussion in the cabinet of Xerxes. (2) I do not pretend to 
 give the exact form of the speeches made : as a writer implies 
 that he does when, without warning the reader, he introduces 
 a speech with the formula, " He said these things " (e'Aeye 
 raSe), 3 instead of "He spoke to this effect" (eXeye roidSe). 
 
 1 Thuc. i. 22. 
 
 * Shilleto remarks (on i. 21 2) : "TCI 5' Zpya T&V irpaxOfrruv is a somewhat 
 bold expression for TO. 5' tpya. TO. irpaxd^ra." It may be added that the 
 phrase has the special effect of bringing out the antithesis between facts of 
 speech &nd. facts of action. 
 
 3 Cp. Her. iii. 80, where the speeches of Otanes, Megabyzus and Dareius 
 are introduced by \tywv raSe . . . \tywv rode . . . ZXege raSe : so v. 91, tXeyov 
 raSe . . . clirov ravra : 92, Xee rode (Sosicles) : vii. 8, ?Xefe H^/>i?s rdde : and 
 so usually. Thucydides nearly always has Ae^cw or ZXeyov roiade, with roiairra 
 (orToo-oOra)attheend. Ini. 85 (of Sthenelaidas), IXe^ev tD5e ("in this manner," 
 not = ra5e). In iv. 58 the speech of Hermocrates is introduced by roiotirovs 
 Sr; \ayovs direv, where 5^ appears to mean "as we may presume ;" i.e. he 
 spoke " to this general effect " the phrase intimating somewhat more plainly 
 than the usual TOLj.de that Thucydides had only a very general notion of the
 
 276 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 (3) On the other hand, I have faithfully reproduced the 
 speaker's general line of argument, the purport and substance 
 of his speech, so far as it could be ascertained. Herodotus 
 disregards this principle when he makes Otanes, Megabyzus 
 and Dareius support democracy, oligarchy and monarchy by 
 arguments which no Persian could have used. And in filling 
 up such outlines, my aim has been to make the speaker say 
 what, under the circumstances, seemed most opportune (ra 
 Beovra yu,aXt<TT<z). 
 
 The last phrase is noticeable as marking a limit of dramatic 
 purpose. According to the regular usage of the words 1 (TO, 
 Seovra) in Thucydides, it can mean only "what the occasion 
 required" not necessarily what was most suitable to the 
 character of the speaker. The latter idea would have been 
 expressed by a different phrase (TO, TrpocnjKovTa). That is, in 
 filling up the framework supplied by the reported "general 
 sense " of a speech, Thucydides has freely exercised his own 
 judgment on the situation. Suppose a report to have reached 
 him in this shape : " Hermocrates spoke in the congress at 
 Gela, urging the Sicilian cities to lay aside their feuds and 
 unite against Athens." In composing on this theme, the first 
 thought of Thucydides would be, "What were the best arguments 
 available?" rather than, "What arguments would Hermocrates 
 have used?" This general rule would, of course, be liable to 
 various degrees of modification in cases where the speaker was 
 well known to the historian as having marked traits of 
 character, opinion or style. 
 
 4. " Set speeches," says Voltaire, " are a sort of oratorical 
 lie, which the historian used to allow himself in old times. He 
 used to make his heroes say what they might have said. . . . 
 At the present day these fictions are no longer tolerated. If 
 one put into the mouth of a prince a speech which he had 
 never made, the historian would be regarded as a rhetorician." 2 
 How did it happen that Thucydides allowed himself this 
 " oratorical lie," Thucydides, whose strongest characteristic is 
 
 1 Thuc. i. 70, TO TO. B^OVTO. Trpa^ai : 138, avToa-xfSid^fLv TO. dtovra : ii. 43, 
 iyvuffKOvrfs ra d^ovra : ii. 60, yvuvai re TO. dfovra KO.I ep/jLTjvevffai ravra. 
 * Preface to the Hist, of Russia, 7.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDWES. 277 
 
 devotion to the truth, impatience of every inroad which fiction 
 makes into the province of history, laborious persistence in the 
 task of separating fact from fable : Thucydides, who was not 
 constrained, like later writers of the old world, by an established 
 literary tradition ; who had no Greek predecessors in the field 
 of history, except those chroniclers whom he despised precisely 
 because they sacrificed truth to effect ? Thucydides might 
 rather have been expected to express himself on this wise : 
 " The chroniclers have sometimes pleased their hearers by 
 reporting the very words spoken. But, as I could not give 
 the words, I have been content to give the substance, when I 
 could learn it." 
 
 In order to find the point of view at which Thucydides 
 stood, we must remember, first of all, the power which epic 
 poetry had then for centuries exercised over the Greek mind. 
 The same love of the concrete and comprehensible which 
 moved the early Greeks to clothe abstract conceptions of a 
 superhuman power in the forms of men and women, " strangers 
 to death and old age for ever," led them also to represent the 
 energy of the human spirit as much as possible in the form of 
 speech. The Homeric ideal of excellence is the man of brave 
 deeds and wise words. The Homeric debates are not merely 
 brilliant, but also thoroughly dramatic in their way of charac- 
 terising the speakers. 1 The Iliad and Odyssey accustomed the 
 Greeks to expect two elements in every vivid presentation of 
 an action first, the proofs of bodily prowess, the account of 
 what men did; and then, as the image of their minds, a 
 report of what they said. Political causes strengthened this 
 feeling. Public speech played a much larger part in the 
 affairs of States than it now does. Envoys spoke before an 
 assembly or a council on business which would now be 
 transacted by the written correspondence of statesmen or 
 diplomatists. Every adult citizen of a Greek democracy 
 had his vote in the assembly which finally decided great issues. 
 
 1 Sir G. C. Lewis, in illustrating this point, instances the embassies from 
 Corcyra and Corinth to Athens (Thuc. i. 68), from Mitylene to Olympia (iii. 9), 
 and from the Athenians and Syracusans to Camarina (vi. 76). (Methods of 
 Observation and Reasoning in Politics, vol. i. p. 232. )
 
 278 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 To such a citizen the written history of political events would 
 appear strangely insipid if it did not give at least some image 
 of those debates which imparted the chief zest to civic life and 
 by which political events were chiefly controlled. He was one 
 who (in modern phrase) had held a safe seat in Parliament 
 from the time when he came of age ; who had lived in the 
 atmosphere of political debate until it had become to him an 
 almost indispensable excitement ; and who would feel compara- 
 tively little interest in hearing the result of a Parliamentary 
 division unless he was enabled to form some idea of the process 
 by which the result had been reached. Such a man would 
 not have been satisfied with the meagre information that 
 the Athenian Ecclesia had discussed the fate of Mitylene, 
 that Cleon had advocated a massacre, that Diodotus had 
 opposed it, and that the view of Diodotus had prevailed by a 
 narrow majority. His imagination would at once transport 
 him to the scene of the parliamentary combat. He would 
 listen in fancy, as he had so often listened in reality, to the 
 eloquence of antagonistic orators, he would balance the possible 
 arguments for severity or clemency, he would conceive himself 
 present at the moment when one uplifted hand might incline 
 the scale of life or death, and he would feel the thrill of relief 
 with which those who supported Diodotus found that Athens 
 was saved at the eleventh hour saved, if the bearers of the 
 respite, rowing night and day, could reach Lesbos in time 
 from the infamy of devoting a population to the sword. 
 When Thucydides gave in full the speeches made by Cleon 
 and Diodotus, he was helping his reader, the average citizen 
 of a Greek republic, to do on more accurate lines that which 
 the reader would otherwise have tried to do for himself. 
 Thucydides was writing for men who knew Greek politics from 
 within, and he knew that, if they were to follow him with 
 satisfied attention, he must place them at their accustomed 
 point of view. The literary influences of the age set in the 
 same direction. At the beginning of the war the Attic drama 
 had been in vigour for more than forty years. The fame of 
 Aeschylus was a youthful memory to men who had passed 
 middle life ; Sophocles was sixty- four, Euripides was forty-nine. 
 Each had given great works to Athens, and was yet to give
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 279 
 
 inure. An age of vivid energy had found the poetry most 
 congenial to it in the noblest type of tragedy, and this, in turn, 
 fed the Greek desire to know character through deed and word. 
 In the hands of Euripides tragedy further became the vehicle 
 of dialectical subtleties and the dramatic mirror of public 
 debate. At the same time Attic oratory was being prepared 
 by two currents of influence which converged on Athens the 
 practical culture of Ionia, represented by the Sophists, and the 
 Sicilian art of rhetoric. 1 
 
 5. If the speeches in Thucydides were brought under a 
 technical classification, the Funeral Oration would be the only 
 example of the " panegyrical" or epideictic class ; the pleading 
 of the Plataeans and Thebans before the Spartan Commissioners 
 might possibly be called " forensic ;" and all the other speeches 
 would be in some sense " deliberative." 2 But such a classifica- 
 tion, besides being rather forced, does not correspond to any 
 real differences of structure or form. If the speeches are to be 
 viewed in their literary relation to the History, it is enough to 
 observe that the addresses of leaders to their troops may be 
 regarded as practically forming a class apart. 3 
 
 The right of an adult citizen to attend the debates of the 
 Ecclesia must have been acquired by Thucydides many years 4 
 before the war began. From its very commencement, as he 
 says, he had formed the purpose of writing its history. There 
 is every probability that he had heard most or all of the 
 important discussions which took place in the Ecclesia be- 
 tween 433 and 424 B.C. It was in 423 B.C., or at the end of 
 the year before, that his exile of twenty years from Athens 
 began. Thence we can name some at least of the speeches 
 to which he probably refers as heard by himself (auro? 
 
 1 The early history of Greek oratory, and the various influences which con- 
 tributed to mould it during the fifth century B.C., have been traced by the 
 writer in the Attic Orators from Antiphon to Isaeos, vol. i. Introduction, 
 pp. xciii-cxxxvii. 
 
 2 /. e. in the largest sense of ffVfj.pov\evriKoi, under which the addresses of 
 leaders to troops would be included as irpoTpeimKoi the speeches in poli- 
 tical debate being dr)fj.T)yopla.i in the proper sense. 
 
 3 See the table at the end ; and below 7. 
 
 4 Probably from 451 B.C., if his birth may be placed in 471 B.C. Cp. K. F, 
 Hermann, Antiq. i. 121 ; Xen. Mem. Socr. iii. 0. 1.
 
 280 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 iJKovcra), and not merely reported to him. Such would be the 
 addresses of the Corcyrean and Corinthian envoys, when they 
 were rival suitors for the Athenian alliance in 433 B.C. ; the 
 speeches of Pericles; the debate on Mitylene in 427 B.C.; and the 
 speech of the Lacedaemonian envoys in 425 B.C., making over- 
 tures of peace to Athens. If he was not present on all these 
 occasions, still, as a resident citizen, he would have exceptional 
 facilities for obtaining a full and accurate account. Taking this 
 group of speeches first, then, we may consider how far they are 
 apparently historical in substance, or show traces of artificial 
 treatment. 
 
 After giving the addresses of the envoys from Corcyra and 
 Corinth in 433 B.C., Thucydides notices the course of the debate 
 in the Ecclesia. Two sittings were held. At the first, he says, 
 the Athenians inclined to the arguments of the Corcyreans, and 
 were disposed to conclude an alliance both offensive and 
 defensive ; at the second they repented of this, but decided to 
 conclude a defensive alliance. The considerations which pre- 
 vailed with them were, that war was unavoidable in any case ; 
 that the Corcyrean navy must not be allowed to pass into the 
 hands of the Corinthians; and that Corcyra was a useful 
 station for coasting voyages. 1 These three arguments are just 
 those on which the Corcyrean speech, as given by Thucydides, 
 chiefly turns. 2 The circumstantial account of the debate in the 
 Ecclesia cannot be treated as fictitious. Either, then, Thucy- 
 dides has given the substance of the arguments really used by 
 the Corcyreans, or he has ascribed to them arguments used on 
 their side by Athenian speakers in the Ecclesia. Now the 
 speech of the Corinthian envoys has at least one mark of 
 substantial authenticity : the references to benefits conferred 
 on Athens by Corinth in the matters of Samos and Aegina 3 
 would certainly have occurred to a Corinthian envoy more 
 readily than to an Athenian writer. In both the Corcyrean 
 and the Corinthian speech it seems probable that Thucydides 
 has given the substance of what was really said, though he may 
 have added touches from his recollections of the subsequent 
 debate in the assembly. Similar is the case of the speech 
 
 1 Thuc. i. 44. - i. 32-3J. 3 i. 42.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 281 
 
 made by the Lacedaemonian envoys at Athens in 425 B.C. 1 The 
 historian's comment on it is as follows : " The Lacedaemonians 
 spoke at such length' 2 [i.e. for Spartans], in the belief that the 
 Athenians had previously desired a truce, and had been 
 hindered only by Spartan opposition ; so that, when peace was 
 offered, they would gladly accept it, and restore the men." 
 This clearly implies that the speech ascribed to the envoys 
 which Thucydides may well have heard is historical in 
 substance. 
 
 The Thucydidean speeches of Pericles raise three distinct 
 questions : How far do they preserve the form and style of 
 the statesman's oratory ? how far do they express the ruling 
 ideas of his policy ? and how far do they severally represent 
 what he said on the several occasions ? 
 
 As Thucydides must have repeatedly heard Pericles 3 
 whom he describes as the first of Athenians, most powerful 
 in action and in speech, 4 it would be strange if he had not 
 endeavoured to give at least some traits of the eloquence 
 which so uniquely impressed contemporaries. Pericles is said 
 to have left nothing written : 5 but Aristotle and Plutarch have 
 preserved a few of the bold images or striking phrases which 
 tradition attributed to him. 6 Several examples of such bold 
 imagery occur in the Thucydidean speeches of Pericles, 7 and it 
 
 1 Time. iv. 17-20. 
 
 2 By roffavra in such a context Thucydides usually means "only thus much, " 
 as ii. 72, roffavra elirbvTwv HXaraiSiv. But in iv. 21, roffavra flirov refers back 
 to iv. 17 2, robs d \6yovs /j-aKportpovs ov Trapd TO eiuObs ^.rjKvvovfjiev. 
 
 3 See e.g. ii. 13, Z\eye 6t Kal d\\a oldirep el&Oei HepiKXfy. 
 
 4 i. 139. 
 
 5 Plutarch, Pericl. c. 8 : <*yypa<fx>v p.tv ovdtv dvoX^Xonre tr\7]v TU>V \l/ri<pi(rfji.a.T<i>v , 
 diro/j.i'rjfj.oi'eveTai dt 6Xiya iravrdiraffiv. 
 
 6 Arist. Rhet. iii. 10 7 : &<rvep HepiK\fjs <pTj rr\v vebrifra. rrjv airo\o^vriv ev 
 T(j)iro\{/J.i{} OUTWJ f)<f>avicr6a.i K TTJS 7r6Xeojs, uffirep et ns rb Hap IK rov tviavrov ^e\oi: 
 ib. TJ]V "Aiyivav dfaXew ^/cAewe ryv XTJ/UTJI/ TOV Heipattws. Plut. Per. 8 5 
 quotes his saying, rbv 7r6Xe^oc ijdi] Kadopav airb HeXoirovvriffov Trpoff<t>tp6fievoi> : 
 and of those who fell at Samos, tyKu/j.idfav eirl rov @rnj.a.Tos aOavarovs ?\eye 
 yeyovtvai KaOairep rovs Oeovs' 01) yap ticelvovs avrovs 6pwfj.ev, dXXa TCUS TI/JLCUS As 
 txovffi Ka.1 rots ayaffois & ira.p^'xovffi.v ddafdrov^ elvai TfK/j.atpt>fie6a. 
 
 7 E.g. ii. 43, rbv dyripuv eiraivov KaXXiffrov Upavov irpoi'ttJ.tvoi . . . : 41, 
 fj.vrjjjif'ia. KdKwi' Ka.ya.duv didia ^vyKaroiKlffavres . . . : 43, avdpCiv firi<pavwv ird<ra 
 yi) ra^os . . . , and others passim in the ^rird^cos : in ii. 62, Kyirlov Kal
 
 282 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 can hardly be doubted that they are phrases which have lived 
 in the historian's memory. But the echo is not heard in single 
 phrases only. Every reader of the Funeral Oration must be 
 aware of a majesty in the rhythm of the whole, a certain 
 union of impetuous movement with lofty grandeur, which 
 Thucydides has given to Pericles alone. There is a large 
 alloy, doubtless, of rhetorical ornament in the new manner 
 of overstrained antithesis : 1 but the voice of the Olympian ' 1 
 Pericles is not wholly lost in it. There can be no question, 
 again, that the speeches of Pericles in the Ecclesia accurately 
 represent the characteristic features of his policy at the 
 time. 3 But how far do they severally represent what Pericles 
 said on the several occasions? Thucydides makes Pericles 
 use different topics of encouragement at three successive 
 stages. 
 
 In 432 B.C. Pericles emboldens the Athenians to reject 
 the Peloponnesian demands by a general comparison of the 
 resources and prospects on either side. 4 In 431 B.C., when 
 Archidamus is about to invade Attica, Pericles repeats his 
 former exhortations, but supplements them by a detailed 
 exposition of Athenian resources, financial and military. 5 In 
 
 e-y/caXXciTTto-^a TrXoirrou, and many more. Bold imagery of this kind was 
 characteristic of the elder school of oratory, and generally of what Dionysius 
 calls the avffr-ripa. ap/j.ovia : cp. Attic Orators, vol. i. p. 27. 
 
 1 The most glaring example is the reiterated contrast of "word" and 
 "deed," which occurs some eighteen times in the Funeral Oration, and is 
 parodied (as Mr. H. M. Wilkins observes, Introduction to the Speeches, p. 
 xxv) in the Platonic Menexenus [Menex. p. 236 D/Epyy /*&> rj/uv o'iSe x owt 
 TO, irpoffriKovra crfplffiv avrois, Giv TV%6vTes iropetiovTai TTJV ifj.ap/J,vr]v iropflav, 
 TrpoirefjupOevTes KOivjj /J.tv virb rrjs ir6Xews, Idig. 5e inrb r&v oiKeiwv' X6y<f> 5 STJ, 
 K.r.X. And immediately afterwards, Zpyuv eS irpaxOevrwv . . . \6yy KO\UIS 
 
 2 Ilept/cX^s ov\ij/j.irios, Ar. Acharn. 530. Eupolis notices the rapidity, the 
 charm, and the sting of his eloquence (A^ot, Frag. Com. i. 162) ; cp. Attic 
 Orators, i. p. cxxx. 
 
 8 Viz., to make no derogatory concessions, but to accept the war; to wage 
 it, however, mainly on the defensive, allowing the enemy to ravage their 
 lands, but guarding their possession of the city and the sea ; to rely chiefly 
 on their navy, and to retain a firm hold upon the allies, whose tribute gave 
 the financial superiority to Athens. 
 
 4 i. 140-144. 5 ii. 13.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDWES. 283 
 
 430 B.C., after the second invasion of Attica, when the land had 
 been devastated and while the plague was raoino- Pericles 
 
 X O O O* 
 
 convened a special meeting of the Ecclesia, 1 with the twofold 
 purpose of reassuring his countrymen and of allaying their 
 resentment against himself. " As to the prospects of the war, 
 you may rest satisfied," he says, " with the arguments by which 
 I have proved to you on many other occasions that you have no 
 cause of uneasiness. But I must notice a special advantage 
 which the scale of your empire confers, one, I think, which 
 has never occurred to you, which I have not mentioned in 
 addressing you before, and which I should not have noticed now 
 as the claim implied might seem too arrogant did I not see 
 you unreasonably dejected. You think that you rule your allies 
 alone. I tell you that of the two fields open to human action, 
 land and sea, the latter is under your absolute dominion, not 
 merely to the extent of -your actual empire, but as much 
 further as you please. While you hold the sea in your present 
 naval strength, you cannot be resisted by the Persian king, or 
 by any nation on earth." 2 Thus, as the pressure on the 
 Athenian spirit becomes more and more severe, the exhorta- 
 tions of Pericles go on from strength to strength, until, at the 
 darkest hour of all, they culminate in a triumphant avowal 
 that the naval empire of Athens is not relative but absolute, is 
 not an empire over a limited confederacy but a boundless 
 supremacy on the sea. If this ascending scale, so fitly gradu- 
 ated, was due to the invention or arrangement of Thucydides, 
 it was a dramatic conception. But it seems more probable 
 that the topics really used by Pericles on these three occasions 
 were substantially those given by the historian. It is difficult 
 otherwise to justify the emphatic clearness with which the 
 special theme of the second speech is distinguished from that 
 of the first, and that of the third, again, from both. 3 On the 
 
 1 ii. 59, v\\oyov irotTJtray, i.e. t->jyK\t}Tov tKK\T]<rtai>, which Pericles could con- 
 vene as one of the Ten Generals (In 5' ta-Tparriyei). 
 
 2 ii. 62 2. 
 
 3 Compare ii. 13 2, Trapyvei 5 ical irepl TWV Trap&vruv airep ical irpbrepov (re- 
 ferring to i. 140-144) . . . dapo-ew re ^/cAei/e, K.T.\. (introducing the fipecial 
 subject of the second speech), with ii. 62 1, introducing the special subject 
 of the third.
 
 284 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 other hand, the first speech of Pericles betrays some remark- 
 able traces of manipulation by the writer. Earlier in the 
 same year the Corinthian envoy at the Peloponnesian congress 
 had given several reasons for believing that the Peloponnesians 
 were likely to prevail in the war. With help from the sacred 
 treasuries of Delphi and Olympia, he had said, they might lure 
 away the foreign seamen of Athens by offering higher pay. 
 They could acquire naval skill by practice. And among the 
 possibilities of the war he suggests the occupation of a fortress 
 in the enemy's country. 1 The speech of Pericles answers these 
 arguments point by point. But the correspondence is not 
 merely in the topics. The very phrases of the Corinthian 
 speech are repeated by Pericles in his reply. 2 Similar paral- 
 lelisms may be traced between the Corinthian speech and 
 that delivered by the Spartan Archidamus on the occasion 
 of the former congress : one with which the Corinthians cannot 
 be supposed to be acquainted in detail, since it was made to 
 the Spartans only, after strangers had withdrawn. 3 The fact 
 is that the eight 4 speeches recorded by Thucydides as delivered 
 at Athens or Sparta before the commencement of the war form, 
 for his purpose, a group by themselves. In these he has 
 worked up the chief arguments and calculations which were 
 current on either side. Collectively, they are his dramatic 
 presentation of the motives at work, the grievances on each 
 side, the hopes and fears, based on a comparison of resources, 
 with which the combatants entered on the struggle. At the 
 end of his first speech Pericles says : " I have many other 
 reasons to give for hoping that we shall prevail; but these 
 shall be given hereafter as the events arise (a/^a rot? epyot?) " 
 thus foreshadowing the speech of which an abstract is given 
 
 1 i. 121 3-4 ; 122 1. 
 
 2 Compare (1) Pericles, i. 143 1, et re ical Kivr/ffavTes TUI> 'OXv/tnKwv T) 
 
 AeA$>o?s 'xpi]}t,o.rwv fuaOip fjLei^ovi , . . virokafieiv TOI)S evovs T&V vavruv, with 
 the Corinthian speech, i. 121 3, curb T&V ev AeA<o?s /cat 'OXu/wr/p xpw*- 
 TUV . . . vTroXafietv fj.iffOy p.eiovL TOVS evovs avruiv vavparas : (2) Pericles, i. 
 142 6, with Corinthian, i. 121 4 ; (3) Pericles, i. 142 2, with Corinthian, 
 i. 122 1. 
 
 3 Compare i. 120-4 with i. 80-85. 
 
 4 See the Table at page 322 ; cp. i. 21, o<ra tiirov
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 285 
 
 on a subsequent occasion. 1 In this particular case, as we have 
 seen, the disposition of topics may well be authentic in the 
 main. But the composer's phrase is significant. It suggests 
 the habit of selecting from a certain stock of available material 
 and disposing the extracts with something of a dramatist's 
 freedom. 
 
 In the Funeral Oration there is nothing, apart from the 
 diction, which distinctly shows the invention of Thucydides. 
 At first sight there is some plausibility in the view that such 
 an oration would probably have contained allusions to the 
 heroic legends of Attica, and that the mind of Thucydides is to be 
 traced in their suppression. 2 But the argument may be turned 
 the other way. The very absence of mythical embellishment, 
 it might be urged, is rather a proof of the fidelity with which 
 Thucydides has reported a speaker who, regardless of the 
 vulgar taste, was resolved to treat a w T ell-wom theme in a new 
 and higher strain. One or two passages, indeed, have been 
 supposed to hint at the moral deterioration of the Athenian 
 democracy in the years which followed the death of Pericles ; 3 
 but the supposition seems gratuitous. 
 
 It remains to notice the debate in the Ecclesia on the 
 punishment of Mitylene. Cleon urges a massacre, Diodotus 
 opposes it. " These views," says Thucydides, " having been 
 stated with nearly balanced effect, the assembly came after all 
 to a division ; and on a show of hands the parties proved nearly 
 equal, but the view of Diodotus prevailed." The words can 
 only mean that, in the speeches of Cleon and Diodotus, Thucy- 
 dides has given the real substance of the arguments which were 
 
 1 i. 144 2, dXX' IKC'IVO. (j.v icai fv fiXXy \6y(f> a/M rots tpyois Srj\uB^ffeTat. The 
 promise is fulfilled by the speech of which an abstract is given in ii. 13, and 
 by that reported in the direct form in ii. 60-64. 
 
 2 The suggestion of F. C. Dahlmann (Hist. Forschungen, i. 23), to which 
 Grote justly opposes the fj.aKprjyope'ii' tv eid6criv ov /3ov\6/j.evos tdvu (Thuc. ii. 36). 
 The analogy of similar extant pieces (the Menexenus, the tirirdfaoi falsely 
 ascribed to Lysias and Demosthenes, the Panathenaicus of Isocrates, etc.) 
 justifies Dahlmann's major premiss, but does not support his conclusion. 
 
 3 Viz. (1) ii. 37 3, the reference to a restraining 5<?<w, and to those laws, 
 6(7oi &ypa(f>oi Svres ala'x.vvTjv ofj.oXoyovfj.tvrji' tpfpovo'i : (2) 40 1, 0iXoKaXoi;/ue' per 
 ( irreXeias /ecu <f>i\o(ro<t>ov/j.ev S.i>ev //aXa/a'as. I cannot assume the allusions which 
 Classen finds here to a subsequent and opposite state of society.
 
 286 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 found to be so " nearly balanced," and which led to so close a 
 division. Cleon's speech has one striking characteristic. In 
 several places it echoes phrases which occur in the speeches of 
 Pericles. 1 But, with these verbal parallelisms, there is a 
 pointed contrast of spirit. As Pericles describes the good 
 side of the intellectual Athenian nature, Cleon brings out its 
 weak side. As Pericles insists on the Athenian combination 
 of intelligence with courage, Cleon declares that this intelli- 
 gence leads men to despise the laws, and prefers ignorance 
 combined with moderation. 2 Pericles is gone: Cleon echoes 
 the words of the statesman as whose successor he poses, at the 
 very moment when he is contradicting his principles. It may 
 be observed that when Thucydides reports the speech of the 
 Syracusan demagogue Athenagoras, he marks his manner by a 
 certain violence of expression. 3 Cleon, whom Thucydides calls 
 "most violent," has no violence of expression. Probably 
 this abstention from vehemence of the demagogic type, this 
 superficial imitation of Pericles, are traits in which the Cleon 
 of Thucydides is historical. 
 
 This closes the series of those seven speeches, delivered at 
 Athens, for which Thucydides probably derived the " general 
 
 1 Compare (1) Cleon, iii. 37 2, rvpawLSa %x ere T V "PX 1 ?"* 'with Pericles, ii. 
 63 2, us TvpaitviSa yap tfSr) <?x eTe T V ^PX^I" ' (2) Cleon, iii. 40 4, tic rov 
 dKivdiJvov dvSpayadi^fffdai, with Pericles, ii. 63 2, ef TIS Kal r6de ev rcj) Trap6vri 
 SeSi&s dirpay/jLOffi''vri dvSpayaOi^erai : (3) Cleon, iii. 38 1, tyw p/lv oZv 6 cn/r6s 
 el/u TTJ yvd}/j.fi, with Pericles, ii. 61 2, Kal tyu /J.ev 6 atiros elui Kal oik ^ia-rafMi. 
 Compare also Cleon's notice (iii. 37 2) of rb KaO' yptpav dSe^s in Athenian 
 life, with what Pericles says of TO. KaB' yfiepav e'7riT??5ei//iaTa, ii. 37 2. 
 
 2 Cleon, iii. 37 3, dfjiadla re fiera ffw<f>poffvv^ w<^eXiyu.wrepov ?} Sejfto-njs fiera 
 aKo\a<rlas, K.T.\., contrasted with Pericles, ii. 40 2, ov TOI>S \6yovs rots Zpyois 
 
 ijyovfievoi, K.T.\., and ii. 62 5, rr^v r6\fj.av . . . i) iW(rts . . . 
 
 8 E.g. vi. 40, dXV ?rt Kal vvv, S> iravrajv d^vveTwraroi, el /J.TJ aavOdvere /caeca 
 T) dfiaG^ffrarol tare Siv lyu olda 'EXX^vw^, ^ dSiKtirraroi, el el56rfs 
 
 In a M6moire sur Thucj/dide, by M. Meierotto (in the Memoirs of the Berlin 
 Academy for 1790-91, p. 530), the writer observes, with reference to the dis- 
 crimination of character in the speeches: "Cleon et Athenagore parlent 
 ordinairement d'un ton dur, offensant et grossier, dont pourtant ils s'ecartent 
 quelquefois. " We have only one speech of Cleon and one of Athenagoras; 
 so far as these go, however, the striking thing, it seems to me, is not the 
 resemblance, but the contrast.
 
 THE SPEECPIES OF THUCYDIDES. 287 
 
 sense " either from his own recollection or from the sources 
 accessible to a resident citizen. The only one of these which 
 exhibits distinct traces of artificial dealing with subject-matter 
 is the first speech of Pericles. And in this the only traces 
 are, first, a certain adjustment of the language to that of 
 the Corinthian speech made earlier in the same year; 1 and, 
 secondly, a phrase by which the composer prepares the reader 
 for a subsequent speech of Pericles. 
 
 6. We now come to the speeches made elsewhere than at 
 Athens from 432 B.C. onwards, or made at Athens later than 
 424 B.C. In regard to all or most of these, Thucydides must 
 have relied on reports of the " general sense " brought to him 
 by others (rot? a\Xo9ev iroOev e/jiol aTrayyeXXovcriv^)? The first 
 general characteristic which claims notice is the occurrence of 
 passages certainly, or almost certainly, written Avith a con- 
 sciousness of later events. These passages may be cast into 
 three groups, according as they relate to (I.) the affairs of 
 
 1 As the Corinthian speech contains a prophecy (after the event) of the 
 occupation of Deceleia (eiriTfixt<r/j.6s, i. 122 1), so the corresponding passage 
 of Pericles contains what may be a reference to the Athenian occupation of 
 Pylos and of Cythera (i. 140 3, einTfixi^iv . . . TrXewrcu'Tas ^s TTJV tKelvwv). 
 
 * Thuc. v. 26 : "It befell me to live in exile for twenty years [423-403 B.C., or 
 nearly so] after my command at Amphipolis. I thus became conversant with 
 both parties indeed, as an exile, I saw most of the Peloponnesians and was 
 enabled to study the events more at my leisure." The phrase here KO.I yevo- 
 ptvip trap' afjL<t>or{pois rots irpdyiMcri certainly implies more than that Thucydides 
 was in the countries which were the theatre of the war. It implies that he 
 was in intercourse with the actors. The words Ka.9' yvvxiav denote the " ease " 
 or "leisure" of one who had no official status, political or military. Hitherto 
 Thucydides had been himself an actor in the war (in the Ecclesia or as ffTpaTrj- 
 76s) ; now he was only a thoughtful spectator. During his exile Thucydides 
 certainly spent some time in Italy and Sicily. Marcellinus quotes ( 25) the 
 statement ws <f>vyu>v ipKT}fffv tv 'IraXt'g, and there was even a tradition of his 
 burial there ( 33). There are traces, I think, of Thucydides' personal know- 
 ledge of Sicily in the speech of Alcibiades (vi. 17 3). Niebuhr conjectured, and 
 E. Wolfflin has shown (Antiochus v. Syrakus u. Coelius Antipater, Winterthur, 
 1872), that Thucydides (vi. 2 ff.)used the St/teXtwrts <rvyypa<f>ri which Antiochus 
 of Syracuse brought down to 424 B.C. These are the chief data for con- 
 jecturing the general nature of the materials which Thucydides may have 
 had for the speeches subsequent to 425 B.C. In many cases, probably, he 
 had good sources of information, though it is hardly likely that the words 
 S>v avrbs iJKova'a can include any speeches except those made at Athens before 
 his exile.
 
 288 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 Sicily, (II.) the Deceleian war, (III.) the final defeat of 
 Athens. 1 
 
 (I.) 1. Speaking in the congress at Gela in 424 B.C., Her- 
 mocrates warns his hearers against the designs of Athens. The 
 Athenians, he says, are now on our coast with a few ships; but 
 some day they will come with a larger fleet, and endeavour to 
 reduce the W 7 hole island. 2 The Athenian fleet on the Sicilian 
 coast at this time must have numbered some fifty or sixty 
 triremes. 3 Hermocrates, speaking in 424 B.C., certainly would 
 not have spoken of these as " a few ships," least of all when it 
 was his object to show that Athens was formidable. 4 But 
 Thucydides, when he composed the speech, had in view the 
 vast fleet at least thrice as numerous 5 sent to Sicily in 
 415 B.C. 
 
 2. Nicias, in his second speech dissuading the Athenians 
 from the expedition to Sicily, says that the only Sicilian cities 
 likely to join the invaders are Naxos and Catana. 6 Both ISTaxos 
 and Catana did, in fact, join the Athenians. But the Athenians, 
 when they opened the campaign in Sicily, had hopes of other 
 cities also. The alliance of Messene 7 was solicited by Alci- 
 biades, though without success. Both Athenian and Syracusan 
 envoys were sent to Camarina, and it was not without much 
 hesitation that Camariua resolved to remain neutral. 8 The 
 
 1 In the list of nine passages noticed here, I have not included any in which 
 the suggestion of acquaintance with subsequent events did not seem to me 
 tolerably strong and clear. Thus I have purposely omitted the passage in 
 which Archidamus says (432 B.C.) of the war, dtdoiica 8t /j.3.\\ov ^ KO! rots 
 Trcucriv avrov viroXiiru/j.ei' (i. 81 6), in which some find a knowledge of its 
 actual duration ; a passage in vi. 11 (in the speech of Nicias), which might 
 possibly be regarded as foreshadowing the aid actually lent by Sicily to Sparta 
 at a later time (viii. 26) ; and a reference by Hermocrates to future feuds and 
 reconciliations between the Sicilian cities (iv. 64). 
 
 Five of these passages have been noticed by previous writers, viz. Nos. 
 1, 5, 6, 7, 9 ; the others Nos. 2, 3, 4, 8 have not, to my knowledge, been 
 considered in this light before. 
 
 2 iv. 60, 6\iyais vaval Trap6vres , . . TrXtovi Trore crroXy eXOovras. 
 
 3 Twenty triremes had been sent in 427 B.C. under Laches (iii. 88), whom 
 Pythodorus had superseded ; forty more were afterwards sent under Euryme- 
 don (iii. 115), and these had now joined the first detachment (iv. 48). 
 
 4 As Grote remarks, vii. 189, n. 
 
 * Thuc. vi. 31. 6 vi. 20. 7 vi. 50. 8 vi. 88.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDWES. 289 
 
 precision of the forecast made by Nicias betrays knowledge of 
 the event. 
 
 3. Again, when the Athenian attack on Sicily is imminent, 
 Hermocrates, in his speech at Syracuse, gives reasons for think- 
 ing that it will fail. Numerous as the Athenians are, he says, 
 they cannot outnumber the united forces of Sicily. " And if 
 they should fail from want of supplies in a foreign country, 
 they will still leave glory to those against whom their design 
 was laid, even though they should be ruined mainly by their 
 own errors." 1 Thucydides elsewhere expresses his own view of 
 the Sicilian disaster. The primary cause of the failure was 
 not, he thinks, a miscalculation of forces, but rather the 
 neglect of the Athenians at home distracted as they were by 
 faction to support the army in Sicily, a neglect which blunted 
 the zeal of those engaged in the campaign. 2 The words 
 ascribed to Hermocrates were written by Thucydides in retro- 
 spective view of the Athenian errors which had led to the 
 Athenian defeat. 
 
 4. The speech of Euphemus, the Athenian envoy at Cama- 
 rina, offers another example. Urging the people of Camarina 
 to join the Athenians rather than the Syracusans, he reminds 
 them that they will not often have an opportunity of securing 
 such powerful auxiliaries. And if, he says, you dismiss them 
 now, " one day yet you will long to see even the least part of 
 them, when their succour can no more avail you." 3 A few 
 years later (405 B.C.), the Carthaginians, already victorious over 
 Selinus, Himera, and Agrigentum, advanced against Gela and 
 Camarina. Dionysius, who had become tyrant of Syracuse, 
 failed to relieve Gela. The inhabitants of Camarina, like those 
 of Gela, were forced to abandon their city; and when the 
 conclusion of peace between Dionysius and the invaders 
 allowed them to return, they returned as tributaries of Car- 
 thage. 4 The protection of Syracuse, in which Camarina had 
 
 1 vi. 33. 2 ii. 65. 
 
 3 vi. 86, ty el rep virbiTTtp 7) AwpaKrov edffere aire\9fiv T) /ecu cr^aXeurcw, tri 
 fiovXyaeffde /ecu iroXXoarbv fj.6pt.oi> avrTjs ISeiv, Sre ov5v ZTI irtpavel irapayevbfjifvov 
 vtuv. (For en thus used in menace or presage, cf. Soph. El. 471. In Aesch. 
 Earn. 812, Shilleto conjectured v/j,fis 5' tr' [for es] &\\6<f>v\ov eXOovcrai \P6va. \ yi,s 
 d' fpaff6rifffff0f.) * Diod. xiii. 108-114; Xen. ffellen. ii. 3. 
 
 T
 
 290 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 trusted, proved a broken reed. Thucydides must have been at 
 work on his History for some years after the end of the Pelo- 
 ponnesian war, perhaps as late as 396 B.C. 1 When he put that 
 emphatic menace into the mouth of Euphemus, the fate which 
 actually overtook Camarina soon afterwards was surely present 
 to his mind. 
 
 (II.) 5. The Corinthian speaker at Sparta in 432 B.C. alludes 
 to the establishment of a fort in Attica as one of the possibili- 
 ties of the war; 2 and Pericles, in the parallel passage of his 
 first speech, admits that the construction of a hostile fort might 
 do harm by facilitating raids and by tempting slaves to desert. 3 
 
 6. Alcibiades, speaking at Sparta in 415 B.C., urges the 
 occupation of Deceleia. " It will benefit you," he says, " and 
 will embarrass the enemy in many ways. I will briefly notice 
 the chief of these. Most of the property in the country will 
 become yours by capture or surrender. The Athenians will 
 forthwith lose their revenues from the silver mines of Laurium, 
 and all their present gains from the land and the law-courts. 
 Above all, they will suffer by the irregular transmission of 
 tribute from their allies, who, when satisfied that you are 
 making war in earnest, will slight their demands." 4 These 
 predictions accurately correspond with the effects of the occu- 
 pation as afterwards described in the historian's own words. 6 
 The temporary presence of the invading enemy had not hitherto 
 hindered the Athenians from reaping the fruits of the soil ; but 
 now " they were deprived of their whole land " including, of 
 course, the mines at Laurium. " More than twenty thousand 
 slaves had deserted to the enemy." All their sheep and oxen 
 
 1 Thucydides mentions an eruption of Aetna in 426 B. c. as the third on record 
 (iii. 116) implying ignorance of that in 396 B.C., noticed by Diodorus, xiv. 59. 
 On the probability that Thucydides was at work on his History for at least 
 some years after 403, cp. Classen, Eiril. xxx. I cannot, however, accept Ullrich's 
 ingenious suggestion that the reference to Antiphon dpicrra T&V fj-fxpi ffJ-ov 
 6a.va.Tov diKrjv a.Tro\oyr)<ra.nevos (viii. 68) points to a tacit comparison with the 
 defence of Socrates (399 B.C.). 
 
 2 Thuc. i. 122 1. 3 i. 142 2. 
 
 4 vi. 91 7. In the sentence, ols . . . TJ %uy>a KaTeffKevaarai, TO. TroXXa 7rp6s v/j,8.s 
 TO. fi.tv \7]<t>6tt>Ta, ra d' avr^fj-a-TO. ^et, the word avr6fjLara, as commentators have 
 seen, refers to the desertion of slaves, included in the KaraffKevat as household 
 chattels or "live stock." 
 
 6 vii. 27-28. On the avTo/j.o\iai of slaves, cf. viii. 40.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF TIIUCYDIDES. 291 
 
 were lost. The whole number of adult male citizens was 
 required for military duty on the walls or in the field, a neces- 
 sity which would suspend the sitting of the law-courts and, as 
 Alcibiades foretold, close that source of profit. 1 The expenses 
 of the State were heavily increased, its revenues were perishing. 
 Alcibiades might easily have foreseen the importance of occu- 
 pying Deceleia. But the minute correspondence between the 
 special results which he is made to predict and those which 
 Thucydides relates in his own person indicates that the pro- 
 phecy followed the event. 
 
 (III.) 7. The Athenian speaker at Sparta in 432 B.C. says to 
 the Spartans : " If you were to overthrow our empire and estab- 
 lish your own, you would soon alienate the good- will which you 
 have gained because we are feared, if you are to continue the 
 policy of which you gave a specimen during your brief leader- 
 ship of Greece against Persia. The usages of your community 
 preclude intercourse with others, and moreover a Spartan 
 citizen on foreign service observes these usages as little as those 
 of Hellas at large." 2 There is a manifest reference here to the 
 period after the close of the war, when the Spartan promises of 
 " liberating Greece " were falsified. And the reference to the 
 misconduct of tha Spartan citizen abroad was certainly not 
 suggested by the case of Pausanias alone. The war had fur- 
 nished two signal instances. Gylippus had been convicted by 
 the Ephors of appropriating part of the treasure taken after the 
 capture of Athens. 3 Lysander the first Greek who received 
 divine honours from Greeks had surpassed the arrogance of 
 Pausanias. 4 
 
 1 The reference of Alcibiades in the words 8<ra . . . fab TWV 
 vw u<pf\ovi>Tcu is to the income which the State derived from court-fees of 
 various kinds, especially the deposits (irpvravfia) made by parties to a law-suit, 
 as well as from pecuniary fines, confiscations, etc. Bockh (Publ. Econ. i. 
 461) understands the passage thus, following the scholiast. Meineke (Hermes 
 iii. 359) and Madvig (Adv. i. 328) conjecture deKarfvrrjpiuv, "places where 
 public tithes and taxes were taken" objecting, as against the vulgate, that 
 it does not appear why even a virtual state of siege should suspend the sitting 
 of the law-courts. Thucydides, vii. 28 2, gives the plain answer all the 
 citizens were required for military duty. 
 
 1 Thuc. i. 77 6. 
 
 * Plut. Lys. 16-17, Nic. 28, cf. Diod. xiii. 106. 
 
 4 With Plut. Lys. 18 cf. Paus. vi. 3 14-15, Athen. xv. 696.
 
 292 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 8. The striking speech of Brasidas to the Acanthians (424 
 B.C.) deserves to be considered in this connection. It is 
 throughout an emphatic assertion that the cause in which 
 Sparta fights is the cause of Greek liberty. " I have not come," 
 he says, "to support a party. I do not consider that I 
 should be bringing you freedom in any real sense if I should 
 disregard your constitution, and enslave the many to the few, 
 or the few to the many. Such freedom would be harder than 
 a foreign yoke : and we, the Lacedaemonians, should reap no 
 thanks for our pains, but rather blame instead of honour and 
 renown." 1 Now. what Brasidas protests that Sparta will not 
 do, is precisely what Sparta actually did at the end of the war, 
 with the result which he anticipates. Oligarchies of the 
 narrowest type boards of ten were established by Lysander 
 in most of the cities, with a Spartan governor and garrison in 
 each to repress the popular party. 2 The many were literally 
 enslaved to the few, and they found the freedom which Sparta 
 had given them harder indeed than any foreign rule. It can 
 scarcely be doubted that this speech of Brasidas composed by 
 Thucydides after the close of the war was inserted by him 
 here, just at the moment when Sparta was making the first 
 advances to the democratic cities of Northern Greece, for the 
 purpose of bringing out the glaring contrast between Spartan 
 promise and Spartan performance. 
 
 9. In the conference between the Athenian and Melian 
 negotiators, the Athenians remark that, in the event of Athens 
 being vanquished, they would have less to fear from the 
 vengeance of Sparta than from the vindictiveness of smaller 
 States. 3 The reference here is unmistakable. After the sur- 
 render of Athens in 404 B.C., a congress was held at Sparta 
 
 1 Thuc. iv. 86 3. In 4 there is no doubt to my mind that ovd' &v 
 [for oi>5 affa<j>ri\ is the right reading, &v eirifapeiv being the oblique of 
 
 2 See Isocr. Panegyricus, 110-114, where he denounces the partisans of 
 the narrow Lacedaemonian oligarchies in the several States ol ruv deKapxiuv 
 KOLvuvriffavres and speaks of the miseries which they inflicted on their own 
 cities by "choosing to be enslaved to a Helot" (i.e. to the /j.66a Lysander : 
 Tjpovvro 5 TU>V EiXi^rwv evi dov\veiv). The passage is a striking commentary 
 on the Acanthian speech of Brasidas. 
 
 3 Thuc. v. 91.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF TIIUCYDIDES. 293 
 
 in which the destruction of the defeated city was advocated, 
 according to Xenophon, " by the Corinthians and Thebans 
 chiefly, but by many other Greeks too." It was by the Spartan 
 vote that Athens was saved. 1 
 
 The effect of such touches as these suggested by a know- 
 
 OO v 
 
 ledge of occurrences subsequent to the dramatic date may be 
 compared with that produced in a Greek tragedy when one of 
 the persons unconsciously utters a word or phrase which fore- 
 shadows the catastrophe. The spectator who knows the destined 
 end of the drama is affected in the same manner as the reader 
 who knows the sequel of the history. In using such touches, 
 however, Thucydides was probably thinking more of logical 
 than of artistic effect. His mind, with its strong concentration, 
 grasped the whole series of arguments or illustrations which 
 the experience of the war could yield ; and he brought the 
 most forcible of these to bear on his point without caring 
 whether the facts which suggested them were earlier or later 
 than the supposed date. 
 
 7. It has already been remarked that the addresses of 
 leaders to their troops may be considered as forming a class 
 apart from the rest. These military harangues, of which there 
 are twelve in all, are usually short. The object is always the 
 same to bring out vividly the essential points of a strategical 
 situation ; and the historian has been less uniformly attentive 
 here to the details of dramatic probability. 2 A modern writer 
 
 1 Xen. Helkn. ii. 2, 19-20. 
 
 2 Thus (1) the harangue is sometimes ascribed to several leaders collec- 
 tively ; e.g. vii. 65, TrapeKe\e6<ravro eKeivois ol re ffrparyyol Kal Fv\nnros Kal 
 e\eav roidde. So ii. 86, 6 Kvrj/j.os Kal 6 Bpavldas Kal oi a\\oi. r&v Hf\OTroi>vT]fflwv 
 ffrparrjyoi . . irapeKe\ev<ravro Kal eXfi-av roidde. In the case of the political 
 speeches, the only similar instance is when a single speech is given as made 
 by the two spokesmen of the Plataeans (irpord^avres ff<j>uv avrwv 'Acrrvfj.axoi' 
 re . . Kal AdKuva). It is obviously a different case when a speech is assigned 
 to envoys collectively (i. 32, ol KepKvpaTot. t\eav roidde, etc.), when one would 
 speak for the rest. (2) The military harangue is sometimes introduced in 
 words which imply that it was made several times over ; thus iv. 91 
 (Pagondas), irpoaKa\(av e/cCurrouj Kara \6xovs, SITUS pi) aOpboi eK\irroie rd 6ir\a, 
 t-n-eiGe . . \eywv roidde. Cf. vi. 68 (Nicias), Kara re eOvr) irnrapiui>> Ka<rra Kal 
 $v/jura<n roidSe irapeKe\evero. (Cf. eiwrapiwv ro ffrparoireSov TrapeKfXevero, iv. 94. ) 
 In vii. 76 Nicias eiriirapiuv iQdpawe re Kal irapefj.v6elro, /So?? re Xf&iur* eri. 
 
 e/cclo-Tots /ca0' ot)s ylyvot.ro, Kal /foi/X^eros w eirl wXeiffrov yeyuviffKuv
 
 THE SPEECHES OF TIIUCYDIDES. 
 
 would have attained the object by comments prefixed or added 
 to his narrative of the operations. Thus Archidamus, address- 
 ing the Peloponnesian officers before the first invasion of Attica, 
 dwells on the certainty of the Athenians being stung into 
 giving battle when they see their lands ravaged. 1 This serves 
 to heighten the reader's sense of the provocation offered, and 
 of the difficulty which Pericles must have had in restraining hi? 
 fellow-citizens. 2 Sometimes the speech of the general on one 
 side is as distinctly a reply to the general on the other as if it 
 had been delivered in debate. The Peloponnesian captains, 
 exhorting their men before the action in the Corinthian Gulf, 
 tell them that, though naval skill is much, it cannot avail 
 against courage. 3 Phormio, exhorting the Athenian crews, 
 tells t lie in, as if in retort, that though courage is invaluable, 
 their decisive advantage is in their naval skill. 4 Pagondas, 
 before the battle of Delium, tells the Boeotians that they must 
 fight, even beyond their own border, for the safety of Boeotia, 
 and reminds them that their fathers secured it for a time by 
 defeating the Athenians at Coroneia. 5 Demosthenes tells the 
 Athenians that they must fight, even on Boeotian ground, to 
 protect Attica, and reminds them of the Athenian victory over 
 the Boeotians at Oenophyta. 6 The speech of Brasidas to his men 
 on his Illyrian expedition is intended to bring out the contrast 
 between Hellenic and barbarian warfare; 7 his speech at 
 Amphipolis serves to explain his tactics. 8 The harangue of 
 Nicias before the last sea-fight at Syracuse marks the peculiar 
 character of the action as " a land-battle on board ship " 
 (jre^ofMa^a. airb z/eaw), and at the same time sums up for the 
 reader the whole meaning of that supreme crisis, when, as 
 Mcias reminds the men about to embark, the fleet is all that 
 remains of Athens and her great name. 9 This, and the cor- 
 responding speech of Gylippus on the Syracusan side, 10 are in a 
 high degree powerful and pathetic ; so, above all, is the last 
 
 1 Thuc. ii. 11. 2 ii. 59 f. 3 ii. 87. 
 
 4 ii. 89. 6 iv. 92. 6 iv. 95. 
 
 7 iv. 126. 8 TJ)V eirlvoia.v typdurai, v. 9. 
 
 9 vii. 61-64, }] i/rroXoiTTOS iroXts /ecu rb /j.tya 8vo/J.a. TUV 'A^Tjj'wj'. 
 10 vii. 65.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 295 
 
 speech of Nicias before the retreat. 1 Nowhere else, perhaps, 
 has Tlmcydides given so free a scope to his own rhetorical 
 power ; yet even here it is strictly subordinated to his primary 
 purpose that of faithfully presenting the cardinal facts of the 
 situation as he conceived them. 
 
 8. The expression of character in the Thucydidean 
 speeches has the same kind of limitation which was generally 
 observed in Attic tragedy. It is rather typical than individual. 
 Tlmcydides seizes the broad and essential characteristics of the 
 speaker, and is content with marking these. We are some- 
 times reminded of the direct simplicity with which the epic or 
 tragic heroes introduce themselves : " I am Odysseus, the 
 marvel of men for all wiles, and my fame goes up to heaven." 
 " I am pious Aeneas, renowned above the stars." 2 "You voted 
 for war," says Pericles, " and now you are angry with me, a 
 man who deems himself second to none in discerning and 
 expounding the right course, a man devoted to his country and 
 proof against corruption." 3 These were salient points in the 
 public character of Pericles as conceived by the historian, 4 and 
 accordingly Pericles is made to say so. The fate of Nicias 
 seemed to Thucydides a signal example of unmerited misfor- 
 tune, since Nicias had been remarkable throughout life for the 
 practice of orthodox virtue. 5 And so, in his speech before the 
 retreat from Syracuse, Mcias says, " The tenor of my life has 
 been loyal to the gods, just and without offence among men." 6 
 
 1 vii. 76. The two last military speeches of Nicias take something of the 
 political character from the fact that, as he says in both, the army is now the 
 city : avdpes yap TnSXts a striking illustration of Sophocles, Oed. Tyr. 56. 
 
 2 Od. ix. 19 ; Aen. i. 379 ; cf. Soph. Oed. Tyr. 8, avrbs &5' t\ri\v6a, \ 6 ira<n 
 K\eivbs OlSiwovs KaXoti/J-fvos. 
 
 8 Thuc. ii. 60. 4 ii. 65. 
 
 6 vii. 86, iJKtcrra Si) 4ios 8>v ru>v ye fir' t/j.ov 'EXXi^wi/ & rovro dvffrvxtas 
 d<f>iK^ffdai, Sia ryv irdffav is dperyv vevofjuffpevriv ^TrirySevcnv : i.e. lit., his 
 whole course of life, regulated by law and tradition (vevop-itr^vy) in the 
 direction of virtue. The apery of Nicias was that which consists in fidelity 
 to the established observances of religion and to received notions of duty 
 as distinguished from the apery, less in conformity with popular concep- 
 tions, which Thucydides can still recognise in such a man as Antiphon 
 (viii. 68). 
 
 6 Thuc. vii. 77, iro\\a fdv es Oeovs v6fj.tfj.a SeSirirr)/mi, iro\\a Se es avOpuwovs 
 Siicaia Kal aveirtydova. As to the Letter of Nicias (vii. 11-15), its substantial
 
 296 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 In the debate at Athens on the Sicilian expedition Alcibiades 
 is introduced by a prefatory sketch of his position and character. 
 Thucydides notices his ambition, his magnificence, especially 
 in the matter of horses and chariots, the licence of his private 
 life, his insolence, his public efficiency, his personal unpopu- 
 larity. 1 Then Alcibiades speaks, and begins by saying in so 
 many words that he has a better right than others to high 
 command ; he boasts of having entered seven chariots at 
 Olympia ; he avows that he does not regard his fellow-citizens 
 as his equals ; he asks whether his personal unpopularity inter- 
 feres with his administrative capacity. 2 The speech is merely 
 the sketch developed. It is the character of Alcibiades, as 
 Thucydides saw its salient points, condensed in a dramatic 
 form ; but it is not such a speech as Alcibiades could conceiv- 
 ably have made on this occasion, or indeed on any. Thucy- 
 dides has given us distinct portraits of the chief actors in the 
 Peloponnesian war, but these portraits are to be found in the 
 clearly narrated actions of the men; the words ascribed to 
 them rarely do more than mark the stronger lines of character ; 
 they seldom reveal new traits of a subtler kind. The tendency 
 of Thucydides was less to analyse individual character than to 
 study human nature in its general or typical phenomena. His 
 observation was directed, first, towards motives and passions 
 which may be considered, in regard to practical politics, as 
 universal influences : 3 next, towards the collective attributes 
 which distinguish whole communities from each other. Thus 
 the normal Spartan character is exhibited in its merits and its 
 defects. 4 The political character of the Athenians is arraigned 
 and defended ; 5 their intellectual character is illustrated in its 
 strength and its weakness. 6 And Thucydides shows a desire 
 to comprehend these conceptions of national character in for- 
 mulas, which he gives as epigrams to his speakers. The 
 
 genuineness might perhaps be argued from the fact that, while it dwells on 
 the wear and tear of the armament, there is no attempt to excuse his own 
 delay and his failure to prepare for the coming of Gylippus ; but the manner 
 of its introduction (drjXovffav roidde) seems to indicate the composition of 
 Thucydides. 
 
 1 vi. 15. 2 vi. 16. 
 
 3 iii. 82 2, yiyvb/j.ei>a /J.tv Kcd del e<r6fj.fva. e'ws &v ij avrij <pvcris TUV avQpwiruv y. 
 
 4 i. 68-72. 80-85. 5 i. 68-72, 73-78. 6 ii. 37 f. : iii. 37-40. '
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 297 
 
 Spartan disposition, says an Athenian, might be described as 
 one which regards everything that is pleasant as honourable, 
 and everything that is expedient as just. 1 The Athenians, says 
 a Corinthian, are, in brief, men who will neither rest nor allow 
 others to rest. 2 Athens, says Pericles, might be described as 
 the school of Greece, and the Athenian nature as the most 
 gracefully versatile in the world. 3 
 
 9. Those cases in which Thucydides gives merely a brief 
 summary 4 of a speech or debate suggest how slight the mate- 
 rials may often have been which he worked up in the oratorical 
 form. The political or ethical reflections with which the 
 meagre outlines were filled up were doubtless supplied in 
 large measure by Thucydides himself. The speeches, taken 
 altogether, are pervaded by certain general conceptions, ex- 
 pressed in formulas more or less constant, which indicate 
 unity of authorship. But it cannot be said, in the same 
 sense, that they bear the stamp of one mind. They do, 
 indeed, suggest certain intellectual habits, but it is seldom 
 possible to distinguish between opinions or modes of thought 
 which were in the air, and such as may have been proper 
 to Thucydides. Nor would much be gained if we could. 
 The real interest of the speeches in this aspect is something 
 more than biographical ; it is their interest as a contribution to 
 the intellectual history of a transitional period in an age of 
 singular mental energy. The age of faith was passing by, and a 
 rational basis for ethics which were then included in politics 
 was only in process of being sought. Thucydides is here the 
 representative of a time which, for the most part, could no 
 longer believe with Herodotus, but which had not yet learned 
 
 1 v. 105. 2 i. 70. 
 
 3 ii. 41. I regard the Melian dialogue as neither less nor more historical 
 than those speeches in which Thucydides had to rely on a slight knowledge 
 of the &fj.Tra.ffa yvw/j.-r). I cannot suppose, with Classen, that Thucydides had 
 any written documents to go upon. The frankness of the Athenians, which 
 Grote finds startling, is Thucydidean : his wish to portray ruling motives is 
 stronger than his regard for dramatic nicety. 
 
 4 E.g. i. 72 (where the general lines of the discourse in 73-78 are indi- 
 cated) ; iv. 21 (the general sense of Cleon's answer to the Spartan envoys) ; 
 iv. 58 and vi. 32 (debates at Gela and Syracuse) ; viii. 53 (debate at Athens 
 in 411 B.C.), etc.
 
 298 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 to bring a Socratic method to bear on generalisations. He 
 appears so far as he is revealed at all as a thinker of intense 
 earnestness, with a firrn and subtle apprehension of his chosen 
 subject, alike in its widest bearings and in its minutest details ; 
 and of profound sensibility in regard to the larger practical 
 aspects, that is the political aspects, of human destiny. He has 
 neither a dogmatic religion nor a system of ethics. He cleaves 
 to positive fact ; his generalisations rarely involve a speculative 
 element, but are usually confined to registering the aggregate 
 results of observation upon human conduct in given circum- 
 stances. In the spirit of a sceptical age he makes his speakers 
 debate questions of political or personal morality to which no 
 definite answer is offered. In Plato's Gorgias Callicles distin- 
 guishes between "natural" and "conventional" justice, contend- 
 ing that " natural justice " entitles the strong to oppress the 
 weak, and that " conventional justice " is merely a device of the 
 weak for their own protection. 1 In the Republic Thrasymachus 
 defends a similar doctrine, namely, that "justice is another's 
 good and the interest of the stronger, and that injustice is a 
 man's own profit and interest, though injurious to the weaker." - 
 The sophist Hippias, in Xenophon's Memorabilia, argues in a 
 like strain that justice and law are merely arbitrary and con- 
 ventional. 3 This, no doubt, was one of the commonplaces of 
 sophistical dialectic in the time of Thucydides. The Athenian 
 speakers in his History defend the aggressive policy of Athens 
 by arguments which rest on substantially the same basis as 
 those of the Platonic Callicles and Thrasymachus. 4 But the 
 historian is content to state their case from their own point of 
 view ; he does not challenge the doctrine as the Platonic 
 Socrates does by comments of his own. The victims of 
 aggression, indeed, the Plataeans or Melians, appeal to a higher 
 justice than the right of might, and Thucydides hints that his 
 sympathies are with them ; 5 but that is all. The abstention is 
 characteristic. On the whole, it may be said that he evinces a 
 
 1 Plato, Gorgias, p. 482, c. 38. 2 Rep. p. 367 c. 
 
 8 Xen. Mem. iv. 4. 14. * Thuc. v. 105 ; vi. 82-87. 
 
 5 Not expressly, but by the naked repulsiveness in which he exhibits the 
 ' ' right of might. "
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 299 
 
 personal liking for moral nobleness, 1 but refrains from deliver- 
 ing moral judgments, 2 as if these would imply laws which he 
 was not prepared to affirm or deny. But he insists on dis- 
 covering a rational basis for action. If a man or a State pursues 
 a certain line of policy, there must be some intelligible reasons, 
 he feels, which can be urged for it. This desire to enter into 
 the mind of the actors to find the motive behind the deed, 
 and to state it with all possible logical force is the mainspring 
 of the oratory in Thucydides, in so far as this is his own 
 creation. It is an element of dramatic vividness ; sometimes 
 also of dramatic untruth, when the reasonings supplied by the 
 historian to his actors are subtler than would probably have 
 occurred to the speakers or commended themselves to the 
 hearers. Thucydides is a philosophical historian, in the sense 
 that he wishes to record the exact truth, in a form which 
 may be serviceable for the political instruction of mankind. 
 But he has not, in the sense of Plato or Aristotle, a theory of 
 ethics or politics. Thucydides groups the observed facts of 
 practical politics, but without attempting to analyse their 
 ultimate laws. It might be possible to piece together Thucy- 
 didean texts and, by filling up a few gaps, to form a tolerably 
 coherent system of doctrine ; but the process would be artificial 
 and delusive. Possibly a Shakespeare might re-create Thucy- 
 dides from the fragments of his personal thought, but the breath 
 of life would be the poet's gift; the broken lights are all 
 that really remain. The paradoxes of one age are said to 
 be the truisms of the next, but the violent contrast sug- 
 gested by the epigram is hardly the important point to seize 
 if we desire to trace the growth of opinion. There was a 
 moment when the so-called paradoxes were neither paradoxes 
 nor as yet truisms, but only rather new and intelligent opinions, 
 seen to be such against the foil of notions which were de- 
 
 1 As Professor Sellar says (" Characteristics of Thucydides," Oxford Essays, 
 1857): "His own feeling shines out in such expressions as this, 'Simple- 
 mindedness, which is mostly an ingredient in noble natures ' (iii. 83). The 
 speeches attributed to Pericles are especially expressive of generous ideas of 
 man." 
 
 2 It is enough to instance the manner in which he relates without comment 
 the treachery of Paches to Hippias (iii. 54), and the assassination of two 
 thousand Helots by the Spartans (iv. 80).
 
 300 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 caying, but had not quite gone out. For instance, when 
 Tlmcydides makes his speakers say, as he so often does, that 
 the future is uncertain, 1 we do more justice to the originality 
 of the remark if we remember that in the time of Thucydides 
 there were those who thought that the future was very fre- 
 quently indicated, at great moments, by signs from the gods. 
 Herodotus, for example, would have disputed the statement 
 that the future is uncertain, if it had been placed before him as 
 an unlimited proposition covering such crises as the Pelopon- 
 nesian war. 2 The same consideration applies to many of the 
 political or moral aphorisms, which may be regarded as those 
 of Thucydides himself. They are in silent controversy with 
 some unexpressed dissidence of contemporaries. The principle 
 of tacit contrast pervades the whole History, as in the Funeral 
 Oration the picture of Athens requires to be supplemented by 
 a mental picture of the Sparta to which it is opposed. 3 This 
 was of the inmost nature of Thucydides : the reluctance " to 
 speak at superfluous length" 4 was deep in him. His general 
 views must be measured both by the credulity and by the 
 higher scepticism of a naive age; so gauged, they are never 
 commonplaces, but, at the least, hints for a part of the history 
 which he has not told in words, because he did not distinctly 
 conceive that it could ever need to be told. "Fortune," 
 Tvxy, is the name by which he usually designates the in- 
 calculable element in human life ; but this " fortune " is no 
 blind chance; it is, as he once explains it, "the fortune given 
 by heaven " (rj rv^n e '* TOV Oelov), the inscrutable dispensation 
 of a divine Providence. 5 The course of this fortune not only 
 baffles prediction, but is sometimes directly opposed to the 
 reasonable beliefs of men concerning the source which dispenses 
 it. Thrice only in the long tragedy of the war, as Thucydides 
 unfolds it, do men appeal expressly to the gods, invoking the 
 
 1 E.g. iv. 62, rb aaraQ^-rfrov rov fj.tX\oi>Tos ws firl TrXeiarov Kparei : vi. 9, wepi 
 T&V d<f>avuv /cat fj,f\\6vTuv KivSvvtveiv : ii. 42, TO dfiaves TOV Karo/>0u>yuaTos : ii. 87, 
 voft.iffa.1 TCUS TIJXO.IS evS^xecr&u ff<pd\\firdai rous dvdpuwovs, etc. 
 
 2 See e.g. Her. i. 45, 6eu>i> rty yu.ot . . . Trpoeffrifiaive ra yaeXXovra ZcreffOai : vi. 
 37, <f>i\tfi 54 KWS Trpoa-nfjialveiv 6 0e6s, K.T.\. On the omens, prodigies, dreams, 
 etc., in Herodotus, see Mure, Bk. iv. ch. 6, 3, and Rawlinson, i. 71 f. 
 
 3 Esp. ii. 37 and 39. 
 
 4 fj.aKpijyope'iv : i. 68, ii. 36, iv. 59. 5 v. 104.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF 7HUCYDWES. 
 
 name of religion, in their agony, against tyrannous strength ; 
 thrice the power behind the veil is deaf, thrice the hand of the 
 avenger is withheld, and the miserable suppliant is struck 
 down by the secure malignity of man. The Plataeans appeal to 
 the altars which had witnessed the consecration of Greek 
 liberty, 1 and the Spartans kill them in cold blood. The 
 Melians are confident against the Athenians as the righteous 
 against the unjust ; 2 their city is sacked, their men are slain, 
 their women and children enslaved. Nicias, after the great 
 defeat at Syracuse, believes that the jealousy of the gods must 
 now be exhausted, and has a firm hope, based on a good life, 
 for himself and his followers ; 3 but the wretched remnant of 
 his defeated army are in great part butchered as they slake 
 their thirst with the bloody water of the Assinarus ; he himself 
 is put to death lest he should tell tales under torture, and the 
 survivors pass into a horrible slavery. Thucydides feels that 
 the ways of Heaven are hard to understand, but he does not 
 complain of them ; they are matters not for reasoning but for 
 resignation. 4 He regards the fear of the gods as a potent check 
 on the bad impulses of men, and notices the loss of this fear 5 
 as a grave symptom of moral anarchy. As to omens, oracles, 
 and similar modes of seeking miraculous light or aid, he no- 
 where denies the possibility of such light or aid being occasion- 
 ally given, though his contempt is excited by the frequency of 
 imposture; 6 this, however, he would affirm that such re- 
 sources are not to be tried until all resources within human 
 control have been tried in vain. 7 There is one way only, 
 Thucydides holds, by which man can certainly influence his 
 own destiny, and that is by bringing an intelligent judgment 
 (7i/ft)//,77) to bear on facts. Some have traced the influence of 
 Anaxagoras in the prominence which Thucydides gives to the 
 intellectual principle ; but no such prompting was needed 
 by a strong understanding of sceptical bent, and it may 
 
 1 iii. 59 2. 2 v. 104, Scrioi irpfc ov 
 
 8 vii. 77 4, iced rifJ-Ss Vos vvv rd re dirb TOV 0eov tXirlfeiv fjiriurepa. e 
 otKTOv yap air' avrwv ditarepoi ijSr) eff/J^v 1) <f>66vov. 
 
 4 ii. 64, cptpfiv re XP^I Ta T ai/j.6via dvayicalus rd re dtrb rCiv jroXf/j.i 
 dvSpdus. s ii. 53 ; iii. 82. 
 
 6 E.g. ii. 21 ; v. 26, 103 ; vii. 50 (of Nicias), ty KOJ. ayav tfetcw/tty re /cat 
 .evos. 7 v. 103.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 be observed that Thucydides has at least not adopted the 
 language of Anaxagoras. 1 It is the peculiar merit of the 
 Athenian character, as portrayed in Thucydides, to recog- 
 nise intelligence as the true basis of action and the true root 
 of courage, 2 instead of regarding mental culture as adverse 
 to civic loyalty and warlike spirit. 3 If soothsayers cannot give 
 us prescience, reason well used can enable such a man as 
 Themistocles at least to conjecture the future. 4 In a trial of 
 human forces the chances baffle prediction, but superiority in 
 ideas (Sidvoiat) is a sure ground of confidence. 5 Yet the man 
 of sound judgment will not presume on this confidence, for he 
 will remember that the other element, " fortune," is beyond his 
 control. 6 Justice, rightly understood, is the "common good," 7 
 and is identical with true self-interest. 8 As the remorseless 
 exaction of an extreme penalty, "justice" may be opposed to 
 " equity ;" 9 or as a moral standard, it may be opposed to " self- 
 interest" in the lower sense. 10 And self-interest, when thus 
 opposed to justice, can appeal to "the immemorial usage," 11 
 believed to obtain among the gods, and so certainly established 
 among men that it may plausibly be called a sort of natural 
 necessity, 12 that the stronger shall rule the weaker. No 
 speaker in Thucydides goes quite so far as Callicles in the 
 Gorgias, or proclaims this to be " natural " as distinguished 
 from "conventional" justice. It is not said to be just, but 
 only natural and not unreasonable. 13 The argument against 
 capital punishment, which is put into the mouth of Diodotus, 
 rests on the observation that no restraints have yet been 
 devised which can be trusted to keep human passions in check. 
 
 1 vous, in Thucydides, occurs only in the phrases ev v$ ?x iv (* intend), rbv 
 vow Hx eiV "7>os TI, or Trpoo^xeti', and Kara, vow, "to one's mind." The general 
 term for the power of the intellect is yvw^rj, with which didvoia and ffwe<ris 
 are sometimes nearly synonymous. 
 
 2 ii. 40 2 ; 62, 5. 
 
 3 As Archidamus does (i. 84), and Cleon (iii. 37). 
 
 4 i. 138, TWV fj,e\\6vT(av eiri TrXeiffTov rov yevqaof^lvov &PL&TOS et/cacrr^y. 
 5 i. 843; vi. 11 6. 6 iv. 64. 
 
 7 TO Kowbv ayaebv, v. 90. 8 i. 41. 9 iii. 40; iv. 19. 
 
 10 i. 76, 79 ; iii. 56 ; v. 90 ; iv. 61. n i. 76, rb del Ka0e<rr6s. 
 
 12 v. 105, i]yovfj,e0a yap TO re Oelov SJ^TJ TO u.i'0puwei.6v re cracpuis dia iravrbs 
 virb <pvfffus dvayKaias, 06 av KpaTy, apxeiv. Cf. iv. 61, vi. 87. 
 
 13 vi. 85, ovStv &\oyov OTI. Kal
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 303 
 
 Legislators have gone through the whole list of possible penal- 
 ties, and even the prospect of death is found insufficient to 
 deter those who are goaded by want or ambition, and tempted 
 by opportunity. 1 The friendship of men and of communities 
 must be founded in the first place 011 a persuasion of mutual 
 benevolence, and on some congeniality of character; 2 but in 
 the long-run the only sure bond between States is identity of 
 interests. 3 The Peloponnesian league is loose just because the 
 interests diverge. 4 In default of a common interest, the only 
 guarantee for an alliance is balanced fear. 5 Similarly, in the 
 relation of the citizen to the State, patriotism is enforced by 
 the dependence of private on public welfare. 6 Pericles even 
 says that no fair or just legislation can be expected from 
 citizens who have not such a stake in the country as is repre- 
 sented by the lives of children. 7 The distinctive merits of an 
 oligarchy always provided that it is constitutional, and not of 
 the narrow type which Thucydides calls a "dynasty" 8 are 
 fairly recognised in the History. Archidamus and Brasidas 
 claim stability, moderation and disciplined loyalty for the 
 Spartan State. 9 A true democracy is pictured as one in which 
 three elements work together for the common good : the rich 
 are the guardians of property, the able men offer counsel, 
 and the mass of the citizens decide on the opinions laid before 
 them. 10 Democracy was the form of government under which 
 Athens had been greatest and most free r 11 and the best phase of 
 the Athenian democracy in his recollection, Thucydides says, 
 was just after the Revolution of the Four Hundred, since then 
 the oligarchic and popular elements were judiciously tempered. 12 
 Destiny may alter the part which a State is called upon to 
 perform, and its institutions may require to be modified 
 accordingly. Thus the Corinthians say to the Spartans, " Your 
 
 I iii. 45 3. 2 iii. 10. 8 i. 124. 4 i. 141. 
 8 rb avriiraXov 5<?oj, iii. 11 ; cf. iv. 92. 6 ii. 60. 7 ii. 44. 
 
 8 The Swaurreia (01) perk i>6(j.uv, unconstitutional) of Thebes in the Persian- 
 wars is opposed to the later 6\iyapxia iV<W/xoj, iii. 62. 
 
 9 i. 84 ; iv. 126 4. 
 
 10 vi. 39 (Hermocrates) ; cf. ii. 37 (Pericles). It is only Alcibiades (at 
 Sparta) who uses d-rj/jLOKparia in a narrow and bad sense, as a synonym for 
 a.Ko\acria ir\ri9ovs (vi. 89). 
 
 II vi. 89 6. ls viii. 97.
 
 3 o 4 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 system is out of date if you are to cope with Athens. In 
 politics, as in art, improvements must prevail. Fixed institu- 
 tions are best for a city at peace. But the call to manifold 
 enterprise imposes the need of manifold development. Hence 
 owing to their varied experience the Athenians have been 
 ' greater ' innovators than you." 1 The analogy suggested here 
 between politics and a progressive art 2 is the more significant 
 when it is remembered what the historian's age had seen 
 accomplished in sculpture, architecture and drama. It is also 
 worthy of remark that the only unqualified censures of demo- 
 cracy which occur in Thucydides, and the only protests against 
 change as such, are ascribed to the " violent " Cleon and the 
 " licentious " Alcibiades. 3 
 
 10. The choice of moments for the introduction of 
 speeches is not, with Thucydides, a matter of rhetorical caprice, 
 but has an intelligible relation to the general plan of his 
 work. A speech or debate reported in the direct form 
 always signalises a noteworthy point in the inner or mental 
 history of the war, as distinguished from the narrative of its 
 external facts : it announces thoughts and arguments which 
 exercised an important influence, and which therefore require 
 to be apprehended with the utmost possible distinctness. The 
 event which furnishes the occasion for inserting a speech need 
 not be of first-rate importance in itself, if only it is typical of 
 its kind, and therefore suitable for the dramatic exhibition of 
 reasonings which applied to several similar cases. The destruc- 
 tion of Plataea by Sparta was an impressive event; but its 
 effect on the general course of the war would scarcely have 
 warranted the amount of space devoted to the Plataean and 
 Theban pleadings, 4 if the occasion had not been a typical 
 illustration of Spartan and Theban policy. Such, again, is the 
 case of Mitylene, viewed as exemplifying the relation between 
 
 1 i. 71. 
 
 2 "Among early inquirers into the nature of human action the arts helped 
 to fill up the void of speculation." (Prof. Jowett, Introduction to Plato's 
 Republic. ) 
 
 3 iii. 37 3 ; vi. 18 7. Thucydides speaks of the 01) drj/j-oriKy irapavo/j-ta of 
 Alcibiades in vi. 28 ; cf. vi. 15, where the same term is applied to him as in 
 i. 132 to Pausanias. 
 
 4 iii. 53-59, 61-67.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 305 
 
 Athens and her subject allies ; and the dramatic form is given 
 accordingly, not merely to the Athenian debate on Mitylene, 
 but also to the appeal of the Mityleneans at Olympia. 1 The 
 speech of Brasidas at Acanthus is given in the direct form as 
 a specimen of his persuasive diplomacy in dealing with the 
 cities of the Chalcidic peninsula. 2 The rival overtures of 
 Athens and Syracuse to Camarina have a similarly represen- 
 tative character in relation to the wavering neutrality of the 
 Sicilian cities, and accordingly the direct form is given to the 
 arguments of Euphemus and of Hermocrates. 3 The absence of 
 speeches in the Eighth Book has been reckoned among the 
 proofs that this book had not received the author's last 
 touches. There can be no doubt that Thucydides was pre- 
 vented by death from completing or revising the Eighth 
 Book : 4 but if his general practice is considered, the argument 
 from the absence of speeches will appear questionable. 
 Much of the Eighth Book is occupied with negotiations, either 
 clandestine or indecisive, or both ; and in a period of similar 
 character which fills the greater part of the Eifth Book 
 Thucydides nowhere employs the dramatic form. 5 It cannot 
 surprise us that Thucydides has not given a dramatic emphasis 
 to the mere misrepresentations by which Alcibiades and Chal- 
 cideus prevailed on the Chians to revolt. 6 The Eevolution 
 
 1 iii. 9-14. 2 iv. 85-87. 3 v. 76-80 ; 82-86. 
 
 4 Classen examines the evidence in his Vorbemerkungen to Book viii. , with 
 these results : (1) Book viii. was left unrevised, owing to the author's death 
 while he was engaged upon it, and hence several inaccuracies of expression or 
 statement remain [cf. e.g. cc. 8 3-4 : the notice of the |3/>axa vav/j.axia in 
 c. 80, compared with c. 102 : c. 89 2 (T&V irdvv ffTparriywv, K.T.\.) : c. 90, 
 1, where ff<f>uv recurs four times in a few lines : c. 101 3, where the 
 geographical details are obscure]. (2) Such defects of the text were early 
 recognised, but for a long time no attempt was made to remedy them. (3) In 
 the Alexandrian or Roman age a recension of the whole History was made, of 
 which codex Vaticanus 126 is the representative. For Books i. vi. the cases 
 in which the codex Vaticanus alone has the true reading are not numerous : 
 in vii. they are more so : in viii. they are so frequent that here the Vati- 
 canus, as compared with all the other MSS., assumes the character of a 
 revised text. 
 
 8 Thuc. v. 14-83 (422-416 B.C.). In Book v. the direct form of speech 
 occurs only in the harangue of Brasidas (v. 9) and the Melian dialogue 
 (85-116). 
 
 6 viii. 14. 
 
 U
 
 ;o6 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 of the Four Hundred certainly afforded opportunities for 
 the insertion of speeches made in debate. But that Revolution 
 was primarily concerned with the form of the Athenian con- 
 stitution ; its special importance for the history of the war lay 
 in the use which Alcibiades was making of it to procure his 
 own recall. This is perhaps the only point in the extant part 
 of the Eighth Book at which the usual practice of Thucydides 
 would lead us to expect the dramatic emphasis ; and just here 
 it is found. Peisander brings his opponents to admit that the 
 case of Athens is desperate without the help of Persia. " This, 
 then," he says, "we cannot get, unless we adopt a more 
 temperate policy, and concentrate the administration in fewer 
 hands, so as to secure the confidence of the king, . . . and 
 recall Alcibiades, the only man living who can gain our end." * 
 In a revision of the book Thucydides would possibly have 
 worked up the speech of Peisander at greater length. 2 
 
 11. As regards the language of the speeches, Thucydides 
 plainly avows that it is chiefly or wholly his own. 3 The 
 dramatic truth, so far as it goes, is in the matter, not in the 
 form. He may sometimes indicate such broad characteristics 
 as the curt bluntness of the ephor Sthenelaidas 4 or the insolent 
 vehemence of Alcibiades. 5 But, as a rule, there is little dis- 
 crimination of style. In all that concerns expression, the 
 speeches are essentially the oratorical essays of the historian 
 himself. At the end of the war, when he composed or revised 
 them, the art of Ehetoric was thoroughly established at Athens. 
 The popular dialectic of the Sophists had been combined with 
 
 1 viii. 53. 
 
 a The absence of military harangues, too, in Book viii. is sufficiently 
 explained by the absence of any good occasion for them. The sea-fights at 
 Euboea (95) and Cyzicus were hardly such : and the narrative breaks off 
 before the more decisive actions of Cynossema and Aegospotami. The 
 question has been discussed lately in an essay, De Thucydidel Operis Libr! 
 viii. indole ac natura, by Paul Hell wig (Halle, 1876). 
 
 3 i. 22, where the d/c/n'/Jeia avrrj rCiv \'xfl^vruv is opposed to the v/j.Traffa 
 -yvdfjLT). 
 
 4 i. 86, TOI)S fiev X670i's TOI)S iroXXoik ruv ' A0Tjva.iii}i> oti yiyvdiffKU, K.T.\. 
 
 8 vi. 18 3, Ta/j.ieve<rOai es 8<rov /3oiA6/u,e6>a </>x e ' : 4, ffropeffw/j-evrb 
 (pobv-qua, etc. , where the scholiast remarks that this is the harshest (aK\r>p6TaToi') 
 or the metaphors in Thucydides, dXXd Kara 'A.\Kifii.<idr]v.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF TIIUCYDIDES. 307 
 
 lessons in the minute proprieties of language. Protagoras 
 taught correctness in grammatical forms, 1 Proclicus in the use 
 of synonyms. 2 The Sicilian Rhetoric had familiarised Athenian 
 speakers with principles of division and arrangement. 3 Gorgias, 
 with his brilliant gift of expression, 4 had for a while set the 
 fashion of strained antithesis and tawdry splendour. It might 
 have been expected from the character of his mind that Thucy- 
 dides would be keenly alive to what was hollow and false in 
 the new rhetoric. Several touches in the History show that 
 he was so. Citizens in grave debate are contrasted with men 
 who play audience to the empty displays of sophists. 5 A con- 
 tempt for rhetorical commonplace is frequently indicated. Thus 
 Pericles declines to dilate on the legendary glories of Athens 6 
 or on the advantages of patriotic fortitude, 7 and Hermocrates 
 begs to be excused from enlarging on the hardships of war 8 or 
 the blessings of peace. 9 On the technical side, however, Thucy- 
 dides shows the influence of the new art. This often appears in 
 his method of marshalling topics and in his organisation of the 
 more elaborate speeches. 10 It is seen still more clearly if his 
 style is compared with that of the orator Antiphon. The 
 extant work of Antiphou as a writer of speeches for the law- 
 
 fireia, Plat. Phaedr. 267 c. 
 
 2 6pd6rT]s 6vo/j.dTuv, Plat. Euthyd. p. 277 E. 
 
 3 The two things which the early Sicilian Rhetoric most sought to teach 
 were skill in marshalling facts and skill in arguing probabilities : cp. Attic 
 Orators, vol. i. p. cxviii f. 
 
 4 Cp. ib. i. cxxiii. Gorgias was not properly either a student of technical 
 rhetoric or a sophist. 
 
 5 Thuc. iii. 38 7. ffotptffrwv [the word only here in Thuc.] dearais {ombres 
 KaB-ri/n^vocs yU.SXXoj' $) irepi 7r6\ews j3ov\evo/j^vois. Of. 5, pera Kaiv6Ti)ros \6yov 
 airaraffdai dpiaroi. Thucydides thrice uses e7ri5eits, but only once in reference to 
 oratory, and then in a general, not in a technical sense (iii. 42). The regular 
 speakers in the Ecclesia are thrice spoken of as pijropes, and always in a more 
 or less unfavourable tone (iii. 40 ; vi. 29 ; viii. 1). 
 
 6 ii. 36. 7 ii. 43. 8 iv. 59. 
 
 9 iv. 62. Compare what Alcibiades says at Sparta in declining to dwell on 
 the evils of democracy dXXd wepl 6/jLd\oyovfji.tvr)s dvoias ov5v &v Kaivdv \tyoiro. 
 
 10 As in the Plataean and Theban speeches to the Spartan judges (iii. 53-59, 
 61-67), in the speeches of Hermocrates and Athenagoras to the Syracusan 
 assembly (vi. 33-34, 36-40), and in the Funeral Oration. We can recognise a 
 conscious partition, more or less complete, into wpooi/Mov, irp60e<rts (or irpoKara- 
 a-Kevrj), dirtyr)cris, irlffreis, tirl\oyos. Cp. Attic Orators, vol. i. pp. 36, 181 ; ii. 4^2.
 
 308 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 courts falls in the years 421-411 B.C. 1 The warmth of the 
 terms in which Thucydides describes him as " a master of device 
 and of expression," 5 a phrase identical with that which is 
 ascribed, as a definition of statesman-like ability, to Pericles 
 testifies at least to an intellectual sympathy. There is, how- 
 ever, no evidence for the ancient tradition that the historian 
 was the pupil of the orator. 3 Thucydides and Antiphon belong 
 to the same rhetorical school, and represent the same early stage 
 in the development of Attic prose. Both writers admit words 
 of an antique or a decidedly poetical cast. 4 Both delight in 
 verbal contrasts, pointed by insisting on the precise difference 
 between terms of similar import. 5 Both use metaphors rather 
 bolder than Greek prose easily tolerated in its riper age. 6 On 
 the other hand, there are three respects in which the composition 
 of Thucydides may be contrasted with that of Antiphon. First, 
 Thucydides has a pregnant brevity which would not have been 
 possible in such measure for a practical orator, since no ordinary 
 
 1 Of his extant works, Or. v., irepi rov'HpdiSov <povov, may be referred to about 
 417 B.C., and Or. vi., irepi rov xopevrov, to about 412 B.C. Cp. Attic Orators, 
 i. 34, 58, 63. 
 
 2 viii. 68, Kpdriffros kvQv^Qrfl'a.i . . . Kai a yvoirj elirelv. Cf. ii. 60, 6s ov5f>>bs 
 oto/juii rjfffftav elvat yv&val re TO. deovra Kal epfjMjvevffai ravra. 
 
 3 Caecilius of Calacte, in the Augustan age, conjectured that Thucydides had 
 been the pupil of Antiphon (Vitt. x. Oratt. ); Hermogenes (wepl IS. ii. 497) 
 notices the belief as current, but rejects it. It seems to have been a mere 
 guess, resting on resemblance of style. See Attic Orators, i. p. 4. 
 
 4 E.g. Antiphon : aArri^pios iroivf) irpoffrpbTraios evOvfiLos dffiraipti} (ii. 5. 5) 
 avOp&trivov <f>v\ov (iv. a. 2) ev8[a (ii. /J. 1) xwpo^tXeZi' (v. 78) <f>i\oOi>T7]s (ii. 
 /3. 12). Thucydides : irepiu-n-fj (=ffK<nrta, iv. 86) axOyduv (ii. 37) vavfidrr)? 
 (i. 121 ; cf. Pollux i. 95, rb vav^dras 6vo/j.dfi.v (rota VO.VTO.S) rpayiKwrepov tffO-f]- 
 (MTO. (iii. 58) effffa.fj.evuv (=idpvffafjLva}v, ib.) KfK/j.t]ures (iii. 59) Trepippvros 
 (iv. 64) <j>v\oicpiveiv (vi. 18) eirr}\vyd^fff&ai (vi. 36), and many more. 
 
 5 E.g. Antiphon: yvupiffrai SiKaffrai Sofaffral Kpiral (v. 94): the Trpd/cropes 
 TUIV aKovviuv distinguished from the atnoi TWV Tra.dTifji.dTwi> (ii. ft. 6) : ra Trap^.x't- 
 utva ffi]/j.eiois iriffTWffai,Td Se /uAAopTa TeKfj.ijplois (ap. Ammon. 127). Thucydides : 
 alrla Karriyopla (i. 68) : <f>p6vrifia Ka.Ta(f>p&i>ri/j.a ai?x 7 7A ta KaTa(f>p6vr]ffis (ii. 62) : 
 eTravdffT7]cra.v anreffrriffav (iii. 39) otf/c d^vverwrepov, KaLKO^iverwrepov 5e (vi. 76) : 
 KaroiKiffcu e^oiKiffai (ib.} Trapalveffts d^ltiiffis (i. 41) doKoiva <paivofj.^vr) (i. 32) 
 TrpofTri^ov\veiv avTeTTifioiiXfiieiv (i. 33) : SiKaffral . . . ffufipoviffrai (vi. 87). 
 
 6 E.g. Antiphon: TO. tx v V T ^ s biro^'ias eh rovrov (f^povra (ii. y. 10): larpovs rfjs 
 drux/as (ii. /3. 13); cf. i. y. 1 andii. /3. 10. Thucydides: ij eiriffT-f)^ eyyrjpdffeTat 
 (vi. 18) t'arpos rrjs 7r6\fwj (vi. 14) Soi'Aotrd (f>p6i>r]fj.a rb al<f>vLSiov (ii. 61) 7r6Xe/iios 
 Si'atos 8i5daKa\os (iii. 82) iriK\acr9ijvai (iii. 59), etc.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 309 
 
 hearer could have followed his meaning with full comprehen- 
 sion. 1 Secondly, Tlmcydides often departs not only from the 
 natural but from the rhetorical order of words, in order to throw 
 a stronger emphasis on the word which is the key-note to the 
 thought ; and in this again he is seen to be writing for readers, 
 not for hearers. 2 Thirdly, the strings of clauses, forming periods 
 of a somewhat loose and inartistic kind, are longer with Thu- 
 cydides than with Antiphon, and this because Thucydides is 
 striving to express ideas of a more complex nature. 3 The 
 originality and the striking interest of the historian's style con- 
 sists, in fact, in this, that we see a vigorous mind in the very 
 act of struggling to mould a language of magnificent but im- 
 mature capabilities. Sometimes the direction of the thought 
 changes in the moment that it is being uttered. 4 Then arise 
 obscurities which have their source in the intense effort of 
 Thucydides to be clear at each successive moment to say 
 exactly what he means at that moment. The strong conscious- 
 ness of logical coherence then makes him heedless of formal 
 coherence. The student of Thucydides has one consolation 
 which is not always present to the student of a difficult \vriter. 
 He knows that he is not engaged in the hopeless or thankless 
 
 1 This brevity appears (1) in such constructions as ywaiicelas operas, Seat. . . 
 ZaovTat. (ii. 45), or rCiv fj.kv dpxew T&V & Siavoelffdat. (sc. fipxew, i. 124) ; (2) in 
 the suppression of a clause which can be supplied mentally, as often before a 
 sentence introduced by ydp (cf. i. 120 ad init.) : (3) in the pregnant use of 
 words, as vi. 11, Strep r/yuas eicfapovffi (=eK<j>opovvTes \tyovat). Cic. de Oral. ii. 22, 
 sententiis magis abundat quam verbis . . . ; 13, ita verbis aptus et pressus 
 est, etc. Quint, x. 1, densus et brevis et semper sibi instans. Dionys., p. 792, 
 says that it belongs to Thucydides TTfipStirOai Si ^\axiffruv 6vo/j.drui> TrXelcrra 
 crrifj.aivfiv, and Marcellinus, 50, speaks of his davfj-aaral ppaxvmjres- 
 
 2 E.g. iii. 39, /J.erd rCiv 7roXe/ua>rdVw' tyuas ffrdvres 8ia<f>0eipa.t. : i. 33, yevfaerai 8t 
 . . KaXr; T) ZwTVxia, Kara TroXXot rrjs ^er^paj xp f l a * ' vi- 82, oOs Zvyyevels <pa.ffiv 
 
 6vras rjfj.as 2ii/Da/c6crioi 5e5ov\&ff6ai : v. 91, irl (rurrjpiq. vvv roi)s X6*youj tpov/j-ev rfjs 
 
 8 E.y. Such a sentence as that in Antiphon v. 21, r\ ^v 7rp6<f>a<ris fKartpy 
 diroOavdv ainbv rbv 'Hpwdyv, may be compared in general structure with Thuc. 
 vi. 82, i}/j.fis yap ' luwes 6i>res . . . 2upa/c6criot SedovX&ffOai, but the latter has 
 a much longer series of clauses. In Thucydides the transition from a simple 
 string of clauses to a period properly so called is commonly made by the inser- 
 tion of explanatory parentheses introduced with ydp. 
 
 4 E.g. vii. 42, rots 2vpaKov<rlou . . . /cordrX^fts lytvero . . . bpwvres, K.T.\. 
 Cp. iii. 36, vi. 24, iv. 108, etc.
 
 3 io THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 task of unravelling a mere rhetorical tangle. Every new light 
 on the thought is sure to be a new light on the words. 1 
 
 O O 
 
 12. The practice of introducing speeches was continued 
 through the whole series of Greek and Roman historians, and, 
 owing to its classical prestige, even maintained itself for a time 
 in modern literature. But it is curious to trace the process by 
 which it was gradually estranged from the spirit and signifi- 
 cance of its origin. For Xenophon, the idea of portraying 
 character in deed and in word was as natural as for Thucydides. 
 Herodotus, Thucydides, and Xenophon, with all their differ- 
 ences, alike belong to an age in which the historian draws 
 from life and for life, setting forth what has been done and 
 said, but rarely theorising or commenting. In the political life 
 which Thucydides and Xenophon represent, public speech 
 wielded the decisive force ; but while the main purpose of 
 Thucydides is political, that of Xenophon is rather ethical. 
 Xenophon. introduces direct speech or dialogue chiefly to 
 enforce the moral lessons of individual character. The collo- 
 quial tone prevails even in political debate, 2 and there is rarely 
 any attempt at condensed reasoning of the Thucydidean type. 
 In the course of the fourth century B.C. the school of Isocrates 
 developed a normal literary prose, and such writers as Ephorus 
 and Theopompus applied a rhetoric more florid than their 
 master's to the misplaced embellishment of history. 3 At the 
 same time the political life of Greece was decaying, and with it 
 
 1 Jelf (following Runner) rightly classes Thucydides with those writers 
 who, " engrossed with the subject, were overpowered by their now of thought, 
 and endeavouring to concentrate these notions in all their fulness in as few 
 words as possible, passed from thought to thought, without taking much 
 care that the several parts of the whole sentence should be connected 
 together with a strict grammatical accuracy." The constructions of Thucy- 
 dides, he adds, "in spite of, or perhaps because of, their grammatical inac- 
 curacy, have a power and depth of expression which perhaps no other prose 
 writer ever attained." (Greek Grammar, ii. 593.) Thucydides wishes his 
 thought to be what Aristotle requires in the period (Rhet. iii. 9) evatvoirrov. 
 Cp. Attic Orators, i. 35. 
 
 2 See e.g. the speeches of Critias and Theramenes in Xen. Hdlen. ii. 3. 
 This colloquial tone is one element of the quality in Xenophon which Quin- 
 tilian (x. 1) calls "iucunditas inaffectata. " 
 
 3 On the rhetorical historians of the Isocratic school, see Attic Orators 
 ii. 48 and 427.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDWES. 311 
 
 the instinct which in earlier days would have been offended by 
 the obtrusion of false ornament on a narrative of civic action. 
 Then came the age of the Alexandrian erudition, and history 
 was made a province of learned research. Polybius is a 
 learned historian with a theory, but he is also a practical 
 statesman and soldier. He is utterly opposed to the rhetorical 
 treatment of historical subjects. He expressly condemns the 
 sensational writers who confound the scope of history with 
 that of tragedy. Tragedy, he says, may stir the emotions by 
 any fiction which is not too improbable : the part of history is 
 to teach lessons of permanent worth " by means of real deeds 
 and words." l At the same time, he is keenly alive to the power 
 of oratory. He observes how a single weighty speaker may 
 turn the tide at a crisis, 2 and he apparently feels bound to 
 make some attempt at representing oratorical effect. When he 
 makes his persons speak, he does so much in the spirit of 
 Thucydides, though less elaborately: that is, he has some 
 definite points or arguments which he wishes to present in the 
 most vivid form at a critical moment. Like Thucydides, he 
 sometimes balances the harangues of generals on opposite 
 sides. 3 Sometimes he begins to give merely the purport of 
 what was said, and then passes from the oblique to direct 
 speech, 4 as Thucydides occasionally does. And it may be con- 
 cluded that, like Thucydides, he gave the " general sense " 
 faithfully whenever it could be ascertained. 5 But Polybius 
 stands alone in this respect among the historical writers after 
 Xenophon. In the period between Alexander and Augustus 
 the rhetorical school of history prevailed. Diodorus Siculus 
 
 1 Polyb. ii. 56 : ^ccei /j,ev yip (i.e. in Tragedy) Set dia r&v tn.9a.vwr6.ruiv 
 \6yii)v Kir\rjl;ou Kal \f/vxayuyf)(rai Kara rb irapbv rovs aKovovras, evOdSe 5e (in 
 History) 5ta rwv d\r}6u>u>v Hpyuv Kal \6yuv els rbv wdvra xp^ov SiSd^ai Kal irelffai 
 robs <t>i\ofj.adovvras. 
 
 2 Polyb. xi. 10 : oOrws els \6yos, evKalpus pyQels vir' dvdpbs d&oirlffrov, 
 
 ov fwvov airorpeirei r&v xeipl<rruv aXXa Kal irapop/jiq irpbs ra Kd\\icrra TOI/J 
 
 3 E.g. of Hannibal and Scipio, Polyb. iii. 108-111. 
 
 4 Polyb. xi. 28; xxii. 14. 
 
 6 See Polyb. xxx. 4 : fy 5' 6 vovs TTJS diroKplffeus roiovros, the ^fiiraffa yvdfjL-ri 
 of Thuc. i. 22.
 
 3 i2 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 and Dionysius of Halicarnassus 1 are both rhetoricians, the 
 rhetoric of Diodorus being combined with a quasi-philosophical 
 bent, and that of Dionysius with aesthetic criticism. Diodorus, 
 indeed, has some quaintly judicious remarks on the introduction 
 of long speeches into history. They interrupt the story, he 
 says, and distract the reader : writers who wish to show their 
 eloquence should do so somewhere else. A history should be 
 an organic whole; a speech which is inserted amiss cannot 
 have vital grace. 2 Still, speeches are sometimes desirable, 
 Diodorus adds, for the sake of variety (TTOIKIXIO). When 
 circumstances require that an envoy or senator should speak, 
 the historian must gallantly accompany his personages into 
 the arena of debate. 3 Diodorus appears to recognise, as he 
 certainly used, the free licence of invention. 4 His view is sub- 
 stantially that of Plutarch 5 and Lucian. 6 They demand that the 
 speech shall be appropriate to the speaker and to the occasion, 
 but the same conditions are equally binding on an epic poet. 
 Among the Eoman historians of the first rank, Livy is the one 
 who has made the largest use of this freedom. He once says, 
 in reference to a speech of Cato's, that, as the real text is ex- 
 tant in Cato's Origines, he will not give the reader a pale copy 
 
 1 I have purposely abstained from examining the criticisms of Dionysius on 
 the speeches in Thucydides, since he regards them exclusively from the point 
 of view of contemporary rhetoric, not at all from the historian's. His 
 criticisms on Thucydides are, for this very reason, immeasurably inferior to 
 those in his excellent essays on the orators. The lengthy speech of Veturia 
 to Coriolanus (Dionys. Ant. Bom. viii. 46-53) is a fair specimen of his own 
 practice in the rhetorical embellishment of history. 
 
 2 tffTtprjTai TTJS \j/vx<-Kijs x<fy" ros > Diod. xx. 2. 
 
 3 Diod. xx. 2, 6 yu.rj redappTiKbrus (nryKaTa^alvuv irpos TOI)S v rots \6-yois ayuvas 
 KCU avros VTrairios SLV etrj. 
 
 * Thus he says, ib., fj.eyd\uv Kal \afj.wpuv rQiv vTrod^aewv ovaCiv, ov irepio- 
 pa.rtov eXdrrova -rCiv tpywv cpavrjvai. rbv \6yov. 
 
 8 Plut., praecept. ger. Reipubl. 6, where he objects to long speeches before 
 battles as out of place. The speeches, often happily dramatic, in his own 
 biographies are the best comment on his remark (de glor. Athen. p. 346), rCiv 
 IffTopiKuv Kpdriffros 6 TTJC 5i.rfyi)cn.v uffirep ypa.<j>T)v irddeai Kal irpoffwirois ei'dwXo- 
 jroiijcras. 
 
 6 Lucian, de conscrib. hist. 58, ty St wore . . . Seiv6rr]Ta : "And if it should 
 ever be necessary to introduce a person speaking, first of all let the speech be 
 suitable to the person and the matter ; next let it be as clear as possible : 
 then, however, you are at liberty to declaim (prjTopevffai) and to show your 
 oratorical power."
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 of that rich eloquence. 1 It might have been inferred that Livy 
 was careful in his speeches to represent individual character 
 and manner. 2 But the inference is scarcely supported by the 
 extant portion of his work, though it is possible that his 
 portraits may have become more accurate in this respect as he 
 came to later times and ampler materials. The speeches are 
 sometimes of great power and beauty, but the rhetorical colour 
 is uniform, and there is sometimes an absolute disregard of 
 dramatic probability. 3 Sallust has higher merit in this de- 
 partment. The war of Jugurtha and the conspiracy of Catiline 
 were, w r hen Sallust wrote, events of recent memory, and each 
 had been illustrated by striking contrasts of character. Ac- 
 cording to Plutarch, the employment of shorthand writers 4 to 
 report debates in the Roman Senate began in G3 B.C. ; it was 
 certainly well established in the closing years of the Republic. 
 Sallust had some advantages for the presentation of character 
 in a manner at once dramatic and historical, and he seems to 
 have used them well. There is no reason to doubt that Caesar's 
 speech in the debate on the punishment of the conspirators 
 was substantially such as Sallust reports ; 5 and his way of 
 introducing a discourse of Memmius in the Jugurthine War 
 implies that it is true not only to the substance but to the 
 manner. 6 Tacitus uses the dramatic form more variously than 
 
 1 "Simulacrum viri copiosi," Liv. xlv. 25. 
 
 * As Quintilian says of Livy, "ita dicuntur omnia, cum rebus turn per- 
 sonis accommodata," x. 1. 
 
 * E.g. Liv. ii. 40 ; xxiii. 8, 9. Livy seems sometimes to have taken hints 
 from Polybius or Thucydides ; cp. xxx. 30 with Polyb. xv. 6, and vii. 30 with 
 Thuc. i. 32. 
 
 4 Plut. (Cat. min. 23) says that the speech of Cato in the debate on the con- 
 spiracy of Catiline is believed to be the only one of his preserved Cicero 
 having taught some of the most rapid writers the use of a shorthand (fftj^ela 
 trpodi5d!;avTos tv fUKpois Kal ppax^fft- TVTTOIS iro\\Cn> ypa.fj.fj.aTuv exovTa 5vvaiJ.iv), and 
 having distributed these writers through the Senate-house. For the Romans, 
 Plutarch adds, did not yet possess TOVS Ka\ov(j.tvovs a"r)fj.ei(rYpd<f>ovs : this was 
 the beginning of it. Suetonius mentions a speech of Julius Caesar which, 
 Augustus thought, must have been imperfectly taken down by the actuarii 
 (Caes. 55). The usual Roman word was notarius. Martial has an epigram on 
 a shorthand writer, xiv. 208. 
 
 8 Sallust, Catil. 51, 52. 
 
 6 Bellum Jugurth. 31 a striking illustration of the Roman feeling that 
 oratory, for its own sake, deserved a place in history.
 
 3i4 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 Sallust, but with a stricter historical conscience than Livy. 
 He resembles Tlmcydides and Polybius in never introducing a 
 speech merely for oratorical effect, but always for the purpose 
 of illustrating a political situation or character. 1 There is a 
 well-known instance the only one in ancient literature in 
 which the discourse given by the historian can be compared 
 with an official record of the discourse really delivered. In the 
 Eleventh Book of the Annals the Emperor Claudius addresses 
 the Senate in support of a proposal for imparting the Roman 
 franchise to the provincials of Gallia Comata. 2 The bronze 
 tablets found at Lyons in the sixteenth century, and now in the 
 Museum there, give what purports to be the real speech of 
 Claudius on this occasion. Tacitus and the tablets disagree 
 hopelessly in language and in nearly all the detail, but agree 
 in the general line of argument. 3 Knowing the antiquarian 
 turn of Claudius, Tacitus might easily have concluded that 
 the Emperor's speech would dwell largely on historical 
 precedents; but it seems more likely that he knew, from 
 oral or written report, the substance of what Claudius had 
 said, and worked up this in his own way. Here, then, 
 is a rough gauge of the approximation which might be 
 made to the truth by a historian who composed a speech 
 based on " the general sense of what was really said." 
 Thucydides and Polybius, Sallust and Tacitus, are widely 
 removed from writers who introduce harangues merely as 
 opportunities of display. 4 The latter tendency prevailed in 
 
 1 Ulrici, indeed (Charakteristik der antiken Historiographie, p. 148) regards 
 some of the speeches in Tacitus as inserted merely for dramatic ornament ; 
 e.g. Ann. i. 17, 22, 42, 43, 58, 59 ; ii. 14, 45, 46 ; iii. 16, 61 ; iv. 34, 35 ; xii. 
 10. But in all such cases, I think, it will be found that a more serious motive 
 is also present. 
 
 2 Tac. Ann. xi. 24. 
 
 3 The text of the two bronze tablets, found in 1524, has been edited by A. 
 de Boissieu in his Inscriptions antiques de Lyons. It is printed in Orelli's 
 edition of Tacitus at the end of Book xi. of the Annals, p. 342. 
 
 4 As they are introduced, for example, by Quintus Curtius, who gives 
 the speech of the Scythian ambassadors to Alexander (vii. 8), and an im- 
 possible harangue of Dareius to his army before the battle of Arbela 
 (iv. 14).
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 what Gibbon calls " the elaborate and often empty speeches 
 of the Byzantine historians." 1 The Latin chroniclers of the 
 middle ages rarely ventured on such ambitious efforts. But at 
 the revival of letters the classical practice of inserting speeches 
 was revived by historical writers, whether they wrote in Latin 2 
 or in their vernacular. 3 M. Daunou 4 quotes some curious 
 examples from the French literature of the three centuries 
 before our own. Thus Vertot, in his Revolutions romaincs, 
 entered into competition with Dionysius, Livy and Plutarch, 
 by inventing a fourth version of the appeal made to Coriolanus 
 by his mother in the Volscian camp. Mezerai could make 
 Joan of Arc address her executioners in a harangue full of 
 violent invective and sinister prediction; and this when the 
 contemporary record of her trial existed, with its notice of the 
 rare and broken utterances which belonged to her last hours. 5 
 By degrees a controversy arose on the question whether a 
 historian is entitled to invent speeches for his persons, and the 
 literary world was long divided upon it. Isaac Voss 6 and 
 Mably 7 were among the more distinguished champions of the 
 oratorical licence ; among its opponents were Voltaire whose 
 opinion has been quoted already and D'Alembert. The latter 
 declared, in 1761, that a historian who filled his work with 
 
 1 Decline and Fall, ch. 43. It is difficult to believe, with Gibbon, that the 
 speech of Attila to his soldiers before the battle of Chalons as given in Cas- 
 siodorus can rest on any basis of fact (ch. 35) ; however it may be with the 
 letter of Belisarius to Justinian given by Procopius, which Gibbon thinks 
 "genuine and original" (ch. 43). 
 
 2 E.g. Paulus Aemilius, Strada Mariana, Buchanan, Grotius, De Thou. 
 
 3 E.g. Machiavelli, Guicciardini, Mezerai. 
 
 4 Cours d'titudes Historiques, vol. vii. p. 466 ff. 
 
 5 As M. Daunou gravely observes : "La plus simple reflexion suffit pour 
 concevoir que les Anglais, tenant en leur pouvoir la malheureuse Jeanne, ne 
 lui auraient pas permis, a sa derniere heure, de debiter publiquement toutes 
 ces sottises " (p. 476). The authentic records of her trial and execution are 
 contained, he adds, in vol. iii. of the Notices et Extraits des Manuscrits de la 
 Bibliotheque du Roi. It is an extraordinary example of the rhetorical taste 
 of the age that Mezerai should have preferred to declaim, when he might have 
 told a true story of the deepest pathos. 
 
 6 Ars Historica, 20. 
 
 7 De la maniere d'ecrire THistoire, Works, vol. xii. 452-461.
 
 316 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 speeches would be sent back to college. 1 But the practice 
 lingered on a little longer, being commonly defended by the 
 plea that it was enlivening, and that it could not be really 
 deceptive. 2 The spirit of scientific criticism has now banished 
 it for ever from history, and has relegated it to its proper 
 sphere in the province of historical romance. 
 
 13. Thucydides set the first great example of making 
 historical persons say what they might have said. The basis 
 of his conception was common to the whole ancient world : it 
 was the sovereign importance of speech in political and civic 
 life. But in Thucydides the use of the licence is dramatic 
 that is, conducive to the truthful and vivid presentment of 
 action. In most of the later Greek and Eoman historians it is 
 either rhetorical that is, subservient to the display of the 
 writer's style or partly dramatic and partly rhetorical. The 
 art of rhetoric passed through two sta.ges of educational signifi- 
 cance in the ancient world. In the first stage, with which 
 Thucydides was contemporary, rhetoric meant a training for 
 real debate in the assembly or the law-courts. Then, as Greek 
 political life died down, rhetoric came to mean the art of 
 writing or declaiming. 3 The speeches in Thucydides have the 
 dramatic spirit, and not the rhetorical, because, although the 
 art of rhetoric has helped to make them, they are in direct 
 relation with real action and real life. The rhetorical historians 
 of the ancient world represent the second stage of rhetoric : 
 
 1 "Tranchons le mot, aujourd'hui Ton renverrait aux amplifications de 
 college un historien qui remplirait son ouvrage de harangues : " quoted by 
 Daunou (vii. 472) from a paper on the art of writing history, read by D'Alem- 
 bert to the French Academy (Ib. p. 115). 
 
 2 Thus Gaillard, in his History of Francis I., published in 1766, answers the 
 charge of a "petite infidelite" by saying : " Je reponds que je ne puis voir 
 une infidelite reelle ou d'un cdte personne ne veut tromper, et ou d'un autre 
 cote personne ne peut-etre trompe " (Daunou, p. 458). This is much the same 
 as the apology for Livy's speeches made by Crevier in the preface to his 
 edition : " Quasi vero cuiquam innocens ille dolus imponat." Botta's History 
 of Italy from 1780 to 1814 contains one of the latest examples, perhaps, of the 
 licence, when he gives (Book iii. ) the speeches of Pesaro and Vallaresso in the 
 debate of the Venetian Senate on the French invasion of Italy (1793), and 
 (Book v.) a debate in the Piedmontese Council. The practice was thoroughly 
 suited to the Italian genius, and maintained itself longest in Italy. 
 
 3 The process of this change has been sketched in the Attic Oratory, vol. ii. 
 ch. xxi\ .
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDWES. 317 
 
 their speeches are only more or less possible declamations. 
 The modern writers who attempted to revive the practice were 
 in a lower deep still, since for them rhetoric was not even a 
 living element of culture. 1 But it may be well to consider a 
 little more closely how far and in what sense Thucydides can 
 be called dramatic. The epithet " dramatic " is sometimes 
 applied to narrative when no more is apparently meant than 
 that it is vivid or graphic. In the proper sense, however, a 
 narrative is dramatic only when it elicits the inherent eloquence 
 of facts. Thucydides is dramatic, for instance, when he places the 
 Melian dialogue 2 immediately before the Sicilian expedition. The 
 simple juxtaposition of insolence and ruin is more effective than 
 comment. The bare recital, thus ordered, makes the same kind 
 of impression which the actions themselves would have made if 
 one had immediately succeeded the other before our eyes. It 
 might not be difficult, with a little adroitness, to represent 
 Thucydides as a conscious dramatic artist throughout his 
 work ; and an ingenious writer has actually shown how his 
 History may be conceived as a tragedy cast into five acts. 3 
 
 1 The Roman historical writers of the Empire were under the influence of 
 the recitations (cp. Mayor on Juvenal iii. ; and Heitland and Raven, in the 
 Introduction to their extracts from Quintus Curtius, in the Pitt Press Series, 
 p. 12). Prejudicial to history as this influence was, it yet gave a special 
 interest to the speeches, regarded as exercises in a familiar art. 
 
 2 In the remarkable speech of the Athenian envoy Euphemus at Camarina 
 (vi. 82-86, 415 B.C.), the dramatic purpose of the Melian dialogue is continued 
 and completed. The plain avowal of Athenian motives is reiterated, and 
 their bearing on the Sicilian expedition is explicitly stated. See vi. 83, 
 ri]v re yap <?/cet d/>xV (in Greece) dp-qKa.fj.ev dia 5^os ?x eiv > Kal TO. evddde (in 
 Sicily) Sia rb avro ijiceiv /j-era rCiv (j}i\uv a.ff<pa\us Ka.Ta,aT~r](T6[j.evoi. 85, wcrre 
 Kal Tou>6d8e dK&s irpbs r \vaire\ovv ical, d \tyofj.ft>, & 2vpa.Ko<r[ov$ 5tos 
 
 8 Ulrici, Charakteristik der antiken Historiographie, p. 313. Book i. is a 
 prologue, he says, which acquaints the reader with the immediate ante- 
 cedents of the drama and the relative positions of the chief actors. The 
 First Act comprises the plague at Athens, the supreme efforts of Pericles and 
 his death, the destruction of Plataea by Sparta, the overthrow of Mitylene by 
 Athens (ii. 1 iii. 68). The Second Act presents the typical party-strife at 
 Corcyra ; fortune wavers ; the Athenians are defeated by the Aetolians, but 
 blockade the Spartans in Sphacteria (iii. 69 iv. 36). The Third Act opens 
 with the surrender of the Spartans ; the Athenians occupy Cythera ; both 
 sides are weary of the struggle, and at length a peace is concluded. But 
 there are signs that it cannot last, and now Alcibiades comes forward to
 
 ,18 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 But it would perhaps be truer to say that the war itself pre- 
 sented striking contrasts, analogous to those which a dramatic 
 poet contrives : the dullest writer could not have wholly 
 missed these contrasts ; and if Diodorus had been the historian, 
 his work, too, might have revealed the five acts ; but Thucy- 
 dides was peculiarly well fitted to bring out these contrasts 
 with the most complete effect. He was so, because he felt 
 the whole moment and pathos of the events themselves ; 
 because he saw them with the distinctness of intense concen- 
 tration ; and because, partly under the influence of language, 1 
 he had even more than the ordinary Greek love of antithesis. 
 It is obvious that the Peloponnesian war, as a subject for 
 history, may be said to have dramatic unity in the sense that 
 it is a single great action : as, by an analogous metaphor, the 
 subject of Herodotus may be said to have epic unity, because 
 the various parts, though they cannot be brought within the 
 compass of one action, 2 can be brought within the compass of 
 one narrative. And, apart from this rudimentary dramatic 
 unity, the Peloponnesian war has a further analogy to a drama 
 in presenting a definite moment at which the cardinal situation 
 is decisively reversed as it is reversed in the Oedipus 
 Tyrannus, for instance, when the king discovers that he is an 
 incestuous parricide. That moment is the Sicilian expedition. 
 The supreme test of " dramatic " quality in a history of the 
 Peloponnesian war must be the power with which the historian 
 
 advocate the Sicilian expedition (iv. 37 vi. 23). The Fourth Act is the 
 crisis the Sicilian expedition, ending in the Athenian defeat (vi. 24 vii.). In 
 the Fifth Act the catastrophe is delayed for a moment by the recall of 
 Alcibiades. He brings back a gleam of prosperity with him. But he is 
 again dismissed ; and then comes the final ruin of Athens (viii.). 
 
 1 The Greek instinct for symmetry and just measure sharpened the percep- 
 tion of contrast, and the desire of vividly expressing contrast helped to mould 
 the language. Thus when it is said of Antigone, wavuv ywaiKwv <lis dva^iu- 
 T&Tt\ | KdKiar' air' gpywv eikXeeo-rdrwj' (f>0ivei (694), it is the keenly felt opposition 
 of things that is striving to utter itself in the forcible opposition of words. 
 Then Rhetoric arose, with its opposition of words even where there was 
 no commensurate opposition of things. Thucydides was partly under 
 this influence of Rhetoric : witness his Zpyov and X67os, etc. ; but, by a 
 reversal of the natural process, the very habit of verbal antithesis tended to 
 quicken the observation of opportunities for its effective employment. 
 
 8 /.e> no drama on the Persian wars could have included (e.g.) the Egyptian 
 and Scythian episodes of Herodotus.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYD1DES. 319 
 
 lias marked the significance of the Sicilian expedition as the 
 tragic "revolution" (peripeteia), the climax of pity and terror, 
 the decisive reversal. Tlmcydides has devoted the whole of 
 his Sixth and Seventh Books to the events of those two years, 
 thus at once marking the significance of the expedition as the 
 turning-point of the war. And every reader knows with what 
 tremendous effect he has traced its course, from the moment when 
 the whole population of Athens was gathered at the Peiraeus 
 in the early midsummer morning to see the splendid fleet sail 
 for Sicily, and the trumpet commanded silence while the whole 
 multitude joined in prayer, and wine was poured from vessels 
 of silver and gold as the paean 1 arose, down to that overthrow of 
 which he writes that they were destroyed with utter destruction, 
 arid that few out of many came home. 2 Here, at the point in 
 his story which supplies the crucial test, Tlmcydides shows 
 that he possesses true dramatic power. By the direct present- 
 ment of the facts, not by reflections upon them, he makes us 
 feel all that is tragic in the Sicilian disaster itself, and also all 
 that it means in relation to the larger tragedy of the war. The 
 same power is seen in many particular episodes of the History : 
 for example, in the self-restrained majesty of Pericles, the great 
 protagonist of the opening war, whose courage, amidst havoc 
 and pestilence, ever rises as the Athenian courage declines ; or 
 in the first appearance of Alcibiades on the scene, with his 
 brilliant versatility and his profound lack of loyalty, with his 
 unmeasured possibilities for good or evil, just when the Sicilian 
 project is trembling in the balance. Without pressing the 
 parallel between the History and a work of dramatic art to 
 any fanciful length, it may be said with a definite meaning 
 that Thucydides has not merely the inspiration of action, but 
 often also the spirit of the noblest tragic drama. 
 
 It is natural to regret his silence in regard to the social and 
 intellectual life of his age. 3 The simplest explanation of it is 
 
 1 vi. 30. s vii. 87. 
 
 8 The names of Aeschylus, Sophocles (the poet), Euripides (the poet), 
 Aristophanes, Pheidias, Ictinus, Anaxagoras, Socrates, are among those which 
 Thucydides nowhere mentions. In addition to Helen (i. 9) and Procne 
 (ii. 29), only four women are named in the whole History, and not one of 
 them has the slightest human interest in reference to the war Chrysis and 
 Phaeinis, successively priestesses of the Argive Hera (ii. 1, iv. 133) ; Strato-
 
 320 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 that he did not conceive such details as requisite for the illus- 
 tration of his purely political subject. The art and poetry of 
 the day, the philosophy and the society, were perhaps in his 
 view merely the decorations of the theatre in which the great 
 tragedy of the war was being played. Though he wrote for all 
 time, he did not conceive of an audience who would have to 
 reconstruct this theatre before they could fully comprehend 
 his drama, 1 No writer has ever been at once so anxiously 
 careful and so haughtily improvident of the future. His 
 characteristic dislike of superfluous detail seems to have been 
 allied with a certain hardness of temperament, such as is 
 indicated by the tone of his reference to the poets. 2 His 
 banishment may also have infused something of bitterness 3 
 
 nice, the sister of Perdiccas (ii. 101) ; and Archedice, the daughter of Hippias 
 (vi. 59). The Parthenon is alluded to as a treasury ; and the Propylaea are 
 noticed as a work which had reduced the balance in it (ii. 13, 3, where ev 
 
 1 Thucydides can, indeed, imagine a time when Sparta shall be desolate, 
 and only the ruins of Athens shall remain ; i. 10 2, AaKeSai/movluv yap 
 tl i} 7r6Xts pi) fj.ii} 6 fir] . , . ' AOyvaiuv d TO avrb TOVTO iraObvTUv, K.T.\. But 
 he has no conception of a time when the Hellenic civilisation that he knew 
 should have passed away. Thus Pericles says that Athens (unlike Troy or 
 Mycenae, he means) needs no Homer to persuade posterity of her greatness : 
 she has established on every shore imperishable monuments of her power for 
 evil or good, where the aidia fj-v-rj^la. are the Athenian settlements on con- 
 quered or on friendly soil. Cf. ii. 64, r)v iced vvv virevdw^v irore . . . fj.vfjfj.fj 
 Ka.Ta\f\el\l/eTcu, K.T.\, where the /W^/M? assumes a purely Hellenic standard. 
 
 2 He cites them simply as authorities for facts, whose statements often 
 require to be modified : i. 21 1. Thus he makes a sort of apology for 
 quoting so equivocal an authority as Homer respecting the power of Agamem- 
 non (i. 9 4), and the size of the Greek fleet (10 3). His extracts from 
 the fine passage in the Hymn to the Delian Apollo are the briefest which 
 could establish his two points that there was an Ionian festival at Delos, and 
 that it included a musical contest (iii. 104). 
 
 3 There is a singular suggestiveness in the speech which the exile Thucydides 
 attributes to the exile Alcibiades (at Sparta in 415 B.C., vi. 92). It is the 
 historian's way of showing how the pain which he himself had known might 
 work in a disloyal character. "My patriotism," says Alcibiades, " is not for 
 a country that wrongs me ; it was given to a country that protected my rights. 
 
 The true patriot is not he who abstains from moving against the country 
 from which he has been unjustly banished, but he who, in his passionate love 
 for her, strives by all means to regain her." 
 
 May not these words KC 0X6?roXtj oOros 6p0cDs, o$x 5s &" TTJV eavrov adl/cus 
 dTToX^tras /J.T-, eirlri have a reference to Thrasybulus and the patriotic exiles 
 who marched from Phyle upon Athens ? Just after the restoration of the 
 democracy the point would have been peculiarly effective.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 3 21 
 
 into his recollections of the Athenian life, with all its gracious 
 surroundings, with all its social and intellectual delights, from 
 which he was suddenly cut off, so that he should know them 
 no more until he came back in his old age and found them 
 changed. Ko one can tell now r how the memories of early 
 sympathies may have grouped themselves in his mind as he 
 looked out in later years from his home in Thrace on the sea 
 over which he had sailed on the long-past day when he failed to 
 save Ainphipolis ; but at least there is a twofold siiggestiveness 
 in those passages 1 which touch on the glories of Athens. 
 There is the feeling of the man who has never lost his love and 
 admiration for the Athenian ideal ; and there is also a certain 
 reluctance to translate this ideal into concrete images, 2 as if, 
 in the words of Oedipus after his ruin, it were sweet for thought 
 to dwell beyond the sphere of griefs. 3 Perhaps in this very 
 reticence the modern world may find a gain when it views his 
 work from the artistic side. Thucydides must always hold his 
 fame by a double right ; not only as a thinker who, in an age 
 of transitional scepticism, clearly apprehended the value of 
 disciplined intelligence as a permanent force in practical politics, 
 but also as a writer who knew how to make great events tell 
 their own story greatly ; and the dramatic power of the im- 
 mortal History is heightened by its dramatic reserve. 
 
 E. C. J. 
 
 1 Most striking of all these, perhaps, is one in the speech of Nicias to the 
 army before the retreat from Syracuse (vii. 63, 3), where, addressing the 
 Hem-Athenians, he reminds them of the pleasure (ijBovri) which they have 
 derived from passing for Athenians through their knowledge of the Attic 
 dialect, and their imitation of Attic manners and so being admired through- 
 out Greece : J A8t]va1oi vofj-ifo/jLevoi ical /JLTJ H>vres . . . TTJS re (fxnii'TJs ^iriarrnj.^ KO.I rCiv 
 Tpbiruv rfj /u/iTjtm tdavfid^fffOe KO.TCI T^V 'EXXciSa. Among Peloponnesians, 
 Italians or Siceliots, the Athenian exile had ever carried about with him the 
 consciousness of belonging to that city which was the Tratdfv<ns 'EXXdSos. 
 
 2 Even in the Funeral Oration that splendid monument of his grave 
 enthusiasm for Athens Thucydides has been restrained, whether by 
 fidelity to the original or by his own feeling, from exceeding the limit of such 
 abstract expressions as T& Ka.6' r)(dpav iwiTt]Sevfj.a.Ta., irdvuv avawavXai, aywvfs, 
 
 iat, <pi\OKa\f?v, <f>i\o<ro<f>e'tv. 
 
 rb y&p | TT)v (ppovriS' w TUI> KaxCov oiKdv yXvKv, Oed. Tyr. 1390.
 
 322 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDIDES. 
 
 TABLE OF THE SPEECHES. 
 
 [Asterisks mark those delivered at Athens before the exile of Thucydides.] 
 
 Book. Date B.C. 
 
 I. 32-36 433 Corcyrean ) 
 
 (> ^ . ~ . ,,. i Envoys to the Athenian Lcclesia.* 
 
 ,, 37-43 ,, Corinthian J 
 
 ,. 68-72 432 Corinthian \ 
 
 __ __ . ,, f Envoys in the nrst Congress at Sparta. 
 
 73- / 8 Athenian ) 
 
 80-85 King Archidamus ~) 
 
 mi -n i Oil. i -j r to the Spartan Assembly. 
 86 The Ephor Sthenelaidas J 
 
 120-24 ,, Corinthian Envoys in the second Congress at Sparta. 
 ,, 140-44 Pericles to the Athenian Ecclesia.* 
 
 II. 35-46 431 Funeral Oration of Pericles.* 
 
 ,, 60-64 430 Pericles to the Athenian Ecclesia.* 
 
 III. 9-14 428 Mitylenean Envoys to the Peloponnesians at Olympia. 
 
 37-40 427 Cleon 
 
 42-48 Diodotus to the Ath eman Ecclesia * 
 
 53-59 Plataeans) 
 
 61-67 Thebans } to the Spartan Judges. 
 
 IV. 17-20 425 Lacedaemonian Envoys to the Athenian Ecclesia.* 
 
 59-64 424 Hermocrates in the Sicilian Congress at Gela. 
 
 85-87 Brasidas to the Acanthians. 
 
 V. 85-116 416 Conference between Athenian and Melian negotiators. 
 
 VI. 9-14 415 Nicias ^ 
 
 16-18 Alcibiades > to the Athenian Ecclesia. 
 
 20-23 Nicias J 
 
 ,, 33-34 Hermocrates "\ 
 
 ,, 36-40 ,, Athenagoras > to the Syracusan Assembly. 
 
 41 A Syracusan General J 
 
 ,, 76-80 Hermocrates as Envoy of Syracuse \ . /-, 
 
 _ .. f at Oaniarina. 
 
 82-86 Euphemus as Envoy of Athens J 
 
 89-92 Alcibiades at Sparta. 
 
 Militavy Harangues. 
 
 II. 11 431 Archidamus to the Peloponnesian Officers before invad- 
 
 ing Attica. 
 87 429 Peloponuesian Commanders to their 
 
 in the Corinthiau 
 
 before an action 
 crews 
 
 89 ,, Phonnio to the men of the Athenian ,,. 
 
 Fleet Gulf " 
 
 IV. 10 425 Demosthenes to his troops at Pylos. 
 
 92 424 Pagondas to the Boeotian troops \ before the 
 
 ,,95 ,, Hippocrates to the Athenian troops / of Deliuni.
 
 THE SPEECHES OF THUCYDWES. 323 
 
 Book. Date B. c. 
 
 IV. 126 423 Brasidas to his troops on the campaign against Arrhi- 
 
 baeus. 
 
 V. 9 422 Brasidas to bis troops before the battle at Amphipolis. 
 
 VI. 68 415 Nicias to his troops before the first battle at Syracuse. 
 VII. 61-64 413 Nicias to the Athenian troops "1 before the last sea- 
 ,, 66-68 ,, Gylippus to the Syracusan troops / fight. 
 ,, 77 ,, Nicias to his troops before the retreat from Syracuse. 
 
 The short speech of the Elean Teutiaplus to Alcidas and the Pelopon- 
 nesian leaders at Embaton (iii. 30, 427 B.C.) is virtually of this class. 
 
 From the set speeches are to be distinguished a few shorter utterances 
 in the direct form, but of a more colloquial character, viz. the dialogue 
 between Archidamus and the Plataeans (ii. 71-74, 429 B.C.) ; the conversation 
 with the Ambracian herald and an Athenian (iii. 113, 426 B.C.) ; and the 
 words of Peisander in the Athenian Ecclesia (viii. 53, 411 B.C.) The letter 
 of Nicias (vii. 11-15, 414 B.C.) would be classed by some with the speeches 
 composed by Thucydides, by others as an authentic document. Cp. p. 98, 
 note 6.
 
 XENOPHON. 
 
 " The sage and heroic Xenophon. " GIBBON. 
 
 IF the learning of Gibbon had chanced or chosen to add 
 another epithet to the two in which he has justly commemo- 
 rated the virtues of Xenophon, perhaps with the cro</>o? and 
 of Plutarch and Longinus he would have coupled the 
 of Polybius ; for the companion of Cyrus, who 
 tramped or galloped over the sandy plains of Mesopotamia 
 seven centuries and a half before the fatal march of Julian, in 
 the end proved himself no less an adept in the art of words 
 than of warfare, and lived to display to after-time, as the out- 
 come of multiform gifts, a triad of interblending qualities as a 
 man, philosopher, and stylist. 
 
 It is under this threefold embodiment that an attempt is 
 here made, in some sort briefly, to estimate the genius of 
 Xenophon. But intentionally, the scope of this Essay is con- 
 fined to an appreciation of the more salient characteristics of 
 the writer. What was the main drift of his talents 1 How 
 was he placed with regard to the times at which he lived ? 
 In what relation does he stand to our own ? The answer, or 
 some answer, to these questions may well present itself as a 
 quite sufficient object without plunging into polemic, even 
 where the views maintained run counter to those of higher 
 authority. On the same principle, it seems right to avoid all de- 
 tailed discussion of the various ' vexed questions ' and perplexi- 
 ties familiar to the student of the life and literature before us. 
 
 Some of these have the abstract interest of problems proper, 
 in which the balance of argument in favour of this con- 
 clusion or the other is so evenly poised, that a tremor of the 
 investigator's hand will turn the scale, and the work will 
 need to be recommenced; as, for instance, the time-honoured 
 inquiry, "de simultate Platonis cum Xenophonte," or the 
 question whether he fought at Delium and was carried off
 
 XENOPHON. 325 
 
 the field on the shoulders of Socrates ; or, again, in what 
 year he was born. Of these, some, it is felt, are compara- 
 tively otiose, others lure the searcher on, in hopes of a 
 discovery, where perhaps discovery is impossible. Thus we 
 may ask, What light does 'the Anabasis' throw upon the 
 question of Xenophon's age at the date of the matters there 
 recorded (B.C. 401) ? Let us suppose, for the moment, that the 
 book itself is simply a splendid work of imagination, of the 
 Robinson Crusoe type, based upon the verisimilitude of thrill- 
 ing incidents such as might have occurred during the actual 
 advance and retreat, and in which a ' well-girt ' Athenian 
 volunteer might have played a conspicuous part, but which 
 were really the clever invention of some Hellenic Defoe : x 
 would such a work fix with certainty the age of this ideal 
 Xenophon, as under thirty-five rather than over forty ? Or, 
 OD the counter supposition that the tale itself is a vera nar- 
 ratio, not more coloured than would be the contributions of 
 a fairly accurate military correspondent to a modern news- 
 paper, w r ho should find himself actively employed in command 
 of a Russian column in Central Asia : in this case, do any 
 expressions used ovSev irpo^aai^o^ai rrjv rjXtfciav, "my age shall 
 not stand between me and your orders," etc., settle the question ? 2 
 Another class of difficulties has this special attractiveness, 
 that being involved with more vital points of interest which 
 lie still in a haze of uncertainty with the elucidation of the 
 one will come, perhaps, an inpouring of light upon the others. 
 What, for instance, was the date of Xenophon's banishment 
 from Athens ? What was the cause of it ? Supposing him to 
 have been sentenced eVt Aa/cavia^a), 3 " on the ground of 
 ' Laconism' " in what way were these objectionable or culp- 
 able proclivities exhibited? Was it through attachment to 
 
 1 To this inventive personage, possibly named Themistogenes, but more 
 probably Xenophon himself, Xenophon is an ideal being. The stone of 
 stumbling, perhaps intentionally placed, is the passage in Hellen. iii. 1. 2. 
 w fJ.v o$v KOpos ffrpdrevfui re o"(WXee Kal rovr 1 'x< av df^i] ^""i r & v ade\<t>6v, Kal 
 wj i] fJ.dx~n tytvero, Kal us a.irt0a.ve, Kal us K TOVTOV a.Trffu6r]ffai> ol "EXX^cej tiri 
 OaXarrav, QepiffToytvei r<p 'SivpaKocritj) ytypairrai. Vide infra, p. 352, for 
 further problems connected with the person of Themistogenes. 
 
 * Xen. Anab, iii. 1. 14 and 25; compare Thirlwall, Xenophon, Niebuhr, 
 and Delbrueck, Philol. Mus. vol. i. p. 510. 
 
 8 Diog. Laert. ii. 7. 15.
 
 326 XENOPHON. 
 
 Cyrus ? or coquettings with Spartan Harmosts, the admirals 
 and governors-general of Byzantium? or were these at worst 
 forgotten bygones ? Was it his new friendship with Agesi- 
 laus, or his presence at Coroneia, or something altogether 
 different, which brought about the sentence ? Again, was 
 Xenophon present at Coroneia ? If present, was he there in a 
 private capacity, as a mere spectator conceivably ? or was he, 
 necessarily, personally engaged ? Or, given that he was present 
 on the field, does it remain important whether he fought or 
 not ? Again, assuming that he was not only there, but fought 
 beside Agesilaus, can his conduct be explained or justified on 
 general grounds ? or by application of any ethical standard 
 suited to the peculiar political situation ? This standard may 
 either be normal, 1 that is to say, in accordance with the more 
 or less fixed Hellenic ' interpolitical ' morality ; or abnormal, 2 
 the outcome of a temporary confusion of ideas. It is clear 
 that such confusion was inevitable, in the struggle between 
 incipient Panhellenism, and a belief in the ' natural ' claims 
 of Sparta to hegemony, which is Laconism, coupled possibly 
 with anti-Theban jealousy ? It is no less clear that these 
 currents and cross-currents must set more or less in a direction 
 contrary to the old customary and sacred separate-State 
 doctrine, which would usually, and more properly, be distin- 
 guished by the name of ' patriotism.' Nor is it to be denied that 
 a right answer to these and other similar questions would lead 
 directly to the better understanding either of Hellenic history 
 as a whole, or of the Socratic and Sophistic era in particular ; 
 of the times or personality of Xenophon ; of his political stand- 
 point or his military and literary genius. Hence their fascina- 
 tion here to be resisted. 
 
 A third class of difficulties, however, intermediate between 
 these latter and the problem proper, may not be so easily 
 
 1 Normal. It must be borne in mind that ' the opposition ' were in all 
 Greek states (even tolerant Athens) liable to find themselves outside the walls 
 of their 7r6\ts, and then civic duties became hazy and ambiguous. Cf. 
 Alcibiades. 
 
 2 Abnormal. The opinions of Isocrates, only a stage later than Xenophon, 
 throw much light on this matter. Vide Jebb, Orators, vol. ii. ch. xii. for his 
 Philippising Panhellenism. Panhellenism in itself is the prototype of modern 
 cosmopolitan morality.
 
 XENOPHON. 327 
 
 avoided, for they run up into the substance of any general ap- 
 preciation ; yet, even so, they can be only dealt with indirectly in 
 this essay. They cluster chiefly round the Memorabilia, or else 
 round the Hdlcniea. Of the first, these are samples : What is 
 Xenophon's estimate of Socrates worth ? Is he unworthy the 
 name of a philosopher, if only as being unintelligent of his great 
 associate ? Of the second, these : Why is his History so one- 
 sided ? Why these astonishing gaps ? Why no mention of 
 Pelopidas in the recapture of the Cadmeia, nor of Epaminondas 
 at Leuctra ? Xot a word of the re-establishment of Messene 
 on Mount Ithome, or of the founding of Panarcadian Megalopolis. 
 What, on the other hand, is the meaning of the encomium passed 
 upon the historian by Lucian, 1 for honesty and impartiality ? 
 It cannot be alleged of these questions, as of others possibly, 
 that they are either insoluble or of no deep biographical interest; 
 yet, to rivet attention, in a sketch, to the difficulties rather than 
 the patent characteristics of a period in the life of a people or 
 an individual ; to arrange the materials before us so as to con- 
 stitute a series of diverting or discouraging riddles, may be the 
 worst mode of distorting the truth ; and, in a rapid survey, it 
 would seem better to allow the lights and shadows to arrange 
 themselves, than microscopically to examine the obscurer por- 
 tions. The former at any rate is the method adopted here. 
 
 But there is yet another class of questions, which, although 
 individually included in one or other of the above divisions, might 
 better be treated separately. I refer to the whole topic of the 
 canon. Which of the works attributed to Xenophon are genuine ? 
 and, amongst those regarded as genuine, which, if any, are sus- 
 pected portions ? However formidable this group ofdiroplcu, its 
 discussion is inadmissible here ; and in lieu of which, it may 
 be deemed sufficient to append a list of works accepted 
 as, for the most part, genuine. Nor does this solution seem 
 objectionable, if, in so doing, we conscientiously refrain from 
 colouring our judgment on any essential point by data drawn 
 from those works, or portions of a work, the genuineness of 
 which we more than half suspect. The list itself, appropriated 
 bodily from Sauppe's stereotyped edition in five volumes, 
 
 1 Lucian, TTWS e? laroplav (rvyypd<peiv ; 39.
 
 328 XENOPHON. 
 
 will serve to draw attention to a point of some importance, 
 not unfrequently forgotten wldle we are thinking of Xeno- 
 phon's talents as pre-eminently embodied in this or the other 
 of his larger works ; as the author of the Anabasis, or the 
 Cyropacdia, of the Hellenica, or the Memorabilia. The point 
 referred to is the versatility and productiveness, and, as a closer 
 consideration reveals, the inventiveness of this writer's genius; 
 while the titles themselves, and still more the subject-matter, 
 show that these qualities are not literary simply, but part of 
 the underlying capacity of the man. 
 
 Lastly, and as might a priori have been expected in the 
 case of so 'vocal' an actor, the writer, it will be admitted, 
 has not failed to reveal either himself, or the stage on which 
 he moved, and this to a quite unprecedented degree. These 
 works l (with their approximate dates) are rich with the best 
 autobiographic matter, and burn brightly with the spirit of the 
 times. But w r hat is meant by biographic, or autobiographic, 
 matter ? I would fain use the words in only the higher 
 sense, and exclude a particular kind of ' inferential ' biography 
 of a type with which the so-called lives of certain saints 
 or sinners have made us in our childhood familiar. We 
 are content to know that Proxenus was a time-honoured 
 friend, and can gather food for reflection from the descrip- 
 tion of the after-supper walk in the camp, in front of the 
 place d'armes, where the two friends paced together a few 
 days before the youthful Boeotian general was murdered. 2 We 
 
 1 [The Polity of Athens, probably not by Xenophon, written about B.C. 426] 
 
 ffiero, written after ,, 394 
 
 Memorabilia (or Recollections) , . . . written about ,, 390 
 
 Treatise on Hunting, ..... written after , , 389 
 
 Hellenica, Part L, written before ,, 387 
 
 The Symposium, ...... written before , , 385 
 
 The Economist, . . . . . . written not before ,, 383 
 
 The Anabasis (or the Advance on Susa and 
 
 the Retreat), . . . . written after ,, 380 
 
 The Polity of the Lacedaemonians, . . written about , , 369 
 
 A Cavalry General's Manual, . . . written about ,, 363 
 
 A Treatise on Horsemanship, . . . written about , , 362 
 
 The Cyropaedia (or the Education of Cyrus), not finished before , , 361 
 
 Agesilaus (a panegyric on), .... written about ,, 360 
 
 Hellenica, Part II., ..... written about ,, 357 
 
 A Pamphlet on Revenues, .... written about ,, 356 
 
 2 A nab. ii. iv. 15.
 
 XRNOFHON. 329 
 
 
 can almost overhear the words they said together. So again 
 the delineation of his friend's character, in juxtaposition with 
 those of Clearchus and Menon, is speakingly suggestive. But 
 we do not care to make this biographic incident a ground for 
 concluding that the early years of Xenophon were spent in 
 captivity at Thebes ; where, with Proxenus, who learnt wisdom 
 as we know from Gorgias, he may have listened to Prodicus 
 expounding the choice of Heracles ; where also he doubtless 
 contracted that general antipathy to Thebans, of which his 
 exceptional affection for Proxenus gives a kind of proof. So 
 again the picture of his life at Skillus, drawn by himself, suffices. 
 Here we see him offering daily sacrifice to his patron goddess 
 Artemis, 1 or worshipping in the miniature model of the temple 
 of the great goddess of the Ephesians at Ephesus by the banks 
 of the miniature Selinus, or hunting antelopes and boars 
 with his sons and friends on the slopes of Pholoe. Nor is 
 any strong desire aroused in us to ascertain what really 
 happened eventually ; whether or not the Eleians restored the 
 recaptured farm, or whether the wanderer was driven to retire 
 to Corinth, where he ended his days. In truth, a question of 
 deeper interest does arise : whether the irepl irpoao^wv was, as 
 we incline to believe, a work of his old age, and, not improbably, 
 written in requital to Eubulus for the kindly service of his 
 restoration ; but whether he actually ended his days at Athens 
 or Corinth, or elsewhere, is not in itself a fact which we ought 
 to jump at inferentially ; or need unduly lament as still rele- 
 gated to the region of open surmise. 
 
 It is, however, not to be denied that within the biography of 
 inference lurk also the germs of better things ; ceasing to deal 
 with trivialities and the more mundane materials, it rises at 
 once in validity and in dignity : so that, instead of a tissue 
 of external ' facts ' whose objectivity is questionable,' we get, 
 in some sort of matter-of-fact setting, a group of rational infer- 
 ences, drawn from the cognition of real and truly apprehended 
 qualities. In such or such way must this man, being of this 
 sort, have behaved in these circumstances. The qualities of 
 the individual and the circumstances being given, the inference 
 of any sympathetic and intelligent biographer will probably 
 
 1 Anal. v. 3. 5-12.
 
 330 XENOPHON. 
 
 be worth recording ; or, in the case of a tradition, the subjective 
 summing up of a whole cluster of unconscious biographers 
 to wit, the age which records it may have the further charm 
 of contributing to the autobiography of humanity itself. This 
 high order of conjectural biography, doubtless, deserves to be 
 called 'ideal' rather than inferential. Such is its true nature, 
 and it is generally interesting as throwing light on the mind 
 of others quite as much as on his who is the subject of the nar- 
 rative. Hence the charm and interest of Plutarch's Lives, which 
 may be spoken of as chapters from the autobiography of Greece 
 and Koine. In them there is still a contribution from the 
 actual life, it may be of a Pompey or an Alcibiades, the rest 
 being the offerings of contemporaries, or posterity constructing 
 inferentially, and only half-consciously, the two lives as they 
 should, nay must, have shaped themselves. In other words, 
 they were sentences of activity or inaction, spoken by twin 
 guardian divinities, to be graven by the fingers of a mortal upon 
 the hearts of men. A stage further, and a whole people writes 
 its own " phase of faith " in the life of its greatest religious 
 teacher, the facts being of the flimsiest historic validity, but the 
 idea stamped as genuine gold with the impress of eternity. 
 When this happens to humanity as a whole, there is only one 
 title to be given to these self-delineations. They are the ever- 
 lasting portraitures of man, the express image of the offspring 
 of divinity. Apart from this, it would seem better to be repre- 
 sented by no biography of the mundane sort, or next to none 
 as is the case with Shakespeare, but to live by works in the 
 faithful hearts of posterity. 
 
 In more self-conscious times, however, the impulse to con- 
 scious self-revelation has produced another type, and, with the 
 growth of science and regard for " objective " truth, perhaps in 
 this direction may be expected the happiest results : when the 
 writer is content to set forth his life simply as it lies spread 
 out before the all-seeing, neither despising the physical and 
 material side of his nature, nor taking part for or against his 
 spiritual self; pending which, we are grateful to those who 
 have written, whether consciously or unconsciously, the history 
 of their religious opinions or their intellectual growth. 
 
 In the particular case before us the inferior inferential bio-
 
 XENOPHON. 331 
 
 graphics are chiefly of modern manufacture ; but the ancients 
 themselves are not altogether guiltless : and, not to speak of mere 
 gossips, the statement of Plutarch, that Xenophon was actually 
 present at Coroneia, has commonly been accepted as of equal 
 authenticity with the remark of Xenophon 1 upon which it 
 doubtless was based. Strabo also, Athenaeus, Diodorus, and 
 Diogenes Laertius, have all more or less interpreted the Xeno- 
 phontine tradition inferentially, but the last named has, at the 
 beginning and end of his life of Xenophon, incorporated two 
 stories which, on ideal grounds, bear the stamp of validity, 
 being not only beautiful in themselves, but as striking the key- 
 note to what we are to discover about him from himself. 
 The one illustrates the hero, the other anticipates the sage, or, 
 more correctly, it has a whisper of the religious nature within, 
 which was the soul's soul. For our purposes let us invert 
 them, and let us first listen to the tale of his old age. His 
 son Gryllus, serving in the Athenian cavalry at Mantinea, 
 fought with might and main, and met his end ; but at that 
 instant fell also Epaminondas, so that afterwards he was said 
 to have fallen by the hand of Gryllus, the son of Xenophon 
 the Athenian. Meanwhile, as the story goes, the father was 
 engaged in offering sacrifice ; the chaplet was upon his brow, 
 when they brought him news saying, "Thy son has fallen," 
 whereupon he removed the chaplet; but as the messengers 
 added ' nobly ' he replaced it on his head, shedding, as others 
 have mentioned, no tear, but only uttering the words, y&eiv 
 dvrjrbv ryeyevvrjKcos, "I knew my child was mortal." The 
 other tale has fully as clear a ring of spiritual truth, though 
 the particular circumstances need never have taken place. It 
 is a tale of boyhood, but its note is a rhythm of the melody 
 of the man. " Xenophon was the son of Gryllus : he was 
 an Athenian, of the deme Erchia; modest of demeanour 
 was he, fair also to look upon beyond description. Tradition 
 tells how Socrates met him in a narrow way, and, stretching 
 his staff athwart him, so as to bar his passage, plied him with 
 inquiries as to where this or that commodity was to be pur- 
 chased, to all which the boy answered fluently: when the 
 
 1 Anab. v. 3. 6 ; Plutarch's Lives, Clough, vol. iv. p. 21 : Agesilaus.
 
 332 XENOPHON. 
 
 sage at length put to him a final question, ' And where are the 
 fair and noble to be found?' The boy shook his head in 
 perplexity; then, said he, 'Follow me, and be taught.' So he 
 followed him, and thereafter became his ' hearer.' " The date of 
 Diogenes is scarcely ascertained, but we may suppose that the 
 above anecdote represents a tradition of perhaps six hundred 
 years ; and, skipping twice that period of time to the date of 
 Kaphael and " The School of Athens" (1510 A.D.), 1 we shall find it 
 still fresh : fresh, doubtless, in the mind of Fabio Calvi, who sup- 
 plied the youthful painter with the hint of information which he 
 needed. The rest was supplied by the spirit of the time, speak- 
 ing through the prophetic soul of the artist. Among the six or 
 seven figures which compose the Socratic group (Socrates 
 himself being so truly depicted as to form a companion to the 
 portrait drawn by Alcibiades in Plato), none are more truth- 
 ful to the imagination than those of Alcibiades and Xenophon. 
 The helmeted, mail-clad warrior facing the philosopher with 
 exquisite proud poise, indicative of a graceful self-confidence on 
 the very verge of vfipis, is unmistakable ; but beside the talker, 
 with back-turned face, hanging on his lips, is a youth with rosy 
 cheeks, auburn-haired, leaning on one arm, in a brooding 
 attitude of deep, earnest, religious gaze: that is Xenophon, 
 the future apologist of the life of Socrates, treasuring one of the 
 recollections of the Memorabilia. 
 
 Pre-eminently among the old writers has Xenophon written 
 a sort of apologia pro vita sua, a many-sided life indeed, as an 
 artist, a citizen, Emigre', philosopher, householder, public man 
 or private friend ; and that not only in the most admissibly 
 autobiographic of his works, the Anabasis, but unconsciously 
 throughout. This also he has done with so naive a trans- 
 parency that he cannot escape the good or the evil of such self- 
 delineation. Only, it should be borne in mind that at one time 
 it is his artistic self that speaks, at another it is to the political 
 man that we are listening ; now we catch the undertone of self- 
 defensive diurnal combativeness, and again predominates the 
 clear voice of single-sighted Hellenic objectivity. The only 
 guide and clew to a fair interpretation is the reader's sympa- 
 
 1 Vide Symonds, The Fine Arts, p. 335, for the notes on Greek philosophy 
 which Fabio Calvi may have supplied to the painter.
 
 XENOPHON. 333 
 
 thetic intelligence ; nought else will avail to arouse and 
 attune our modern minds or feelings to a wakeful harmony, 
 in response with the pulses of old days : the world of Hellas 
 at a crisis of spiritual turmoil ; the apx>l w&ivcov of thought 
 in the person of Socrates, whose issues are eternal ; the 
 quickening of a politico-ethnic consummation, ere long to spring 
 to life in the person of Alexander, with consequences by nature 
 temporal, but on a scale colossal. Portions, indeed, of this self- 
 revelation of the man or of his times a later age may, through 
 its own defects, or even merits, fail duly to appreciate ; or 
 again, in other cases, we may withhold our moral while accord- 
 ing our intellectual sympathy, and this from some moral pro- 
 gress or regress of to-day in which we share. But in the main, 
 to the scientifically trained mind it will seem sufficient to 
 understand the time, neither praising nor blaming over greatly ; 
 and Xenophon is qualified to help us to this scientific, or, if we 
 please to call it so, this optimistic apprehension. 
 
 To science and to the God of natural laws, as to the God of 
 Paradise, everything is ' wie am ersten Tag,' very good. How 
 can we, therefore, trained in this school, and considering the 
 progressive tendency of human nature, which is our faith, and 
 which gives an optimistic colour to our dTrofjivrjf^ovevf^ara, how 
 can we, as a whole, do other than sympathise with the past, 
 out of which that which is ideal in us has grown, and in which 
 it is rooted ? This or that thing we may turn our backs upon 
 in scorn or disgust, but, calmly considering, the whole sub- 
 stratum of ourselves seems excellent, it has played its part 
 well enough. What seems less good and more doubtful is 
 ourselves, as the substratum of the future. Here our verdict 
 swings round self-accusingly, but not of necessity unscienti- 
 fically, unless indeed the principle of progress 'I count not myself 
 to have apprehended ' is psychologically false. Here, at the 
 same time, let us guard against a misconception. However high 
 and optimistic our appreciation of Xenophon, to intercede as 
 his apologist would be impertinent. Inevitably, in the case 
 of so transparent a human being, tenets and points of view 
 revealed in naked simplicity present themselves, with which it 
 is hard if one man in a thousand will feel more than the 
 scantiest sympathy. His views about the democracy, about
 
 334 XENOPHON. 
 
 the political problems of the day, about war or the chase, are 
 not as our views ; if we had lived then, we trust we should 
 have been differently disposed. But is not all this, in the 
 language of Xenophon or Socrates, to stamp ourselves as " busy- 
 bodies and vain fellows "? Why not take Xenophon as we find 
 him, and make the best of him ? We shall not find him so very 
 bad ; nor his times. Even where we dissent, as children of a 
 democratic age, perhaps, from his prejudices in favour of oi 
 /3e\Ti(TTOi, "the better classes;" as befrienders of animals from 
 his inveterate love of hunting ; or, again, as British sportsmen, 
 from his methods of snaring hares ; or, on general grounds, from 
 this, that, or the other limitation of his horizon, we may still to 
 ourselves seem to see how this partial view and these arrifrtf 
 tenets were natural and appropriate to him. 
 
 Neither impelled by any prejudice as ag'ainst any past phase 
 of humanity, nor furnished with any critical apparatus of art, or 
 philosophy, or religion, by which to bind or loose the men of 
 old, we may take an acquiescent joy in contemplating the great 
 art products of a world which is past, but, like the scenes of our 
 childhood, still abides closer to us, in a sense, than our present 
 surroundings. Not indeed that such criteria of art, religion, and 
 philosophy as will square with science are wanting. Hegel's, 1 
 for instance, in the well-known passage where he bids us take, 
 as a key to the understanding of Greece, " an insight into the 
 ideal forms of sculpture," instructing us that " the images of 
 statesmen and philosophers, as well as epic and dramatic 
 heroes, must be regarded from the point of view of plastic 
 art, for that is the character of all, actors, poets, thinkers, 
 alike; great and free they have grown up on the soil of 
 their own individuality, creating themselves out of them- 
 selves, and moulding themselves to what they were and willed 
 to be. The age of Perikles is specially rich in them. Perikles 
 himself, Phidias, Plato, above all Sophocles : Thucydides also, 
 Xenophon and Socrates, each in his own department : none 
 greater or less than another : ideal artists of themselves ; cast 
 in flawless mould : works of art which stand before us as an 
 immortal presentment of the gods." Such is the sentence of 
 
 1 Hegel, JEsthetik, 3. 2. 3, translated in Pater's Studies in the History of the 
 Renaissance, pp. 192, 193, Winckelmann.
 
 XENOPHON. 
 
 art, a sentence of salvation and security against the finger of 
 corruption and temporal decay, wherewith the verdict also of 
 Religion and Philosophy accords. " But the souls of the right- 
 eous are in the hand of God. There shall no torment touch 
 them. But they are in peace." 
 
 " Then all this earthly grossness quit, 
 Attired with stars, we shall for ever sit, 
 
 Triumphing over Death, and Chance, and thee, Time." 
 
 To the profound antique philosophy the modern deep makes 
 answer, "Notre nature a besoin d'etre epuree par la mort, pour quo 
 ses meilleurs attributs puissent assez ressortir en surmontant les 
 grossieres necessites qui d'abord les dominent. C'est uniquenient 
 ainsi que pent s'accomplir la sublime inversion oii tend 1'anima- 
 lite ;" while to narrow-souled censure of ever-shifting Sittlicli- 
 Jceiten the old rebuke suffices: &io dva7ro\6jrjTo^ el, w avOpwrre 7ra<? 
 6 Kpivwv. Let Xenophon and the rest be judged by their own 
 a-vvelBtjcr^, not by another, alien to ourselves and everything 
 except the particular historical instant, or temporary moral need, 
 from which it was abstracted for illegitimate and unseasonable 
 application elsewhere. Let us not do this ; which is to do 
 violence to the historic sense, and in so far to dull the best 
 and most precious gift of progressive humanity. 1 Lastly, the 
 attitude here pleaded for is not more in agreement with the 
 spirit of art and religion than consonant with the scientific 
 movement of the day. If in one sense the GraBCO-Rornan world 
 seems less important to us than to the humanists of the Renais- 
 sance ; " if the first enthusiasm for antiquity shall never be 
 restored, nor trie classics yield that vital nourishment they 
 offered in the spring-time of the modern era," 2 still there is a 
 charm in the lengthening shadows ; or, more truly, we seem to 
 be cresting to-day the last high-tidal waves of a rediscovery, 
 which confronts us face to face with the very soul of past 
 humanity, and scientifically we are nearer than when we en- 
 thusiastically believed. To trie half-appeased hunger of a 
 passionate curiosity it is as if their secret would soon be out, 
 and we should know them ' even as we are known.' 
 
 1 An intelligent respect for the Sittlichkeiten of the moment, past and 
 present, seems essential for the preservation of the spiritual continuity no 
 less than the solidarity of our race. 
 
 8 Symonds, Revival of Learniny, p. 539.
 
 336 XENOPHON. 
 
 But, for the present, the question of the a-vveiSrjais of the 
 Socratic age of Greece claims our attention : What was the re- 
 lation of Xenophon to his era ? It does not concern us whether 
 his birth falls about the date of the thirty years' truce (445 B.C.), 
 or only somewhere near the commencement of the Pelopon- 
 nesian war (in 431 B.C.) ; nor again is the actual date of his death, 
 between 359 1 and 355, or 354 B.C. in all probability, of any serious 
 importance. In any case we shall be right in regarding the 
 adult Xenophon as a representative pre-eminently of the period 
 from 411 (at which point he takes up the History of Thucydides) 
 to 359, the first year of Philip of Macedon. Thanks to the 
 genius and " good fortune " of the Athenian people, it was not 
 possible or conceivable that this century of time should pass 
 unchronicled. Hence it is that Thucydides appears as the his- 
 torian of the great war; and when his voice is hushed, a most vocal 
 witness and participator of the subsequent events presents him- 
 self in the person of Xenophon. It is thus that we also assist 
 at the uncoiling, as it were, of two mighty lengths of Hellenic 
 history : the thread of the first being the conflict between 
 Athens and Sparta, fully unwound at the ^king of Athens by 
 Lysander (in 404) ; the second representing the struggle for hege- 
 mony between Sparta and the rival powers, with the momentary 
 supremacy of Thebes and the apotheosis of Epaminondas at 
 Mantinea, which form the last links of a chain of closely 
 connected incident. 
 
 Of this later period Xenophon is at once the mouth- 
 piece and a product. In him we have a witness whose 
 combined qualities as a thinker, writer, and man of action 
 make him, even where he is defective or incomplete in his 
 character and views of existence, pre-eminently representative. 
 Briefly stated, what we find is that certain features of an inter- 
 esting time are in this individual written large, so that he 
 who runs may read ; though others doubtless are less apparent 
 or altogether absent. What then are these characteristic 
 features, " the signs of the times " ? 
 
 1 The assassination of Alexander of Pherae, mentioned by Xenophon, Hellen. 
 vi. 4. 35-37, took place between 359 B.C. and 357 B.C. The date of the irepl 
 Trpoffbdwv, or cle Seditibus (if correctly ascribed to Xenophon), extends the 
 life of its author four or five years longer than the earlier of these two dates.
 
 XENOPHON. 337 
 
 In the spiritual world they are the emergence of " sub- 
 jectivity," of self-examination and self-expression of all sorts, 
 the awakening of self-consciousness, the earnest application 
 to one's-self and others of the Delphic injunction TvwOi, 
 creavrov with a view to self-culture, which is an epitome 
 of the Socratic method, the spiritually -minded sophistry. 
 Parallel with this is the development of dialectic, the art 
 of words and of conduct, the sharpening of the instrument 
 of mind, and the working up of the raw material of subtle 
 thought as a power in itself, to be wielded irrespectively of the 
 moral guidance of the lVo/09, and the limited requirements of the 
 public weal, but so as to suit the taste and exigencies of the 
 thought-emancipated individual with a view to personal success, 
 which is an epitome of the carnally -minded sophistry. " The pre- 
 Socratic thinkers," it has been said, 1 " from Thales downwards, 
 were all primarily devoted to ontological research, but by the 
 middle of the fifth century B.C. the clash and conflict of their 
 dogmatic 2 systems had led some of the keenest minds to doubt the 
 possibility of penetrating the secret of the universe. This doubt 
 found expression in the reasoned scepticism of Gorgias, and pro- 
 duced the famous doctrine of Protagoras, that the human appre- 
 hension is the only standard of what is and what is not. A 
 similar view of the natural limits of the human intellect repelled 
 the philosophic ardour of Socrates from physico-metaphysical 
 inquiries." Again the same writer says, " This emergence of an 
 art of conduct with professional teachers cannot thoroughly be 
 understood, unless it is viewed as a crowning result of a general 
 tendency at this stage of Greek civilisation to substitute 
 technical skill for traditional procedure and empirically de- 
 veloped faculty. In the age of the Sophists we find, wherever 
 we turn, the same eager pursuit of knowledge and the same 
 eager effort to apply it directly to practice. The method of 
 earth-measurement was rapidly becoming a science ; the astro- 
 
 1 Ethics, Encyc. Metrop. pp. 576-7, but I think the writer of the article him- 
 self would state the matter differently. The antithesis might be put thus : In 
 one aspect, an age of Doubt, of emancipation of the questioning subject from 
 Tradition and Custom. In another, an age of Faith, of belief in the largest 
 possibilities of Art, Science, Method. This last is Mr. Sidgwick's point. 
 
 2 Cf. Xen. Mem. I 1. 14. 
 
 Y
 
 538 XENOPHOX. 
 
 nomy of Meton was introducing precision into the computation 
 of time ; Hippodamus was revolutionising architecture by 
 building towns with straight broad streets ; old-fashioned 
 soldiers were grumbling at the new pedantries of tactics 
 and ' hoplitics ; ' the art of music had recently received a 
 great technical development ; and a still greater change had 
 been effected in that training of the body which constituted 
 the other half of ordinary Greek education. If bodily vigour 
 was no longer to be left to nature and spontaneous exercise, but 
 was to be attained by the systematic observance of rules laid 
 down by professional trainers, it was natural to think that the 
 same might be the case with mental excellences." Briefly, this 
 was an age stamped, as we might say, ' internationally,' with the 
 conflict or contrast of rival vopoi, of ' creeds ' and national 
 political theories ; in private life, with the escape from VO/AOS 
 of the individual, with ' atheism,' as it was called, in the wake 
 of physics. 1 
 
 In the world of politics, the ' signs of the times ' are the red 
 and lowering clouds which betoken a new and turbulent 
 day. These are, the accentuated antithesis of stable (or rela- 
 tively stable) rule, and the liberty of anarchic minorities or 
 majorities. At Athens are to be seen the confronting idols 
 of Laconism and the Demos ; at Thebes, of autonomy and pan- 
 Bceotarchy ; in Peloponnese there are symptoms of anti- 
 Spartan Argolism ; 2 north of the isthmus, of embryo empires 
 in Thessaly or Thrace. Everywhere miso-Persian Hellenism is 
 confronted with the incompatible desire for hegemony, only to 
 be obtained at the price of Persian assistance ; everywhere, also, 
 the hand of the ISuorrj^ is against the hand of the TroXi'r^, or that 
 
 1 Physics = a sort of physico-metaphysical philosophy, running inevitably 
 counter to theology, or possibly theoseby, "theology and even religious feeling. " 
 [Cf. Aristoph. Clouds, 380. Not God, but Vortex reigns, according to Anaxa- 
 goras.] It is true, physical science, in the stricter sense, was silently working 
 in the direction of real discovery, and, as the Comtists say, encyclopaedic 
 knowledge. Not to speak of numerical and geometrical conceptions carried 
 up to the point of their application to astronomy, to Thales and Democritus 
 are already due the sphericity of the earth and the " atomic " theory. Hip- 
 pocrates also should be coupled with Meton and Hippodamus. 
 
 4 Hellen. iv. 8. 34, ttrei y&p ol'Apyewi TI\V K6piJ>Oov"Apyo^ tTreirolijvTo, K.T.\. ; 
 cf. ibid. v. 2. 6.
 
 of the State against society ; : everywhere there is a bourgeoning 
 of ranhellenic vitality at the expense of (state) patriotism. 
 
 Of some of these propensities, the evidence of a disjointed 
 world, Xeuophon is either the victim or the scarcely unwilling 
 tool, of others he is the censor and the antagonist, and in all cases 
 (consciously or unconsciously) the exponent and interpreter; 
 while (which is only tantamount to realising the completeness of 
 his assimilation) through good report and evil report his voice is 
 not only a witness to the present but a prediction of the future. 
 To quite a startling extent, perhaps only in a chance word or a 
 cherished aspiration, we discover in him an earnest of things 
 which are yet to lie. For if the political world was out of joint, 
 he that was destined to set it for a season right was nigh at hand ; 
 if, in a deeper sense also, the age itself was travailing and heavy- 
 laden, the times of refreshing were not far distant ; nor was their 
 labour destined to be in vain, but rather rich with the fruitage 
 of intellectual achievement ; of the consummation and world- 
 wide diffusion of the gifts of Hellenism. The era of Aristotle and 
 of Alexander was speedily approaching. Under this head Xeno- 
 phon is wonderfully typical. As a man of action, and personally 
 mixed up with the incidents of the day, and tossed on a sea of 
 political troubles, he is individually and conjointly with others 
 of a kindred spirit (as Alcibiades perhaps, certainly Agesilaus 2 
 and Jason of Pherae 3 ), anticipative of Alexander the Great. As 
 a thinker he is symptomatic of the approach of Aristotle. 4 As 
 a stylist and part-inventor of the KOivrj Stake/cros, he is one of 
 the fountain-heads of the great common literature of the Eastern 
 empire, the lineal ancestor of the Septuagint, of Lucian, and 
 perhaps of the best style of modern Greek to-day. 
 
 1 Not unfrequently. Of. the two famous occasions on which Socrates found 
 himself in isolated opposition to the government of the day, Mem. i. 1. 18 ; 
 iv. 4. 3 ; Hellen. ii. 3. 39, and, generally speaking, many an emigre doubtless 
 was the victim of State oppression. Cf. Hellen. v. 4. 2. 
 
 - Hellen. iv. 2. 3. 3 Ibid. vi. 1. 12. 
 
 4 Xenophon, the crowds or <ro(pi<TT7)s, seems to some extent to have anticipated, 
 from a common-sense point of view, the Ethics of Aristotle ; while, as a 
 prirwp, and author of such treatises as the Polity of the Lacedaemonians, he 
 foreshadows the Politics. This view might be pushed further in reference 
 to the more technical treatises on Hunting, Horsemanship, etc. But in the 
 pamphlet on Revenues, or the panegyric of Agesilaus, the reader's thought is 
 carried forward no further than Isocrates. In other ways also he is an dppafiuv 
 
 T7JS K\1)pOVO/J.ia.S.
 
 340 XENOPHON. 
 
 Nor, if we now turn to the second question raised 
 above, and ask ourselves, What is the closest bond of intimacy 
 between us ? what is there common to our mental and 
 spiritual horizon and that of Xenophon ? shall we find him 
 barren or devoid of interest. Indeed, that we have one such 
 link of connection of a firm sort will appear obvious to him 
 who recognises that the underlying personal quality of the man, 
 the primitive substratum of his character, is nothing more nor 
 less than his piety and devotion (TO eucreySe? and 6eoa-e8ei.a). 
 His motto, many times repeated, and oftener implied, is not to 
 be mistaken : 2vv rofr eols iravro^ apxeatfcu epyov (Ask the 
 blessing of Heaven upon all thy purposes) is the daily and 
 hourly watchword of his soul. 1 It is true that this Seto-iSat- 
 fjiovia? is a quality not peculiar to Xenophon, but one which he 
 holds largely in common with his fellow-countrymen ; which 
 endears the Hellenic world to us, and the existence of which 
 it would be foolish in us to ignore. Possibly, in the case 
 of Xenophon, his natural piety was refined and even crystal- 
 lised in what we must call his second nature, as a loyal 
 " listener " to Socrates. But if the " theoseby " of the 
 natural man brings him close to us on grounds of common 
 humanity and common needs, so also is Xenophon ' after the 
 (Socratic) spirit' welcome as a personal friend, on grounds 
 of transmitted inherited philosophy. Without here entering 
 into the question of supposed metaphysical or philosophic 
 deficiencies, it is clear that the disciple was largely appre- 
 ciative of the master's ethical stand-point ; neither blind to 
 his originality as " the inventor of morals," nor throughout a 
 long life forgetful of the painstaking self-command and improve- 
 ment which was the practical side of the teaching which he 
 reverenced. But (1) Evo-efieia is a quality suited to all times, 
 and not less interwoven with the texture of humanity to-day 
 than with the life of ancient Hellas ; in spite of many external 
 and some intrinsic differences in the attempt to deal with that 
 most real world beyond, which, with all reverence, we formulate 
 as GOD. Also, (2) at the basis of our own popular or quasi- 
 
 1 Cf. Agesilaus, i. 27. 
 
 2 Acts xvii. 22, and Mr. Kuskin's comment on the mistranslation in his pre- 
 face to The Economist of Xenophon in the B ibl. Pastorum, vol. i. p. xxv.
 
 XENOPHON. 341 
 
 philosophic moral theology lies the "teleology" of Socrates. 1 
 To this twofold extent Xenophon appears as the clear-toned 
 e&jyrjTris of his times and not of his times only, but in some 
 sense also of Hellas as a whole. 
 
 Of this general thesis we may find ample illustration, either 
 in the main characteristics of his writings, however rapidly sur- 
 veyed, or by direct handling of the matter in answer to the ques- 
 tion, What are the various personal or professional, philosophical 
 or literary, qualities of the author ? Let us then, in pursuance 
 of such an object, review these various qualities. Those which 
 we call personal would seem to depend chiefly on a certain 
 healthiness of body and brain (eve%ia) ; original probably, and 
 emphasised by the regular gymnastic of the city, which we 
 are aware was indorsed by Socrates. 2 Tradition tells us that 
 Xenophon was Ka\os and eve^ecrraro^, and conjecture adds that 
 he must have possessed great bodily strength and endurance. 
 Indeed, with the exception of his piety and affectionate remem- 
 brance of Socrates, nothing is more pronounced in him than his 
 devotion to jv^vacrrLKt] : field-sports and field-work, being a sort 
 of duty to one's-self and to the State, so <that the bodily frame 
 may be inured " by toils and sweat " to the more serious busi- 
 ness of life and war. " Agriculture, devotion to the tillage of 
 the soil, has this high praise, that it implies a training of the 
 limbs till they are capable of performing everything that a free- 
 man should. Though earth gives of her abundance, yet her 
 blessings are not showered on the lap of laziness ; but in hus- 
 bandry she inures her servitors to suffer gladly summer's heat 
 and winter's cold. Those that labour with their very hands, 
 the actual delvers of the soil, she trains in a wrestling ground 
 of her own, giving them strength for strength ; while those 
 others whose devotion is confined to the overseeing eye and to 
 studious thought she makes more manly, rousing them with 
 
 1 The distinctive teaching of our Lord, taken in the deepest modern sense, 
 as the gospel of human fraternity and love, being either ignored or non- 
 assimilated (cf. the unchristian acceptance of much needless war) ; and re- 
 garded practically as a quite separate inner and independent principle of 
 action, or else added as the graceful coping-stone and crown of the pagan 
 morality of Greece and Rome. 
 
 2 Cf. Mem. iii. xii. ; also Socrates' humorous defence of dancing, Symp. 
 ii. 15-18.
 
 342 XENOPHOX. 
 
 the crowing of the cock, and compelling them to be up and 
 doing betimes in many a long day's march." 1 In these and 
 similar passages the scent of the morning air is so keen and in- 
 vigorating, and the play of the limbs so joyous and godlike, 
 that we catch the hunter's or the husbandman's enthusiasm ; 
 riding with Ischomachus cross country over his estates, or 
 running a novel ' lampadephoria ' with the soldiers after wild 
 asses in the desert of Arabia; or coursing hares and shouting to 
 the dogs with the old Athenian Emigre and his sons and friends 
 on the farm at Skillus ; or now with Astyages, smiling a proud 
 smile at sight of his grandson, about fifteen years old, and 
 allowed, after much supplication, to hunt large game for the 
 first time. "The heart of the old man was overjoyed to see his 
 grandson, unable to keep silence in the excess of his delight, 
 but ' baying ' with excitement like a well-bred whelp whenever 
 he came to close quarters with a beast, and shouting to his 
 fellows by name." But the fullest gospel of 'Ty/em, or Eue^'a 
 is to be found in the treatise on hunting, in the prefatory chapter, 
 and again later near the siispected attack on the Sophists : " My 
 word of exhortation to the young is : do not despise hunting or 
 the other training of your boyhood, if you desire to grow r up to 
 be good men good not only in war, but in all else of which 
 the issue is perfection in thought, word, and deed." " Those 
 that make this their passionate pursuit will reap their reward 
 in the health which will accrue to their bodily frames the 
 quickening of the eye and the ear the postponement of old 
 age ; not to speak of the warlike training w r hich is given, so 
 that long marches under arms will seem mere child's play." 
 This bodily training is, in fact, the keystone to Xenophon's 
 theory of education. He seems to have said to himself : " Here 
 is the one great pleasure which is harmless in itself ; whereas 
 all the other rival pleasures, either in themselves or incidentally, 
 may become ruinous to health of body and soul ; but this is 
 innocuous, and in its consequences most useful, as a training in 
 virtue and good habit." These warning voices to the young 
 have a genial cheery ring in them, like the voice of the Aiicalos 
 ^6709 in Aristophanes, 2 expounding to us the old theory of 
 
 1 Oecon. v. 4. 
 
 2 Arist. Clouds, 961, etc., and cf. Symonds, Greek Poets, vol. i. p. 280.
 
 XENOPHON. 343 
 
 
 education in that blissful time " when he flourished, and 
 modesty and temperance were practised : " " If you do what I 
 tell you, and apply your mind moreover, you will have big 
 brawny shoulders and a polished chest, with the fair white 
 complexion of health." Indeed, taken in cxtcnso, the Xeno- ; 
 phontine passage reads much like a prose version of the Aristo- 
 phanic moral. If we are also curiously reminded of educational 
 doctrines in vogue in our own particular polity of modern 
 Europe, that is only another instance of what may be called a 
 modern element in our author, which seems to make us, even in 
 education, more akin to the ancients than we might suppose. 1 
 
 Even while we confine our attention to this matter of health 
 and educational training, two other traits silently obtrude 
 themselves, and may conveniently be dealt with at this point. 
 In the first place, there is the amiable air of didactic teaching, 
 which we should now-a-days call " moralising" a touch of the 
 doctrinaire, short of pedantry certainly, and dulness, but still 
 noticeable and truly Xenophontine. The minor works on 
 hunting and horsemanship are full of this, as also is the Cavalry 
 General's Manual (a work which the inferential biographer 
 shall be allowed to consider as addressed by the old philosopher 
 soldier in his declining years to his son Gryllus, the same who 
 fought in the Athenian squadron at Mantinea, and fell face to 
 face with Epaminondas). In these it was natural perhaps to 
 fall into a didactic vein, and to speak as one of ' those who 
 know.' But the opening paragraphs of the Cyropaedia, and 
 other passages interspersed in the larger and probably more 
 youthful compositions, testify to the same propensity. We 
 seem at times to be listening to a sweet- tongued talker, a wise 
 man and a good, whose style reminds us of the Vicar of Wake- 
 field. In spite of his sage talk he presents to us the appearance 
 
 1 It is interesting to compare the elaborate Spartan education, with its proud 
 motto, rtf raireivoi elvai neyaXtivovrai (Lac Pol. viii. 2): " The Spartans mani- 
 fest a lordly pride in submissiveness : " vide M tiller's Dorians, vol. ii. p. 309. 
 " During the progress from the condition of an ephebus to manhood, the 
 young Spartans were called Sphaereis, probably because their chief exercise was 
 football, which game was carried on with great emulation, and indeed 
 resembled a battle rather than a diversion. In their nineteenth year they 
 were sent out on the crypteia, " etc. To such training, as tradition tells us, 
 were the sons of Xenophon submitted.
 
 XENOPHON. 
 
 of a practical man who has seen men and manners, and tasted 
 wisdom at the fountain-head. Nothing is pleasanter than to 
 sit by and listen to his reflections somewhat loosely and yet 
 pretentiously delivered. 
 
 The other something referred to is easier to feel than to define 
 in words, yet it is absolutely Xenophontine ; being neither 
 more nor less than the consciousness of the man himself his 
 personalism or individualism, or by whatever name we are to 
 name it, which probably owes its origin to the general subjec- 
 tivity of the age, in the spirit of which he so largely shares ; to 
 the Socratic training and the lessons in self-knowledge which that 
 implied when faithfully carried out. It is a self-consciousness, 
 enhanced conceivably in this case by the isolation of exile, and 
 the sharp differentiation of the personal against the impersonal 
 element within ; as if the ISuoTrjs rose in judgment against the 
 TroXtTT??, and the TroTu'r^ against the tSwiyny?, and the one self 
 accused or else excused the other, with the result at last of a 
 novel and, for a Greek, curiously modern egoism. 1 Hence these 
 phrases : e^ol pev Boicel " I should say," or " if you ask my 
 opinion," or " my observation tells me;" and these first personal 
 beginnings, iJKovaa &e TTOTG ol8a [Jiev, on, 7roAA,a/a? edavftaaa ; 
 or the personal pronouns anticipative of the pleonastic usage of 
 a later day, which again give a modern feeling to this subjective 
 artist. Connected with this is a higher personal quality, or, in 
 other words, the same quality when brought into grander rela- 
 tions with the world beyond man's control and knowledge 
 " the region of obscurity, the home of things about which we 
 cannot say whether they will turn out thus or otherwise ; which 
 really includes the most important elements even of things 
 that lie within the circumscribed region of our own knowledge 
 and activity; where we are bound to reflect and exert our- 
 selves without superstitiously turning for querulous help to 
 heaven." 2 
 
 1 The naivete of the egoism of Herodotus is childlike, suggestive of wonder- 
 ment at once and a desire to speak the truth : that of Xenophon has a 
 touching parental gravity. 
 
 2 Mem. i. 8. Doubtless the &dr)\a STTWS d.7ro/3i7<rercu here are things mundane 
 and practical ; but Xenophou would almost have applied the term to the 
 larger issues of life, and the general government of the world.
 
 XEXOPHOX. 
 
 This, which the hearer has shown us to have been his 
 teacher's creed, was certainly his own also ; and no heart can 
 fail to be touched by the utterance of so genuine a faith, as 
 profound as it is simple, in which he lias chronicled their com- 
 mon conduct as a self-annihilating trust in the goodness of 
 God. " He prayed to the gods simply to give him what was 
 good for him ; for they know best what good things are." 
 " To pray for gold and silver or a despotism is no better than 
 to make a particular throw at dice or a battle the subject of 
 prayer, when no man can prophesy what the consequences of one 
 or other will be." 1 Here indeed we have reached the most central 
 and vital thing in all Xenophon, his devoutness or holiness ; it 
 cannot help bringing him close to us, and otherwise doubtless 
 has a direct bearing upon ourselves. But as it would be a 
 mistake to exaggerate the matter in his favour, as if he only 
 and Socrates, 2 and a few other exceptional specimens of that 
 people, were capable of pure and lofty religious feelings, so also 
 we ought not to overlook something which is original and 
 idiosyncratic in the 'religiosity' of this particular follower of 
 the unique teacher. It is, to begin with, to some extent an 
 accident that we hear so much of piety ; that devotion is so 
 prominent a virtue on his lips devotion especially as shown 
 in prayer and pavTitcrj. Why, for instance, is no light thrown 
 on that other large department of Greek religious feeling which 
 found satisfaction in the Mysteries ? The explanation of this 
 outspokenness in particular directions, this insistance on the 
 necessity of prayer, etc., seems to be that the moment required 
 it. We gather our views largely from The Recollections of 
 Socrates, a work written under certain self-imposed limitations 
 in a truthful, loving, but ' apologetic ' strain, and for a 
 distinct object, viz., to set his ' master's ' reputation right in 
 the eyes of the Athenian people. Now an indictment against 
 his friend was, that he refused to acknowledge and believe in 
 
 1 Mem. i. 3. 2. 
 
 2 The commentators compare the poet's prayer in Plato, Alcib. ii. 143 A : 
 
 ZeO f$affi\eu, ret (j.tv teffXa Kal evxpfttvois Kal dcev/crotj 
 
 " Afifu Sldov, ra 8 dfiva Kal evxo/J.tvois airaX^eiv. 
 
 ' ' King Zeus, grant to us all blessings, whether we pray for them or not, 
 and deliver us from evil, even to the denial of our prayers. "
 
 346 XENOPHOX. 
 
 the gods of the state, preferring to introduce new divinities of 
 his own. These charges were contrary to the patent everyday 
 witness of the philosopher's life, who came not to destroy but 
 to fulfil, and was particularly punctual and conservative in all 
 acts of worship in prayer and sacrifice in what may with 
 reverence be called the machinery of daily worship ; while as 
 to the introduction of new divinities, if by these ^aiyuovia was 
 meant the divine whisper, which checked or propelled his 
 ' master's ' action, was not that simply a form of /jiavnKr] like 
 any other admonition howsoever vouchsafed to man from 
 heaven, whether by flight of birds, or a voice heard, or a sound 
 uttered, or something crossing the path ? 
 
 But with regard to the Mysteries, whatever w r e are to think 
 of them in our present imperfect knowledge, we must hold that 
 they were not " generally necessary to salvation : " we may 
 indeed speculate as to whether they were the relics of some 
 primitive worship " ancient foreign rudiments containing no 
 greater wisdom than already existed in the consciousness of 
 the Greeks " which is Hegel's view, 1 and introduces his re- 
 mark that " all Athenians were initiated in the Mysteries 
 Socrates excepted, who refused initiation, because he knew 
 well that science and art are not the product of mysteries ; 
 that wisdom never lies among arcana." Or, our opinion may 
 incline us to believe with others that, even so, there was 
 a deep underlying meaning in the scenic representation of 
 old Chthonian creeds, calculated to work powerfully upon 
 the spiritual emotions of the beholder : some steeping in the 
 blackest gloom of a night of sorrow and bereavement sud- 
 denly, in the twinkling of an eye, relieved by an inrush of 
 light and joy and rejuvenescence; the renewing, with the 
 passion of early spring, of wintry weeds outworn. In any 
 case, this side of the religious life of their times is not divulged 
 to us by either Plato or Xenophon. So far as the age of Peri- 
 cles goes, the least faint echo of what it betokened is to be 
 got from the parody of Aristophanes in the Frogs ; while the 
 deep implication of religious feeling in the name is sufficiently 
 
 1 Hegel's PJiil. of Hist., Engl. transl. p. 248, also 257, 258 ; compare 
 Hausrath, Neutest. Zeityesch., Die Mysterien, p. 68, etc.
 
 XENOPHON. 347 
 
 attested by the description in Thucydides of the mutilation of 
 the Hermae. 1 
 
 It also appears that apart from 'apologetically' explaining 
 the tenets of Socrates, Xenophon a man of culture as well 
 as of action was satisfied to follow that leading ; holding 
 
 o / O 
 
 the hand of his guide with confidence, and following in 
 
 O O 
 
 his path, hand passibus acquis. In illustration of which 
 there is the famous story of his going against the wise 
 elder friend's advice to his cost in the matter of accepting 
 Proxenus's invitation to join Cyrus. 2 The sage has an instinct 
 (possibly the voice of the Sat^oviov] that no good will come 
 of this, but he advises his associate to ask the will of God at 
 Delphi. From whatever cause, Xenophon asks, not " Shall I 
 go?" but " To which god should I sacrifice on this journey?" 
 The answer is given accordingly : but the rebuke of Socrates is 
 too late now : and there is nothing for it but to do as the 
 oracle has said and go. In the Recollections Xenophon 3 tells 
 us "that so strong a faith had Socrates in the intimations 
 vouchsafed to him by heaven, that without a moment's appre- 
 hension of writing himself down ' fool or impostor,' he would 
 freely, and on the authority of the divine voice alone, tender 
 advice to his friends to do this, or to abstain from doing that ; 
 and so with those who followed his injunctions it went well, 
 while those who lent a deaf ear lived to repent of their obsti- 
 nacy." Thus it requires all the childlike religious trust, recon- 
 ciling contraries, on the part of Xenophon, to discover how in 
 the end after the pains and perplexities of the advance and 
 retreat the w r ays of God were finally justified, and the 
 promised help of Zeus, whose name is kindness, literally 
 fulfilled. This touch of superstition in him has Xenophon by 
 comparison with the pure faith of Socrates. But <rvv Oeols 
 TrpaTTeiv, trust in heaven, has become to him so emphatically 
 a part of his theory of life and practice, that in one of the works, 
 probably of his old age, the Hipparchicos, he touchingly apolo- 
 gises for the reiteration of the phrase in such a context ; not as 
 though he used it as a mere phrase, but as an English colonel 
 
 1 Thuc. vi. 28. 1, KO.I T& fj.vffT-ripia Upa. u.-s Trotetrai tv oMcur Ifi Cftpfi. 
 
 2 A nab. iii. 1. 4-8. 3 Mem. i. 1.
 
 348 XENOPHOX. 
 
 might apologise, so to speak, for some custom in his regiment of 
 prayer-meetings or reading of the Bible : " If the repetition of 
 the phrase throughout this treatise, ' act \vith God,' surprises 
 any one, he may take my word for it, that with the daily or 
 hourly recurrence of perils which must betide him, his wonder- 
 ment will diminish ; as also with the clearer recognition of the 
 fact that, in a time of war, the antagonists are full of designs 
 against each other; but the precise issue of these plots and 
 counterplots is rarely known : to what counsellor then can a 
 man apply for advice in his extremity save only to the gods, 
 who know all things, and forewarn whomsoever they list by 
 victims, or by omens, by voice or vision ? And is it not rational 
 to suppose that they will prefer to help in their need, not those 
 who merely seek them in time of momentary stress and trouble, 
 but who in the halcyon days of their prosperity make a practice of 
 rendering to heaven the service of heart and soul?" 1 The senti- 
 ment, it may be retorted, is the sentiment of Christian times, 
 but the means are the measure of a creed that is past : which 
 is so far true that the lepa and r\nai, the olwvol and ovelpara, 
 take us out of ourselves into a pre-scientific world ; but to insist 
 further is neither fair nor rational. The question of the relative 
 value of creeds must be discussed with less prominence given 
 to a machinery commdn to the whole ancient world, Jewish and 
 Gentile alike, and more in reference to the spirit which animates 
 the worshipper ; when the gain will not all be on the side of later 
 times or ' purer ' beliefs. 
 
 To test this matter fairly then, to escape purblindness 
 so as to see clearly into the Xenophontine heart at any 
 rate, we must, without laying sacrilegious hands on our own 
 sacred things, " not to speak it profanely," mentally remove 
 the religious machinery of to-day, our sacramental feasts, 
 our prayer and thanksgivings, our devotional musings ; 
 replacing these by the secret rites of Demeter and lacchos, 
 by all that is comprehended under [Aavritcr), from the roll of 
 thunder, or the dream or chance word of good or evil import, 
 down to the still small voice, not refused to Socrates, which was 
 the oracle of " private judgment," by the public oracles, by 
 
 1 Hipparch. ix. 8, 9.
 
 XENOPHON. 349 
 
 prayer for prayer, by faces veiled in sorrow and beaten breasts 
 in lieu of bent knees and contrite hearts, by lifted Lands and 
 chanted pagans of the Adorante in lieu of jubilates and choral 
 hallelujahs. Some of these cover the same ground, however 
 different in outward appearance or construction ; others point 
 to real chasms between the ancient Hellenic spirit and that 
 which is the breath of our life to-day. But just as in the 
 origin of species, the very progress in and through the 
 continuity may, if we neglect the true links, seem to imply 
 a gap which does not really exist, so here; and what is of 
 equal importance, we may fail to notice the solidarity of the 
 advanced peoples of ancient times as regards the machinery of 
 their worship, however divergent their creeds. It seems the 
 in&anique celeste of the soul of man is the same for long 
 ages together ; and thus in the Acts of the Apostles, 1 when St. 
 Peter is quoting the prophet Joel, the opdcreis, evinrvia, repara, 
 o-rjfjLela all occur in a perfectly rational and natural way, as 
 judged by the common mind of the time. " ^?;/z^ a voice 
 from heaven," " Bath Kol," one calls it ; " An angel spake to 
 him," says another ; " it thundered," to a third ; but thunder in 
 a clear sky that is a word of warning. These strange coinci- 
 dences between the world beyond myself and what is thrill- 
 ing me must be ' symbolic ' of the divine will. 
 
 It is not easy for the scientifically trained mind to go out of 
 itself, reverting to the every-day surroundings, the scenery of a 
 religion that is past. The demarking barrier between then and 
 now (or there and here, this very day) is hard to cross ; yet it 
 is science at least the supreme science which bids this to 
 be done. Nor, even for sympathetic natures, is it easy to revive 
 and realise the diffused condition of religion in a world, or 
 among peoples, in which sanctity is conterminous with existence, 
 and the godhead peers through every cranny of nature : the 
 days when baptisms were not so much a type of the spirit, as 
 literally spiritual ; when every fountain was sacred, and the 
 huntsman is enjoined not to interfere with springs and streams, 
 ra vd/jiara Kal ra peWpa edv, for to meddle with these is ugly 
 and base TO jap airTea-dai TOVTWV ala-'xpov Kal KUKOV : not 
 
 1 Actsii. 16-22.
 
 350 XENOPHON. 
 
 to speak of the bad example of lawlessness set to the be- 
 holder Kal Iva p,r) TW vofJiw evavrioi MCTLV ol t'Soz^re?. 1 Some 
 dim intelligence of these things we may get from the remini- 
 scences of childhood and the natural sacraments of inventive 
 innocence ; when our nurse blessed us if we sneezed ; and we 
 held in secret silence commemorative feasts. Such is the 
 simple-minded, extended religiousness of early days, not subtle 
 indeed nor intense, but more thoroughly permeating every 
 hour and movement of existence religion interbleiit with life. 
 As to Xenophon personally, only a Hellene among Hellenes, 
 a specimen of a particular race, the product of a period interest- 
 ing but transient, we can see that he was doubly conditioned 
 by these circumstances, in the direction of superstition 
 " naturally," in the direction of monotheism through Socratic 
 training, 2 or something infectious in the great searcher's faith. 
 On the other hand, oracles and omens, prayers and fj,avTi/crj 
 generally, are his essentials (for he is at one with the 
 kindly race of man), and his theology revealed to him in the 
 ' cities and tribes of men ' a region of rational common-sense 
 religion, God-fearing in the appointed ways ; but at either limit 
 of this religious world he beheld two " maniacal " extremes 
 here the worshippers of stocks and stones, 3 or again of animals 
 and there those who contrived to pass through life without 
 God or gods at all. Probably he had as little intellectual 
 sympathy with a fetichist or animal- worshipper, a mad Mossy n- 
 oecian 4 turning all customs upside down, as with a civilised 
 non-barbarian atheist like Aristodemus the little, who figures in 
 the memorable conversation with Socrates on the omnipresence 
 of God. But if (and it is an open question only, an inference, 
 in fact) Xenophon was so far narrow in his sympathies, or, as 
 we may say, unscientifically disposed, we must do him the 
 justice to admit that he is also in advance of his times in his 
 theologic views. It is to him we owe the clear appreciation of 
 
 1 Cyn. v. 34. 
 
 2 Cf. Cicero's very interesting criticism, de Nat. Deorum, ii. v. 18. An 
 argument is drawn from the mind in man to establish a directing principle 
 in the universe, rb i]yefj.oviK6v, taken from Plato and the Xenophontine 
 Socrates. 
 
 8 Cf. Mem. i. 1. 14, and i. 4. 19. 4 Vide infra, p. 365.
 
 XENOPHOX. 351 
 
 some of the most important of his master's tenets : his natural 
 theology, his ' teleologic ' proofs of a beneficent Providence, 
 his speculations on immortality. These are not only conveyed in 
 reported conversations of the teacher, but they interpenetrate the 
 writings of the disciple. Once and again we listen to them in the 
 conversations, and they fall in most clear accents from the lips 
 of the dying Cyrus. 1 Xor, once propounded, have they been 
 allowed to die away. We do not compare them with the 
 argument of a later lover of mankind in 1 Corinthians xv., 
 but handed on from age to age through the Stoics, through 
 Plutarch, through Cicero (through the Fathers surely and the 
 schools), we hear a ring of them in the Evidences and sermons 
 of to-day : and of these Socratic " mysteries " the hierophant 
 is Xenophon. 
 
 Let us, however, abandoning " the things concerning the 
 gods," turn and consider the bent of our author's mind towards 
 his fellow-men. His (f)i\av0pa)7rta and his appreciation of human- 
 heartedness in others are remarkable. Here again the words 
 which he applies to Socrates, " that he was perpetually trying 
 to be of service to those with whom he was brought in contact," 
 may with certain restrictions be applied to himself ; for in the 
 main, and in spite of strong political bias, and the prejudices of 
 "a beautiful and good" but still circumscribed nature, he is full 
 of loving-kindness, and of a friendly disposition to his fellow- 
 men, Hellenes and barbarians alike. He bears no spite or 
 grudge against humanity, being devoid, as far as we can dis- 
 cover, of any deep-seated selfishness or arribre pensfo. Of 
 Socrates he says : 2 "If his friends were ever in difficulties, 
 where ignorance was the cause, he tried to heal the trouble by 
 a dose of wisdom ; or where want and poverty were to blame, 
 by lessoning them that they should assist one another as far as 
 in them lay." And of Cyrus, whom he selects to represent the 
 ideal ruler, he says : " In legend and song he is still com- 
 memorated by the Eastern world as of bodily shape most fair to 
 look upon, but in soul so replete with the threefold love of 
 man, of knowledge, and of honour, that there was no toil he 
 would not suffer, or danger incur, to win the praise and admira- 
 
 1 Cyropaed. viii. 7. 17-19. 2 Mem. vii. 7.
 
 352 XENOPHON. 
 
 tioiiof mankind." "\Vith the " philanthropic" type of character, 
 and for true friendship with its duties, the writer has evidently 
 the deepest sympathy and concern ; but his personal possession 
 of the quality is proved rather by the manifest warmth of 
 his affection for many personal friends, etc. It is an admira- 
 tion reaching the point of ' hero-worship ' in the case of 
 Socrates, and perhaps Agesilaus ; but not less genuinely 
 exhibited, after humble human fashion, in the tender panegy- 
 rics or criticisms of Proxenus, his " ancient friend," or of 
 the younger Cyrus. " Among those who were brought into 
 communion with Socrates, and recognised his greatness, all 
 true lovers of virtue still to this day cease not to lament his 
 incomparable loss with the bitterest regret, as for him who, 
 as none else could, helped them in the pursuit of perfection. 
 For iny part, when I think of his qualities . . ." l Part of the 
 brightness of the Anabasis and Hellenica is due to his warm- 
 hearted sympathy with this or that human being ; sometimes 
 a friend and companion, like Teleutias the Spartan admiral, 
 brother of Agesilaus ; 2 sometimes a stranger associate, like 
 Seuthes ; 3 or only some distant hero whose splendidly shining life 
 has caught the historian's attention, and still gleams upon his 
 page, like Pasimachus. 4 But their name is legion. Others are 
 nameless heroes, like the two whose /ca\oKaya6ia and needless 
 sacrifice during the Ptetreat have touched his heart, and whose 
 epitaph he writes : " See, they have died thus, these ' galant- 
 uomini,' and we were not able to remove their bodies or bury 
 them." 5 
 
 It would be safe to conjecture that this generosity of disposi- 
 tion must find vent for itself in all natural and orderly ways ; 
 that the broad-souled philanthropist and staunch friend would 
 also prove, under the right circumstances, a passionate lover 
 husband father ; but for proof we are not left to surmise or 
 even inferential biography or tradition. To the old grammarian 
 Tzetzes, indeed, Themistogenes appears as Shakespeare's Mr. 
 W. H. ; and he regards him as in a special sense " the only 
 
 1 Mem. iv. 8. 11, TUV 5e Zwscpdr^i' yiyvuffK6vT<av ofos fy, K.T.\. 
 
 2 Hellen. iv. 4. 19. s Anab. vii. 6. 43. 
 4 Hellen. iv. 10. 5 Anal. iv. 1. 19.
 
 XENOPHON, 
 
 begetter" of the Analxisis. " As Phidias made statues for the 
 Eleian Pantarces inscribing the name so did Xenophon 
 with regard to his ' Advance of Cyrus' setting a certain name 
 to the work to please him whom he loved." Who can contra- 
 dict this ? A similar tale in Diogenes Laertius 1 contradicts itself. 
 That writer first tells us that Aristippus relates in Book iv. of 
 his treatise irepl 7ra\aia$ rpvffis that Xenophon loved Cleinias, 
 whom he apostrophises thus, vvv <yap ejco KXeiviav r/Siov fj,ev 
 Oewfjiai ?} ToX\a Trdvra ra ev dvOputTrois /ca\d, quoting totidem 
 verbis from a speech of Critobulus, one of the interlocutors in the 
 Symposium, a work which later on he justly assigns to Xeno- 
 phon. To Critobulus (the real lover of Cleinias) the time has 
 come, according to the rules of the after-supper entertainment, 
 to defend as his thesis " that on which I pride myself most is 
 my beauty." This he does in the broadly humorous but still 
 delicately ironic style suited to the occasion and the author, 
 who at will infuses a touch of bombast. " ' It is now my turn, 
 I think, to state to you the grounds on which I pride myself 
 on beauty.' A chorus of voices rejoined, ' Say on.' ' To 
 begin with, if I am not beautiful, as methinks I be, you will 
 bring on your own heads the 'penalty of perjury one and all : 
 for, without waiting to have the oath administered to you, 
 you are always taking the gods to witness that you find me 
 beautiful : and I must needs believe you are you not all 
 honourable men ? If then I be so beautiful, and affect you 
 even as I also am affected by him whose fair face here attracts 
 me, I swear by all the company of heaven, I would not choose 
 the Great King's empire in exchange for what I am, the 
 beauty of the world, the paragon of animals; and at this 
 instant I feast my eyes on Cleinias gladlier than on all other 
 sights which men deem fair. Joyfully will I welcome blind- 
 ness to all else, if but these eyes may still behold him, and 
 him only. With sleep and night I am sore vexed, which rob 
 me of his sight, but to daylight and the sun I owe eternal 
 thanks, for they restore him to me, my heart's joy, Cleinias.' " 
 Unauthentic, as that of Tzetzes was apocryphal, this tale 
 proves nothing which we did not perceive already. Xeno- 
 
 1 Diog. Laert. Xenophon. 
 2
 
 354 XENOPHON. 
 
 phon, like Socrates, understood the influence of the masculine 
 epaxt. This to him is the highest type of passionate affec- 
 tion. 1 Nor need we further witness than his own words to put 
 us at the right point of view with regard to him : " The men 
 of old, Achilles, Heracles, and the rest, learnt at the feet of 
 the Centaur Cheiron many a noble art, and they began with 
 the chase. From these they attained to great virtue, and 
 became men of renown, and are admired even to this day for 
 their goodness, goodness, who numbers all men as her lovers, 
 as is very plain ; only, because of the pains they must take to 
 win her many fall away, for the achievement of her is hid 
 in obscurity, but the pains that cleave to her are manifest. 
 Perchance, if only she were endowed with a visible bodily 
 frame, men would less have neglected her, knowing that even as 
 she is visible to them, so they also are not hid from her eyes. 
 For is it not so, that when a man moves in the presence of him 
 whom he dearly loves, he rises to a height above himself, 
 being incapable of aught base or foul, in word or deed, in sight 
 of him ? but, fondly dreaming that the eye of virtue is closed 
 to them, they are guilty of many a base thing and foul before 
 her very face, who is hidden from their eyes. Yet she is pre- 
 sent everywhere, being dowered with immortality ; and those 
 who are perfect in goodness she honours, but the wicked 
 she thrusts aside from honour. If only men could know that 
 she regards them, how eagerly would they rush to the embrace 
 of toilful training and tribulation, by which alone she is hardly 
 taken; and so should they gain the mastery over her, and she 
 should be laid captive at their feet." 
 
 More striking perhaps, as being possibly more exceptional, is 
 his guardedness. He is so fully aware of the danger which 
 lurks in the things of 'A<j>po8lrrj and epcos that his mature creed 
 is almost puritanic. Unconscious carelessness, followed by 
 a storm of personal struggles to end in eventual calm, may pos- 
 sibly be pointed at in the biographic passage of the Recollections, 
 apropos of the same Critobulus and Cleinias : 2 " A touch of the 
 lips " in certain temperaments may be " the poisonous bite of 
 the tarantula ; nay, this creature is less deadly, for it must cling 
 
 1 Cyn. xii. 18-21. 2 Mem. i. 3. 8-14.
 
 XENOPHON. 355 
 
 to its victim in order to inject its poison ; but do you not know 
 that this wild beast which men call beauty is so much more 
 terrible than the tarantula, that, by a mere glance, it will 
 inject something into you yards away which will drive you 
 mad ? . . . My advice to you, Xenophon, is, ' Whenever you set 
 eyes on any fair face or form, to run helter-skelter without 
 casting a glance behind you ;' and to you, Critobulus, my 
 advice is, ' Go abroad for a year; so long will it take you to be 
 healed of this wound.' " " Such," adds the biographer, " in the 
 affairs of Aphrodite, should be the attitude of those who do not 
 stand firm as a rock." But perhaps Xenophon was not more 
 distinguished from other Hellenes of this date in this than in 
 the kindred subject of intersexual or domestic relations, and the 
 state of marriage. The dignity of the wife, the education of 
 women, the humane treatment of slaves, are matters in which 
 he is for some reason (perhaps the Socratic self-discipline of 
 a naturally philanthropic disposition) in advance of his com- 
 peers ; or, if that seems too partial a statement, to his art of 
 words, at any rate, we owe the revelation of the most pleasing 
 pictures of inner life and manage in contrast with that of the 
 reigning beauty of the day ; and to the same gift we owe a series 
 of portraits of great women, which, for truth of delineation and 
 inventiveness of design, would alone mark this writer as a great 
 artist of a noble school of realism. 
 
 In reference to tenderness and the topic now before us, it is 
 sufficient to record an interview of Socrates with Theodote 1 in 
 the Recollections, and to compare it with the conversation be- 
 tween Ischomachus, an Athenian country gentleman, and his 
 young wife, in the Economist. Theodote is probably painted 
 from life, and nothing certainly could be more life-like, while 
 round all objects, and the persons present with the two that are 
 speaking, and the words and manner of their speech, plays a 
 delicate air of Hellenic grace, and the irony of Socrates stings 
 innocuously; so that he also who, to-day, has surreptitiously 
 listened, departs wiser and more tender-hearted than when he 
 entered. Perhaps it is base to unveil a portion of so charm- 
 ing a scene. The lady says, at last : " ' Oh ! why, Socrates, 
 
 1 Mem. iii. 11. 1.
 
 356 XENOPHON. 
 
 why are you not at my side (like the huntsman's assistant) to 
 help me snare my friends and lovers ?' ' That will I be/ he 
 answered, ' if only you can woo and win me.' ' How shall I woo 
 and win you?' she asked. ' Seek and you will find means, if 
 you truly need me.' ' Then come and visit me often/ she said. 
 And Socrates, poking sly fun at his own lack of business occu- 
 pation, answered, ' Nay, Theodote, leisure is not a commodity in 
 which I largely deal. I have a hundred affairs of my own to 
 attend to ; and then there are my lady-loves my dear friends 
 who will not suffer me day or night to leave them, for ever 
 studying to learn love-charms and incantations at my lips.' 
 ' Why ! are you really versed in those things, Socrates ?' 'Of 
 course, or else how is it, do you suppose, that Apollodorus here 
 and Antisthenes never leave me, and why have Cebes and 
 Simmias come all the way from Thebes to stay with me ? Be 
 assured, these things cannot happen without divine love-charms 
 and incantations and magic wheels.' 1 ' I wish you would lend 
 me your magic wheel then/ she said, ' and I will set it spinning 
 for you first/ ' Ah, but/ he answered, ' I do not wish to be 
 drawn to you. I wish you to come to me/ ' Then I will come/ 
 she answered, ' only will you be " at home " to me ?' ' Yes/ he 
 answered, ' unless I am already engaged/ " 
 
 Let us turn to a scene in domestic life : ^Socrates is inter- 
 rogating the "husband who had received into his arms his 
 young wife of fifteen, absolutely ignorant of the world and its 
 ways," as Mr. Lecky tells us. 2 " ' Then all else/ said I, ' you 
 taught your wife yourself, Ischomachus, until you had made her 
 proficient in careful attention to her appointed duties ?' ' That 
 did I not/ replied he, ' until I had first offered sacrifice and 
 prayed, that I might teach and she might learn all that could 
 conduce to the happiness of us twain/ ' And did your wife 
 join in sacrifice and prayer to that effect ?' ' Most certainly, 
 with many a vow registered to heaven to become all she ought 
 to be ; giving plain proof that, if the teaching failed, it should 
 not be from want of due attention on her part/ ' Pray nar- 
 rate to me what you first essayed to teach her ; to hear that 
 
 1 Cf. Theocr. ii. 17. 
 
 2 History of European Morals, vol. ii. 305 ; Xenophon, Oecon. vii.
 
 XENOPHON. 357 
 
 story would please me more than any description of the most 
 splendid gymnic contest or horse-race you could give me.' " 
 As soon as the fluttering fawn-like little creature had become 
 accustomed to her husband's hand, and was now sufficiently 
 trained to bear the effort of discussion, he commenced by ask- 
 ing : " Did it ever strike you to consider what led me to choose 
 you as my wife among all women, or your parents to intrust 
 you to me of all men?" Gently and gradually, drop by drop, 
 with infinite tact and delicacy, the questions and answers come, 
 until the girlish wife is led to realise her position clearly ; and 
 the raison d'etre, practical and spiritual alike, of matrimony, 
 with its providentially devised scheme of manifold co-operation, 
 is revealed. She is to be the Queen-bee in her hive ; and the 
 works and duties, for which her woman's nature is so well 
 adapted, will not be of trifling importance. For God, perceiv- 
 ing that a fearful spirit would be no detriment to guardianship, 
 has endowed her with a larger measure of timidity than he 
 bestowed on man. She must receive and register the products 
 of their joint estate, apportioning part for daily and current 
 use, and making provision to garner and guard the rest, so that 
 the outgoings destined for a year may not be expended within 
 a month. " ' There is just one of the occupations which 
 devolve upon you,' says the husband, ' that you may find not 
 altogether pleasing : when any member of our household falls 
 sick, it will be your care to see and tend them to the recovery 
 of their health.' ' Nay,' replies the wife, ' that will be my 
 pleasantest of tasks, if careful nursing may touch the springs 
 of gratitude and leave them friendlier than heretofore.' " We 
 are reminded of the Euripidean Alkestis parting with her 
 slaves : 
 
 " All of the household servants wept as well, 
 Moved to compassion for their mistress ; she 
 Extended her right hand to all and each, 
 And there was no one of such low degree 
 She spoke not to, nor had an answer from. " ' 
 
 "With a very tender and delicate care to avoid everything 
 resembling a reproach, the husband persuades his wife to 
 give up the habits of wearing high-heeled boots in order 
 
 1 Browning, Balaustion's Adventure, p. 38.
 
 358 XENOPHON. 
 
 to appear tall, and of colouring her face with vermilion and 
 white-lead. He promises her that if she faithfully performs 
 her duties he will himself be the first and most devoted of her 
 slaves. He assured Socrates that when any domestic dispute 
 arose, he could extricate himself admirably if he was in the right, 
 but that whenever he was in the wrong he found it impossible to 
 convince his wife that it was otherwise." l Let us once more 
 overhear the last few words of this dialogue. Ischomachus 
 is speaking and says : " ' Things have indeed now got so 
 far, that it has happened to me to be taken apart and to 
 have judgment passed upon me, what penalty I must pay 
 or what requital I must make.' 'And at whose bar,' I asked, 
 ' is the sentence given ? I cannot guess.' ' Whose but my own 
 wife's? 'he answered. 'And pray how do you conduct your 
 own case ? ' ' Not so badly when truth and interest are on 
 one and the same side ; but when these are opposed indeed, 
 Socrates, I have no skill to make the worse appear the better 
 argument.' To which I : ' No, in truth, Ischomachus, black 
 cannot be made to look white.' " 2 
 
 But, for the light which it throws on this matter, let us 
 turn to another discourse quoted by Cicero from the Socratic 
 Aeschines, as a specimen of the "inductive" method. 3 The 
 interlocutors are Aspasia, Xenophon's wife, and Xenophon 
 himself. Aspasia asks, " ' Tell me, wife of Xenophon, if your 
 neighbour possesses better jewellery than you, would you 
 rather have hers or yours ? ' ' Hers.' ' If her dresses, etc., are 
 better and costlier, would you rather have your own or hers ? ' 
 ' Hers, I suppose.' ' Well ! well ! and if she has a better husband 
 than yours, which would you rather have, hers or your own ? ' 
 A blush suffused the lady's cheeks ; and Aspasia turned to 
 Xenophon : ' Tell me, Xenophon, if your neighbour rides a 
 better horse than yours, would you rather have his or yours ?' 
 ' His.' ' Well, if he owns a better farm than yours, would 
 you rather have his farm or yours?' 'The better one, of 
 course.' ' Well ! but if he has a better wife than yours, which 
 would you choose ? ' Silence sealed his lips. Then Aspasia : 
 
 1 Lecky, ibid. I.e. 
 
 2 Oecon. xi. 25. 3 De Invent. 1. xxxi. 51 et seq.
 
 XENOPHON. 359 
 
 ' Very well ! since you will neither of you tell me the only thing 
 I wished to hear, let me interpret to you your thoughts. You, 
 lady, wish to have the best of husbands, and you, Xenophon, 
 the queen of wives ; but if you fall short of a perfection that 
 lies in your own hands, you will feel an aching void which 
 nought else can supply since you both covet earnestly this 
 best possession.' They assented." This tale, which has a 
 dramatic truth about it, is not, of course, to be used for 
 purposes of biography, and we need not speculate whether 
 the lady's name was Soteira or Philesia ; but for the uses 
 of ideal biography we shall, with a good conscience, let it 
 throw w T hat light it can upon the matrimonial happiness of 
 our author ; and if we feel inclined we shall say that Philesia 
 or Soteira or some other real woman, " better than any portrait 
 by Zeuxis," was the prototype, in some sort, of the wife of 
 Ischomachus, the Portia at whose judgment-seat we have lately 
 sat ; or of Panthea that fairest lady in all the land, and most 
 loyal of wives the wife of Abradatas ; or of the wife of 
 Tigranes ; x and the other Xenophontine women, worthy to 
 rank, not with Antigone perhaps, but with many of the women 
 of Euripides. 
 
 As to Panthea, for her at least have our hearts melted ' with 
 the droppings of warm tears ;' like Araspas we have been made 
 unawares captive in love, and at the hands of the wicked 
 sophist "Epax; have been taught wisdom ; to know that we have 
 two souls, and that when the good and lovely soul prevails, all 
 lovely and good things are wrought, but the villain soul lays to 
 her hand to work things base and ugly. 2 But this whole story, 
 " perhaps the most pathetic recital embodied in the works of 
 Hellenic antiquity," 3 is too good and sacred to spoil by breaking 
 up into fragments. For the present let us only recognise that it is 
 a tale of conjugal love, which we keep among the eternal /crr/para 
 owing to the inventive genius of Xenophon. Less tragical, 
 but much to the point, is the narrative of Tigranes, the son of 
 the king of Armenia, and the Armenian princess his wife, in 
 Book iii. of the Cyropaedia, of whom Heywoode writes : " The 
 
 1 Heywoode has put these two deservedly into his Jfwcu/cetoj' (1624), pp. 
 126, 245. 
 
 2 Cyr. vi. 1. 41. ' Grote, Plato, chap, xxxix. vol. iii., Xenopkon.
 
 360 XENOPHON. 
 
 wife of Tygranes having been with her husband at a sumptuous 
 banquet made by King Cyrus in his Pallace Boy all, when every 
 one extold the majestie and applauded the goodlinesse of the 
 King's person ; at length Tygranes askt his queen what her 
 opinion was of his magnitude and person. She answered : ' I 
 can say nothing, sir, for all the time of the feaste mine eyes were 
 stedfastle fixed upon you, my deare husband ; for what other 
 mens beauties are it becomes not a married wife to inquire.' " 
 That is graceful, but the original is more graceful arid simpler 
 than the Elizabethan reflection. The father of Tigranes, also 
 called Tigranes, beleaguered in a fastness with his wives and 
 daughters and all that he had, has been forced to come down 
 and submit to be tried by the conqueror Cyrus. At that 
 crisis the eldest son of the Armenian monarch Tigranes, an 
 old hunting companion of Cyrus, was returning home after a 
 long journey, and when he heard what was done he presented 
 himself to Cyrus even as he was ; but when he saw his father 
 and his mother, his brethren, yea, and his own wife also, that 
 were made prisoners, he could not refrain himself from tears. 
 Constrained by Cyrus, he assists at the trial of his father. 
 There is just that tinge of Oriental feeling which gives the 
 Cyropaedia part of its charm ; as of the meeting of Hellenism 
 and the Eastern world. Is this the court of Solomon ? or are we 
 in a sort of philosophic dicasterion of the Elect, such as might be 
 found in Plato's ideal state ? It is hard to say ; we seem to be 
 in two places at once, yet there is no confusion, so great is the 
 potency of the poetry of this master: behind the Socratic dialogue 
 and the Spartan character of the Buler and true Prince we are 
 made aware of the parabolic wisdom of Nathan, and the king of 
 kings. 1 The Armenian monarch is forced to pass a sentence of 
 death upon himself ; but the son pleads for the father, and the 
 conqueror, who is as clement as he is politic and princely, yields. 
 " But when they were gotten home they talked of Cyrus one 
 praising his wisdom, another his endurance, and a third the 
 gentleness of his nature, and a fourth his beauty and magni- 
 ficent stature. Then Tigranes turned to his wife and asked : 
 ' Did Cyrus seem beautiful in thine eyes also ? ' To whom 
 
 1 Of . Sidney's An Apologie for Poetrie, 1595: "So right a prince as 
 Xenophon's Cyrus," p. 25.
 
 XENOPHON. 
 
 he answered : ' Xay, my lord, for I set not mine eyes upon 
 him.' ' But on whom then ? ' asked Tigranes. ' On him 
 who, to free me from slavery, offered his own life.' For that 
 proposal had the husband made. . . ." The next day it is a 
 question whether the son or father shall command the Ar- 
 menian contingent. The father says : " He of us twain upon 
 whom thou slialt lay this injunction." But the son says : 
 " Nay, Cyrus, if I must even follow as one of your baggage- 
 bearers, I will never leave you." Then with an arch smile 
 Cyrus asked : " And what will you take that your wife should 
 learn of you that you are become a baggage-bearer ? " " She 
 will not need to learn the fact from others, for I shall take her 
 with me, and she can see for herself with her own eyes all that 
 I do." " It is time then you two got your ' kit ' together." So 
 the wife followed her husband on the campaign ; and when the 
 empire of Cyrus was established, and the rewards of valour 
 were to be distributed at Hey woode's " sumptuous banquet," he 
 brought out and gave to Tigranes a woman's attire and adorn- 
 ment, bidding him bestow it on his wife ort avftpeiws 
 <Tvve<n pareveTo rq> avSpi " for that she manfully followed 
 her own man to war." 
 
 Side by side with these pictures of fair women and good 
 wives ought to be placed, not only on artistic grounds, but as 
 throwing a clear light on a leading portion of our author's 
 human-heartedness, the boyhood of Cyrus ; and if Philesia may 
 have been the model for the wife of Tigraues, so certainly may 
 the childhood of Cyrus have been studied from one or other 
 of Xenophon's sons. Xenophon is a true artist, and, with- 
 out possessing the chief distinguishing Euripidean qualities, 
 curiously witnesses to the realism of his time, coming to much 
 the same point as the great poet analyst, by opposite means. 
 He sees the character or object or personage he wishes to 
 describe, en bloc, but with the clear-sighted precision of a photo- 
 grapher's lens; and his hand hardly falters in the delinea- 
 tion ; his ' negatives ' are generally good ; in the case of this 
 young boy, perhaps, exceptionally perfect; but what purges 
 the artist's vision here is the philanthropy of the father and 
 the man. Throughout a long sustained account, extending over 
 several quarto pages, the relations of the boy to his mother ;
 
 362 XENOPHON. 
 
 his school-fellows, his grandfather, his uncle, his admirers, the 
 chief butler, etc., are all exquisitely and inimitably drawn, and 
 preserved without perhaps one false note. We have seen 
 Cyrus hunting to the admiration of his grandfather ; and if 
 space permitted, we might see him slay his stag and boar, even 
 as his great historic compeer, the ideal monarch of a neigh- 
 bouring people, slew a lion and a bear. We might represent 
 scene upon scene some of proverbial notoriety : the judgment 
 of the coat, and the whipping consequent ; the exclamation at 
 sight of his grandly-attired Median grandfather, 009 KO\.OS poi 
 6 TraTTTTo? ; his overflow of animal spirits ; the stirrings of his 
 soul by affection ; the light-as-air whispers of the divine epeo<? 
 in his ear ; the heavy-hearted contritions and short, sharp pangs 
 of boyish remorse, etc. etc., and we should at no moment doubt 
 but that the delineator had a true and loving conception of 
 boyish nature, as being the " programme of all good." 
 
 But this topic has detained us long enough ; only, in kindred 
 connection, and before we turn to consider qualifying points, 
 let us in a series of pictures appreciate that most untranslat- 
 able of all qualities the humour and geniality, without which 
 a man is scarcely a man, and to which the healthy irony of the 
 Greeks gives so rare and intellectual a beauty. We will let 
 our minds revert freely to the Anabasis, though the special 
 quality in question is not confined to that buoyant work, but is 
 everywhere, and is made the staple of the broader fun of the 
 Symposium, which holds its sides and ' guffaws,' like a Brob- 
 dingnagian expansion of the gossamer wit of Lilliputia. 
 
 Bacon has recounted to us in vivid style the humorous 
 interview, after Cunaxa, between the generals and Phalinus, 
 the agent of the Great King, himself a Greek and a sort 
 of professor of strategics at the Persian court. Bacon was 
 not troubled by any manuscript reading Theopompus for 
 Xenophon, nor disturbed by doubts as to the absolute authen- 
 ticity of so graphic a history. 1 Therefore the passage which is 
 here quoted, for the humour of the situation, is also an epitaph 
 engraven with the high encomium of "the young scholar or philo- 
 
 1 Advancement of Learning, i. vii. 30. Lord Bacon's Works, vol. iii. p. 313. 
 (Spedding and Ellis.)
 
 XENOPHON. 
 
 sopher :" " The message imported that they should deliver up 
 their arms, and submit themselves to the king's mercy. To 
 which message, before answer was made, divers of the army con- 
 ferred familiarly with Falinus, and amongst the rest Xenophon 
 happened to say, ' "NVhy, Falinus, we have now but these two 
 things left, our arms and our virtue ; and if we yield up our 
 arms, how shall we make use of our virtue ? ' Whereto Falinus, 
 smiling on him, said, ' If I be not deceived, young gentleman, 
 you are an Athenian, and I believe you study philosophy, and 
 it is pretty that you say ; but you are much abused if you think 
 your virtue can withstand the king's power.' Here was the 
 scorn ; the wonder followed : which was that this young scholar 
 or philosopher, after all the captains were murdered in parley 
 by treason, conducted those ten thousand foot through the heart 
 of all the king's high countries, from Babylon to Grecia, in safety, 
 in despite of all the king's forces, to the astonishment of the 
 world, and the encouragement of the Grecians in times suc- 
 ceeding to make invasion upon the kings of Persia ; as was 
 afterwards proposed by Jason the Thessalian, attempted 
 by Agesilaus the Spartan, and achieved by Alexander the 
 Macedonian, all upon the ground of the act of that young 
 scholar." But while considering his heroism, let us not forget 
 the humour of Xenophon. 2 On the night after the murder of 
 the generals we are fairly resolved on the march ; our wagons 
 and tents are burnt ; we have shared with each other what we 
 need from our superfluities, and thrown the rest into our watch- 
 fires ; and with a good conscience we betake ourselves to break- 
 fast. Just then up rides Mithridates with about thirty horsemen. 
 Summoning the generals to within earshot, he makes us a fine 
 long speech : ' Men of Hellas, I was faithful to Cyrus, and 
 I am well-disposed to you, and now I am here living in great 
 dread. What are you going to do ? If it seems rational, I am 
 disposed to join you with my retainers/ etc. etc. This sounds 
 promising, but after various consultations out it comes. In the 
 style of a preacher the excellent Asiatic tries to persuade us 
 
 1 Grote is still at Bacon's point of view ; and seems hardly sufficiently to 
 recognise the colouring element of Xenophon's strong subjectivity. 
 
 2 Altai, iii. 3.
 
 364 XENOPHON. 
 
 that without the good graces of the Great King our salvation is 
 hopeless. We part friends. After the mid-day meal we cross 
 the great Zab, and are jogging along in regular inarching 
 order. But before we have got very far, lo and behold, eVt- 
 (fraivercu Trakiv 6 MidptSdrrj^, 1 there he is again. Yes, surely, 
 that's he Mithridates with a couple of hundred horse at his 
 back this time, and twice as many bowmen and slingers ; and 
 in another five minutes we are in the thick of a pelt of arrows 
 and stones. The cavalry of this false friend, whose appear- 
 ance we shall never forget, dog us all day. The scene changes : 
 We are on the edge of a river with beetling Carduchian 
 crags hemming us in. We sound the depth of the river. We 
 can't bottom it with our long spears. In the midst of our per- 
 plexities a lihodian comes up with a proposal : 2 ' I am ready, 
 sirs, to carry you across 4000 heavy infantry at a time, if you 
 will furnish me with what I need, and give me a talent for my 
 services.' ' What will you need ? ' ' Only 2000 wineskins. 
 I see there are multitudes of sheep and goats and asses. 
 They have only to be flayed and their skins inflated, and they 
 will readily give us a passage. I shall want also the straps you 
 use for the baggage-animals. With these I shall couple the 
 skins to one another, and then I shall moor each skin, by 
 attaching stones and letting them down like anchors into the 
 water. Then I shall carry them across, and when I have fas- 
 tened the links at both ends, I shall place layers of wood on 
 them and a coating of earth on the top of that. You will see 
 in a minute that there is no danger of your drowning, for every 
 skin will be able to support a couple of men without sinking ; 
 and the wood and earth will prevent your slipping off.' This 
 seems a pretty invention enough ; but the generals think it 
 not altogether practicable in the face of cavalry on the other 
 side, etc. Every now and again the march is enlivened 
 by 'chaff' and repartee between the quick-witted Athenian 
 and the respectable Laconian Cheirisophus. Views of educa- 
 tion are compared. 3 The Athenian suggests, a propos of steal- 
 ing a march upon the enemy, that the Spartan training will 
 
 1 Anab. iii. 3. 6. 2 Ibid. iii. 5. 
 
 3 Ibid. iv. 6. 14-16.
 
 XENOPIION. 365 
 
 now be of use. The Spartan mutters something in the nature 
 of a tu q_uoq_uc, about those who are taught to filch the public 
 moneys in a democratic state, of which he has heard. On 
 the slopes above Trebizond there is a great sacrifice and games. 1 
 The master of the ceremonies, a Spartan, Dracontius by name, is 
 asked to conduct them to the course. He merely waved his hand, 
 pointing to where they were standing, and said : ' There, this 
 ridge is just the place for running anywhere, everywhere.' 
 ' But how will they manage to wrestle on the hard scrubby 
 ground ?' ' Oh ! worse knocks for those who are thrown.' 
 There was horse-racing also. The riders had to gallop down 
 a steep incline to the sea, and then turn and come up 
 again to the altar ; and on the descent more than half rolled 
 head over heels, and then back they came toiling up the 
 tremendous steep, scarcely out of a walking pace. Loud were 
 the shouts, the laughter, and the cheers. The quaint cus- 
 toms of semi-barbaric tribes in matters of eating and drink- 
 ing are a constant source of mirth, as we sit imbibing beer 
 through long reeds ; 2 or, in Thrace, Seuthes throws us junks of 
 meat ; or the wine-cup is handed, and we must get up and 
 make speeches and promise gifts. 3 Again, 110 one who ever 
 visited the Mossynoecians, i.e. the wooden-tower dwellers, 
 will ever forget them. Transported suddenly into the world 
 of Sir John Mandeville, he feels as if pavia were only next 
 door; but there is a comical method in this madness. The 
 customs of these people were the customs of civilised folk 
 turned inside out. They do in a crowd what nous autres do 
 in private, and vice versa* There they go, talking and laugh- 
 ing to themselves, standing and capering about, as if their 
 sole business were to show off to the rest of the world. They 
 are very white-skinned, the men as well as the women. One 
 of their entertainments consists of an exhibition of fatted 
 children belonging to the wealthy classes, fed up on boiled 
 chestnuts until they are as white as white can be, and very 
 nearly as broad as they are long." But these humorous situa- 
 tions are endless. 
 
 1 Anab. iv. 8. 26. 2 Ibid. iv. 5. 26. 
 
 3 Ibid. vii. 3. 22, 26 et seq. 4 Ibid. v. 4. 32-34.
 
 3 66 XENOPHON. 
 
 Xenophon then is, without exception, a type of the 
 dpwTTos, but of course it is a ^>L\av6pa)7rta conditioned by his 
 age and " political " circumstances, neither of which does he 
 transcend to any miraculous extent. His world is peopled, 
 somewhat unduly to our democratic minds, with ol fieXria-Tot 
 and ol KaXol rcdr/adoi. The better classes and the people of 
 culture limit or confine the horizon of his sympathies ; even as 
 now-a-days, when caste prejudices are clearly decadent, the garb 
 or general appearance of a man may impose on the imagination 
 of a Christian, or as the philosophy of some thinkers seems to 
 be warped by contact with coloured races and less advanced 
 civilisations. The eye of Xenophon may similarly have looked 
 askance at some one whose political or social setting was not 
 to his taste ; but this Trpoa-wn-oXrj-^la does not render him less 
 graphic, nor, in any deep sense, poison the springs of his phil- 
 anthropy. Indeed his sympathy is so akin to clear-sightedness, 
 and in keeping with the bright keen atmosphere and sunny 
 Heiterkeit of his native olive-clad hills and vales, that nothing, 
 not even anti-Theban political partisanship, can dull its trans- 
 parency ; and so, whatever he may have thought of the two 
 heroes who slipped through the fingers of Agesilaus from the 
 closely-watched citadel of Phlius, his description of them 
 lives in our memory, through the vividness of his style. 1 
 " Agesilaus granted a truce for the embassy, but at the same 
 time he was so angry at their setting his personal authority 
 aside that he sent to his friends at home, and arranged that the 
 fate of the little township should be left to his discretion, and 
 meanwhile proceeded to tighten the cordon of investment, so 
 as to render it impossible that a single soul should escape." In 
 spite of which he was not clever enough for Delphion. " This 
 brilliant organiser of the defence, with a single comrade (crrvy- 
 fjuartas Tt<?), a branded dare-devil, who had already shown great 
 dexterity in relieving the besieging parties of their arms, 
 escaped in the night." 
 
 In close connection with the healthy humanity of our author 
 (which in reference to others is faXla, to one's-self eve^la, 
 and negatively implies an absence of Tr\eove%ia and //3pt<?), 
 
 1 Hellen. v. 3. 22-24.
 
 XENOPHON. 367 
 
 are to l>e ranged his favourite virtues : the special ' rule of 
 life/ to which his nature was doubtless prone; but with the 
 emphasising of which ' the great companion ' must surely be 
 largely credited, though to what extent we can only dimly con- 
 jecture. For undoubtedly on many important moral questions 
 or (to speak correctly) ethical theories, the disciple differed largely 
 from his master, and was, so far, nearer to the average mind of 
 even later ages. 1 Thus, according to Xenophon, who is inter- 
 preting the Socratic mind to ' the Athenians,' i.e. to a general 
 audience, and in a somewhat apologetic style, in keeping 
 with the mental vernacular, to Xenophon virtue is a branch 
 of /jidOrjaii; (learning) indeed, and so far a thing to be taught ; 
 but then aaKTjo-is, discipline (including objective discipline of 
 the individual and subjective self-discipline), is a means of 
 teaching. Again, ema-T^i], the highest type of intellectual 
 knowledge (science), readily transforms itself into cro^la, the 
 highest sort of wisdom. Possibly the transformation, so far 
 as Xenophon himself is concerned, takes place through some 
 such train of thought as the following, taken from a con- 
 versation between Socrates and Euthydemus : 2 
 
 Question. And what shall we say of wisdom ? Tell me : do 
 the wise seem to you to be wise in things they know, or are 
 there, who are wise in what they know not ? 
 
 Answer. Clearly in what they know ; for how should a man 
 have wisdom in what he know^s not ? 
 
 Quest. The wise, in fact, are wise in knowledge ? 
 
 Ans. Why, in what else could a man be wise, save only in 
 knowledge ? 
 
 Quest. And wisdom ! is it aught else, think you, than that 
 wherein men are wise ? 
 
 Ans. Certainly not. 
 
 Quest. It seems, knowledge is wisdom ? 
 
 Ans. I think so. 
 
 1 I do not mean, contrariwise, to imply that the true Socrates is to be found 
 in Plato rather than in Xenophon (vide note ' next page, and note x page 369), 
 but rather, that the Aristotelian theory of virtue was latent in the common- 
 sense views of the moralist. What the profound identification of <ro<pla. with 
 tiri(TTJiij.T) was in the mind of Socrates, lies beyond the present discussion. 
 
 2 Mem. iv. 6. 7.
 
 ;68 XENOPHON. 
 
 Quest. Do you think that a man is capable of knowing all 
 the things that are ? 
 
 Ans. I should say he cannot know even the millionth part 
 of them. 
 
 Quest. It seems a human being cannot be all-wise ? 
 
 Ans. Certainly not. 
 
 Quest. The conclusion is, the wisdom of each man is limited 
 to that which he knows. 
 
 This is by no means tantamount to saying that <jo$ia = 
 eTnaTrj/^rj : but one sees that wisdom and knowledge might 
 easily come to be convertible, in inexact thought or expres- 
 sion ; and the practical loss (or gain) is the same. 1 On the 
 other hand, aofaa is apt to fade away, and to transform 
 itself into o-co^poavvrj (an untranslatable "mixed mode"- 
 temperance, modesty, sobriety, and rhythmical self-completion 
 and adjustment). 2 " Now wisdom and awp^ocrvvr] he did not 
 distinguish, his verdict being that the one thing needful was 
 that a man should make himself acquainted with ' the beautiful 
 and the good,' and practise them ; or, again, he should learn to 
 know the ugly and base, and avoid it. Such a man was o-o^o? 
 and <r<t)(f)p(i)v, wise and well-regulated. For justice (or upright- 
 ness) and all things that are wrought with virtue are beautiful 
 and good." 3 And, again, "justice and all the rest of virtue are 
 wisdom." 
 
 Whether, then, in these kaleidoscopic views Xenophon is 
 only expressing his own reading of the philosopher's mind, or 
 whether he has also the mind of the philosopher, which, 
 thirdly, he may be translating into language to be understood of 
 the mass of men, is a most serious investigation, raising as it does 
 
 1 It may be urged that, as far as this passage goes, the disciple is truly, 
 if perhaps crudely, intelligent of his master ; for, admittedly, the identification 
 of knowledge, wisdom, and virtue is the most characteristic of Socratic 
 doctrines ; while the scope and intention of the Recollections exclude severe 
 philosophising. But, even so, the impression left upon the mind is that 
 Xenophon himself took merely a common-sense view of the subtleties of the 
 spirit, in which the teacher dealt ; and, except as a moralist and sympathiser, 
 failed to fathom the distinctive doctrine. Nor does it appear that Plato, 
 from another side, was more successful. 
 
 3 Cf. J. S. Mill, Dissertations and Discussions, vol. iii. 326, 327. 
 
 8 Mem. iii. 9. 4, 5.
 
 XENOPHON. 369 
 
 the whole question of the philosophic value of the Recollections. 
 But its pursuit would lead us too far afield, and it seems suffi- 
 cient to get an insight into the mind of the Hearer rather than 
 of the Inspirer ; for if we find it next to impossible to separate 
 the chaff of Xenophon 1 from the wheat of Socrates, we have no 
 similar difficulty in detecting the idiosyncratic virtues of this 
 particular Hellene. AVe have only to carve them out of the 
 whole assemblage of moral qualities which make up the dperrj 
 of man ; and the " virtues," which constitute the sum of ethical 
 principle, whether of the unwritten code, the aypa^oi vo^o^ 
 (with which Socrates confutes the scepticism of Hippias), or 
 that wherein the law of the State is embodied, are for the 
 main easily enumerated. Often hard, or even impossible, to 
 represent by any one equivalent or string of half-equivalents in 
 English, they are not hard to realise with tolerable definiteness. 
 The names of several occur in Mem. iv. 6, and are so current 
 indeed in all Greek literature that if Plato and Xenophon and 
 Aristotle were destroyed we still should possess or re-discover 
 them. The four ' cardinal ' virtues are 3 (1) o-cxfria; (2) SIKCIIO- 
 avvTf)\ (3) dvSpela; (4) crax^poa-vvr] (1) wisdom; (2) justice or 
 social uprightness (in New Testament " righteousness ") ; (3) 
 courage; (4) temperance. 4 Akin to a-w^poo-vvr] is eyKparela 
 (self-control), and in the same breath with crotyla must be 
 mentioned (f>p6vr](ri<; (prudence or practical wisdom) and eVt- 
 
 1 Again, by this expression I do not wish to suggest that the Socrates of 
 Xenophon is more (or less) real or true than that of Plato. Personally, I 
 regard these portraitures as both true, both defective. They are single-sided 
 and opposite ideals ; and, pro tanto, caricatures in part of the actual being, 
 whose real self was not truly depicted by any mortal. Whose has been ? 
 The Xenophontine Socrates (of the Recollections) is drawn to suit the every- 
 day spectator, and possesses a certain precious, if limited, "historic"' truth. 
 The limitations of the Platonic draught are of a different kind. The theorist 
 and philosopher needs the high-aiming, unselfish eristic inspirer and searcher, 
 as the most important of his dramatis personce. Plato also is a poet ; and 
 will ' poetise ' the real man to the same extent that the historian ' historicises ' 
 him askew. Yet both are good and noble portraits. 
 
 2 Mem. v. 4. 19. 
 
 3 Ibid. iv. 6 : 2-4, Piety (eforejSefo) ; 5-6, Justice (8iKaio<rtvi)) ; 7, Wisdom 
 (ffO(f>la.) ; 8-9, le Beau (rt> ica\6t>) ; 10-11, Courage (&i>5pela). 
 
 * '" Temperance, ' while corresponding to a part of the word, is ridiculously 
 inadequate to the whole." J. S. Mill, on "Mixed Modes," different from 
 or corresponding to our use. Dies, and Disc. vol. iii. 328. 
 
 2 A
 
 370 XENOPHON. 
 
 These, with others, constitute the full perfection of 
 man : they are virtue. But roaming among these the soul of 
 Xenophon was chiefly enamoured of evaefteia, of dv&peta, and 
 of aaxfrpoavvri in its kinship to ey/cparela rather than croc/ua ; i.e. 
 on the moral and emotional rather than the intellectual side ; but 
 as a follower of Socrates it is sufficient for him to put consciously 
 into the foreground growth in Ka\o/cdya6ia, as the chief aim 
 and rule of life. For the religious, temperate, self-controlled, 
 rhythmically attuned, just, righteous, prudent, scientific, wise, 
 and good man is he who has absorbed into himself the KaXa 
 Kay add, the whole list of beautiful and noble things ; or, in the 
 language of Lycurgean training, ra rca\d simply, the chivalrous 
 " code of honour " at Sparta. In a less formal way, but with 
 a still more penetrative persistence, as of a man who knows 
 that he has no better gospel of salvation to give, he insists on 
 a still unmentioned virtue which must be regarded as highly 
 idiosyncratic: to M'it, eTripeXeia, painstaking care. Possibly 
 there is the slightest aristocratic tinge to this excellence ; 
 perhaps a touch of superiority in its possessor is implied 
 as of the overseer's care ; but however incompatible with 
 things low and sordid (ra Pavava-i/cd), the doctrine is the 
 same : ov$ev avev TTOVOV /cal eTrtyiieXeia? <yv/j,va<TTeov trvv TTOVOIS 
 Kai IBpwri, which Cicero would turn "nihil sine sudore et 
 studio," nothing without painstaking care, and trouble ; x and 
 this it is which, with (evae/Betd) his piety, endears Xenophon 
 to the heart of Mr. Euskin, and most deservedly, for when it 
 enters in and dwells with a man, out of his heart perishes 
 all d\a%ovLa and fMiTaior^, all moral thinness and quackery ; 
 and it is therefore quite comprehensible how, to a practical 
 temperament, such as Xenophon's, the problem, Can virtue be 
 taught ? resolves itself for the most part into an affair of 
 training (aa-K^ais). 
 
 With regard to "King IVo//,o<?," his bias is strongly Athenian, 
 or else Laconian. " The laws " of Thebans or Eleians shock or 
 revolt him, or are beyond even his stricture as something alien 
 much as a good English Protestant not so long ago might have 
 been scandalised by the beliefs and customs of the Parisians or 
 
 1 Mem. ii. 1. 28.
 
 XENOPHON. 371 
 
 Catholics, and as for the political or religious views of Turks 
 or Russians, would not reckon them as within the pale of his 
 observation. This analogue, if not pressed too far, throws some 
 faint light on Xenophon's limitations, which are ' national,' 
 nothing more. 1 
 
 Orderliness, not to speak of piety, economy, self-cultiva- 
 tion these lead to success in life, but also to the highest per- 
 fection of the Hellenic soul. By comparison with these, even 
 (f)i\oTi/j,ia, that first and last infirmity of noble-minded citizens, 
 ambition and the love of honour, ranks nowhere ; and it is easy 
 to see how closely connected with this somewhat Spartan (or 
 Socratic ?) self-supervision is what we venture to call the Puri- 
 tanism, or even Calvinism, of his soul. Over and over again we 
 seem to hear a prophecy of language which we think appro- 
 priate enough on the lips of St. Paul, but which startles 
 us some four hundred odd years before those birth-throes of our 
 spirit. " The majority of pleasures are bad," says Xenophon, 2 
 and hence an argument in favour of the healthy excitement and 
 the joyous discipline of the chase ; for, of course, the pains and 
 pleasures of animals are ignored then as now. If he has said, 
 or rather has introduced Simonides as saying to Hieron, " All 
 the troubles which you 'tyrants' endure are well repaid, 
 since in the end you receive more abundant honour than 
 the rest of mankind ; and no pleasure which men can 
 enjoy approaches nearer to the divine than the delight in 
 being honoured ;" he has also written this apostolic passage: 3 
 "Where, then, is the difficulty of supposing that a man 
 may be virtuous and temperate to-day, and to-morrow the 
 reverse ; or that he who once has had it in his power to do what 
 is right, may not quite lose that power? No ; if I may venture 
 to express an opinion of my own, I would say that all beautiful 
 and noble things are a matter of constant practice and training ; 
 and this applies pre-eminently to the virtue of temperance, 
 
 1 Socrates, in his famous speech in the Symposium, viii. 34, argues against 
 Pausanias's theory of the invincibility of a sacred band of lovers, and as to 
 the customs of Elis and Thebes adduced in support of his view, " that," says 
 Socrates, " is a one-legged proof at best, for what they accept as highly 
 proper we regard as simply scandalous." The point to bear in mind is that 
 NOMOI correspond to our CREEDS pretty much. 
 
 2 Cyn. xii. 12. * Mem. i. 2. 23.
 
 372 XENOPHON. 
 
 seeing that in one and the same bodily frame pleasures are 
 planted and spring up side by side with the soul, ever whisper- 
 ing in her ear, ' have done with self-restraint, make haste to 
 gratify us and the body (our common lord).'" 
 
 In these last considerations we seem to have been exploring 
 a mind partly 'Socratic,' partly independent of Socrates; and at 
 length when we come to the writer's philosophic self, the o-oc/uo-- 
 T?;?, or 0-0009, or (^tXocro^o?, as we may term it, within him, this 
 ambiguity is intensified. We find ourselves fully launched in- 
 deed into ' Socratic ' influence, with all the external apparatus 
 of method, the elenchos, the dialectic process, the cut and parry 
 and thrust of eristic argumentation, the epaktic or inductive 
 reasoning, the arrangement of what we talk about by " families," 
 i.e. " generalisation ; " but while caught into this wise man's 
 debating ground, we seem to be in it, and not of it. To say 
 that our feelings resemble those of the poor old Athenian country 
 gentleman in the Thinkery, (jjpovrtcrrrjpiov, would be libellous, 
 because the ^aO^rr]^, Xenophon, is at anyrate quite at home. 
 Possibly he is hardly aware of the gap which separates him 
 from the philosophy of him at whose feet he sat ; even as Aris- 
 tippus, Antisthenes, Euclides, and the rest, may have regarded 
 their own fragments over fondly as the keystone of the palace 
 of thought. Here the distinction seems not difficult to grasp. 
 
 Between the world of the wise man and that region which is 
 inhabited by the ol TroXXot, the children of everyday life, there is 
 a gulf fixed, but there is no want of intercommunication ; there 
 is what may be termed the Xenophontine bridge, and on this, 
 which is neutral ground for the philosopher and the mass of 
 men to meet, there are no hostile catchwords ; " the stock argu- 
 ment and the ready-to-hand reproaches " are in abeyance. On 
 the far side is the most original of men seeking as an abso- 
 lutely lofty and philanthropic object to awaken self-conscious- 
 ness in his fellows or in himself; this is the noble, nay 
 sublime, Hellenic effort for " the salvation of souls." 1 As Mr. 
 Sidgwick in the treatise already quoted says : z " The radical 
 and most impressive article of his creed was constituted by his 
 
 1 " Socrates, the Jesus Christ of Greece." SHELLEY. 
 
 2 Ethics, Ency. Metrop. p. 576.
 
 XENOPHON. 373 
 
 exalted estimate of this knowledge that was so hard to find, his 
 conviction that ignorance of the good and evil in human life 
 was the source of all practical error." " Take heed," he was 
 always saying in his own language, " take heed, therefore, that 
 the light which is in thee be not darkness." This enlighten- 
 ment is at once knowledge and goodness and moral attainment. 
 When shall we attain to Socratic wisdom ? when, in Xenophou- 
 tine hunting metaphor, shall virtue be laid captive at our feet ? 
 These are the questions \ve ask, as we take our stand on the hither 
 side with the ordinary Hellene, bent upon self-culture. 1 From. 
 this point of view we persuade ourselves that Socrates did really 
 care less for his method, his elenchos, his induction, his novel 
 class or clan system of arrangement (TO Kara yevr) BiaXeyew) , 
 than for benefiting, by hook or by crook, the interlocutor (or 
 possibly some other at his expense), but with infinite "philan- 
 thropy " in all cases. As performing a solemn and charitable duty, 
 he sought to awaken self-consciousness, to throw a stream of 
 light into a dark place, and to convict of ignorance, confusion 
 and obscurity of thought and behaviour, for the sake of clearer 
 intelligence and a firmer moral foothold. The machinery was 
 the whole " maieutic " apparatus of the new method : so im- 
 portant indeed in the history of philosophy, that Aristotle can 
 sum up his great discovery thus : " he sought the abstract 
 (TO Ka06\ov), 2 and was the first who thought of giving 
 definitions." But to himself neither the method nor any 
 part of the machinery was of vital necessity, only these 
 were the natural handiest instruments for his purposes. (If 
 ' anaesthetics ' would have served, he would have applied 
 them.) The important point was, not the intellectual or meta- 
 physical training, or the philosophising even by a better 
 method though " to make his associates more dialectic," to 
 sharpen and keep bright their lancets, was in its due place 
 part of his daily business, 3 but better philosophising as a 
 step forward in the direction of manly virtue and human 
 completeness, which is happiness. 
 
 In some such light we may imagine that Socrates revealed 
 
 vrj irepl roi)j 9eoys, irepl r-qv diiccuoffiji'T)v a rhythmical self -completion 
 and adjustment towards God and the righteousness of man (social uprightness). 
 2 Arist. Metaph. xiii. 4. 3 Mem. iv. 6. 1.
 
 374 XENOPHON. 
 
 himself to the concrete mind of Xenophon. Some of his 
 doctrines may have been absorbed at once ; others, really put 
 forward tentatively for the awakening of another soul, Xenophon 
 may have assimilated in the half-ripe condition; hence the 
 rounded teleology and the views about immortality (in the 
 Memorabilia and Cyropaedia). In other cases, he gives rein to 
 his own philosophic propensities, and in the satisfaction of his 
 own highest nature, attempts to answer various questions, 
 which he had often heard raised for the twofold purpose of 
 getting a clear concept, and of creating a thorough moral 
 awakening. The result of this fashion of his own is some of 
 the most beautiful pieces of Greek literature : the Economist, 
 the Hieron, the Cyropaedia. He asks, Who is the economic 
 man ? Who is the despot ? Who is the kingly personage 
 with the gift of ruling? and with some semblance of the 
 Socratic "induction," his own thoughts the while working 
 along the " epaktic " grooves, he comes to a conclusion which 
 is, if you like, a generalisation, but is nevertheless embodied 
 in a concrete shape ; he has, in fact, drawn upon his canvas, as 
 an answer to the philosophic inquiry, with which we started, a 
 Cyrus or a Hiero, or an Ischomachus. That which might have 
 ended in metaphysics turns out to be an exquisite work of art, 
 carefully elaborated line for line, but at the same time not 
 devoid of ethic and allegoric import. 
 
 Here, however, we will be quit of the o-ofaarris and turn to 
 interrogate the prfrcop, the political reformer, and professor of 
 strategics, the author ; not indeed of the earliest political bro- 
 chure, for we are agreed to exclude from our canon that " oldest 
 extant specimen of literary Attic prose," and otherwise remark- 
 able work, the essay On the Athenian Polity; 1 but of the 
 Laconian Polity, the Hipparchicos, the pamphlet on Revenues. 
 We will confront the artist, who has skilfully worked into the 
 texture of his larger works much that belongs to the statist and 
 the tactician ; and this to so great an extent that in the eyes of 
 the modern military historian " tactics " seem to form the main 
 thread of the Cyropaedia, and the chief point of interest of the 
 Anabasis (or Hellenica). 2 
 
 1 420 B.C., Jebb, Greek Literature Primer, and vide supra, p. 328, note. 
 
 2 Vide Rustowand Kochly passim, also the former's HilitarischeBiographieen.
 
 XENOPHON. 375 
 
 To speak of these "political" and professional gifts in a breath 
 is not easy, though there is a marked ' solidarity ' between 
 the diverse selves of the man whom we are cross-questioning ; 
 and the native rhythm of even so many-sided and Odyssean a 
 character predominates. Under favourable circumstances it is 
 quite likely that Xenophon might have appeared in history 
 as another Iphicrates, 1 a /^op/jLoo and bugbear 2 to Spartan allies or 
 Boeotians, or as a second Chabrias or Charidemus, a higher type 
 of military reformer or captain of mercenaries than the Ccera- 
 tidases and Phalinuses whose features he has so indelibly 
 imprinted on our minds. 3 His interest at any rate in military 
 matters is obvious ; 4 and, if sentiment is to weigh, the Hip- 
 parchicos, addressed to a commandant of cavalry for the 
 benefit possibly of his own son, and as a seal of reconciliation 
 to his fatherland, has a special interest for us : a remark 
 applicable also to the latest work of his old age, written as 
 tradition infers for Eubulus, the finance minister of Athens, 
 who had been instrumental in rescinding the vote of banish- 
 ment, and in that case doubly, for the sake of peace. As prac- 
 tical works the value of these political tracts would probably 
 be as great in the eyes of the modern reader as the companion 
 treatises on Hunting and Horses, if only the species of things 
 with which they deal were of a type as fixed as horses and 
 grooms, dogs and hares. Dealing with the more shifting 
 or evanescent topics of cavalry tactics, and of Athenian 
 finance, they may easily be misjudged. For instance, as far 
 as the military manual goes, we ought not to allow mere 
 change in numbers or equipment to affect our judgment, if, 
 as regards evolutional and other efficiency, the precepts appear 
 to possess a more permanent value. A fairer difficulty, the 
 insertion of pompous regulations which would have no par- 
 allel in a similar modern treatise, is to be explained by the 
 close connection in a Greek city community between the 
 citizen soldier's service as a defender of his country in war. 
 
 1 Xenophon's Seuthes' experiences present a strong family likeness to those 
 of Iphicrates and Cotys. 
 
 2 Hell. iv. 4. 17. 8 Anab. vii. 1. 21-25 ; ibid. ii. 1. 6-15. 
 
 4 Plutarch says Xenophon taught Agesilaus. Cicero tells us Scipio Afri- 
 canus carried a copy of the C'yropaedia about in his breast pocket.
 
 XENOPHON. 
 
 and his employment in religious processions during peace. 1 
 Her Majesty's household troops throw little light on this side 
 of the matter, which, however, in Xenophon's time could hardly 
 have been omitted. So, again, our more advanced views of 
 political economy our intelligent appreciation of the applica- 
 tion of " the, law of diminishing returns " to mineral products, 
 ought not to lead us to laugh at the fundamental hypothesis of 
 the de Reditibus that the silver mines of Laurium were inex- 
 haustible. Better economised labour, and more of it, would 
 probably have rendered them more lucrative. Besides which, 
 they were as inexhaustible for the Athenians, at any rate, as 
 the coal-fields of Great Britain are for the people of England ; 
 nor is there anything in the rest of the scheme to stamp its 
 author as an unpractical politician. 
 
 Of course it is not pretended that these treatises have, or 
 ever had, any claim to rank highly among the 7roA.m/oH Xoyoi, 
 the production of which, in the eyes of Isocrates, guarantees to 
 the author the title of philosopher refused to the verbose or 
 disputatious professor of wisdom; moreover, we have hardly 
 the means of gauging the value attached by his contempor- 
 aries to any of these minor works. The fact that they were 
 written by Xenophon would have preserved them ; and what is 
 more profitable here is to discover in the mature treatise the 
 floating schemes and enthusiastic aspirations of youth or middle 
 age. In the nonagenarian Nestor, of the Revenues, devising 
 means to counteract pauperism and turn exceptional wealth to 
 account, while adding honour to the state, we hear the voice of 
 the youthful and athletic captain of the Eetreat, brimming 
 with an Odyssean joy in experience and irrepressible good- 
 humour. Our minds revert to the fatal night of the murder of 
 the generals ; the dream and the resolution are past, the first 
 hurried meetings have taken place, the new generals have been 
 appointed. The council is held as day breaks; the speeches 
 follow : Cheirisophus' laconic, as it ought to be ; Cleanor's 
 of Orchomenus artistically suited; then Xenophon rose he 
 was arrayed for war in all his finery. 2 If the gods grant us 
 victory, thought he, the finest attire will accord with the event; 
 
 1 Hipparch. iii. 2 Anab. iii. 2. 7.
 
 XENOPHON. 377 
 
 or, if death is our doom, then for him who has claimed the 
 finest it is as well there should be some correspondence between 
 the expectation and the end. 1 ..." But perhaps," he urged, 
 " it is well we did not stop, for I fear that if we once learn to 
 live in idleness and luxuriously to batten, in intercourse with 
 these tall and handsome Median and Persian women and 
 maidens, we shall be like the lotos-eaters, and forget the road 
 home altogether. It seems to me it is only rational and right, 
 in the first instance, to make an effort to return to Hellas and 
 to revisit our hearths and homes, if only to prove to our 
 countrymen that it is their own fault that they are poor and 
 needy, seeing it is in their power to give to those now living 
 a pauper life at home a free passage hither, and to convert 
 them into well-to-do burghers at once." Here seems to be 
 the germ of the colonisation scheme, of which we hear again 
 and again, whether in the shape of a project of forming a 
 settlement at Cotyora, 2 or of sailing off for a similar purpose to 
 the mouth of the Phasis, or of establishing a new "politeuma" 
 on the auspicious promontory of Calpe. The scheme of the de 
 Eeditibus half a century later is more elaborate, but is marked 
 by the same philanthropic savoir faire? 
 
 The special evils of a still later date have been described as, 
 " 1. The accumulation of wealth in the hands of the rich, and 
 the corresponding growth of rapacity on the part of the poor. 
 2. The growth of egotism and unprincipled ambition since the 
 rupture between society and the state. 3. The swarms of men 
 without cities, paupers, political exiles, malefactors, for ever 
 moving over the face of Greece, ready for mercenary service, and 
 ripe for mischief." 4 Of all these things we are aware from the 
 pages of Xenophon, who lived, indeed, down to the days of Philip, 
 but is representative of a generation earlier. Still stronger light 
 is thrown on the underlying causes of this " political decom- 
 position " and increasing chaos, by a great modem thinker. 5 
 The philosopher has done speaking of the " diversion of Greek 
 
 1 Anab. iii. 2. 25. * Ibid. v. 6. 15. 
 
 3 De Redit. i. , td 5 rty rov ir\-f)0ovs ireviav dvayKa^effdai Hfiaffav adiKtbrepoi 
 flvai Trepl rds 7r6Xeis ; also vi., /coi 6 /j.i> STJ/J.OS rpo<prjs eviropi?icrfi, ol d 
 K.T.\. 4 Jebb, Orators, Isocrates, ch. xii. p. 15. 
 
 5 Comte, vol. iii. of Pos. Polit. p. 245, Engl. transl. (Beesly.)
 
 378 XENOPHON. 
 
 intellect from politics," and is concerned with the spectacle of 
 independent states united by common sentiments and beliefs. 
 " The political decomposition served as a new impelling force, 
 for it kept before men's eyes the continual spectacle of an 
 intellectual and moral association between states independent 
 of each other. That spontaneous church, even then as much a 
 reality as the cities composing it, could by no territorial restric- 
 tion be hindered from arousing in those whose qualities of 
 heart and mind inclined them towards social generalisations, 
 an unmistakable desire for a universal communion." l In other 
 words, the reign of the NO/AO? dynasty in the different states 
 was tottering to its fall, and out of the void (no real vacuum, 
 but the abiding-place of the aypafoi v6fj,oi), was fast shaping 
 itself the new law, whose best name in history is " the scientific 
 conscience," the heirloom of Hellenic intellect. To this chaos 
 and decomposition Xenophon, amongst others, has borne testi- 
 mony ; for better or for worse he is a veritable " enfant du 
 siecle," and that is his high praise ; but we ought not to restrict 
 our regard for him to that view. By a kind of accident, owing 
 to the preservation of the diverse products of his fertility, and 
 because his genius is that of the universally representative 
 rather than exceptionally original artist in some one depart- 
 ment of things the child of Thalia or Calliope or Melpomene ; 
 for these reasons, and for others which go deeper, to wit his 
 humanity, his moral earnestness, his appreciation of Socrates, 
 he has always, even when his fame suffered declension, been 
 honoured as the foreordained depositary of precious in- 
 formation about the ancient Greeks, which, but for him, would 
 certainly have perished. This, then, is a high prestige, but it 
 is one which a man has to share with the Moabitish Stone, 
 the obelisks, or the ruins of Nineveh. Not " half-sunk," indeed, 
 or " shattered is the visage " of this ancient Hellene, but rather 
 he is a "pyramid built up by renewed might of all Time's 
 
 1 To understand ' ' Laconism, " we ought to go to a somewhat analogous period 
 the Italy of the Republics, where Venice with her relative stability and 
 oligarchical government = Sparta ; Florence with her intellectual turmoil and 
 political self -consciousness = Athens. The comparison would be worth work- 
 ing out in detail. Vide Symonds, Age of Despots, chap. iii. passim, and ch. iv. 
 p. 236 ; also Freeman, Historical Essays, 2d series, p. 32.
 
 XENOPHOX. 379 
 
 artificers," by Plutarch, by Cicero, by Alberti, Sidney, Bacon, 
 down to the warm-hearted and broad- souled exponent of 
 the great Athenian Demos, of whom we have all been 
 ' hearers.' 1 
 
 But for Xenophon one may claim a more than monumental 
 title. He is also essentially a stylist, the forerunner of the 
 masters of belle Icttcre. Like Herodotus, like Pindar, like his 
 other literary compeers, he has, if in a less degree, some claim 
 to the additional meed of absolute originality, not only as 
 the inventor of a style of literature, but of many of its minor 
 subdivisions. " For Xenophon, who did imitate so excel- 
 lently, as to give us cffiyiem justi imperil, the portraiture of a 
 just empire under the name of Cyrus (as Cicero saith of him) 
 made therein an absolute heroicall poem." 2 And there are 
 poems within the poem. How novel must have appeared this 
 Eastern version of King Arthur, this premonition of the Table 
 Round, written in the choicest " euphuism " of that day ; in 
 which, round 3 the blameless king, are grouped a dozen lesser 
 characters, whose action harmoniously adjusts itself to the main 
 thesis, enlivening and assisting its development. While there 
 is room, in a natural way, also, for disquisitions on military 
 matters, for moral delineations and the growth of character, for 
 pathetic tales and skilfully interwoven episodes, like that of 
 Gobryas and Gadatas, or of Panthea and Abradatas "the 
 earliest prose love-story in European literature ;" where a place, 
 too, is found for comic supper-parties and interludes, in which 
 the fun is of a robust, broad type, contrasting with the delicately 
 ironic humour which ripples through the Anabasis, but helping, 
 and helped by, our appreciation of the Aristophanic vein of 
 the Symposium ; in both, the breadth? of the jocularity being 
 redeemed, as in Shakespeare, by truth to nature and grace of 
 style. Scarcely behind the Cyropaedia in inventiveness, and 
 its superior in a certain quality of opaline beauty, ranks the 
 Economist. It is full of the Xenophontine limpidity, the little 
 bells of alliteration, the graceful antithetic balance; the sweet 
 
 1 Grote, Hist. vol. viii. passim, compared with his Plato, vol. iii. ch. xxxix. 
 4 Sir Philip Sidney, An Apologiefor Poetrie, p. 28. 
 
 a Compare the \fsvxpfo |3a<nXei>s with Tennyson's King Arthur, Araspas with 
 Lancelot or Sir Bedivere, etc.
 
 380 XENOPHON. 
 
 sounds helping out the health} 7 sense, as of a fragrant air 
 breathed upon us from fresh and well-worked fields, where we 
 cherish content in winter by a blazing fire, or in summer lulled 
 by a trio of babbling streams, soft airs, and tender shades. 1 
 This is a work the careful thoroughness of which, and its 
 praise of Masserizia, found great favour with the Italians of the 
 Renaissance, so that Alberti, or some other, speaks of imitating 2 
 " quel Greco dolcissimo e soavissimo scrittore Seriophonte." 
 
 This Cicero indeed had done before, 3 whose remarks upon 
 the style of Xenophon are worth remembering. 4 " The Muses 
 they say spoke by the lips of Xenophon." " I have come across 
 students of forensic oratory who wished to take Xenophon as 
 their model, cujus sermo est ille quidem melle dulcior, sed a 
 forensi strepitu remotissimus ; " 5 and in praise of his portrait of 
 Agesilaus, " Xenophon's one little book, as a panegyric, is 
 better than all the pictures and statues put together," " in 
 eo rege laudando facile omnes imagines omnium statuasque 
 superavit ;" 6 or again, in an interesting discussion of the 
 qualities requisite for writing history, in which we get a 
 comparison of Roman and Greek standards with criticisms of 
 different historians, Xenophon and Callisthenes, two "philo- 
 sophic" historians, emanating respectively from Socrates and 
 Aristotle, are contrasted. The Aristotelian wrote "rhetorico 
 paene more ;" the Socratic " leniore quidem sono est usus, et qui 
 ilium impetum oratoris non habeat, vehemens fortasse minus, 
 sed aliquanto tamen est, ut mihi quidem. videtur, dulcior." 7 
 Reference has already been made to Cicero's translations of 
 Xenophon, and the rendering by this great monotheistic Latin 
 of Cyrus's dying speech on immortality was nothing less than a 
 handing on of the torch to after times, a torch not yet quite anti- 
 quated in pattern. 8 His estimate of the work itself is nearly 
 
 1 Oecon. v. 7. The ' horizontal ' structure of the Xenophontine sentence is 
 conspicuous in this work ; the members balancing with a tender minuet-like 
 movement. 2 Opere volgari cli Leon-Battista Alberti. 
 
 3 Fragments of Cicero's translation of the Economist remain. 
 
 4 Cic. Or. xix. 62. 
 
 * Ibid. ix. 32, and on this point cf. Jebb, ii. ch. xxiv. p. 449. 
 4 Cic. Ep. ad Div. v. 12. 7. 7 Cic. de Oral. ii. xiv. 58. 
 
 8 Cicero's monotheism is felt to be more consistent and denned than Plato's 
 or Xenophon's ; de Nat. Deoiitm, i. xii. 31.
 
 XENOPHON. 381 
 
 that of Sir Philip Sidney, as above recorded. The letter to his 
 brother Quintus, 1 in which he recommends him to follow 
 the example of Africanus, and make its chapters his constant 
 companions, as containing " the whole duty of government," 
 " nullum est enim praeterniissum in his officium diligentis et 
 moderati imperii," shows the practical value attached to so 
 poetical a work. And later criticism, while ready to assign 
 greater historical importance, 2 retains the idea of a philosophic 
 and poetic treatise on the ideal monarchy, as of a work written 
 (caeteris paribus) with an object similar to that of Tacitus's 
 Germania. 
 
 The Anabasis is so well-known a book, and has been so 
 universally appreciated, that to add even a few words seems an 
 impertinence ; as if to whole generations of schoolboys tied 
 down to fragments of the classics for many years, in this book 
 at any rate had not come an " apocalypse " of Greek life ; 
 or as if its more essential, epic and Homeric, qualities had not 
 been fully and affectionately enough insisted on in the pages 
 of Grote (and his followers) ; yet the topic of its literary merits 
 is by no means exhausted. Like the Hellenica, it seems to 
 hinge on a kind of unconscious "peripety;" also, like the 
 Hellenica, read as a whole work, it contains what we may call 
 a double (Euripidean) plot. In the Anabasis the battle is the 
 crisis, and Trebizond the solution of the first plot; then comes 
 the really tragic, swinging round of Fate, the true " peripeteia." 
 Just when the situation becomes so dramatic that the joyous 
 cry from the hill-top, " The sea ! the sea !" has become a proverb, 
 and their final escape is accomplished out of the jaws of death 
 into the bosom of that friendly sea which girds their islanded 
 home ; then as a matter of fact, and perhaps in the mind of 
 the narrator, the too cruel reversal of good fortune. Persians 
 and savage tribes, and the inclemencies of Armenian snows, 
 or the intricacies of Kurdistan defiles, are nothing which 
 stout hearts cannot without too great strain surmount; but 
 at the instant at which the ingenuous grumbler, with Homer 
 on his lips, sighs to give up all this forced marching and 
 
 1 Ep. ad Qu. Fratr. 1.1. viii. 23. 
 
 8 Xenophon clearly was working upon legendary accounts ; vide Duncker, 
 Breitenbach, etc.
 
 382 XENOPHON. 
 
 picket duty, preferring to tumble into a hammock and sail 
 away home like Odysseus, 1 the real troubles of the heroic 
 little band are about to commence troubles chiefly of their 
 own countrymen. Cheirisophus goes to fetch ships from his 
 friend the Spartan admiral, but his absence is interminable ; 
 when after various vicissitudes they eventually reach Europe, 
 they are regarded, as what indeed they partly are, a wolfish 
 rabble, barely to be trusted if not tearing barbaric sheep or 
 turning their teeth against one another. The Spartan governor- 
 general in Byzantium by a ruse succeeds in kidnapping and 
 knocking down to the hammer as slaves about 600 of the band. 
 The semi-barbarian Thraciaii Seuthes is no better than the civi- 
 lised Greek. Dissension too has broken up their ranks, and it 
 requires all the piety of Xenophon to sustain him until the 
 finger of Zeus Meilichios is plainly visible at Pergamus, 2 when 
 " the Lacedaemonians, the captains and the rest of the generals, 
 and the soldiers generally, united to give him the pick of horses 
 and cattle and other spoil, so that now he could do a friend a 
 good turn ; and meanwhile Thimbron arrived, and he received 
 the Cyreiaus, whom he incorporated with the rest of his 
 Hellenic forces, and proceeded to prosecute a war against Tissa- 
 phernes and Pharnabazus." 
 
 In the Hellenica there is a similar twofold climax corre- 
 sponding to the well-known division of the work : the first 
 attained in the reconciliation of the Demos and the Eleusiniaii 
 supporters of the Thirty is the finale of the work of Thucydides. 3 
 The second and larger volume has been described as The Epic 
 of Agesilaus, who is certainly to some extent the protagonist ; 
 but the pivot of the piece, the peripety, is the turn of the tide 
 of Laconian prosperity, consequent, in the eyes of Xenophon, 
 upon the lawless seizure of the Theban citadel by the Spartan 
 general Phaebidas. " I do not think it would be necessary to 
 ransack either Hellenic or foreign history in proof of the pro- 
 position that the divine powers are extreme to mark what is 
 
 1 Odyssey, xiii. : " Then they alighted from the benched ship upon the land, 
 and first they lifted Odysseus from out the hollow ship, all as he was in the 
 sheet of linen and the bright rug, and laid him yet heavy with slumber 011 
 the land." BUTCHER and LANG. 
 
 2 Anab. vii. 8. 3 Hellen. ii. 4. 43.
 
 XENOPHON. 383 
 
 done amiss, winking not either at impiety or the commission of 
 unhallowed acts ; but at present it is my duty to confine myself 
 to the facts before me." 1 When the end draws nigh not too 
 soon indeed, but with a certain dimly realised dramatic effect, 
 owing to the long-sustained silence in praise and blame alike, 
 the fire of the old soldier burns ; and the historian's tongue is 
 loosed in a panegyric of the strategy of Epaminondas, and the 
 pall descends upon the great Theban, but upon Sparta herself 
 the penumbra of total eclipse. Nor is there wanting a touch of 
 pathos in the half-baffled realisation of the beginning of the end. 
 As to Guicciardini, reviewing the posture of affairs after the 
 peace of Cambray, 2 things seem pretty much unaltered ; so to 
 Xenophon after Mantinea the old balance is renewed, or rather, 
 in the language of the Greek, "Where it was expected that 
 one or other of these fell combatants would rule an empire, 
 there set in once more confusion worse confounded (not an 
 dpxn, but worse anarchy)." In the one case really the knell of 
 Venice was sounded ; in the other the prestige of humbled 
 Sparta fled with the triumphant spirit of her mighty rival. 
 The other questions connected with the Hellcnica do not fall 
 within the scope of this Essay, nor is any attempt to harmonise 
 the antique acceptance and the modern mistrust of the historian 
 here offered. Only it is well to bear in mind that the title of a 
 Sl/cato? a-wyypafavs a just historian 3 has been accorded to 
 Xenophon ; and, apart from the omissions extraordinary to a 
 modern reader, it is plain that the quality of transparency 
 which belongs to all his writings holds here even in the moral 
 import of the word ; so that his demerits, if demerits they be, 
 amount to nothing worse than a species of colour-blindness. 
 We know and he does not attempt to conceal, the point of 
 view from which he writes; moreover, as a philosopher, he- 
 has a right to his philosophy, however defective it may render 
 him as a philosophic historian, and he makes no secret of 
 his sympathy with the ideal of Sparta and Lycurgus (his 
 Laconism), or for the "aristocratic" sections of society. But 
 the quality which, like the vigour and the humour and the 
 
 1 Hellen. v. 4. 2 Symonds, Aye of Despots, iv. p. 232. 
 
 3 Lucian, vide supra, p. 327.
 
 384 XENOPHON. 
 
 healthy, joyous youthfulness of the Anabasis, permeates this 
 sadder and more sober production, is a certain vividness 
 and brightness of delineation suited to the clear skies of 
 Hellas and Asia Minor, and the sparkling waves of the Aegean 
 and the Straits. What M. Eenan has said of the Acts of the 
 Apostles may be almost verbatim applied to this work : 
 " Une brise matiuale, une odeur de mer, si j'ose le dire, in- 
 spirant quelque chose d'allegre et de fort, penetre tout le livre et 
 en fait un excellent compagnon de voyage ; le bre" viaire exquis 
 de celui qui poursuit des traces antiques sur les mers du midi." 1 
 The Hellenica is not a dull book, and the period with which it 
 is concerned however sad in part and disheartening is never 
 tedious. With it in our hands we bound over the glancing 
 waves in rhythmical obedience to our beloved Keleustes, 2 or scale 
 the heights of besieged citadels, or for the moment are friends 
 with the living personalities of a tumultuous time. We have 
 been Spartans and tramped along by forced marches in the 
 night, after the destruction of a whole army corps, on its road 
 to Amyclae : 3 thus we proudly sneaked, for fear, not so much of 
 the jeers of lukewarm friends or half foes, as of ourselves and 
 the evil that might come of it. We have crossed the heights at 
 Creusis between Attica and Boeotia, and our shields have been 
 snatched by a violent tornado from us and whirled into the 
 abyss. 4 We have watched the deadlock at Coroneia, and seen the 
 slain with their shields battered, their swords snapt off at the 
 hilt, their daggers still clutched between their fingers, etc.; 5 and 
 all these things, page after page, has Xenophon by his photo- 
 graphic art arid his Euripidean or Zeuxis-like skill, 6 wrought for 
 us ; so that the feeling left on our minds is one of exhilaration 
 and content. Of course, if we had had the making of those 
 days and persons, we should have provided that the hero friend 
 of Xenophon should be Epaminondas not Agesilaus ; but the 
 gods, it seems, willed it otherwise, and so this matter has 
 issued thus. 
 
 1 Eenan, St. Paul, pp. 12, 13. 2 Cf. Oecon. xxi. 3. 4. 
 
 8 Hetten. iv. 5. 4 Ibid. v. 4. 17. 6 Ibid. iv. 3. 19 ; Agesil. ii. 14. 
 
 6 Three instances, at least, of what may be called Euripidean art, may be 
 mentioned, how (Anab, ii. 5. 33) after the generals were seized and the 
 army waited in expectation, suddenly sight was caught of a man galloping
 
 XENOPHON. 385 
 
 Before we part with our author, let us briefly summarise 
 certain things in which, ceasing to be merely representative of 
 his days, he seems to utter things to come. His pregnancy in a 
 variety of departments is remarkable, and to be traced probably 
 to the underlying subjectivity of his disposition, which takes 
 him as it were out of the ordinary objective setting of his 
 fellows. Hence his colonisation schemes and higher specula- 
 tions on the conquest of the east already mentioned, the pro- 
 phecy here pointing through Agesilaus and the rest to the 
 times of Alexander, but as yet there are many years to run, 
 and Xenophon will not live to see that day. Again, in his 
 quasi-philosophical and political pamphlets he may be said to 
 be pointing through Isocrates and his school to Aristotle. In 
 his high standard of moral self-culture, in the rcaprepia of his 
 women, he is anticipative of stoicism. In just that faint 
 touch of orientalism, the unnameable somewhat reminding us 
 of Mithra worship in the east ; possibly also in his admiration 
 of the same Cyrus who restored the Jews, he is anticipative 
 of the interblending of two worlds of Semitic monotheism 
 and Greek science. In his purity and mistrust of pleasures 
 which seduce the soul, and in his religiousness generally, he 
 makes us realise how the earth prepared herself for the seed 
 of Pauline Christianity; nay, in a certain sense we seem to 
 be aware of something which we held to be peculiar to Pro- 
 testantism. Is this a Hellenic Havelock ? But not least of 
 all this pregnancy belongs to his style, the antithesis and grace 
 of which have a ring of Italian or Elizabethan " euphuism." l 
 The love-story of Panthea, and the whole court and courtesy 
 
 wildly the Arcadian Nicarchus who had escaped with a wound in the belly 
 he rode into camp holding his entrails in to tell the news ; or, again, how 
 (Cyr. vi. 4. 9) Panthea bade sad but stout-hearted farewell to her husband 
 whom she was not to see alive again, and ran to give a last kiss unperceived 
 to the chariot which held him. Abradatas turned and looked upon her and 
 said, "Be strong and of a good courage, Panthea, and hie thee home." And 
 how (Cyr. vii. 3. 9) the same lady tenderly kissed and replaced the poor 
 dismembered right hand of her dead lord, which Cyrus, unwitting of what 
 was done, had grasped in friendly sorrow. With Cyrus we also weep for some 
 time in sorrow. 
 
 1 The ancients fully appreciated the yorjrela or witchery of his style ; a 
 quality not to be discerned in translations offered only as reminiscences of the 
 writer's thought. 
 
 2 B
 
 386 XENOPHON. 
 
 of the prince, are as near the romance of chivalry as aught 
 Hellenic can be ; while last of all, in the mere lucidity and 
 " plainness " of his Attic, not excluding foreign and poetic words, 
 he is the author of what must always from the first Imve been, 
 and in modern Hellas is probably destined in a still higher 
 degree to become, the model of expression, a transcendental 
 
 Is the fame of Xenophon decreasing ? That is scarcely cred- 
 ible. At various periods he has stood high in the appreciation 
 of mankind, and for various reasons ; nor is it likely that any 
 partial obscuration of his brightness will last long. The modern 
 historic sense will assuredly remove the scales from our eyes. 
 Nor though it has chanced to Xenophon, because he wrote 
 history, to be weighed in the balances against Thucydides, and 
 condemned ; though it has also befallen him, on the ground of 
 his delineation of Socrates, to be compared with Plato and 
 voted no philosopher ; though it has been his paradoxical fate 
 to have stood somewhat in his own light, and, as the author of 
 the Anabasis, partly to have effaced his own reputation as the 
 author of less appreciated works, none of these mishaps are 
 real misfortunes. The " chef-d'ceuvre," Victor Hugo has said, 
 " is on a par with the chef-d'ceuvre," or, as a more ancient 
 prophet words it, " One star differeth from another star in glory." 
 The glory of philosophic history is one ; the glory of Pla- 
 tonic philosophy is another ; and there is a third glory of the 
 " fair and gentle " " beautiful and brave " Hellenic culture, 
 which is Xenophon. If pallid, the light of this genius has a 
 lustre of its own, once discerned, not soon to be lost sight of, 
 a potency of tender, transparent brightness, which invites the 
 gaze, undimmed by the fiercer rays, or more mystic brilliancy, 
 of larger luminaries blazing in envious proximity. But to the 
 scientific student the spectrum yielded by this planet is of even 
 weightier importance. 
 
 H. G. D.
 
 POLYBIUS. 
 
 No ancient writer of equal interest and importance finds fewer 
 readers than Polybius. It is probable that for a hundred 
 Englishmen familiar with Herodotus and Thucydides not more 
 than three or four would be found who had made the acquaint- 
 ance of the third great Greek historian. The struggle between 
 Eome and Carthage for the foremost place in the world, and 
 its result in the establishment of Eoman domination over the 
 whole circle of the Mediterranean States, present a topic un- 
 surpassed in history; and in knowledge, in industry, and in 
 candour, Poly b his is not unworthy of his subject. His own life 
 and fortunes are intimately involved in the great events which 
 he records. The Eoman conquest bore away the Achaean 
 statesman, brought up at the feet of Philopcemen, to be a 
 prisoner in Italy, a man of literary leisure, and a cosmopolitan 
 student of politics ; it sent him back to his native land as the 
 mouthpiece of the conquering power ; above all, it bound him 
 in ties of the closest intimacy to a Eoman friend. His life 
 seems framed as of set purpose to mould the historian who was 
 to bridge over for us the interval between the Greek and the 
 Eoman world. With all his excellences, it is not probable that 
 Polybius will ever be widely read. He cannot command the 
 tones to sway or impress the mind. His book remains a store- 
 house from which the historian and the antiquary may draw, 
 rather than a possession to enrich the mind of the ordinary 
 reader. The neglect which he has experienced leaves a wide 
 choice of comparatively fresh and unknown material, and may 
 justify the endeavour to give a short account of Polybius and 
 his work, with some attempts at criticism, and some elements 
 of a judgment on his qualifications as a writer of history. 
 
 Polybius was by birth a citizen of Megalopolis in Arcadia, 
 the most vigorous and uncompromising member of the Achaean
 
 388 POLYBIUS. 
 
 League. He tells us with pride how Megalopolis and Stym- 
 phalus were the only cities in which Cleomenes of Sparta 
 could not find a partisan or a traitor. 1 Cleomenes, with the 
 aid of some Messenians, to whom Megalopolis had given hos- 
 pitable shelter, finally succeeded in surprising and capturing 
 the town (223 B.C.) The inhabitants for the most part escaped 
 and retired into Messenia. There a message reached them 
 from the Spartan king, -with offers to restore their town and 
 territory uninjured, if only they would separate themselves 
 from the Achaean Federation. The refugees refused to hear 
 the letter to the end. "They chose," says their countryman, 2 
 " to be deprived of their lands, their graves, their country, and 
 their goods, of everything, in a word, that men hold dearest, 
 rather than flinch from their good faith to their allies." The 
 full wrath of Cleomenes now fell on the town itself : " he laid 
 it waste so savagely and vindictively, that no one supposed it 
 could ever be made habitable again." 3 
 
 The victory of Antigonus and the Macedonians, and the 
 extinction of the power of Sparta after its brief flicker of 
 renewed life under Cleomenes, restored the people of Megalo- 
 polis to their ruined home. What followed is known to us by 
 Polybius's account of a commission granted by the Achaean 
 League to their President, Aratus, four years later, to settle 
 the discords of Megalopolis ; the passage may be worth quoting 
 as an illustration of the sort of difficulties which beset the 
 internal politics of a Greek State : 
 
 " Their spirit was unbroken, but they were crippled by want 
 of means, public or private. And, as usual, when means are 
 deficient, controversies and jealousies and quarrels were rife 
 amongst them. The first subject of dispute was about the 
 fortifications ; some thought they ought to contract them to a 
 size which would enable them to make an end of the business 
 of building at once, and also to man them in any sudden 
 emergency ; and they attributed their present disaster to the 
 extent of the works and the difficulty of guarding the whole 
 line. Besides, it was held by some that the landowners ought 
 to contribute a third of their possessions, so as to fill up the 
 
 1 ii. 55. 8 ii. 61.
 
 POLYBIUS. 3 8 9 
 
 ranks by addition of fresh citizens. The other party would 
 neither submit to make the city smaller, nor consent to con- 
 tribute a third of their land. But the chief cause of contention 
 was the constitution drawn up by Prytanis. He was one of 
 the leaders of the Peripatetic sect, and had been nominated to 
 legislate for them by Antigonus." l 
 
 The Achaean arbitrator seems to have been more successful 
 than the Aristotelian philosopher. The difficulties were at 
 length settled, and the city took its old place in the League. 
 Aratus himself was a native of Sikyou. But the other great 
 men whose policy gave dignity to the last years of Greek 
 freedom, Philopcemen, Lycortas, and Polybius, all sprang from 
 Megalopolis : 
 
 " The League," after years of modest obscurity, " at last 
 found leaders worthy to represent it, and then it quickly mani- 
 fested its power by accomplishing the noblest of tasks, the 
 concord of Peloponnesus. The credit of being the originator 
 and pioneer of this policy must be assigned to Aratus of Sikyon; 
 Philopcemen of Megalopolis was its champion, and consum- 
 mated it in action ; and its consolidation and subsistence, up to 
 the present time, is due to Lycortas and those who followed 
 his lead." 2 
 
 Philopcemen served as a young man under Antigonus in the 
 decisive battle with Cleomenes (221 B.C.), and on the death of 
 Aratus, in 213 B.C.,' succeeded to the position of foremost man 
 of the League. Lycortas first appears in the narrative in 186 
 B.C., 3 and must have been many years junior to Philopcemen. 
 Polybius was the son of Lycortas. 
 
 Our historian was thus brought up in the midst of the circle 
 of Greek statesmen who staked their hopes upon the Achaean 
 League, and who, while anxious above all things to avoid 
 collision with the overpowering strength of Kome, and willing 
 to appear as her ally in all her contests in the East, never- 
 theless strove to maintain an attitude of independence, and to 
 manage the affairs of Greece without Roman intervention. 
 Their policy is summed up in the rebuke which Philopoemen 
 administered to Aristsenus, the leader of the Roman party: 
 
 1 v. 93. ii. 40. xxiii. 1.
 
 390 POL YSIUS. 
 
 " Man, why are you in such haste to behold the fate that waits 
 for Greece ?" 
 
 Polybius was selected as the youth who was to bear the urn 
 containing the ashes of Philopcemen to the tomb (183 B.C.). 
 The first reference in his History 1 to his own personal recol- 
 lection is the record of a political conversation held by 
 Philopcemen two years before his death, in the presence of 
 Polybius, in which the young man silently disapproved the 
 conclusions of the President. Polybius afterwards wrote a 
 biography of Philopcemen, which has not been preserved. In 
 his History, while freely criticising some of Philopcemen's 
 actions, he always shows a loyal respect and affection for the 
 memory of his leader. 
 
 We next find Polybius, three years later (180 B.C.), selected 
 as one of the ambassadors who were to renew the alliance of 
 the Achseans with Ptolemy Epiphanes, king of Egypt. He 
 tells us 2 that at this time he was too young to be legally 
 qualified for the post, but was nevertheless chosen on account 
 of the friendly relations existing between his father, Lycortas, 
 and the Egyptian Court. The death of Ptolemy rendered this 
 mission abortive. 
 
 We now pass on to the year 169 B.C. The great struggle 
 between Perseus and the Romans was at its height. Lycortas, 
 Polybius, and Archon had succeeded Philopcemen as leaders of 
 the moderate party among the Achseans, which had to steer a 
 difficult and dangerous course between the servile tools of 
 Rome on the one hand, and the reckless partisans of Macedon 
 on the other. Their attitude of neutrality had caused offence 
 at Rome, and the Roman commissioners sent by Mancinus, the 
 consul of the previous year, are said to have intended to 
 denounce them all as secret supporters of Macedon, but to have 
 been deterred by the utter lack of evidence against them. 3 
 
 Polybius, convinced that action was necessary, now 
 separated from the policy of his father, who still counselled 
 neutrality, and declared, along with Archon, for an alliance 
 with Rome. Archon was thereupon elected President for the 
 year, with Polybius for Master of the Horse. 4 
 
 1 xxiii. 10 a. 2 xxv. 7. 
 
 s xxviii. 3. 4 xxviii. 6.
 
 POLYS I US. 30 1 
 
 It was now formally resolved to raise a general levy of the 
 Achaean forces, to assist the Romans against Macedon; and 
 while his chief was collecting the troops, Polybius was 
 despatched into Thessaly to inform the consul, Marcius 
 Philippus, of their approach. Marcius, while thanking the 
 Achteans, declined the proffered assistance. The levy was 
 countermanded, but Polybius remained in the Roman camp, 
 and_took part in the campaign. Afterwards, by direction of 
 the consul, he returned home to relieve the Achoeans from 
 the burden of a requisition of 5000 troops which had been 
 made on them by a subordinate Roman officer who had the 
 command in Epirus. 1 
 
 It was probably about this time that Polybius introduced a 
 system of telegraphy for use in war. Preconcerted fire-signals 
 had long been used. We hear of " hostile " and " friendly " 
 signals, i.e. "danger," and "all's well;" 2 and this principle 
 had been elaborated by ingenious contrivances which enabled 
 a longer or shorter display of the light to indicate this or that 
 message; 3 but its use was necessarily limited to the con- 
 veyance of information that was expected, and for which the 
 signals could be arranged beforehand. The new system was to 
 telegraph single letters instead of sentences. The idea was 
 due, says Polybius, 4 to Cleoxenus and Democleitus ; but he 
 himself was the first to work it out in practice. The alphabet 
 was written out on five tablets, each containing five letters. 
 The signal-station consisted of two beacon-towers. The 
 number of lamps displayed on the left-hand beacon showed 
 the tablet to be referred to ; that on the right showed the 
 number of the letter signalled in its own tablet. Thus, one 
 lamp to the left and three to the right indicates the third letter 
 in the first tablet, 7. Two lamps displayed to the left and one 
 to the right means the first letter on the second tablet, In 
 this way letter after letter might be telegraphed, until a com- 
 plete message was conveyed. 
 
 Next year we find Polybius nominated as lieutenant to his 
 
 1 xxviii. 11. * xii. 12 a. 
 
 3 In the system described in x. 44, this was managed by a sort of water- 
 clock set running at each station so long as the light was displayed. 
 
 4 x. 45-47.
 
 392 POLYBIUS. 
 
 father, who was to lead a small Achaean contingent to Egypt 
 at the request of the sons of the late king, to aid in protecting 
 them against the Syrians. It may seem strange that those who 
 aspired to the position of the leading statesmen of Peloponnesus 
 should have been content to become the captains of a body of 
 twelve hundred men who were to serve as mercenaries in a 
 foreign country. But such an adventure was quite in character 
 with the habits of the Greek statesmen of the day. Even 
 Philopcemen more than once employed an interval of leisure 
 from Peloponnesian politics, by serving as a soldier of fortune 
 in the constant wars between the petty townships of Crete. 
 In the present case, Lycortas and his son doubtless felt that 
 their game was played out in Greece. The fate of the Mace- 
 donian monarchy could no longer be doubtful to such keen 
 observers ; and with the complete victory of Borne would come 
 the domination in Greece of the party which had thrown away 
 all regard for right and patriotism, and resolved to know no 
 rule of conduct except the rule of subserviency to every whim 
 of a Eoman commissioner. Thus the prospect of an honourable 
 exile, with some chance of glory and booty, was not unaccept- 
 able to the Achaean chiefs. Their rival Callicrates urged that 
 there was no occasion for an armed contingent, and that it 
 would be enough to send an embassy to mediate between the 
 belligerents. The matter was on the point of being decided in 
 favour of Lycortas, when a letter was brought into the assembly 
 from Marcius Philippus, requesting that the Achseans would 
 support a mission of mediation which the Romans were sending 
 to Egypt. The request was taken as a command, and the pro- 
 posal for an armed expedition was withdrawn. 1 
 
 These instances of compliance did not serve to avert the 
 impending danger. Perseus was defeated and made prisoner, 
 and ten commissioners were sent by the Senate to arrange, in 
 concert with the victorious general, ^Emilius Paullus, the 
 affairs of the peninsula (167-165 B.C.). This was the oppor- 
 tunity of Callicrates and the so-called " Eoman party." They 
 denounced all their opponents as enemies of Eome, and the 
 commissioners were only too ready to lend an ear to their 
 calumnies. JEmilius Paullus himself disapproved the action 
 
 1 xxix. 8-10.
 
 POLYBIUS. 393 
 
 of the commission. 1 The papers of Perseus were ransacked in 
 vain for proofs of complicity. But the judges had made up 
 their minds beforehand. We are not informed of the fate of 
 Lycortas ; but Polybius was one of a thousand of the leading 
 men of the Achseaiis who were deported to Italy, nominally to 
 await a trial before the Senate on the charges brought against 
 them. No trial ever took place : the suspected persons were 
 detained year after year in Italy, and the Senate put aside 
 every petition either for the investigation of their guilt or for 
 leave to return to their country. In Greece the popular 
 indignation against the sycophants who had procured their 
 ruin was intense. The children as they came from school used 
 the privilege of infancy to shout " traitor " after them in the 
 street. If one of them gained a prize in the public games, the 
 announcement of his name was greeted with storms of hissing. 
 If one of them used the public baths, no one else would enter 
 until the bath-man had let out all the water and put in fresh ; 
 " for every one thought he would be polluted by washing in 
 the water which Callicrates or Aiidronidas had touched." 2 
 
 At length, after seventeen years, when death had thinned 
 the ranks of the exiles, and it became evident that, as Cato 
 said, " the only question that remained was whether the under- 
 takers of Italy or of Greece were to have the burying of them," 
 the remnant, to the number of three hundred, were released. 
 Meanwhile their native land, stripped of its best citizens, had 
 been torn by factions. Servility had been followed by reaction. 
 In their despair men plunged into wild schemes of resistance 
 to Rome, and of savage vengeance on their domestic enemies. 
 Rome was in no temper to pardon ; her sentences were harsh 
 and humiliating ; the party of revolt got the upper hand, and 
 a hopeless war followed (146 B.C.). 
 
 " Fortune," Polybius says, 3 " strove to save Greece ; but the 
 folly of the rulers trampled all her gifts underfoot. At last, as 
 the only means of salvation, she granted a complete and speedy 
 defeat, before the Romans had time to be exasperated by resist- 
 ance, or the revolutionists to be encouraged to fresh excesses 
 by a momentary triumph." 
 
 His exile in Italy was the turning-point of the life of 
 
 1 xxx. 10. 2 xxx. 20. 8 xl. 5 (abridged).
 
 POL YBIUS. 
 
 Polybius. It removed him from political conflicts ; it gave 
 him at once leisure for his great work, and rare opportunities 
 for observing events and collecting information. He became 
 the friend of the most eminent Eomans of the day. We find 
 him accompanying Scipio in Africa, and Mummius in Greece. 
 His influence at Rome is illustrated by the fact that he had 
 interest enough to procure for the Locrians of Italy a much- 
 coveted exemption from service in the Spanish and Dalmatian 
 wars. 1 
 
 Apart from his labours as a historian, the interest of 
 Polybius's life henceforth centres round two points : first, his 
 position as mediator between his countrymen and the con- 
 querors ; and secondly, the romantic friendship which united 
 him to the younger Scipio. 
 
 Polybius returned to Greece to see the political ideal of his 
 youth rudely shattered. Corinth, the capital of the Acheeans, 
 was destroyed under his eyes, and he records how he saw the 
 choicest pictures of Greece lying on the ground, and the Roman 
 soldiers using them as boards to play dice on. 2 Polybius had 
 the satisfaction of pleading with success for the preservation of 
 the statues of Aratus and Philopoemen, which some of the 
 more brutal of the Romans wished to destroy. 3 But the 
 Achaean League, their true monument, was swept away beyond 
 all hope of restitution. In the bitterness of his heart Polybius 
 exclaims that it would be better to be even as Carthage : 
 
 " Though the fate of Carthage might seem to be the greatest 
 of all possible calamities, yet one may well regard that which 
 then befel Greece as not less, or even in some respects greater. 
 For the former, their end is their plea with posterity, 4 but the 
 latter have left not so much as a plausible excuse for those 
 who would fain plead their cause. The Carthaginians, at the 
 moment of their fall, perished from off the face of the earth, 
 and were thenceforth insensible of their misfortunes : but the 
 Greeks look on at their own calamities, and hand down their 
 losses as an inheritance to their children's children ; so that just 
 as we count those who live on under torture more wretched 
 
 1 xii. 5. 2 xl. 7. 3 xl. 8. 
 
 4 T!6Trov !:crx aTOV o.Tro\oyias ye ?rp6s TOUS tiriyiyvofjitvovs irepl a<f>>v 
 Compare Shakespeare's "If not, the end of life cancels all bonds."
 
 POLYS I US. 395 
 
 than those who expire under their torments, so we should 
 esteem the fate of the Greeks yet more pitiable than that which 
 befel the Carthaginians." 1 
 
 Worse than all, Folybius felt that his countrymen had 
 brought their fate on themselves, and that it was his duty as a 
 historian to expose their faults, and to give his verdict against 
 them. There is something pathetic in the contrast between 
 his feelings as a Greek and the sternness of his historical 
 judgment : 
 
 " Some perhaps will blame me and think that I write in a 
 hostile spirit, I who ought of all men to palliate the errors of 
 the Greeks. But I hold that men of sense will never esteem 
 him a true friend who shrinks through fear from downright 
 speaking, nor him a good citizen who deserts the truth because 
 of any offence it may give at the moment. It is unpardonable 
 for the historian to set anything whatever above the truth. A 
 record handed down 'to posterity extends to more persons and 
 to a further time than words uttered for a present purpose ; 
 and bearing this in mind, the writer ought to make truth his 
 first object, and his hearers to welcome this disposition. At 
 the time of these disasters it was my part, as a Greek for the 
 Greeks, to give them my aid in all ways, defending them, 
 palliating their faults, deprecating the anger of the conquerors ; 
 and this I did then and there with all sincerity. But I here 
 record for posterity the memory of the events, untinged with 
 any animosity, not seeking to please for the moment the ears 
 of my readers, but to edify their minds and save them from 
 committing the same faults again. And so I leave this 
 subject." 2 
 
 It is characteristic of Polybius that he threw himself with 
 all his might into the task of making the best of the disastrous 
 circumstances, and of alleviating as far as possible the subjec- 
 tion of his countrymen. He had thoroughly won the confidence 
 of the Eomans, and was now selected by them as the repre- 
 sentative of the Imperial power in Greece during the period of 
 transition. Polybius's own opinions were democratic, and his 
 party had always rested on popular support ; but now he was 
 
 1 xxxviii. la. a xxxviii. 1 d.
 
 396 POLYS I US. 
 
 constrained to arrange the affairs of each state in accordance 
 with the oligarchical models which their Roman masters 
 preferred. We subjoin his own account of this painful but 
 necessary and honourable task : 
 
 " The ten commissioners having completed these arrange- 
 ments sailed for Italy early in the spring, leaving behind in 
 view of all Greece an honourable specimen of Roman policy. 
 At their departure they instructed Polybius to make a progress 
 through the various states, and to clear up any points about 
 which people were in uncertainty, until they should get accus- 
 tomed to the constitution and the laws. And this charge he 
 fulfilled in process of time, so that men acquiesced in the con- 
 stitution which had been given them, and no obscurity remained 
 about any point of law, public or private." l 
 
 Polybius regarded this labour as the most useful and 
 important of his life. His countrymen recognised his services 
 with gratitude, and set up his statue where he would be best 
 pleased to have it, side by side with those of Aratus and 
 Philopcemen. 2 
 
 We turn with relief from the melancholy spectacle of the 
 enslavement of Greece to the story of the friendship of Polybius 
 and Scipio ^Emilianus. 
 
 Scipio was by birth the son of ^Emilius Paulrus, but was 
 adopted when a child by the son of Scipio Africanus the elder, 
 the conqueror of Hannibal. The early death of his adoptive 
 father left young Scipio the possessor of a great fortune, and the 
 inheritor of the first name in Rome. He was hardly more than 
 a boy when he accompanied Paullus in the war against Perseus. 
 After the victory his lather gave him the free run of the royal 
 forests of Macedon. These had been jealously preserved for 
 years ; the sport they afforded was the finest then to be found 
 in the world, and young Scipio was happy as a king 3 in his 
 magnificent playground. When he returned to Italy he shunned 
 the morning calls and the practice in the law-courts, which 
 occupied the time of other young nobles. They strove, says 
 Polybius, to keep themselves before the eye of the world by 
 
 1 xl. 10. a xl. 8. 
 
 3 I'Ofj.'.aas olov el pa
 
 POLYS I US. 397 
 
 being constantly in the Forum. Scipio found in his friend 1 
 Polybius a passionate lover of sport, and the two spent their 
 days together in the chase. Scipio's daring exploits in the 
 hunting-field passed from mouth to mouth. " Before long he 
 outstripped all his contemporaries, and gained an unprecedented 
 reputation, though the way he took to acquire it ran counter to 
 all the habits and customs of the Eomans." 2 
 
 The beginning of their intimacy must be told in Polybius's 
 words. 3 
 
 " As the process of our story and the period of events bring 
 us to this family, I wish now to fulfil, for the benefit of the curious, 
 the promise I held out in the last book. I undertook to relate 
 why and how the reputation of Scipio in Eome rose to such a 
 height and burst forth into such unexpected lustre ; and further, 
 how the affection and the intimacy between him and Polybius 
 became so strong, that not only did the fame of it reach through- 
 out Italy and Greece, but even distant nations heard the story of 
 their friendship and association. I have already stated that 
 their first relations arose out of reading books together and 
 literary conversation. As their intimacy advanced, Fabius and 
 Scipio, the sons of Paullus, begged of the praetor to have Poly- 
 bius remain at Rome, when the other Achseans who were under 
 detention were interned in the country towns of Italy. After 
 this they were constantly in one another's society. One day 
 the three walked together out of the house of Fabius, and Fabius 
 took the turn towards the Forum, while Polybius and Scipio 
 went in the other direction. As they walked, Scipio, blushing 
 scarlet, and in subdued and gentle tones spoke thus : ' How is 
 it, Polybius, we have been dining, two brothers together, and 
 yet you always talk to Fabius, and put your questions and 
 address your remarks to him and set me aside ? It is clear that 
 you share the opinion which I hear my fellow-citizens have of 
 me : they think me tame and dull, unlike a Roman in character 
 and action because I do not choose to speak in the courts ; and 
 they say that I am not the stuff for the head of such a house as 
 I am sprung from ; and this grieves me to the heart.' Polybius 
 
 rbf TOV IIoXi//3foi/ Trpis roOro rb /a^pos ti>0ovffiaff/j.6v. 
 2 xxxii. 15, * xxxii. 9.
 
 398 POLYBIUS. 
 
 was astounded to hear the lad (for he was not more than eighteen 
 years old at the time) begin the conversation in this strain, and 
 he replied, ' For heaven's sake, Scipio, do not speak so, or let 
 such notions enter your head. I am not despising you or set- 
 ting you aside ; far from it, but as your brother is the elder, 
 when w r e are in company I begin with him, and refer my 
 remarks and plans to his decision, and lean on his judgment, 
 assuming that you share his views. But you astonish me when 
 you say that you are too gentle for the son of such a house ; 
 this reserve is the best evidence of force of character. For my 
 part I would gladly devote myself as your fellow-worker to 
 make you in speech and action worthy of your ancestors. For 
 in the studies, into which you now throw your interests and 
 your efforts, neither you nor your brother will have any lack of 
 ready helpers ; for I see that a throng of such persons is pouring 
 over from Greece. But in the matters which now distress you, 
 as you say, I think you will not find any fitter companion and 
 fellow-worker than myself.' Before Polybius had done speak- 
 ing, Scipio seized his hand with both his own, and pressing it 
 fervently, exclaimed ' Would that I might see the day when 
 you will make me your first interest and be my comrade. From 
 that day forth I shall feel that I am not unworthy of my house 
 and my ancestors.' Polybius was charmed with the fervour and 
 open-heartedness of the lad, but was not without misgiving as 
 he thought of the greatness of his house and the wealth and 
 station of its members. But from the time of this compact 
 young Scipio would never part from Polybius, and preferred his 
 society to everything else. And as time went on, and the 
 friends found each other faithful through the course of an un- 
 broken intimacy, they conceived for one another an affection 
 and devotion as of kindred or brethren." 
 
 Apart from its interest as an account of this notable friend- 
 ship, the passage is instructive as showing that Scipio, like 
 most great orators, was a man of nervous and sensitive tempera- 
 ment. In later years, when he had overcome his reserve and 
 shyness, he was a master of impassioned outbursts of invective. 
 When the Roman mob, swollen with a motley throng of en- 
 franchised slaves, tried to shout him down whilst speaking, he 
 exclaimed, " Silence, you to whom Italy is not mother but step-
 
 POL YBIUS. 399 
 
 mother ; " and as the clamour rose again, " Do you think I will 
 fear those let loose, whom I brought in chains to the slave- 
 market ? " 
 
 Another anecdote of Polybius's life in Rome shows the 
 historian in a somewhat unexpected light, as a man with a 
 love for an adventure, and ready to run a considerable risk 
 from a good-natured wish to help an acquaintance in difficulty. 
 Demetrius, a grandson of Antiochus the Great, had been shame- 
 fully treated by the Roman senate. He had been sent to Rome 
 when a child, as a hostage on behalf of his father, Seleucus, 
 who was then king of Syria. Seleucus died, and was succeeded 
 by his brother, Antiochus Epiphanes. Demetrius now claimed 
 release ; for he was no sort of hostage for the behaviour of his 
 uncle, who would have been glad enough to see him out of the 
 way. The Senate refused his petition. In process of time 
 Antiochus died, and Demetrius, as the eldest member of the 
 family, was the lawful heir to the throne. The Senate, how- 
 ever, preferred to acknowledge the young son of Antiochus, 
 and sent commissioners, nominally to act as guardians to the 
 infant prince. These commissioners, acting on instructions 
 from Rome, proceeded to burn the ships of their ward, to ham- 
 string his elephants, and to weaken the kingdom by every 
 means in their power. The ministers whom they set up were 
 notorious for misgovernment, and were hated by the people ; 
 and there was no doubt that if Demetrius could once set foot 
 in Syria he would be received with acclamation. The preten- 
 der was jealously detained in Italy, where he consoled himself 
 with wine and hunting. This last amusement brought him 
 into contact with Polybius : he confided his troubles to him, 
 and Polybius resolved to plan his escape. He persuaded a 
 Greek friend, who was at Rome on a mission from Ptolemy, to 
 charter a vessel as if for his own return to Egypt. At the last 
 moment the Alexandrine envoy sent word to the captain of the 
 vessel that business detained him in Rome, and that he would 
 send in his stead some friends with important letters for home. 
 Demetrius, to avoid suspicion, sent out his servants with dogs 
 and nets, instructing them to meet him at Circeii for a hunting 
 party. He then went to dinner at the house of a friend. 
 Polybius was at the time confined to his bed by illness, and
 
 400 POLYBIUS. 
 
 was uneasy for fear that Demetrius should spoil everything by 
 getting drunk at his dinner-party. He therefore sent one of 
 his slaves with a sealed packet which was to be silently placed 
 in Demetrius's hand at the dinner-table. The letter when 
 opened contained no signature, but only a string of wise say- 
 ings extracted from the poets about the virtues of sobriety, 
 resolution, and prompt action. Demetrius took the hint and 
 retired from table. He left Eome, as if to join the hunters at 
 Circeii, and hurried on board the ship which was moored at 
 Ostia. The captain had not the least suspicion who was his 
 passenger, and set sail immediately. It was not till the fourth 
 day that Demetrius's retinue, uneasy at his breaking his appoint- 
 ment at Circeii, returned to Eome and gave the alarm ; and by 
 the time the matter came to the ears of the government, 
 Demetrius was beyond the Straits of Messina. He recovered 
 his kingdom without much difficulty ; but the maxims on 
 sobriety, which Polybius had been so careful to copy out for 
 him, failed to impress him permanently, and hard drinking 
 soon put an end to his life. The plans of his Greek friends 
 were so well laid, that no suspicion seems to have been aroused 
 as to their part in the escape, till Polybius himself told the 
 story years after in the course of his narrative. 1 
 
 The great business of Polybius's life was the collection of 
 materials for his History. He had the advantage of living at 
 the capital, in the very centre of political events, yet with the 
 leisure and impartiality of a spectator. He was the most un- 
 wearied and conscientious collector of information. He knew 
 that his work would be read by Roman critics, and he specially 
 appeals to them to confirm the accuracy of his account of 
 Roman institutions. He has the true instinct of a great 
 historian in dealing with original documents. He does not 
 load his pages with references to petty inscriptions, and he 
 laughs good-humouredly at Timpeus, 2 a sort of Dryasdust, who 
 would pounce with delight on an error of three months in the 
 synchronism of Athenian archons and Argive priestesses, and 
 " who pried into what was written on the columns in the back 
 premises of temples and the compacts of hospitality on the 
 
 xxxi. 19-23. *xii. 11.
 
 POLYBIUS. 401 
 
 door-posts." But where inscriptions will throw light on any 
 questions that lie along the main lines of the history, he spares 
 no trouble to avail himself of them. Finding contradictory 
 accounts of the various treaties between Rome and Carthage, 
 he studied and translated the originals, some of them written 
 in language so archaic as to be almost unintelligible to the 
 Romans of his day. 1 If he gives the numbers of Hannibal's 
 army at different dates, it is always on the authority of an 
 inscription set up by Hannibal himself at the Lacinian pro- 
 montory before he left Italy. 2 For events before his time, or 
 out of the reach of his personal knowledge, Polybius hunted 
 up the evidence of eye-witnesses. He still found men alive 
 who remembered the passage of Hannibal over the Alps. 3 He 
 checked the Roman accounts of the Punic Wars by cross- 
 questioning Carthaginians, and he refers especially to the infor- 
 mation given him by Massinissa, the veteran king of Numidia, 
 who had fought under the first Scipio, and who lived to see the 
 beginning of the Third Punic War. 4 In his account of the 
 obscure negotiations of Perseus and Eumenes (a matter in 
 regard to which modern historians have been inclined to throw 
 doubt on the veracity of Polybius), we find that he gathered his 
 information from the Macedonian courtiers who were privy to 
 the transaction. 5 
 
 Polybius travelled far and wide to see with his own eyes 
 the scenes of the events he describes. He points out most 
 fairly the disadvantages under which previous writers had lain 
 in their geographical descriptions. Eye-witnesses of distant 
 countries were rare ; and even these were hampered by the 
 difficulties of language and the dangers of savage lands, and had 
 every temptation to eke out their scanty information by the 
 invention of mere travellers' stories. So far, then, from blaming 
 his predecessors for their mistakes, he would rather give them 
 all credit for any advance in knowledge which they effected. 
 
 " But in our day Asia, by the conquests of Alexander, and 
 the rest of the world, by the supremacy of the Romans, have 
 become almost everywhere accessible by sea and by land ; and 
 the same events, by withdrawing from men of energy all objects 
 
 1 iii. 22 seq. 2 iii. 33. 3 iii. 48. 
 
 4 ix. 25. 5 xxix. 1 e. 
 
 2 C
 
 402 POL YBIUS. 
 
 of ambition in war and politics, have given occasion to great 
 interest and curiosity about those other subjects ; and thus 
 it is incumbent on us to acquire better and more accurate 
 knowledge of what was before obscure. This it shall be my 
 endeavour to set forth in its place, and this was my chief in- 
 centive to undergo the dangers and hardships of journeys in 
 Libya, Spain, and Gaul, and on the sea that forms the further 
 boundary of these countries." 1 
 
 He is thus able to speak from personal measurements of the 
 plan of the city of Carthagena ; 2 and he followed the footsteps 
 of Hannibal across the Alps that he might be the better 
 qualified to write the history of his passage. 3 Unfortunately, 
 Polybius's power of graphic delineation of localities is not 
 equal to his industry, and his account of Hannibal's route falls 
 far short of the clear and exact description which he is careful 
 to promise his readers. 
 
 Polybius makes use of his notes of travel to enrich his book 
 with much curious information about the countries through 
 which he passed. The fertility of Spain, for instance, is illus- 
 trated by elaborate statistics of the price of commodities, 
 evidently gained from personal experience. 4 The natural 
 history of the island of Corsica gives him an opportunity of 
 correcting his rival Timseus, on whose blunders he always 
 comments with satisfaction. 
 
 " His assertions about the island of Corsica are on a level 
 with his random talk about Libya. He states, in his account 
 of Corsica, in the second book, that it contains numbers of 
 wild goats, sheep, and oxen ; and likewise deer, hares, wolves, 
 and other game ; and that the inhabitants employ themselves 
 in hunting these, and make the chase the business of their 
 lives. Now, in that island, far from there being wild goats or 
 oxen, there is not so much as a hare, a wolf, or a stag, nor any 
 other animals of the sort, excepting only foxes, rabbits, and 
 wild sheep. The rabbit at a distance looks like a small hare ; 
 but when you come to handle it, it is quite distinct both in 
 form and in the taste of its flesh, and it generally lives under 
 ground. The fact is, that the animals of the country have the 
 
 2 x. 11. 3 iii. 48.
 
 POL YB1US. 403 
 
 appearance of being wild, for the following reason. The herds- 
 men are not able to follow their beasts about on the pastures, 
 owing to the wooded, steep, and rocky nature of the ground. 
 But when they wish to collect them, they post themselves at 
 convenient stations, and sound a call with the trumpet to their 
 animals, who come running together without fail, each to its 
 own trumpet-call. The consequence is, that when persons 
 coasting along the island see goats and oxen pasturing un- 
 tended, and wish to catch them, the animals will not suffer 
 the strangers to approach them, but run away ; and when the 
 herdsman sees them making off, he blows his trumpet, and 
 immediately they hurry headlong in a drove, congregating 
 towards the call. This gives them the appearance of wildness ; 
 and thus Timasus is led into his random statement by careless 
 and insufficient inquiry. As for their obedience to the 
 trumpet, there is nothing to wonder at in that ; for in Italy, 
 likewise, the owners adopt the same plan in pasturing swine. 
 The swineherds do not follow at the heels of their beasts, as 
 among the Greeks, but walk in front, blowing the horn at 
 intervals, and the beasts follow behind, and run together 
 towards the note ; and the familiarity which each shows with 
 his proper horn is so remarkable, that those who hear of it for 
 the first time are astonished and inclined to be sceptical." 1 
 
 Another extract from Polybius's travelling note-book gives 
 us a glimpse of the cost of board and lodging in Cisalpine Gaul, 
 a land which must have been in those days a very Paradise for 
 an economically-minded tourist. 
 
 " As to the details of the produce of wine, and of the plenty 
 of the means of subsistence, we may best form a notion of 
 them from the following fact. When persons travelling 
 through the country put up at an inn, they do not bargain with 
 the landlord as to the price of each article, but ask how much 
 he charges to receive a guest ; and the innkeeper as a general 
 rule admits his lodgers, undertaking to provide them with all 
 they want, at the rate of half an as (that is a quarter of an obol) 
 for each day ; and this charge is rarely exceeded." 2 
 
 The as, when Polybius wrote, was equal in value to the 
 
 1 xii. 3. 8 ii. 15.
 
 404 POLY J3 1 US. 
 
 sixteenth part of the denarius, and a denarius contains silver to 
 the amount of about eightpence-halfpenny : it follows that a 
 man could live en pension in the valley of the Po for a fraction 
 over one farthing per diem. Two hundred years later, wine 
 was still so cheap in this district, that the jest ran that pure 
 water was a more costly liquor to drink; and Martial could 
 complain that he was cheated by the tavern-keeper, who, when 
 he called for wine and water, served him the wine neat. 1 
 
 The plan of Polybius's History was altered and extended 
 during the course of its composition. His original scheme is 
 explained in the first book, and recapitulated at the beginning 
 of the third. After two preliminary books in which are nar- 
 rated the events of the First Punic War, the revolt of the 
 Carthaginian mercenaries, the war between Eome and the Cis- 
 alpine Gauls, and the affairs of Greece in the age of Cleornenes 
 and Aratus, all as preliminary to the main subject the body 
 of the work commences with the third book, and is to comprise 
 the period of fifty-three years, from the commencement of the 
 Second Punic War down to the destruction of the kingdom of 
 Macedon after the war with Perseus. Within it fall the wars 
 with Philip of Macedon and with Antiochus, king of Syria. It 
 is the history of the steps by which Eome attained the position 
 of the dominant power in the world. 
 
 " This is the conclusion of our fifty-three years' period, and 
 within this the growth and advancement of the Eoman domina- 
 tion was accomplished; and further, it seemed agreed and 
 forced on the conviction of all men, that all that remains to 
 the world is to submit to the Eomans, and to perform whatever 
 they shall enjoin." 2 
 
 But as early as the time when Polybius published his third 
 book he had come to feel that this was insufficient. He must 
 also show how the Eomans used their supremacy, what view 
 they took of their rights and duties as the rulers of the world, 
 what was the political and social condition of the subjects, and 
 what was their state of feeling towards their masters. 
 
 1 Book iii. Ep. 56 and 57. 
 
 2 iii. 4. The fifty-three years are counted (inclusively) from 219 B.C., the 
 year of Hannibal's attack on Saguntum, to 167 B.C., the year of the settle- 
 ment of Macdonia after Paullus's victory.
 
 POL YBIUS. 405 
 
 " For it is obvious that it is by considering these points that 
 we must instruct our contemporaries whether the supremacy of 
 the Romans is a thing to be abhorred or to be accepted, and 
 form the judgment of future generations whether they are to 
 praise and imitate the Eomans, or to condemn them." 1 
 
 He will therefore make a fresh start, and relate the events 
 which succeeded the establishment of the Roman dominion, 
 down to the time when fresh wars led to the revelation of the 
 full results of the new system in the overthrow of Carthage 
 and of Greece. This adds another period of twenty-one years 
 (167-146 B.C.) to the subject-matter of his History. He is 
 urged, he says, " partly by the greatness of the events, partly by 
 the astounding nature of their consequences, but most of all 
 because he was himself so largely not only a spectator but an 
 actor in them." 2 
 
 With reference to this last point it may be noticed that 
 Polybius adopted the very strictest views as to the limits 
 of historical credibility. In the two preliminary books he 
 does not claim to be an original historian, but founds on the 
 works of his predecessors, Aratus, Philinus, and Fabius. But 
 for the main body of his work he chooses a period within the 
 reach of his own personal inquiries. 
 
 " The period which follows this date (219 B.C.), and forms the 
 subject of our History, corresponds partly with our own days 
 and partly with those of our fathers ; and from this it results 
 that some of the events happened before our eyes, and of the 
 rest we heard from those who had seen. For to stretch into 
 earlier times so as to write down a report of a report appeared 
 to us to give no security either for conclusions or assertions." 3 
 
 The traces of a change in the point of view of the writer 
 are left here and there on his work. Take, for instance, the 
 following account of the Achaean League in the second book. 4 
 
 " Concerning the Achaean nation and concerning the house 
 of Macedon, it will not be out of the way to indulge in a short 
 retrospect, seeing that our generation has witnessed the com- 
 plete annihilation of the one and the marvellous growth and 
 unity of the other. Many have attempted in past times to 
 
 1 iii. 4. 2 iii. 4. iv. 2.
 
 406 POL YBIUS. 
 
 lead the Peloponnesians to an appreciation of their common 
 interests, and none have succeeded, because they were anxious 
 rather for their own supremacy than for a liberty in which all 
 should share. But in our time this undertaking has attained 
 such a success and consummation, that not only is there an 
 association for political purposes as of friends and allies, but 
 they all have the same laws, the same weights, measures, and 
 coins, the same magistrates, senators, and judges; and, in a 
 word, the whole of Peloponnesus differs in construction from a 
 single state only in this, that the inhabitants do not live within 
 the same walls." 
 
 It is obvious that these words were written after the war 
 with Perseus, and before the destruction of the Achrean League 
 (i.e. between 167 B.C. and 146 B.C.). The writer either did not 
 foresee, or with a natural and patriotic optimism refused to 
 recognise, the ruin that was coming on his country. 
 
 The explanation no doubt is, that the two preliminary 
 books were published before the final catastrophe had taken 
 place. It was one effect of the transmission of books by 
 manuscript copies, that it was impossible to correct what had 
 once got abroad. The Littera scripta manet was strictly 
 true. The author had none of the opportunities of the 
 " new and revised edition " of modern times. We find this 
 amusingly illustrated in the case of a Ehodian historian 
 named Zeno, who had shocked Polybius by describing a 
 Spartan expedition as passing through Sellasia on its way to 
 Thalamse and Pharse ; whereas Sellasia lay to the north-east of 
 Sparta, and the other places to the south-west. 1 Polybius 
 wrote off in hot haste to Zeno, but the book was already 
 published, and correction was impossible. " Zeno was as 
 vexed as could be, but the thing was beyond remedy : 
 however, he acknowledged my efforts in the most friendly 
 terms." 2 
 
 Only the first five books of Polybius's History are pre- 
 served to us entire. The third book carries the history of the 
 Second Punic War down to the battle of Cannre, while the 
 
 1 xvi. 16. Modern maps represent Sellasia as due north, and Thalamae and 
 Pharse as south, or a point to the south-east of Sparta. 
 
 2 xvi. 20.
 
 POLYBIUS. 407 
 
 fourth and fifth books deal with the contemporary history of 
 Greece and Asia. The remaining thirty-five books are known 
 to us by fragments. By far the longest is the account of the 
 Roman constitution and military system, from the sixth book. 
 This comprises fifty-eight chapters, probably about half the 
 original book. The lost portion doubtless described the civil 
 administration and financial system of Eome. " One may with 
 justice reproach Fortune " (to borrow a phrase of our historian) 
 for having preserved in the fourth and fifth books so much 
 that is petty and off the main lines of the history, while with- 
 holding from us the light which would have been shed on 
 some of the most difficult and interesting questions of ancient 
 politics, if the sixth book had come to us unmutilated. 1 
 
 Besides the usual sources of fragments in the quotations 
 and allusions of other ancient writers, we have in the case of 
 Polybius the help of volumes of compiled extracts which have 
 survived the destruction of the complete works from which 
 they were drawn. 
 
 A volume of Epitomes (so the MS. calls them) was known 
 as early as the year 1549. These are really not epitomes 
 in our sense of the word, but extracts tolerably copious from 
 Books 1. xvin. The earlier editors amused themselves with 
 the fancy that they had in their hands the work on which, as 
 Plutarch tells us, 2 Brutus was engaged on the eve of the battle 
 of Pharsalia. Schweighauser points out 3 that a much later 
 date is determined for these extracts by comparing those of 
 them which are taken from the first five books with the con- 
 tinuous manuscripts of these books. All our copies of the 
 extracts conform, he says; exclusively to the readings of that 
 family of manuscripts of which the Vatican is the chief, ignor- 
 ing those of the other group on which the earlier editors 
 framed the textus receptus. This seems to prove that the com- 
 pilation was effected after the divergence of the two types 
 which are respectively followed by these two classes of manu- 
 scripts. It is probably safest to attribute this collection to 
 Byzantine compilers of a comparatively recent date. 
 
 1 See Marquardt, Romische Staats- Verwaltung, vol. ii. p. 76. 
 3 Zypaijie ffwrdrruv ^irirofj.Tjv IIoXu/3(ov. Plutarch, Brutus, 4. 
 8 Preface, p. civ.
 
 POL YfilUS. 
 
 Of a second, and scarcely less important, compilation we 
 have fuller information. 1 Constantino Porphyrogenitus, a 
 Byzantine Emperor of the tenth century, ordered the forma- 
 tion of a sort of Digest of Historical writers for the use of 
 persons who found the complete works too long and wearisome 
 to study. Extracts from them were selected and arranged 
 under different headings according to their subjects. He 
 claimed to have included everything which was important 
 in the Greek historians within the limits of his fifty-three 
 volumes. Two of the fifty-three survive nearly complete, the 
 one entitled Embassies (irepl Ilpea-Peiwv), the other Virtue and 
 Vice (irepl 'Aperf)? /cal Ka/a'a?). Both draw largely from 
 Polybius; they were first printed in 1582 and 1584 respec- 
 tively, and Casaubon included the extracts from both in his 
 great edition of Polybius. In the present century fragments 
 of another volume, Maxims (irepl TVWJJLWV}, have been dis- 
 covered in the Vatican Library by Cardinal Mai, and later 
 editors have incorporated in the text many fresh extracts from 
 Polybius drawn from this source. 
 
 The extracts and fragments preserved are longer by 
 nearly a half than the five complete books, and they are also, 
 taking them as a whole, far more interesting and valuable. 
 The most striking passages were naturally selected for the 
 compilations ; and though we have to look elsewhere for the 
 continuous history, and though we feel that the silence on 
 particular points of interest is vexatious, yet in what remains 
 we have evidently the pith of the work, and can find the 
 picture of the age and its great events as the historian wished 
 to portray them. 
 
 The task which Polybius proposed to himself was to write 
 the history of the world during the period he had chosen for 
 his subject. Such a universal history was demanded, so he 
 thought, by the appearance of a universal Empire. 
 
 " Now in the times preceding this period, the events of the 
 world's history may be said to have happened in a state of 
 isolation, because each action, both in its inception and in 
 its development, was disconnected with all others by time or 
 
 1 See Schweighauser's Preface, p. cxxxix.
 
 POL YBIUS. 409 
 
 place. But from this period we find that the history has 
 become an organic whole, and the affairs of Italy and Libya 
 are bound up with those of Asia and Greece, and the general 
 current of events sets to one fixed point." l 
 
 " The distinctive feature of our work corresponds with the 
 marvellous characteristic of our times ; for as Fortune has 
 swayed almost all the affairs of the world to one centre, and 
 compelled every force to set in one and the same direction, so 
 we would by means of our History bring under a common view, 
 for the benefit of our readers, the operations which Fortune has 
 employed for the completion of a combined system of the 
 world. Indeed it was this above everything that incited and 
 urged us to attempt the writing of history, and an additional 
 incentive was the consideration that none of our contemporaries 
 have attempted to construct a universal history ; otherwise for 
 my own part I should have been much less eager to occupy 
 this ground. But now, seeing that many writers employ 
 themselves on individual wars, and on some of the actions 
 associated with them, but that the universal and connected dis- 
 position of events, when and from what causes they took their 
 rise, and how they reached their full development, are questions 
 which no one of them, so far as I know, even attempts to 
 analyse, I conceived that it was absolutely necessary not to 
 omit nor let pass without recognition this which is at once the 
 noblest and most instructive of all the operations of Fortune. 
 For while she is for ever working revolutions, and for ever busy- 
 ing herself over the lives of men, she never yet accomplished 
 such a task, nor fought through such a struggle as has been 
 exhibited in our day. But of this it is impossible to gain a clear 
 conception from those who write history in isolated segments. 
 
 " It is by gaining a view of the connection and relationship 
 of all events to each other, and of their resemblances and 
 differences, that alone we can reach the goal, and be enabled to 
 get both profit and pleasure out of history." 2 
 
 Polybius is thoroughly impressed with the majesty of his 
 subject. In this conception of a systematic whole, and in the 
 recognition that he must search for the hidden threads of reason 
 
 1 i. 3. * i. 4.
 
 410 POLYBIUS. 
 
 which bind events together, he finds an informing principle 
 for his work. He gains from it the support of a duty clearly 
 apprehended and loyally adhered to, and it supplies a certain 
 elevation and dignity which would otherwise be wanting both 
 to his thought and writing. It sets him in a sphere removed 
 above the temptations of the rhetorician and the pamphleteer, 
 and makes him the most trustworthy of historians. Polybius 
 is an enthusiast for the truth wherever he finds it. He shows 
 throughout a calm determination to probe to the bottom the 
 conditions of the time with which men had to deal : what is 
 inevitable he will accept without murmuring : he will state for 
 his contemporaries the facts, whether agreeable or not, to which 
 their conduct must be suited. Neither fear nor favour, he 
 contends, must tempt the historian to waver for a moment in 
 his allegiance to the truth. In this spirit he criticises the rival 
 histories of Fabius and Philinus for their partisan accounts of 
 the First Punic War. 
 
 " Now in most affairs of life, perhaps, a man would do ill 
 to divest himself of such a fellow-feeling. For a good man 
 should be attached to his friend and to his country, and out of 
 sympathy for these should hate their enemies and love their 
 friends. But when a man assumes the attitude of mind that is 
 proper to history, he is bound to leave out of sight all such 
 considerations, and he must often speak well of his enemies and 
 adorn them with the highest praises when the facts demand 
 this ; and again he must often blame his nearest friends, and 
 bring their faults home to them whenever their conduct 
 requires it. For just as, if the eyes of a living animal are put 
 out, the whole creature becomes maimed and helpless, so, if you 
 take away the truth out of history, what is left is merely an 
 unprofitable tale." 1 
 
 Polybius's own practice shows that this homage to the 
 truth is not merely a lip-service. We have seen how all his 
 political hopes and aspirations were bound up with the Achaean 
 League. Of all men of his age, Aratus, the founder of Achaean 
 greatness, might seem to claim from him indulgent treatment, 
 while Cleomenes, whose whole life was a struggle against the 
 
 1 i. 14.
 
 POLYBIUS. 
 
 Achneans, and who had dealt a deadly blow at Megalopolis, 
 Polybius's native town, might seem a natural mark for enmity 
 and detraction. Yet he is careful to point out the great defects 
 of Aratus, his want of skill and energy in the field of battle, 
 and the numerous disasters which his incapacity inflicted on 
 his countrymen. " All Peloponnesus was full," he says, " of 
 the trophies which had been erected for victories over Aratus." 
 On the other hand, when he comes to describe the death of 
 Cleomenes, though it does not fall within his province to give 
 the picturesque details which we learn from Plutarch, he fully 
 recognises the dignity and heroism of his end. When all their 
 efforts had failed, he and his companions " killed themselves 
 bravely and as became Spartans : and this was the end of 
 Cleomenes, a man of winning manners towards his fellow r s, and 
 of ability in the affairs of State, and, in a word, framed by 
 nature to be a leader and a king." 1 
 
 To pass to the next generation: his character of the last 
 Philip of Macedon leaves nothing to be desired in discrimina- 
 tion and soundness of moral judgment. He does equal justice 
 to the courage, prudence, and self-restraint of his youth; to 
 the reckless vice and tyranny of his middle life ; and to the 
 splendid resolution with which the old man, braced and sobered 
 by misfortune, bent himself to the tremendous task of retriev- 
 ing his shattered fortune, and reviving his country after the 
 shock of its first great calamity. 
 
 Or again, let us consider Polybius's picture of Rome. Rome 
 is the triumphant hero of his story. The object of his book is 
 to show that the success of the Romans was not an accident, 
 but the natural result of their character and their institutions. 
 He accepts the supremacy of Rome as the voice of fate, and 
 urges submission on the world. Yet he is never tempted by 
 the desire for a false consistency to slur over the unjust, cruel, 
 or mean actions of the Romans. Their conduct to Demetrius 
 and to the kingdom of Syria is only a specimen of many dis- 
 creditable deeds recorded by their historian : he tells of each 
 occurrence in its place calmly and judicially, without fear or 
 favour. 
 
 1 v. 39.
 
 412 POLYBIUS. 
 
 With this absorbing passion for truth, Polybius has the 
 " defects of his qualities " in a certain unfortunate contempt 
 for the artistic presentation of the truth. The following is his 
 criticism on his Rhodian friend : 
 
 " What shall we say, then, is the defect of Zeno ? That he 
 is anxious, not so much about inquiring into his facts and 
 dealing with his subject, as about perfecting his style ; and it 
 is clear from many passages that this is what he prides himself 
 on, as is the case with many other distinguished historians. 
 Now I hold that a man should by all means take pains and 
 exert himself about the fitting presentation of what he has to 
 say, for it is manifest that this contributes greatly to the effect 
 of the narrative; but men of sound sense should not set up 
 this as their first and leading object. Far from it ; there are 
 other nobler elements of history on which a statesmanlike 
 historian would rather pride himself." l 
 
 The doctrine, as it stands, is of course indisputable; but 
 Polybius in practice allowed his scrupulous performance of the 
 first duty of a historian to serve him as an excuse for wholly 
 neglecting the second. His style must, indeed, be acquitted of 
 the very worst faults, those which spring from conceited 
 pedantry and laborious folly. It is not vicious, nor forced, nor 
 inflated, nor false. You listen to a man of sense telling his 
 story in a way that is natural to him. Thus, whenever the 
 events he is describing are in themselves sufficiently exciting 
 to fix the attention of the reader by their intrinsic interest, he 
 does not throw away the advantage, nor spoil the narrative by 
 tinsel ornament. Some of the battle-scenes, for instance, in 
 which Polybius's own bent towards military pursuits furnished 
 a stimulus to his mind, are really well described. Perhaps the 
 passages where one feels least the defects of the writer are the 
 description of the revolt of the Carthaginian mercenaries in 
 the first book, and that of the capture and death of Achseus in 
 a fragment of the eighth. 
 
 Carthage had collected into her mercenary army a throng 
 of Libyans, Celts, bastard Greeks, runaway slaves, and deserters 
 from all parts of the world. These burst into mutiny after 
 
 1 xvi. 17.
 
 POLYBIUS. 413 
 
 their return to Africa at the end of the First Punic War (2-41 
 B.C.). The long-suppressed hatred of the African population 
 towards their Carthaginian tyrants assisted them in their 
 revolt, and stimulated them to wild orgies of cruelty and 
 destructiveness. They had no common language, and the only 
 word they all understood was the Greek /3a\Xe, "pelt him." 
 The leaders of the mutineers had only to raise this cry against 
 any one who opposed them, and it was taken up from mouth 
 to mouth, and the designated victim was stoned to death as a 
 supposed spy or traitor. A reign of terror ensued, founded on 
 mutual suspicion ; no one was trusted unless he had given 
 security for his fidelity by unpardonable crimes. The whole 
 nature of these men became brutalised and poisoned with 
 malignant passions ; they tortured or mutilated every prisoner : 
 Gesco, their favourite general, was seized when he came at their 
 own request to treat with them in the camp, and put to death 
 with horrible torments. Driven to bay, they resorted to canni- 
 balism in their despair, and were at length either exterminated 
 on the field, or else crucified or trodden under the feet of 
 elephants by their conquerors. 1 It has been said by one who 
 first read this description at the time when news was being 
 brought by every mail of the events of the Indian Mutiny, that 
 it was the story told by Polybius which best enabled him to 
 enter into the spirit of what was passing in the East, and which 
 brought most vividly before his mind the horrors of the armed 
 rebellion of a savage race. 
 
 Not less striking is the story of the unfortunate pretender 
 Achseus, besieged in the fortress of Sardis by King Antiochus. 2 
 He was enticed out by night by a traitorous Cretan named 
 Bolis, who, having received a great sum of money to effect his 
 escape, sold him to Antiochus. Acheeus, who had doubts of 
 the fidelity of his guide, had disguised himself, and instructed 
 the leader of his party to tell the Cretan that Achseus had 
 remained behind, and would content himself with sending three 
 or four friends as messengers to his partisans outside. Bolis, 
 now utterly puzzled, accompanied them through the darkness ; 
 but he soon noticed that there was one of the party to whom 
 
 i. 66-88. 2 viii. 17-23.
 
 4H POLYBIUS. 
 
 the others seemed to show deference, taking care of him and 
 helping him over rough and dangerous places. This, he rightly 
 concluded, must be the prince ; he suddenly flung his arms 
 round him, the attendants were cut down by armed men who 
 w r ere lying in wait, and the Cretan, marching in the dead of 
 night into the tent where Antiochus sat anxiously awaiting 
 the issue of the plot, flung down the rebel, bound hand and 
 foot, before the king. 
 
 In such passages as these, we feel that it is the thrilling 
 character of the events described which gives pow r er and 
 interest to the description. Where Polybius lacks the stimulus 
 of such a topic, and has to depend on his own skill for the 
 artistic presentation of his subject, he fails from sheer care- 
 lessness and slovenliness. His sentences trail along without 
 beginning, middle, or end. His remarks fall out pell-mell, 
 without any regard to their suiting the tone or spirit of the 
 context. As long as he can say what he wants to say, the 
 manner has to take care of itself. He writes, indeed, not so 
 much in a bad style, as with no style at all. The result is 
 that, although hardly any writer has said more interesting 
 things than Polybius, he is tedious and uninteresting as a 
 whole. It is characteristic of the man that the fragments 
 should be the most valuable part of his work. The extant 
 portions of his writings occupy altogether nearly 1200 octavo 
 pages of Bekker's edition. We may almost apply to him what 
 Macaulay says of Spenser that if the whole forty books, 
 printed on some 4000 octavo pages, had remained to us, " we 
 doubt if any heart less stout than that of a commentator would 
 have held out to the end." 
 
 The Nemesis of his contempt for the form and style of his 
 writing has come on Polybius in the neglect which he has 
 experienced at the hands of the modern world. He can hardly 
 have a place in the regular educational curriculum, for there 
 could not be a worse book from which to teach boys Greek. 
 His language lacks all the subtlety and depth of classical 
 Greek, and has the indescribable flavour of a modern language, 
 such as we find about the Dog-Latin of the Middle Ages. It 
 is a cosmopolitan language, without character and without 
 idiom, fitted only to serve as a medium of communication for
 
 POLYBIUS. 415 
 
 the dead and colourless civilisation which remained to the 
 Hellenised East under the crushing power of Rome. 
 
 In arrangement and choice of materials, we find in Polybius 
 the same want of artistic sense. His proper subject is so vast, 
 and embraces such a multiplicity of details, that, with all his 
 anxious care for truth, he despairs of attaining absolute 
 accuracy ; l but, not content with this, he can never resist the 
 temptation of talking and arguing about other matters. He 
 cannot let his History speak for itself, but is always trying to 
 justify his method, or his style, or his arrangement ; if he 
 introduces a new subject, he wastes time over an apology, and 
 an attempt to show that the discussion is to the point ; if he 
 decides to omit something, still he cannot be silent about it, 
 but must explain, generally at very unnecessary length, why it 
 is not convenient to enter on this or that subject at present. 
 He will not say a thing once and have done with it, but keeps 
 harping on the same topics. It was useful and proper that he 
 should point out the difference between his subject-matter and 
 that of the writers of " special histories ;" but, from mere want 
 of literary skill and critical sense, he insists on the theme till 
 the reader is weary of it. 
 
 It is interesting to notice in this connection the different 
 effects of the conditions of composition among the ancients on 
 the form of their writings. The footnote, the reference, the 
 appendix, the magazine criticism, are all modern inventions, 
 and by their means the modern writer may purge his text. 
 Whatever the ancient historian wished to say, he must intro- 
 duce into the body of his work. Polybius sets no limits to this 
 licence of forcing in extraneous matter. Side by side with the 
 record of great events we find in him elaborate criticisms of 
 rival historians the fragments of that on Timasus alone occupy 
 forty octavo pages apologies, answers to objections, and even 
 a sort of publisher's advertisement, which explains that the 
 public are not to be alarmed at the size and price of his w T ork, 
 for that his forty books are really cheaper to buy and easier to 
 read, in comparison of the ground they cover, than the works 
 of the " special historians." 2 By such indiscriminate loquacity 
 
 1 xxix. 6 a. a iii. 32.
 
 416 POLYBIUS. 
 
 the dignity and beauty of the History is seriously impaired ; 
 and the fault appears the greater, if we contrast the effect of 
 the same conditions of writing upon the great masters of his- 
 torical style. The responsibility of choice seems to strengthen 
 and brace them; their taste and judgment are polished till they 
 attain an almost unerring instinct of w T hen to speak and when 
 to keep silence. Polybius claims a place in the highest rank 
 of ancient historians, and such a claim challenges a comparison 
 with the greatest names with the severe and stately thought 
 and diction of Thucydides ; with Tacitus, who carries the art 
 of writing to its highest pitch, in whom no expression, no turn 
 of a sentence, no hint, no digression, fails to heighten the effect 
 of the whole ; with Herodotus, who, whether by the simplicity 
 of genius, or by art so consummate that the observer cannot 
 distinguish it from nature, delights generation after generation 
 of readers with a tale that leaves nothing to be desired in finish 
 and beauty. Would it be well for ordinary classical students 
 to give up any one of these to spend the time over Polybius ? It 
 must be confessed that Polybius as a writer cannot stand for a 
 moment in the light of such a comparison. If " the style is 
 the man," Polybius has no place in the first rank. He has not 
 the genius, and will not take the trouble to acquire the trained 
 sensitiveness of art which might have supplied its place ; and 
 thus his writing has no distinction and no charm, and we miss 
 in reading him what gives half their value to great writers 
 the consciousness that we are in the hands of a master. 
 
 It is more difficult to come to a correct judgment as to the 
 moral side of Polybius's writings. Mommsen, in his generally 
 judicious criticism, lays down that " his treatment of all ques- 
 tions in which right, honour, religion are involved, is not only 
 shallow but radically false." 1 This seems a harsh and unfair 
 sentence. To judge Polybius rightly, we must take account of 
 the experiences which formed his character. The life which 
 he had led, and the events which he had witnessed, were not 
 calculated to develop in a man the highest moral capabilities 
 self-sacrifice, devotion to a great cause, faith in an ideal, 
 sympathy with great currents of human feeling. High hopes 
 
 1 Hist, of Rome, vol. iii. p. 467 (English translation).
 
 POLYBIUS. 41 
 
 and sentiments, however delusive, are a necessary element in 
 the lives of the deepest human interest, and such hopes and 
 sentiments the triumph of Borne had crushed out except in the 
 narrow circle of her own republican liberty. The spectacle of 
 a heroic life like that of Hannibal, struggling against this 
 terrible nation, is a tragedy for all time. But for those who 
 saw the drama played out, the obvious moral was that such a 
 life was an anachronism and a failure. Polybius has a hearty 
 admiration for Hannibal ; but he must have felt that his fate 
 and the fate of his country decided once for all the question 
 whether the struggle was worth continuing 
 
 ' ' si Pergama dextra 
 Defend! possent, etiam hac defensa fuissent." 
 
 Polybius could not but be a " disillusionised man;" religion 
 was dead to all reasonable men in his day, and patriotism, as it 
 had been hitherto understood in the world, hopelessly wrecked. 
 We have no right to blame Polybius for being a sceptic, and it 
 should be put to his credit that he was not a cynic, that he 
 kept his moral judgment of men and things clear, that he still 
 believed in justice and right, and had the courage to speak his 
 mind in praise or censure with a single eye to truth. What 
 was an honest Greek to do in such a time ? Mommsen sneers 
 alike at Philopcemen, who hoped against hope for liberty and 
 independence, and at Polybius, who, when this last chance was 
 obviously and completely lost, resolved to accept what was in- 
 evitable, and to accommodate both his conduct and his counsels 
 to that which history had decreed. It seems more rational to 
 esteem both of them as men who with true wisdom and 
 sincerity of purpose strove to do their best for their country 
 and for the world under most difficult or even desperate circum- 
 stances. One article of faith remained to Polybius, and to 
 this he clung with unswerving loyalty. 
 
 " I believe," he says, 1 " that nature has given to man Truth 
 as the greatest deity, and has endued her with strength above 
 everything. Sometimes when every one unites to beat her 
 down, and when every plausibility is ranged on the side of 
 falsehood, yet one way or other, by virtue of her own nature, 
 
 1 xiii. 5. 
 2 D
 
 4i 8 POLYBIUS. 
 
 she penetrates into the souls of men, sometimes revealing her 
 might at once, sometimes after long eclipse, winning her way 
 at last and fighting down falsehood." 
 
 He saw that it was his duty to look every fact in the face, 
 to clear away every illusion, to conceal nothing and extenuate 
 nothing; and he believed that the truth thus studied cannot 
 but have its practical lessons, and that reality once fairly 
 grasped and accepted must contain the germs of a policy which 
 can secure a tolerable, if not a desirable, solution of the pro- 
 blems of the time. 
 
 Polybius's attitude towards religion deserves a more special 
 notice. We see in it the strong effort of the man towards fair- 
 ness and candour. Obviously an unbeliever himself, he is 
 eager to recognise the good moral effect of the continuance of ' 
 religious belief among the Romans. 
 
 " The most salutary feature of the Eoman constitution is the 
 belief it inculcates ill the gods. And I think that the Eoman 
 state is held together by a quality which is a reproach among 
 other men I mean by superstition. For this motive is 
 heightened in effect and enters into the life of the people and 
 into public affairs to an almost incredible extent. This may 
 seem astonishing to some, but I think that the Romans have 
 acted thus out of regard to the multitude. For if it were 
 possible to collect a nation of wise men, such a practice would 
 perhaps be unnecessary. But since every multitude is fickle 
 and full of lawless desires, of unreasonable anger, and of violent 
 passions, it only remains to curb them with invisible terrors 
 and such -like machinery. For this reason I think that the 
 notions about the gods, and the belief in a future world, were 
 not introduced by our fathers carelessly or at random, but 
 that the recklessness and folly is rather on the side of this 
 generation who reject them. And so amongst public officers in 
 Greece, if a single talent be intrusted to their care, they have 
 ten indorsers and as many seals and two witnesses to each 
 signature, and with all this they cheat ; while the Romans, as 
 commissioners, pass great sums of money through their hands 
 and never transgress, by virtue of the mere sanctity of their 
 oath." 1 
 
 
 1 vi. 56.
 
 POLYBIUS. 
 
 To maintain this wholesome spirit he is willing to make 
 some allowance for the introduction of myths and legends into 
 
 / o 
 
 history, though it is a liberty which he will grant to others but 
 not use himself. Only the stories must be such as tend to keep 
 up the reverence of the people for the gods, and must confine 
 themselves within the limits of the possible, if not of the pro- 
 bable. This requisition leads him to reject peremptorily a 
 fragment of primitive folk-lore, which lingered in his native 
 Arcadia. We know from Plato 1 that the belief in were-wolves 
 was localised in the temple of the Arcadian Zeus, and here we 
 tind another superstition which we are accustomed to think of 
 as purely medieval, that of the "man without a shadow," 
 attaching to the same spot. 
 
 " To say that some bodies when placed in the light cast no 
 shadow, marks a mind beyond the influence of sense; and 
 this is what Theopompus does when he says that those who 
 enter into the forbidden precinct of Zeus in Arcadia lose their 
 shadows." 2 
 
 Polybius, however tolerant of religion in its proper place, 
 is indignant when the credit which statesmen and generals 
 deserve for wisdom or courage is taken from them by ascrib- 
 ing their success to providence or inspiration. The elder 
 Scipio claimed to be a special object of the favour of the gods, 
 and allowed his most successful enterprises to be attributed to 
 divine admonition. It is amusing to see Polybius's anxiety to 
 clear his hero from the suspicion of having sincerely believed 
 any such nonsense. Scipio did not rely on dreams or 
 mysterious voices for the measures by which he founded the 
 greatness of his country; but he, like Lycurgus, perceived 
 " that the masses will not accept any policy which is strange 
 to them, nor meet danger with courage unless they hope for 
 some assistance from heaven," and therefore " he inculcated the 
 belief that his plans were suggested by inspiration, and thus 
 put his men in good heart against danger. But that each of 
 his actions was really done by calculation and foresight, and 
 that his success was the legitimate issue of his plans, will be 
 clear from the subsequent narrative." 3 The best example 
 
 1 Rep. viii. 16. Also frequently in Polybius. - xvi. 12. 3 x. 2.
 
 420 POLYBIUS. 
 
 perhaps is the siege of Carthagena. Scipio, after a careful 
 study of the habits of the tidal water in the harbour, timed his 
 assault to coincide with an unusually low tide, and informed 
 his troops that Neptune had promised him notable assistance 
 at the crisis of the battle. 1 When the soldiers saw the water 
 fall so as to permit of a party fording the harbour and attack- 
 ing the fortress in flank, their enthusiasm at the divine inter- 
 position made their onset irresistible. 
 
 In another passage 2 Polybius attempts to establish a 
 modus vivendi between religion and reason, by dividing the 
 field of human life between them. 
 
 " Whenever it is difficult or impossible for human power to 
 apprehend causes, we may fairly in our uncertainty refer such 
 things to God or to Fortune ; as, for instance, a continuance of 
 storms and violent rainfall, or of droughts and frosts, and the 
 loss of crops resulting from these, and in the same way, un- 
 healthy states of atmosphere, and other things of the same kind, 
 whose causes are not easy to discover. Therefore, in our un- 
 certainty about such cases, we naturally conform to the 
 opinions of the multitude, and propitiate heaven by supplica- 
 tions and offerings, and send to inquire of the gods what we 
 are to do or say to obtain a blessing and a relief from the ills 
 that beset us. But where it is possible to discover the origin- 
 ating and efficient cause of what has occurred, in such cases I 
 think it wrong to refer it to the will of heaven. To take 
 an instance : In our time all Greece has been smitten with 
 childlessness and deficient population, by which the cities are 
 desolated, and sterility reigns, although no long wars nor un- 
 healthy seasons have occurred. Supposing, then, that any one 
 should advise us to send and inquire of the gods what we are 
 to say and do to become more numerous and replenish our 
 cities, would not this be manifestly silly, when the cause is 
 evident and the correction lies in our own hands ? For men 
 have fallen into habits of ostentation and greed and indolence, 
 and they will neither marry nor bring up the children who are 
 born to them out of wedlock, or else they rear one or two at 
 the most, in order to leave these rich and luxurious, and the 
 
 1 x. 11. 2 xxxvii. 4.
 
 POLYS I US, 421 
 
 mischief, though not much noticed, has grown rapidly. For it' 
 this only child, or one of the two, is carried off by war or 
 disease, it is manifest that houses must needs be left desolate, 
 and before long the cities too become weak from lack of men, 
 like a hive without bees. 1 And in all this there is not the 
 least occasion to ask the gods how we may be released from 
 such a calamity ; for any man of ordinary intelligence will tell 
 us that we can apply the remedy ourselves by reforming the 
 objects of our ambition, or if this be impossible, then by 
 making laws to provide for the rearing of all children born." 
 
 The reader can hardly fail to notice a peculiar modern tone 
 in Polybius's manner of dealing with such questions ; and this 
 modern tone is the prevalent one throughout his work. The 
 great difficulty in understanding classical writers is that they 
 seem, almost all of them, to move and work in a different plane 
 of thought from ourselves. It is probably this newness and 
 freshness of the world they open, out to us that constitutes the 
 chief value of the classics in education. But it is not to be 
 wondered at if, until the mind is thoroughly imbued with 
 classical culture, a sense of bewilderment and impatience is 
 produced. The schoolboy generally believes in his heart that 
 there is no nonsense so enormous that it may not be a probable 
 translation of a passage of Greek. Sometimes this strangeness 
 in the tone of thought of ancient books to that of the every-day 
 world leads men to desire to reject the first altogether, and to 
 prefer the political wisdom of the Times to that of Thucy- 
 dides. If there are any who seriously feel this often-quoted 
 preference, they should be sent to make their peace with the 
 ancients by reading Polybius. No effort is required to get at 
 his point of view. Whatever question he starts, his attitude 
 of mind towards it is such as to appeal to the sympathy, if not 
 to the conviction, of the average modern reader. His remarks 
 are always full of an obvious good sense, always enlightened, 
 candid, and judicious, and, it must be added, rather common- 
 place. 
 
 Polybius is never so happy as when he is correcting a 
 
 1 KaOd-irep iirl TU>V peXiTT&v T& ff^vrj. The sentence is obviously imperfect, 
 and the text is faulty throughout the fragment.
 
 422 POLYB1US. 
 
 popular error, or explaining and analysing what may appear at 
 first sight a paradox. A few characteristic specimens may 
 serve to complete the picture of our author. The first is a 
 curious instance of accurate observation conveyed in a some- 
 what pedagogic tone : 
 
 "Most men suppose that cities which contain hills and 
 sloping-ground will hold more houses than those of the same 
 circumference built on a plain. But this -is entirely wrong, 
 because the houses must be built perpendicular, not to the 
 slopes, but to the level below, on which the hills themselves 
 are planted. One may prove this from w r hat is manifest to any 
 child, as the saying is. For if we conceive the houses on the 
 slopes built up until they are all the same height, it is clear 
 that the roofs of the houses will form a single plane, and that 
 this plane will of necessity be parallel and equal to the plane 
 on which the foundations of the walls and the hills themselves 
 rest." 1 
 
 Mention has been already made of Polybius's discriminat- 
 ing account of Aratus. He lays down clearly the merits and 
 defects of the man, an excellent organiser, and unsurpassed 
 in careful preparation and wise laying of plans, but destitute 
 of energy, courage, and resource, at the moment of action. The 
 spectacle of these discordant qualities in the same person leads 
 Polybius to generalise on the different grooves in which courage 
 and capacity run with different men. 
 
 " This is no paradox, but a familiar phenomenon, accepted 
 by judicious observers. Sometimes you have men courageous 
 in hunting, who will face wild beasts with boldness, and yet 
 these same men will be cowards when set in arms against the 
 enemy ; or again, some who are skilful and successful in single 
 combat, but useless when drawn up in line of battle. Then 
 there is the Thessalian cavalry, whose shock is irresistible when 
 they charge by troop or squadron, but they are slow and of no 
 avail for risking themselves in hand-to-hand conflict as place 
 and occasion serve, while just the contrary is true of the 
 ^Etolians. The Cretans, both by land and. sea, are invincible 
 
 1 ix. 21. Modern land-surveyors apply Polybius's principle to vegetable 
 growths as well as to buildings, and estimate the acreage of hilly ground for 
 agricultural purposes in accordance with it.
 
 POL YB I US. 423 
 
 in ambushes and marauding expeditions, and in kidnapping 
 enemies, and in night attacks, and in all such individual ser- 
 vices where cunning is required ; but when the phalanx charges 
 face to face on fair ground they turn cowardly and unsteady. 
 The Acha-ans and Macedonians exhibit just the opposite 
 temper." 1 
 
 Another interesting passage in the same tone is where he 
 defends the Greeks from the charge of fickleness and ingrati- 
 tude in giving some sympathy to Perseus in his struggle against 
 Rome. 
 
 " I think that the disposition of their minds is to be 
 accounted for in this way. The phenomenon is the same as 
 that which one often sees in athletic contests. For when a 
 distinguished and seemingly invincible champion is opposed 
 by an obscure and inferior antagonist, the multitude at once 
 gives its good-will to the weaker man, and cheers him on and 
 sympathises with his efforts ; and if he touch his adversary's 
 face and leave some mark of the blow, the spectators feel as if 
 they had a share in the struggle, and sometimes they begin to 
 clamour against his opponent not that they dislike him or 
 wish for his disgrace, but because they are carried away by 
 sympathy, and so favour the weaker side. But if any one 
 administers a timely rebuke, they soon repent and check their 
 indiscretion." 
 
 After illustrating this by the case of a notable athlete, 
 Clitomachus, who had thus recalled the sympathies of the 
 spectators to an old and tried favourite, he proceeds : 
 
 " The popular feeling towards Perseus is a parallel case. 
 For if any one had withstood them, and asked them frankly if 
 they desired to see such a supremacy fall into the hands of a 
 single man, and to feel the weight of a monarchical power 
 absolutely irresponsible, I conceive that they would soon have 
 recanted and gone over to the other side ; and still more if the 
 speaker had briefly reminded them of all the injuries which the 
 Greeks had experienced at the hands of the house of Macedon, 
 and of all the benefits which they had received from the 
 supremacy of Rome, I think that the revolution in their senti- 
 
 iv. 8.
 
 POLYBIUS. 
 
 merits would have been complete and immediate. But under 
 the irresistible influence of the first wave of opinion, the multi- 
 tude betrayed its satisfaction at the news, being flattered by 
 the unexpected appearance of a champion able to stand face to 
 face with Borne. And so I close this discussion, the object of 
 which has been to show that it is only a thoughtless judgment, 
 and one ignorant of human nature, which will cast the reproach 
 of ingratitude on the temper which the Greeks showed on this 
 occasion." 1 
 
 In the selection of these and the other pieces quoted in 
 this paper the object has been to give passages illustrative of 
 Polybius as a man and a writer, rather than those which are 
 of intrinsic historical importance. The latter class of extracts 
 would find their place in a picture of the Greek and Eoman 
 world in Polybius's time, which is a task too long to be 
 attempted within the limits of this essay. For the present it 
 must suffice to have placed before the reader materials for a 
 judgment on the merits and the limitations of the Historian of 
 the Eoman Conquest. 
 
 It will be difficult, perhaps, to arrive at a more judicious 
 verdict than that in which Mommsen sums up his criticism : 
 
 " Polybius is not an attractive author ; but as truth and 
 truthfulness are of more value than all ornament and elegance, 
 no other author of antiquity, perhaps, can be named to whom 
 we are indebted for so much real instruction. His books are 
 like the sun in Koman history ; at the point where they begin, 
 the mist which still envelopes the Samnite and Pyrrhic wars 
 is raised; and at the point where they end, a new and, if 
 possible, still more vexatious twilight begins." 2 
 
 J. L. S. D. 
 
 1 xxvii. 7 a. 2 Hist, of Home, vol. iii. p. 468 (English translation).
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 PREFATORY NOTE. 
 
 AMONG the sources to which I have been indebted in the composition of 
 the following Essay, my first acknowledgments are due to the works of 
 Mr. Tylor, Sir John Lubbock, and other ethnologists, whose labours in the 
 comparative study of primitive beliefs and customs are perhaps even more 
 important for the history of religion than were the great philological genera- 
 lisations which immediately preceded them. On Greek religion, and Greek 
 oracles in particular, I have consulted, among others, the following authors : 
 -Becker and Marquardt, Botticher, Bouche-Leclercq, 1 Bowen, Cox, Creuzer 
 and Guigniaut, Curtius, Decharme, Fontenelle, Gb'tte, Hendess, Hermann, 
 Hoffmann, Hiilbnann, Klausen, Lloyd, Lobeck, Maury, August Mommsen, 
 Nagelsbach, Preller, Rodiger, St. Hilaire, Tzschirner, Vacherot, Van Dale, 
 Wachsmuth, Welcker, F. A. Wolf, G. Wolff, Zander ; and the important 
 monographs of Carapanos on Dodona, Foucart on Delphi, and Lebegue and 
 Homolle on Delos. I owe special obligations to Maury's Religions de la Grece, 
 which contains an excellent collection of references to ancient authors, and 
 to G. Wolff's two tracts Porphyrii de Philosophia ex Oraculis haurienda 
 Reliquiae, and De Novissima Oraculorum Aetate, from which many of my 
 later references are derived. In a subject which has been so often discussed 
 it is no longer possible to lay claim to originality of citation, though much 
 significance remains to be educed from the texts already known. And in 
 fact, as will be seen by persons familiar with the literature of the subject, 
 my treatment of the history of Greek oracles in some places differs widely 
 from that adopted by my predecessors. While suggesting my own views 
 with much diffidence, and venturing on very few definite conclusions, I 
 cannot but feel that the difficulties of this manifold subject have hardly 
 received adequate attention from scholars, and are as yet to a great extent 
 unsolved. It would be tedious to specify the ancient writers consulted. 
 Herodotus and Eusebius are the most important, but there is scarcely a 
 Greek author, from Homer to Zosimus, from whom some illustration may not 
 be drawn, and the range of such illustrations has been limited in the following 
 Essay by the defect, not of applicable material, but of erudition, of space, 
 and of tune. 
 
 1 Only the first volume of M. Bouche-Leelercq's Histoire de la Divination dans I'AntiquiU 
 has as yet appeared (July 1879). The third volume is to treat of Delphi and other Greek 
 oracles, and is likely to form one of the most important works on the subject. Unfortunately, 
 however, the lessons and methods of comparative ethnology are expressly excluded from 
 M. Bouche-Leclercq's plan (Preface, p. 2).
 
 Ou /JL^V 7TWS VVV i!ff7lV CLTTb SpV&S Oi}5' ttTTO 
 
 TO; dapL^e/jievai, a re TrapOevos rjWeos re, 
 Trapdfvos TjWe&s T' oapi^erov a.\\rj\ouv. 
 
 I. 
 
 IT is not only in the domain of physical inquiry that the 
 advance of knowledge is self-accelerated at every step, and the 
 very excellence of any. given work insures its own speedier 
 supersession. All those studies which bear upon the past of 
 mankind are every year more fully satisfying this test of the 
 genuinely scientific character of the plan on which they are 
 pursued. The old conception of the world's history as a collec- 
 tion of stories, each admitting of a complete and definitive recital, 
 is giving way to a conception which would compare it rather 
 with a series of imperfectly-read inscriptions, the sense of each 
 of which is modified by the interpretations which we gradually 
 find for its predecessors. 
 
 And of no department is this truer than of the comparative 
 history of religion. The very idea of such a study is of recent 
 growth, and no sooner is the attempt made to colligate by 
 general laws the enormous mass of the religious phenomena of 
 the world than we find that the growing science is in danger 
 of being choked by its own luxuriance that each conflicting 
 hypothesis in turn seems to draw superabundant proof from the 
 myriad beliefs and practices of men. We may, indeed, smile 
 at the extravagances of one-sided upholders of each successive 
 system. We need not believe with Bishop Huet 1 that Moses 
 was the archetype both of Adonis and of Priapus. Nor, on the 
 other hand, need we suppose with Pierson 2 that Abraham 
 
 1 Demonatr. Evang. iii. 3, viii. 5. 2 Ap. Kuenen, Religion of Israel, i. 390.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 427 
 
 
 himself was originally a stone god. We may leave Dozy 1 to 
 pi;rsue his own conjecture, and deduce the strange story of the 
 Hebrew race from their worship of the planet Saturn. Nor 
 need the authority of Anonymus dc Rebus Incrcdibilibus 2 con- 
 strain us to accept his view that Paris was a young man who 
 wrote essays on goddesses, and Phaethon an unsuccessful 
 astronomer. 
 
 But it is far from easy to determine the relative validity of 
 the theories of which these are exaggerated expressions, to 
 decide (for instance) what place is to be given to the direct 
 transference of beliefs from nation to nation, to fetish- worship, 
 to the worship of the heavenly bodies, to the deification of dead 
 men. In an essay like the present, dealing only with a frag- 
 ment of this great inquiry, it will be safest to take the most 
 general view, and to say that man's fear and wonder invest 
 every object, real or imaginary, which strongly impresses him, 
 beasts or stones, or souls and spirits, or fire and the sun in 
 heaven, with an intelligence and a power darkly resembling 
 his own ; and, moreover, that certain phenomena, real or sup- 
 posed, dreams and epilepsy, eclipse and thunder, sorceries and 
 the uprising of the dead, recur from time to time to supply 
 him with apparent proof of the validity of his beliefs, and to 
 modify those beliefs according to the nature of his country and 
 his daily life. Equally natural is it that, as his social instincts 
 develop and his power of generalisation begins, he will form 
 such conceptions as those of a moral government of the world, 
 of a retributory hereafter, of a single Power from which all 
 others emanate, or into which they disappear. 
 
 Avoiding, therefore, any attempt to take a side among con- 
 flicting theories, I will draw from the considerations which 
 follow no further moral than one which is wellnigh a truism, 
 though too often forgotten in the heat of debate, namely, that 
 we are assuredly not as yet in a position to pass a final judg- 
 ment on the forms which religion has assumed in the past ; we 
 have traversed too small a part of the curve of human progress 
 to determine its true character; even yet, in fact, "we are 
 ancients of the earth, and in the morning of the times." The 
 
 1 Ap. Kuenen, i. 262. * Opuscula Mytfiologica (Amst. 1688).
 
 428 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 difficulty of bearing this clearly in mind, great in every age, 
 becomes greater as each age advances more rapidly in know- 
 ledge and critical power. In this respect the eighteenth cen-- 
 tury teaches us an obvious lesson. That century witnessed a 
 marked rise in the standard of historical evidence, a marked 
 enlightenment in dealing with the falsities and superstitions of 
 the past. The consequence was that all things seemed expli- 
 cable; that whatever could not be reduced to ordinary rules 
 seemed only worthy of being brushed aside. Since that day 
 the standard of evidence in history has not declined, it has 
 become stricter still ; but at the same time the need of sym- 
 pathy and insight, if we would comprehend the past, has become 
 strongly felt, and has modified or suspended countless judg- 
 ments which the philosophers of the last century delivered 
 without misgiving. The difference between the two great 
 critics and philosophers of France, at that day and in our own, 
 shows at a glance the whole gulf between the two points of 
 view. How little could the readers of Voltaire have antici- 
 pated Eenan! How little could they have imagined that 
 their master's trenchant arguments would so soon have fallen 
 to the level of half-educated classes and half-civilised nations, 
 would have been formidable only in sixpenny editions, or 
 when translated into Hindostani for the confutation of mis- 
 sionary zeal ! 
 
 What philosophical enlightenment was in the last century, 
 science, physical or historical, is in our own. Science is the 
 power to which we make our first and undoubting appeal, and 
 we run a corresponding risk of assuming that she can already 
 solve problems wholly, which as yet she can solve only in part, 
 of adopting under her supposed guidance explanations which 
 may hereafter be seen to have the crudity and one-sidedness of 
 Voltaire's treatment of Biblical history. 
 
 The old school of theologians were apt to assume that 
 because all men or all men whom they chose to count had 
 held a certain belief, that belief must be true. Our danger lies 
 rather in being too ready to take for granted that when we 
 have explained how a belief arose we have done with it 
 altogether; that because a tenet is of savage parentage it 
 hardly needs formal disproof. In this view the wide diffusion
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 429 
 
 of a belief serves only to stamp its connection with uncivilised 
 thought, and "quod semper, quod ubiqiie, quod ab omnibus" 
 has become to many minds rather the badge of superstition 
 than the test of catholic truth. That any one but ourselves 
 should have held a creed seems to lower the average intelli- 
 gence of its adherents. 
 
 Yet, on behalf of savages, and our ancestors in general, there 
 may be room for some apology. If we reflect how large a part 
 of human knowledge consists of human emotion, we may even 
 say that they possessed some forms of knowledge which we 
 have since lost. The mind of man (it has been well said), like 
 the earth on which he w r alks, undergoes perpetual processes of 
 denudation as well as of deposit. We ourselves, as children, 
 did in a sense know much which we know no more ; our 
 picture of the universe, incomplete and erroneous as it was, 
 wore some true colours which we cannot now recall. The 
 child's vivid sensibility, reflected in his vivifying imagination, 
 is as veritably an inlet of truth as if it were an added clearness 
 of physical vision ; and though the child himself has not judg- 
 ment enough to use his sensibilities aright, yet if the man is to 
 discern the poetic truth about Nature, he will need to recall to 
 memory his impressions as a child. 
 
 Now, in this way too, the savage is a kind of child ; his 
 beliefs are not always to be summarily referred to his ignorance ; 
 there may be something in them which we must realise in imagi- 
 nation before we venture to explain it away. Ethnologists have 
 recognised the need of this difficult self-identification with the 
 remote past, and have sometimes remarked, with a kind of 
 envy, how much nearer the poet is than the philosopher to the 
 savage habit of mind. 
 
 There is, however, one ancient people in whose case much 
 of this difficulty disappears, whose religion may be traced 
 backwards through many phases into primitive forms, while 
 yet it is easy to study its records with a fellow-feeling which 
 grows with our knowledge till it may approach almost to an 
 identity of spirit. Such is the ascendency which the great 
 works of the Greek imagination have established over the 
 mind of man, that it is no paradox to say that the student's 
 danger lies often in excess rather than in defect of sympathy.
 
 430 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 He is tempted to ignore the real superiority of our own 
 religion, morality, civilisation, and to re-shape in fancy an 
 adult world on an adolescent ideal. But the remedy for over- 
 estimates, as well as for under-estimates, lies in an increased 
 definiteness of knowledge, an ever-clearer perception of the 
 exact place in the chain of development which Greek thought 
 and worship hold. The whole story of Greek mythology must 
 ere long be retold in a form as deeply modified by comparative 
 ethnology as our existing treatises have been modified by com- 
 parative philology. Such a task would be beyond my powers ; 
 but while awaiting some more comprehensive treatment of the 
 subject by a better-qualified hand, I have in this Essay 
 endeavoured to trace, by suggestion rather than in detail, but 
 with constant reference to the results of recent science, the 
 development and career in Greece of one remarkable class of 
 religious phenomena which admits to some extent of separate 
 treatment. 
 
 Greek oracles reflect for a thousand years 1 the spiritual 
 needs of a great people. They draw their origin from an 
 Animism 2 which almost all races share, and in their early 
 and inarticulate forms they contain a record of most of the 
 main currents in which primitive beliefs are wont to run. After- 
 wards closely connected both with the idea of supernatural 
 possession and with the name of the sun-god Apollo they 
 exhibit a singular fusion of nature-worship with Shahmanism 
 or sorcery. Then, as the non-moral and naturalistic concep- 
 tion of the deity yields to the. moral conception of him as 
 an idealised man, the oracles reflect the change, and the 
 Delphian god becomes in a certain sense the conscience of 
 Greece. 
 
 A period of decline follows ; due, as it would seem, partly 
 to the depopulation and political ruin of Greece, but partly 
 
 1 Roughly speaking, from 700 B.C. to 300 A.D., but the earliest oracles 
 probably date much further back. 
 
 2 It is hardly necessary to say that by Animism is meant a belief in the 
 existence around us of souls or spirits, whether disembodied, as ghosts, or 
 embodied in fetishes, animals, etc. Shahmanism is a word derived from 
 the title of the Siberian wizards, who procure by agitated trance some 
 manifestation from their gods.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 431 
 
 also to the indifference or scepticism of her dominant schools 
 of philosophy. But this decline is followed by a revival which 
 forms one of the most singular of those apparent checks which 
 complicate the onward movement of thought by ever new 
 modifications of the beliefs of the remote past. So far as this 
 complex movement can be at present understood, it seems to 
 have been connected among the mass of the people with the 
 widespread religious upheaval of the first Christian centuries, 
 and to have been at last put an end to by Christian baptism or 
 sword. Among the higher minds it seems to have rested 
 partly on a perplexed admission of certain phenomena, partly 
 on the strongly-felt need of a permanent and elevated revela- 
 tion, which yet should draw its origin from the Hellenic rather 
 than the Hebrew past. And the story reaches a typical con- 
 clusion in the ultimate disengagement of the highest natures 
 of declining Greece from mythology and ceremonial, and the 
 absorption of definite dogma into an overwhelming ecstasy. 
 
 II. 
 
 The attempt to define the word " oracle " confronts us at 
 once with the difficulties of the subject. The Latin term, 
 indeed, which we are forced to employ, points specially to cases 
 where the voice of God or spirit was actually heard, whether 
 directly or through some human intermediary. But the corre- 
 sponding Greek term (jtavreiov) merely signifies a seat of sooth- 
 saying, a place where divinations are obtained by whatever 
 means. And we must not regard the oracles of Greece as rare 
 and majestic phenomena, shrines founded by a full-grown 
 mythology for the direct habitation of a god. Eather they 
 are the products of a long process of evolution, the modified 
 survivals from among countless holy places of a primitive race. 
 
 Greek literature has preserved to us abundant traces of the 
 various causes which led to the ascription of sanctity to some 
 particular locality. Oftenest it is some chasm or cleft in the 
 ground, filled, perhaps, with mephitic vapours, or with the 
 mist of a subterranean stream, or merely opening in its dark 
 obscurity an inlet into the mysteries of the underworld. Such
 
 432 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 was the chasm of the Clarian, 1 the Delian, 2 the Delphian 
 Apollo ; and such the oracle of the prophesying nymphs on 
 Cithaeron. 3 Such was Trophonius' cave, 4 and his own name 
 perhaps is only a synonym for the Mother Earth, " in many 
 names the one identity," who nourishes at once and reveals. 5 
 
 Sometimes as for instance at Megara, 6 Sicyon, Orcho- 
 menus, Laodicea the sanctity gathers around some {3airv\os 
 or fetish- stone, fashioned, it may be, into a column or pyramid, 
 and probably in most cases identified at first with the god 
 himself, though, after the invention of statuary, its significance 
 might be obscured or forgotten. Such stones outlast all 
 religions, and remain for us in their rude shapelessness the 
 oldest memorial of the aspirations or the fears of man. 
 
 Sometimes the sacred place was merely some favourite post 
 of observation of the flight of birds, or of lightning, like 
 Teiresias' " ancient seat of augury," 7 or the hearth 8 from 
 which, before the sacred embassy might start for Delphi, the 
 Pythaists watched above the crest of Parnes for the summons 
 of the heavenly flame. 
 
 Or it might be merely some spot where the divination from 
 burnt- offerings seemed unusually true and plain, at Olympia, 
 for instance, where, as Pindar tells us, "soothsayers divining from 
 sacrifice make trial of Zeus who lightens clear." It is needless 
 to speak at length of groves and streams and mountain-summits, 
 which in every region of the world have seemed to bring the un- 
 seen close to man by waving mystery, or by rushing murmur, or 
 
 1 Iambi, de Myst. p. 74. 
 
 - Lebegue, Recherches sur Ddlos, p. 89. 
 
 3 Pans. ix. 3. See also Paus. v. 14 for a legend of an oracle of Earth herself 
 at Olympia. 
 
 4 Paus. ix. 39. 
 
 5 Tpo<f>i!}vios from rptcpw. The visitor, who lay a long time, 01) /j.d\a ffvp,<f>povC>v 
 eva/xyws etr' eyp-rjyopev eiV diveipoTr6\ei (Plut. de Genio Socratis, 22), had doubt- 
 less been partially asphyxiated. St. Patrick's Purgatory was perhaps con- 
 ducted on the same plan. 
 
 6 Paus. i. 43, and for further references on baetyls see Lebegue, p. 85. See 
 also Lubbock, Origin of Civilisation, p. 225. 
 
 7 Soph. Ant. 1001 ; Paus. ix. 16 ; and cf. Eur. Phoen. 841. 
 
 8 Strabo, ix. p. 619. They watched a,irb rfjs tvx&P -* r v dcrTpa.Tra.lov 
 Ai6s. Even a place where lots were customarily drawn might become a seat 
 of oracle. Paus. vii. 25.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 433 
 
 by nearness to the height of heaven. 1 It is enough, to under- 
 
 v U O 
 
 stand that in Greece, as in other countries over which successive 
 waves of immigration have passed, the sacred places were for 
 the most part selected for primitive reasons, and in primitive 
 times ; then as more civilised races succeeded and Apollo 
 came, whence or in what guise cannot here be discussed, the 
 old shrines were dedicated to new divinities, the old symbols 
 were metamorphosed or disappeared. The fetish-stones were 
 crowned by statues, or replaced by statues and buried in the 
 earth. 2 The Sibyls symbol of the divinations that issue 
 from chasms died in the temples, and the sun-god's island 
 holds the sepulchre of the moon-maidens of the northern 
 sky. 3 
 
 It is impossible to arrange in quite logical order phenomena 
 which touch each other at so many points, but in making our 
 transition from these impersonal or hardly personal oracles of 
 divination to the " voice-oracles " 4 of classical times, we may 
 first mention the well-known Voice or Eumour which as 
 early as Homer runs heaven-sent through the multitude of 
 men, or sometimes prompts to revolution by " the word of 
 Zeus." 5 
 
 To this w r e may add the belief that words spoken at some 
 critical and culminant, or even at some arbitrarily-chosen 
 moment, have a divine significance. We find some trace of 
 
 1 There is little trace in Greece of " weather-oracles," such as the Blocks- 
 berg, hills deriving a prophetic reputation from the indications of coming 
 rain, etc., drawn from clouds on their summits. The sanctity of Olympus, as 
 is well known, is connected with a supposed elevation above all elemental 
 disturbances. 
 
 2 Find. 01. viii. 3, and for further references see Hermann, GriecJi. Ant. ii. 
 247. Maury (ii. 447) seems to deny this localisation on insufficient grounds. 
 
 3 The Hyperborese, see Reff. ap. Lebegue, p. 69. See also Klausen, Aeneas 
 und die Penaten, p. 207 foil., on the connection of Sibyls and xd<rfJ.a.Ta. Hero- 
 phile had herself prophesied from the Delphian baetyl, but in her epitaph 
 she thanks Apollo and complains of nobody but Fate. The bones of the 
 oracular Demo also were interred in a water-pot in the temple of Apollo at 
 Cumae. Paus. x. 12. 
 
 4 ~KpT)<r/j.ol (f>6ey/j.a.TiKol. 
 
 5 6ff<TCL, <f>-fifJ.t), KXTtS^v, 6fj.<jrri II. ii. 93 ; Herod, ix. 100 ; Od. iii. 215, etc. 
 These words are probably used sometimes for regular oracular communica- 
 tions. 
 
 2 E
 
 434 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 this in the oracle of Teiresias, 1 and it appears in a strange form 
 in an old oracle said to have been given to Homer, which tells 
 him to beware of the moment when some young children shall 
 ask him a riddle which he is unable to answer. 2 Cases of 
 omens given by a chance word in classical times are too familiar 
 to need further reference. 3 What we have to notice here is 
 that this casual method of learning the will of heaven was 
 systematise*! into a practice at certain oracular temples, where 
 the applicant made his sacrifice, stopped his ears, went into the 
 market-place, and accepted the first words he happened to hear 
 as a divine intimation. We hear of oracles on this pattern at 
 Memphis, 4 and at Pharae in Achaea. 5 
 
 From these voices, which, though clearly audible, are, as it 
 were, unowned and impersonal, we may pass to voices which 
 have a distinct personality, but are heard only by the sleeping 
 ear. Dreams of departed friends are likely to be the first 
 phenomenon which inspires mankind with the idea that they 
 can hold converse with a spiritual world. We find dreams at 
 the very threshold of the theology of almost all nations, and 
 accordingly it does not surprise us to find Homer asserting 
 that dreams come from Zeus, 6 or painting, with a pathos which 
 later literature has never surpassed, the strange vividness 
 and agonising insufficiency of these fugitive visions of the 
 night. 7 
 
 And throughout Greek literature presaging dreams which 
 form, as Plutarch says, " an unfixed and wandering oracle 
 
 1 Od. xi. 126. 
 
 2 dXXa vtuv Traldwi> afcfy/ia <t>v\a%ai. Paus. x. 24 ; Anth. Pal. xiv. 66. This 
 conundrum, when it was at length put to Homer, was of so vulgar a 
 character that no discredit is reflected on the Father of Poetry by his per- 
 plexity as to its solution. (Homeri et Hesiodi certamen, ad fin.) 
 
 3 Herodotus ix. 90 may be selected as an example of a happy chance in 
 forcing an omen. 
 
 4 Dio Chrys. ad Alex. 32. 13, voides &irayy4\\ov(ri Traifovrfs rb SOKOVV rip 0e<p. 
 
 5 Paus. vii. 22. 
 
 6 n. i. 63. Or from Hermes, or earth, or the gods below. 
 
 7 n. xxiii. 97. If we accept the theory of an older Achilleid we find the 
 importance of augury proper decreasing, of dreams increasing, in the Homeric 
 poems themselves. Geddes, Horn. Probl. p. 186 ; cf. Mure, Hist. Gr. Lit. i. 
 492. Similarly Apollo's darts grow more gentle, and his visitations more 
 benign. Geddes, p. 140.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 435 
 
 of Night and Moon. 1 " are abundant in every form, from the 
 high behest laid on Bellerophon "when in the dark of night stood 
 by him the shadowy-shielded maid, and from a dream, suddenly, 
 a waking vision she became," 2 down to the dreams in the temples 
 of Serapis or of Aesculapius which Aristides the Rhetorician 
 has embalmed for us in his Sacred Orations, the dream which 
 " seemed to indicate a bath, yet not without a certain am- 
 biguity," or the dream which left him in distressing uncertainty 
 whether he were to take an emetic or no. 3 
 
 And just as we have seen that the custom of observing 
 birds, or of noting the omens of casual speech, tended to fix 
 itself permanently in certain shrines, so also dream-oracles, or 
 temples where the inquirer slept in the hope of obtaining an 
 answer from the god seen in vision, or from some other vision 
 sent by him, were one of the oldest forms of oracular seats. 
 Brizo, a dream-prophetess, preceded Apollo at Delos. 4 A 
 similar legend contrasts " the divination of darkness " at Delphi 
 with Apollo's clear prophetic song. 5 Night herself was be- 
 lieved to send visions at Megara, 6 and coins of Commodus still 
 show us her erect and shrouded figure, the torches that glimmer 
 in her shade. Amphiaraus, 7 Amphilochus, 8 Charon, 9 Pasiphae, 10 
 Herakles, 11 Dionysus, 12 and above all Aesculapius, 13 gave 
 answers after this fashion, mainly, but not entirely, in cases of 
 sickness. The prevalence of heroes, rather than gods, as the 
 
 Plut. Ser. Num. Vind. 22. 2 Piiid. 01. xiii. 100. 
 
 Ar. Rhet. vol. i. p. 275 (Dind.), ?X" P^ v Tiva ^vvoiav Xotirpov, ov n^vroi 
 virovolas, and i. 285. 
 
 4 Athen. viii. 2, and see Lebegue, p. 218 ; comp. Aesch. Ag. 275. 
 
 5 Eur. Iph. Taur. 1234 foil. 6 Paus. i. 40. 
 
 7 Paus. i. 34. 8 Dio Cass. Ixxii. 7. 
 
 9 Eustath. Schol. ad Dionys. Perieg. 1153. 
 
 10 Cic. de Div. i. 43 ; Plut. Agis. 9, and cf. Maury, ii. 453. 
 
 11 Paus. ix. 24, comp. inscr. ap. G. Wolff, de Noviss. p. 29, and see Plut. de 
 Malign. Herod. 31 for the dream of Leonidas in Herakles' temple. 
 
 12 Paus. x. 33. 
 
 13 Ar. Rhet. passim, ; Iambi. Myst. 3. 3, etc. See also Val. Max. i. 7 ; 
 Diod. Sic. v. 62; Ar. Rhet. Sacr. Serm. iii. 311, for dreams sent by 
 Athene, the Soteres, Hemithea. Further references will be found in 
 Maury, iii. 456, and for the relation of Apollo to dreams see Bouche-Leclercq, 
 Hist, de la Divination, i. 204.
 
 436 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 givers of oracles in dreams seems still further to indicate the 
 immediate derivation of this form of revelation from the 
 accustomed appearance of departed friends in sleep. 
 
 The next step takes us to the most celebrated class of oracles, 
 those in which the prophetess, or more rarely the prophet, 
 gives vent in agitated trance to the words which she is inspired 
 to utter. We encounter here the phenomena of possession, so 
 familiar to us in the Bible, and of which theology still main- 
 tains the genuineness, while science would explain them by 
 delirium, hysteria, or epilepsy. It was this phenomenon, con- 
 nected first, as Pausanias tells us, 1 with the Apolline oracles, 
 which gave a wholly new impressiveness to oracular replies. 
 No longer confined to simple affirmation and negation, or to 
 the subjective and ill-remembered utterances of a dream, they 
 were now capable of embracing all topics, and of being pre- 
 served in writing as a revelation of general applicability. 
 These oracles of inspiration, taken in connection with the 
 oracles uttered by visible phantoms, which become prominent 
 at a later era, may be considered as marking the highest point 
 of development to which Greek oracles attained. It will be 
 convenient to defer our consideration of some of these pheno- 
 mena till we come to the great controversy between Porphyry 
 and Eusebius, in which they were for the first time fully dis- 
 cussed. But there is one early oracle of the dead, different in 
 some respects from any that succeeded it, 2 which presents so 
 many points for notice that a few reflections on the state of 
 
 1 Paus. i. 34. 
 
 2 The distinction drawn by Nagelsbach between this and other " Todten- 
 orakeln " (Nachhom. Theologie, p. 189) is surely exaggerated. See Klausen, 
 Aeneas und die Penaten, p. 129 foil., for other legends connecting Odysseus 
 with early necromancy, and on this general subject see Herod, v. 92 ; Eur. 
 Ale. 1131 ; Plat. Leg. x. 909 ; Plut. dm. 6, de Ser. Num. Vind. 17 ; 
 Tylor, Prim. Cult. ii. 41. The fact, on which Nagelsbach dwells, that 
 Odysseus, after consulting Teiresias, satisfied his affection and his curiosity by 
 interviews with other ghosts in no way alters the original injunction laid on 
 him, the purport of his journey faxy -xp^abp-evov Q-rj^alov Tetpecrtao. Nagels- 
 bach's other argument, that in later times we hear only of a dream-oracle, 
 not an apparition-oracle, of Teiresias seems to me equally weak. Readers 
 of Pausanias must surely feel what a chance it is which has determined the 
 oracles of which we have heard.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 437 
 
 belief which it indicates will assist us in comprehending the 
 nature of the elevation of Greek faith which was afterwards 
 effected under the influence of Delphi. 
 
 For this, the first oracle of which we have a full account, 
 the descent of Odysseus to the underworld, " to consult the 
 soul of the Theban Teiresias," shows in a way which it would 
 be hard to parallel elsewhere the possible co-existence in the 
 same mind of the creed and practices of the lowest races with 
 a majesty, a pathos, a power, which human genius has never 
 yet overpassed. The eleventh book of the Odyssey is steeped 
 in the Animism of barbarous peoples. The Cimmerian entrance 
 to the world of souls is the close parallel (to take an instance 
 among many) of the extreme western cape of Vanua Levi, a 
 calm and solemn place of cliff and forest, where the souls of 
 the Fijian dead embark for the judgment-seat of Ndengei, and 
 whither the living come on pilgrimage, thinking to see ghosts 
 and gods. 1 Homer's ghosts cheep and twitter precisely as the 
 shadow-souls of the Algonquin Indians chirp like crickets, and 
 Polynesian spirits speak in squeaking tones, and the accent of 
 the ancestral Zulu, when he reappears on earth, has earned 
 for him the name of Whistler. 2 The expedition of Odysseus 
 is itself paralleled by the exploit of Ojibwa, the eponymous 
 hero of the Ojibbeways, of the Finnish hero Wainamoinen, and 
 of many another savage chief. The revival of the ghosts with 
 blood, itself closely paralleled in old Teutonic mythologies, 3 
 speaks of the time when the soul is conceived as feeding on the 
 fumes and shadows of earthly food, as when the Chinese beat 
 the drum which summons ancestral souls to supper, and pro- 
 vide a pail of gruel and a spoon for the greater convenience 
 of any ancestor who may unfortunately have been deprived 
 of his head. 4 
 
 Nay, even the inhabitants of that underworld are only the 
 semblances of once living men. " They themselves," in the 
 terrible words of the opening sentence of the Iliad, " have been 
 left a prey to dogs and every bird." Human thought has not 
 
 1 Prim. Cull. i. 408. 2 Ibid. ii. 42. 
 
 3 Ibul. ii. 346. 4 Ibid. ii. 30.
 
 438 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 yet reached a point at which spirit could be conceived of as 
 more than the shadow of matter. 
 
 And if further evidence were needed, the oracle of Teiresias 
 himself opening like a chasm into Hades through the sunlit 
 soil of Greece reveals unwittingly all the sadness which 
 underlies that freshness and power, the misgiving which so 
 often unites the savage and the philosopher, the man who 
 conies before religions and the man who comes after them, 
 in the gloom of the same despair. Himself alone in his wisdom 
 among the ineffectual shades, Teiresias offers to Odysseus, in the 
 face of all his unjust afflictions, no prevention and no cure ; 
 " of honey-sweet return thou askest, but by God's will bitter 
 shall it be ; " for life's struggle he has no remedy but to 
 struggle to the end, and for the wandering hero he has no 
 deeper promise than the serenity of a gentle death. 
 
 And yet Homer " made the theogony of the Greeks." 1 
 And Homer, through the great ages which followed him, not 
 only retained, but deepened his hold on the Hellenic spirit. 
 It was no mere tradition, it was the ascendency of that essen- 
 tial truth and greatness in Homer, which we still so strongly 
 feel, which was the reason why he was clung to and invoked 
 and explained and allegorised by the loftiest minds of Greece 
 in each successive age ; why he was transformed by Polygnotus, 
 transformed by Plato, transformed by Porphyry. Kay, even 
 in our own day, and this is not the least significant fact in 
 religious history, we have seen one of the most dominant, 
 one of the most religious intellects of our century, falling 
 under the same spell, and extracting from Homer's almost 
 savage animism the full-grown mysteries of the Christian 
 faith. 
 
 So dangerous would it be to assume such a congruence 
 throughout the whole mass of the thought of any epoch, how- 
 ever barbarous, that the baseness or falsity of some of its tenets 
 should be enough to condemn the rest unheard. So ancient, 
 so innate in man is the power of apprehending by emotion 
 and imagination aspects of reality for which a deliberate 
 
 1 Herod, ii. 53, oi/roi 5^ (Homer and Hesiod) eicri ol Troirjcrai'Tes
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 439 
 
 culture might often look in vain. To the dictum, so true 
 though apparently so paradoxical, which asserts " that the 
 mental condition of the lower races is the key to poetry," we 
 may reply with another apparent paradox, that poetry is the 
 only thing which every age is certain to recognise as truth. 
 
 Having thus briefly considered the nature of each of the 
 main classes of oracular response, it is natural to go on to some 
 inquiry into the history of the leading shrines where these 
 responses were given. The scope of this Essay does not admit 
 of a detailed notice of each of the very numerous oracular seats 
 of which some record has reached us. 1 But before passing 
 on to Delphi, I must dwell on two cases of special interest, 
 where recent explorations have brought us nearer than else- 
 where to what may be called the private business of an oracle, 
 or to the actual structure of an Apolline sanctuary. 
 
 The oracle of Zeus at Dodona takes the highest place 
 among all the oracles which answered by signs rather than 
 by inspired speech. 2 It claimed to be the eldest of all, and 
 we need not therefore wonder that its phenomena present an 
 unusual confluence of streams of primitive belief. The first 
 mention of Dodona, 3 in that great invocation of Achilles 
 which is one of the glimpses which Homer gives us of a world 
 far earlier than his own, seems to indicate that it was then 
 a seat of dream- oracles, where the rude Selloi perhaps drew 
 from the earth on which they slept such visions as she sends 
 among men. But in the Odyssey 4 and in Hesiod 5 the oracle 
 is spoken of as having its seat among the leaves, or in the 
 hollow or base of an oak, and this is the idea which prevailed 
 in classical times. 6 The doves, 7 if doves there were, and not 
 merely priestesses, whose name, Peleiades, may be derived from 
 
 1 The number of Greek oracular seats, with the Barbarian seats known to 
 the Greeks, has been estimated at 260, or an even larger number ; but of very 
 many of these we know no more than the name. 
 
 2 Strab. viii. Fragm. txP' r l 'l J -<p5ei 5' ofi 5ia \6ywv dXXoi did nvuv 
 tiffirep rb ev AL^VTJ 'A/u/awvta/civ. So Suid. in voc, Audwvrj, etc. 
 
 3 II. xvi. 233. 
 
 4 Od. xiv. 327, xix. 296. 
 
 * Hes. Fr. 39. 7, valbv T' Iv irv6^vi. tfirjyov. See Plat. Phaedr. 275. 
 
 6 Aesch. Prom. 832 ; Soph. Track. 172 and 1167. 
 
 ~ See Herod, ii. 54, and comp. Od. xii. 63.
 
 440 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 some other root, 1 introduce another element of complexity. 
 Oracles were also given at Dodona by means of lots/ 2 and by 
 the falling of water. 3 Moreover, German industry has estab- 
 lished the fact, that at Dodona it thunders on more days 
 than anywhere else in Europe, and that no peals are louder 
 anywhere than those which echo among the Acroceraunian 
 mountains. It is tempting to derive the word Dodona from 
 the sound of a thunderclap, and to associate this old Pelasgic 
 sanctuary with the propitiation of elemental deities in their 
 angered hour. 4 But the notices of the oracle in later days are 
 perplexingly at variance with all these views. They speak 
 mainly of oracles given by the sound of caldrons, struck, 
 according to Strabo, 5 by knucklebones attached to a wand held 
 by a statue. The temple is even said to have been made, of 
 caldrons, 6 or at least they were so arranged, as a certain Demon 
 tells us, 7 that " all in turn, when one was smitten, the caldrons 
 of Dodona rang." The perpetual sound thus caused is alluded 
 to in a triumphant tone by other writers, 8 but it is the more 
 
 1 On the Priestesses, see references in Herm. Griech. Antiq. ii. 250. 
 
 2 Cic. de Div. ii. 32. 
 
 3 Serv. ad Aen. iii. 466. 
 
 4 I do not think that we can get beyond some such vague conjecture as 
 this, and A. Mommsen and Schmidt's elaborate calculations as to months of 
 maximum frequency of thunderclaps and centres of maximum frequency of 
 earthquakes, as determining the time of festivals or the situation of oracu- 
 lar temples, seem to me to be quite out of place. If a savage possessed 
 the methodical patience of a German observer, he would be a savage no 
 more. Savants must be content to leave Aristotle's rvx~n xal rb avr6fj.aTov, 
 chance and spontaneity, as causes of a large part of the action of primitive 
 men. 
 
 The dictum of Gotte (Delphische Orakel, p. 13) seems to me equally un- 
 proveable : "Dodona, wohin die schwarzen aegyptischen Tauben geflogen 
 kamen, ist wohl unbestreitbar eine aegyptische Cultstatte, die Schwester- 
 anstalt von Ammonium, beide Thebens Tochter. " The geographical position 
 of Dodona is much against this view, the doves are very problematical, and 
 the possible existence of a primitive priesthood in the Selloi is no proof of an 
 Egyptian influence. 
 
 5 Strab. lib. vii. Fragm. ap. Hermann, Griech. Ant. ii. 251, where see 
 further citations. 
 
 c Steph. Byz. s. voc. AuSurt), quoted by Carapanos, in whose monograph on 
 Dodona citations on all these points will be found. 
 
 7 Miiller, Fragm. Hist. Gr. iii. 125. 
 
 8 Callim. Hymn, in Del. 286 ; Philostr. Imag. ii. 33 (a slightly different 
 account).
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 441 
 
 difficult to determine in what precise way the will of Zeus was 
 understood. 
 
 Among such a mass of traditions, it is of course easy to 
 find analogies. The doves may be compared to the hissing 
 ducks of the Abipones, which were connected with the souls of 
 the dead, 1 or with the doves in Popayan, which are spared 
 as inspired by departed souls. The tree-worship opens up 
 lines of thought too well known for repetition. We may 
 liken the Dodonaean " voiceful oak" to the tamarisks of Beer- 
 sheba, and the oak of Shechem, its whisper to the " sound of 
 a going in the tops of the mulberry-trees," which prompted 
 Israel to war, 2 and so on down the long train of memories to 
 Joan of Arc hanging with garlands the fairies' beech beside 
 her father's door at Domremy, and telling her persecutors that 
 if they would set her in a wood once more she would hear the 
 heavenly voices plain. 3 Or we may prefer, with another 
 school, to trace this tree also back to the legendary Ygdrassil, 
 " the celestial tree of the Aryan family," with its spreading 
 branches of the stratified clouds of heaven. One legend at 
 least points to the former interpretation as the more natural. 
 
 1 Prim. Cult. ii. 6. The traces of animal-worship in Greece are many and 
 interesting, but are not closely enough connected with our present subject to 
 be discussed at length. Apollo's possible characters, as the Wolf, the 
 Locust, or the Fieldmouse (or the Slayer of wolves, of locusts, or of field- 
 mice), have not perceptibly affected his oracles. Still less need we be 
 detained by the fish-tailed Eurynome, or the horse-faced Demeter (Paus. viii. 
 41, 42). And although from the time when the boy-prophet lamus lay 
 among the wallflowers, and "the two bright-eyed serpents fed him with the 
 harmless poison of the bee" (Find. 01. vi. 28), snakes appear frequently in 
 connection with prophetic power, their worship falls under the head of 
 divination rather than of oracles. The same remark may be made of ants, 
 cats, and cows. The bull Apis occupies a more definite position, but though 
 he was visited by Greeks, his worship was not a product of Greek thought. 
 The nearest Greek approach, perhaps, to an animal-oracle was at the fount of 
 Myrse in Cilicia (Plin. H.N. xxxii. 2), where fish swam up to eat or reject 
 the food thrown to them. " Diripere eos carnes objectas laetum est con- 
 sultan tibus, " says Pliny, "caudis abigere dirum." And it appears that live 
 snakes were kept in the cave of Trophonius (Philostr. Vit. Apoll. viii. 19), in 
 order to inspire terror in visitors, who were instructed to appease them with 
 cakes (Suid. a. v. /xeXiroCrro). 
 
 2 2 Sam. v. 24. 
 
 8 " Dixit quod si esset in uno nemore bene audiret voces venientes ad earn." 
 On Tree-worship see Lubbock, Origin of Civilieation, p. 206 foil.
 
 442 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 For just as a part of the ship Argo, keel or prow, was made of 
 the Dodonaeau oak, and Argo's crew heard with astonishment 
 the ship herself prophesy to them on the sea : 
 
 ' ' But Jason and the builder, Argus, knew 
 Whereby the prow foretold things strange and new ; 
 Nor wondered aught, but thanked the gods therefore, 
 As far astern they left the Mysian shore," J 
 
 so do we find a close parallel to this among the Siamese, 2 
 who believe that the inhabiting nymphs of trees pass into the 
 guardian spirits of boats built with their wood, to which they 
 continue to sacrifice. 
 
 Passing on to the answers which were given at this shrine, 
 we find that at Dodona, 3 as well as at Delphi, 4 human sacrifice 
 is to be discerned in the background. But in the form in 
 which the legend reaches us, its horror has been sublimed into 
 pathos. Coresus, priest of Bacchus at Calydon, loved the 
 maiden Callirhoe in vain. Bacchus, indignant at his ser- 
 vant's repulse, sent madness and death on Calydon. The 
 oracle of Dodona announced that Coresus must sacrifice 
 Callirhoe, or some one who would die for her. No one was 
 willing to die for her, and she stood up beside the altar to be 
 slain. But when Coresus looked on her his love overcame 
 his anger, and he slew himself in her stead. Then her heart 
 turned to him, and beside the fountain to which her name 
 was given she died by her own hand, and followed him to the 
 underworld. 
 
 There is another legend of Dodona 5 to which the student 
 of oracles may turn with a certain grim satisfaction at the 
 thought that the ambiguity of style which has so often 
 baffled him did once at least carry its own penalty with it. 
 Certain Boeotian envoys, so the story runs, were told by 
 Myrtile, the priestess of Dodona, " that it would be best for 
 them to do the most impious thing possible." The Boeotians 
 
 1 Morris's Life and Death of Jason, Book iv. ad fin. 
 
 1 Prim. Cult. iL 198. 8 Paus. vii. 21. 
 
 * Eus. Pr. Ev. v. 27, irapOtvov AtTrvrldav K\ijpos /caXet, etc. See also the 
 romantic story of Melanippus and Comoetho, Paus. vii. 19. 
 
 5 Ephor. ad Strab. ix. 2 ; Heracl. Pont. Fragm. Hist. Gr. ii. 198 ; Proclus, 
 Chrest. ii. 248, and see Carapanos.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 443 
 
 immediately threw the priestess into a caldron of boiling 
 water, remarking that they could not think of anything much 
 more impious than that. 
 
 The ordinary business of Dodona, however, was of a less 
 exciting character. M. Carapanos has discovered many tablets 
 on which the inquiries of visitors to the oracle were inscribed, 
 and these give a picture, sometimes grotesque, but oftener 
 pathetic, of the simple faith of the rude Epirots who dwelt 
 round about the shrine. The statuette of an acrobat hanging 
 to a rope shows that the " Dodonaean Pelasgian Zeus " did not 
 disdain to lend his protection to the least dignified forms of 
 jeopardy to life and limb. A certain Agis asks " whether he 
 has lost his blankets and pillows himself, or some one outside 
 has stolen them." An unknown \voman asks simply how she 
 may be healed of her disease. Lysanias asks if he is indeed 
 the father of the child which his wife Nyla is soon to bear. 
 Evaudrus and his wife, in broken dialect, seek to know " by 
 what prayer or worship they may fare best now and for ever." 
 And there is something strangely pathetic in finding on a 
 broken plate of lead the imploring inquiry of the fierce and 
 factious Corcyreans, made, alas ! in vain, " to what god or 
 hero offering prayer and sacrifice they might live together in 
 unity?" 1 "For the men of that time," says Plato, 2 '-'since 
 they were not wise as ye are nowadays, it was enough in their 
 simplicity to listen to oak or rock, if only these told them true." 
 To those rude tribes, indeed, their voiceful trees were the one 
 influence which lifted them above barbarism and into contact 
 with the surrounding world. Again and again Dodona was 
 ravaged, 3 but so long as the oak was standing the temple rose 
 anew. When at last an Illyrian bandit cut down the oak 4 the 
 presence of Zeus was gone, and the desolate Thesprotian valley 
 has known since then no other sanctity, and has found no 
 other voice. 
 
 I proceed to another oracular seat, of great mythical 
 celebrity, though seldom alluded to in classical times, to which 
 
 1 TVw KO. Oeuv % i]pww> Otiovres /ecu Ax&Ufvoi b^ovoolev tirl TayaObv. 
 * Phaedr. 275. Recherches sur Delos, par J. A. Lebgue, 1876. 
 Strab. vii. 6 ; Polyb. ix. 67, and cf. Wolff, de Novis*. p. 13. 
 4 Serv. ad Afn. iii. 466.
 
 444 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 a recent exploration has given a striking interest, bringing us, 
 as it were, into direct connection across so many ages with 
 the birth and advent of a god. 
 
 On the slope of Cynthus, near the mid-point of the Isle of 
 Delos, ten gigantic blocks of granite, covered with loose stones 
 and the debris of ages, form a rude vault, half hidden in the 
 hill. The islanders call it the " dragon's cave ; " travellers had 
 taken it for the remains of a fortress or of a reservoir. It was 
 reserved for two French savants to show how much knowledge 
 the most familiar texts have yet to yield when they are 
 meditated on by minds prepared to compare and to compre- 
 hend. A familiar passage in Homer, 1 illustrated by much 
 ancient learning and many calculations of his own, suggested 
 to M. Burnouf, Director of the French School of Archaeology at 
 Athens, that near this point had been a primitive post of 
 observation of the heavens ; nay, that prehistoric men had 
 perhaps measured their seasons by the aid of some rude instru- 
 ment in this very cave. An equally familiar line of Virgil, 2 
 supported by some expressions in a Homeric hymn, led M. 
 Lebegue to the converging conjecture that at this spot the 
 Delian oracle had its seat ; that here it was that Leto's long 
 wanderings ended, and Apollo and Artemis were born. Every 
 schoolboy has learnt by heart the sounding lines which tell 
 how Aeneas " venerated the temple built of ancient stone," and 
 how at the god's unseen coming " threshold and laurel trembled, 
 and all the mountain round about was moved." But M. 
 Lebegue was the first to argue hence with confidence that the 
 oracle must have been upon the mountain and not on the 
 coast, and that those ancient stones, like the Cyclopean treasure- 
 house of Mycenae, might be found and venerated still. So far 
 as a reader can judge without personal survey, these expecta- 
 tions have been amply fulfilled. 3 At each step M. Lebegue's 
 
 1 Od. xv. 403. Em. Burnouf, Revue Archtologiqiie, Aug. 8, 1873. 
 
 2 Aen. iii. 84 ; Horn. Hymn., Del. 15-18, and 79-81. 
 
 3 M. Homolle (Fouilles de Delos, 1879) gives no direct opinion on the matter, 
 but his researches indirectly confirm M. Lebegue's view, in so far as that 
 among the numerous inscriptions, etc. , which he has found among the ruins 
 of the temple of Apollo on the coast, there seems to be no trace of oracular 
 response or inquiry.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 445 
 
 researches revealed some characteristic of an oracular shrine. 
 In a walled external space were the remains of a marble base 
 on which a three-legged instrument had been fixed by metal 
 claws. Then came a transverse wall, shutting off the temple 
 within, which looks westward, so that the worshipper, as he 
 approaches, may face the east. The floor of this temple is reft 
 by a chasm, the continuation of a ravine which runs down 
 the hill, and across which the sanctuary has been intentionally 
 built. And in the inner recess is a rough block of granite, 
 smoothed on the top, where a statue has stood. The statue 
 has probably been knocked into the chasm by a rock falling 
 through the partly-open roof. Its few fragments show that it 
 represented a young god. The stone itself is probably a fetish, 
 surviving, with the Cyclopean stones which make the vault 
 above it, from a date perhaps many centuries before the 
 Apolline religion came. This is all, but this is enough. For 
 we have here in narrow compass all the elements of an oracular 
 shrine ; the westward aspect, the sacred enclosure, the tripod, 
 the sanctuary, the chasm, the fetish-stone, the statue of a 
 youthful god. And when the situation is taken into account, 
 the correspondence with the words both of Virgil and of the 
 Homerid becomes so close as to be practically convincing. It 
 is true that the smallness of scale, the sanctuary measures 
 some twenty feet by ten, and the remote archaism of the 
 structure, from which all that was beautiful, almost all that 
 was Hellenic, has long since disappeared, cause at first a shock 
 of disappointment like that inspired by the size of the citadel, 
 and the character of the remains, at Hissarlik. Yet, on reflec- 
 tion, this seeming incongruity is an additional element of 
 proof. There is something impressive in the thought that 
 amidst all the marble splendour which made Delos like a 
 jewel in the sea, it was this cavernous and prehistoric sanc- 
 tuary, as mysterious to Greek eyes as to our own, which 
 their imagination identified with that earliest temple which 
 Leto promised, in her hour of trial, that Apollo's hands should 
 build. This, the one remaining seat of oracle out of the 
 hundreds which Greece contained, was the one sanctuary 
 which the Far-darter himself had wrought ; no wonder that 
 his mighty workmanship has outlasted the designs of men !
 
 446 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 All else is gone. The temples, the amphitheatres, the colon- 
 nades, which glittered on every crest and coign of the holy 
 island, have sunk into decay. But he who sails among the 
 isles of Greece may still note around sea-girt Delos " the dark 
 wave welling shoreward beneath the shrill and breezy air ; " l 
 he may still note at sunrise, as on that sunrise when the god 
 was born, "the whole island abloom with shafts of gold, as 
 a hill's crested summit blooms with woodland flowers." ~ 
 " And thou thyself, lord of the silver bow," he may exclaim 
 with the Homerid in that burst of exultation in which the 
 uniting Ionian race seems to leap to the consciousness of all 
 its glory in an hour, " thou walkedst here in very presence, 
 on Cynthus' leafy crown ! " 
 
 " Ah, many a forest, many a peak is thine, 
 On many a promontory stands thy shrine, 
 But best and first thy love, thy home, is here ; 
 Of all thine isles thy Delian isle most dear ; 
 There the long-robed lonians, man and maid, 
 Press to thy feast in all their pomp arrayed, 
 To thee, to Artemis, to Leto pay 
 The heartfelt honour on thy natal day ; 
 Immortal would he deem them, ever young, 
 Who then should walk the Ionian folk among, 
 Should those tall men, those stately wives behold, 
 Swift ships seafaring and long-garnered gold : 
 But chiefliest far his eyes and ears would meet 
 Of sights, of sounds most marvellously sweet, 
 The Delian girls amid the thronging stir, 
 The loved hand-maidens of the Far-darter ; 
 The Delian girls, whose chorus, long and long, 
 Chants to the god his strange, his ancient song, 
 Till whoso hears it deems his own voice sent 
 Thro' the azure air that music softly blent, 
 So close it comes to each man's heart, and so 
 His own soul feels it and his glad tears flow. " 
 
 Such was the legend of the indigenous, the Hellenic Apollo. 
 But the sun does not rise over one horizon alone, and the 
 glory of Delos was not left un contested or unshared. Another 
 hymn, of inferior poetical beauty, but of equal, if not greater, 
 authority among the G-reeks, relates how Apollo descended 
 from the Thessalian Olympus, and sought a place where he 
 
 1 Hymn. Del. 27. * Ibid. 138-164.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 447 
 
 might found his temple : how he was refused by Tilphussa, and 
 selected Delphi ; and how, in the guise of a dolphin, he led 
 thither a crew of Cretans to be the servants of his shrine. 
 With this hymn, so full of meaning for the comparative 
 mythologist, we are here only concerned as introducing us 
 to Apollo in the aspect in which we know him best, " giving 
 his answers from the laurel-wood, beneath the hollows of Par- 
 nassus' hill." l 
 
 At Delphi, as at Dodona, we seem to trace the relics of 
 many a form of worship and divination which we cannot now 
 distinctly recall. From that deep cleft "in rocky Pytho," 
 Earth, the first prophetess, gave her earliest oracle, 2 in days 
 which w r ere already a forgotten antiquity to the heroic age of 
 Greece. The maddening vapour, which was supposed to rise 
 from the chasm, 3 belongs to nymph-inspiration rather than to 
 the inspiration of Apollo. At Delphi too was the most famous 
 of all fetish-stones, believed in later times to be the centre of 
 the earth. 4 At Delphi divination from the sacrifice of goats 
 reached an immemorial antiquity. 5 Delphi too was an ancient 
 centre of divination by fire, a tradition which survived in the 
 name of Pyrcon, 6 given to Hephaestus's minister, while Heph- 
 aestus shared with Earth the possession of the shrine, and in 
 the mystic title of the Elame-kindlers, 7 assigned in oracular 
 utterances to the Delphian folk. At Delphi too, in ancient 
 days, the self-moved lots sprang in the goblet in obedience to 
 Apollo's will. 8 The waving of the Delphic laurel, 9 which in 
 later times seemed no more than a token of the wind and 
 
 1 Hymn. Pyih. 214. 
 
 2 Aesch. Eum. 2 ; Paus. x. 5 ; cf. Eur. Iph. Taur. 1225 sqq. 
 
 3 Strabo, ix. p. 419, etc. In a paper read before the British Archseological 
 Association, March 5, 1879, Dr. Phene has given an interesting account of 
 subterranean chambers at Delphi, which seem to indicate that gases from the 
 subterranean Castalia were received in a chamber where the Pythia may have 
 sat. But in the absence of direct experiment this whole question is physio- 
 logically very obscure. 
 
 4 Paus. x. 16, etc. 
 
 5 Diod. Sic. xvi. 26. Pliny (Hist. Nat. vii. 56) ascribes the invention of this 
 mode of divination to Delphos, a son of Apollo. 
 
 6 Paus. x. 5. 7 Plut. Pytli. 24. 
 
 8 Suidas, iii. p. 237 ; cf. Callim. Hymn, in Apoll. 45, etc. 
 
 9 Ar. Plut. 213 ; Callim. Hymn, in Apoll. 1, etc.
 
 448 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 spiritual stirring which announced the advent of the god, was 
 probably the relic of an ancient tree-worship, like that of 
 Dodona, 1 and Daphne, priestess of Delphi's primeval Earth- 
 oracle, 2 is but one more of the old symbolical figures that have 
 melted back again into impersonal nature at the appearing of 
 the God of Day. Lastly, at Delphi is laid the scene of the 
 sharpest conflict between the old gods and the new. What- 
 ever may have been the meaning of the Python, whether he 
 were a survival of snake-worship, or a winding stream which 
 the sun's rays dry into rotting marsh, or only an emblem of 
 the cloud which trails across the sunlit heaven, his slaughter 
 by Apollo was an integral part of the early legend, and at the 
 Delphian festivals the changes of the " Pythian strain " com- 
 memorated for many a year that perilous encounter, the god's 
 descent into the battle-field, his shout of summons, his cry of 
 conflict, his paean of victory, and then the gnashing of the 
 dragon's teeth in his fury, the hiss of his despair. 3 And the 
 mythology of a later age has connected with this struggle the 
 first ideas of moral conflict and expiation which the new 
 religion had to teach ; has told us that the victor needed 
 purification after his victory ; that he endured and was for- 
 given ; and that the god himself first wore his laurel- wreath 
 as a token of supplication, and not of song. 4 
 
 With a similar ethical purpose the simple narrative of the 
 Homerid has been transformed into a legend 5 of a type which 
 meets us often in the middle ages, but which wears a deeper 
 pathos when it occurs in the midst of Hellenic gladness and 
 youth, the legend of Trophonius and Agamedes, the arti- 
 
 1 1 cannot, however, follow M. Maury (ii. 442) in supposing (as he does in 
 the case of the Delian laurel, A en. iii. 73) that such tree-movements need 
 indicate an ancient habit of divining from their sound. The idea of a wind 
 accompanying divine manifestations seems more widely diffused in Greece 
 than the Dodonaean idea of vocal trees. Cf. (for instance) Plut. DeDef. orac. 
 of the Delphian adytum, evudias a.vairlfj.w\arai Kal Tn^/xaros. 
 
 2 Paus. x. 5. 
 
 3 A/jLTreipa, Ka.Ta,Ke\fv<T[j.6s, crdXiriy!;, Sa/cruXot, oSovricr/ios, vtipiyyes. See August 
 Mommsen's Delphilca on this topic. 
 
 4 Botticher, Baumcultus, p. 353 ; and see reff. ap. Herm. Griech. Ant. ii. 
 127. Cf. Eur. Ion, 114 sqq. 
 
 5 Cic. Tusc. i. 47 ; cf. Plut. De Consol. ad Apollon. 14.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 449 
 
 ficcrs who built the god's home after his heart's desire, and 
 whom lie rewarded with the guerdon that is above all recom- 
 pense, a speedy and a gentle death. 
 
 In the new temple at any rate, as rebuilt in historic times, 
 the moral significance of the Apolline religion was expressed 
 in unmistakable imagery. Even as " four great zones of 
 sculpture" girded the hall of Camelot, the centre of the 
 faith which was civilising Britain, " with many a mystic 
 symbol" of the victory of man, so over the portico of the 
 Delphian god were painted or sculptured such scenes as told 
 of the triumph of an ideal humanity over the monstrous 
 deities which are the offspring of savage fear. 1 
 
 There was " the light from the eyes of the twin faces " of 
 Leto's children ; there was Herakles with golden sickle, lolaus 
 with burning brand, withering the heads of the dying Hydra, 
 " the story," says the girl in the Ion who looks thereon, "which 
 is sung beside my loom ; " there was the rider of the winged 
 steed slaying the fire-breathing Chimaera ; there was the tumult 
 of the giants' war ; Pallas lifting the aegis against Enceladus ; 
 Zeus crushing Mimas with the great bolt fringed with flame, 
 and Bacchus " with his unwarlike ivy-wand laying another of 
 Earth's children low." 
 
 It is important thus to dwell on some of the indications, 
 and there are many of them, which point to the conviction 
 entertained in Greece as to the ethical and civilising influence 
 of Delphi, inasmuch as the responses which have actually 
 been preserved to us, though sufficient, when attentively con- 
 sidered, to support this view, are hardly such as would at once 
 have suggested it. The set collections of oracles, which no 
 doubt contained those of most ethical importance, have 
 perished ; of all the " dark-written tablets, groaning with many 
 an utterance of Loxias," 2 none remain to us except such frag- 
 
 1 The passage in the Ion, 190-218, no doubt describes either the portico 
 which the Athenians dedicated at Delphi about 426 B.C. (Paus. x. 11), or (as 
 the words of the play, if taken strictly, would indicate) the facade of the 
 temple itself. 
 
 2 Eur. Fr. 625. Collections of oracles continued to be referred to till the 
 Turks took Constantinople, i.e. for about 2000 years. See reff. ap. Wolff, 
 de Noviss. p. 48. 
 
 2F
 
 450 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 ruents of Porphyry's treatise as Eusebius has embodied in his 
 refutation. And many of the oracles which we do possess owe 
 their preservation to the most trivial causes, to their connec- 
 tion with some striking anecdote, or to something quaint in 
 their phraseology which has helped to make them proverbial. 
 The reader, therefore, who passes from the majestic descriptions 
 of the Ion or the Eumenides to the actual study of the existing 
 oracles will at first run much risk of disappointment. Both 
 style and subject will often seem unworthy of these lofty 
 claims. He will come, for instance, on such oracles as that 
 which orders Temenus to seek as guide of the army a man 
 with three eyes, who turns out (according to different legends) 
 to be either a one-eyed man on a two-eyed horse, or a two- 
 eyed man on a one-eyed mule. 1 This oracle is composed 
 precisely on the model of the primitive riddles of the Aztec 
 and the Zulu, and is almost repeated in Scandinavian legend, 
 where Odin's single eye gives point to the enigma. 2 Again, the 
 student's ear will often be offended by roughnesses of rhythm 
 which seem unworthy of the divine inventor of the hexameter. 3 
 And the constantly recurring prophecies are, for the most part, 
 uninteresting and valueless, as the date of their composition 
 cannot be proved, nor their genuineness in any way tested. 
 As an illustration of the kind of difficulties which we here 
 encounter, we may select one remarkable oracle,* of immense 
 celebrity in antiquity, which certainly suggests more ques- 
 tions than we can readily answer. The outline of the familiar 
 story is as follows : Croesus wished to make war on Cyrus, 
 but was afraid to do so without express sanction from heaven. 
 It was therefore all-important to him to test the veracity of the 
 oracles, and his character, as the most religious man of his time, 
 enabled him to do so systematically without risk of incurring 
 the charge of impiety. He sent messages to the six best-known 
 
 1 Apollod. ii. 8 ; Paus. v. 3. 2 Prim. Cult. i. 85. 
 
 3 Bald though the god's style may often be, he possesses at any rate a 
 sounder notion of metre than some of his German critics. Lobeck (Aglao- 
 phamus, p. 852), attempting to restore a lost response, suggests the line 
 
 ffTevvypTjv 5'evoevv evpvycurTopa ov Kara ycuaf, 
 
 He apologises for the quantity of the first syllable of fvpvyaffropa, but seems to 
 think that no further remark is needed. 
 
 * Herod, i. 47.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 451 
 
 oracles then existing, to Delphi, to Dodona, to Branchidae, to 
 the oracles of Zeus Ammon, of Trophonius, of Arnphiaraus. 
 On the hundredth day from leaving Sardis, his envoys were to 
 ask what Croesus was at that moment doing. Four oracles 
 failed; Amphiaraus was nearly right; Apollo at Delphi 
 entirely succeeded. For the Pythia answered, with exact 
 truth, that Croesus was engaged in boiling a lamb and a 
 tortoise together in a copper vessel with a copper lid. The 
 messengers, who had not themselves known what Croesus was 
 going to do, returned to Sardis and reported, and were then 
 once more despatched to Delphi, with gifts so splendid that in 
 the days of Herodotus they were still the glory of the sanc- 
 tuary. They now asked the practically important question 
 as to going to war, and received a quibbling answer which, in 
 effect, lured on Croesus to his destruction. 
 
 Now here the two things certain are that Croesus did 
 send these gifts to Delphi, and did go to war with Cyrus. 
 Beyond these facts there is no sure footing. Short and pithy 
 fragments of poetry, like the oracles on which the story hangs, 
 are generally among the earliest and most enduring fragments 
 of genuine history. On the other hand, they are just the 
 utterances which later story-tellers are most eager to invent. 
 Nor must we argue from their characteristic diction, for the 
 pseudo-oracular is a style which has in all ages been cultivated 
 with success. The fact which it is hardest to dispose of is the 
 existence of the prodigious, the unrivalled offerings of Croesus 
 at Delphi. Why were they sent there, unless for some such 
 reason as Herodotus gives ? Or are they sufficiently explained 
 by a mere reference to that almost superstitious deference with 
 which the Mermnadae seem to have regarded the whole re- 
 ligion and civilisation of Greece ? With our imperfect data, 
 we can perhaps hardly go with safety beyond the remark that, 
 granting the genuineness of the oracle about the tortoise, and 
 the substantial truth of Herodotus's account, there will still 
 be no reason to suppose that the god had any foreknowledge 
 as to the result of Croesus's war. The story itself, in fact, 
 contains almost a proof to the contrary. We cannot suppose 
 that the god, in saying, " Croesus, if he cross the Halys, shall 
 undo a mighty realm," was intentionally inciting his favoured
 
 452 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 servant to his ruin. It is obvious that he was sheltering his 
 ignorance behind a calculated ambiguity. And the only in- 
 telligence to which he or his priestess could, on any hypothesis, 
 fairly lay claim, would be of the kind commonly described as 
 " second-sight," a problem with which ethnologists have 
 already to deal all over the world, from the Hebrides to the 
 Coppermine Eiver. 
 
 It is obvious that the documents before us are far from 
 enabling us to prove even this hypothesis. And we are 
 further still from any evidence for actual prophecy which can 
 stand a critical investigation. Hundreds of such cases are 
 indeed reported to us, and it was on a conviction that Apollo 
 did indeed foretell the future that the authority of Delphi 
 mainly depended. But when we have said this, we have said 
 all ; no case is so reported as to enable us altogether to exclude 
 the possibility of coincidence, or of the fabrication of the 
 prophecy after the event. But, on the other hand, and this 
 is a more surprising circumstance, it is equally difficult to 
 get together any satisfactory evidence for the conjecture which 
 the parallel between Delphi and the Papacy so readily 
 suggests, that the power of the oracle was due to the 
 machinations of a priestly aristocracy, with widely-scattered 
 agents, who insinuated themselves into the confidence, and 
 traded on the credulity, of mankind. We cannot but suppose 
 that, to some extent at least, this must have been the case, 
 that when " the Pythia philippised," she reflected the fears of a 
 knot of Delphian proprietors ; that the unerring counsel given 
 to private persons, on which Plutarch insists, must have rested, 
 in part at least, on a secret acquaintance with their affairs, 
 possibly acquired in some cases under the seal of confession. 
 In the paucity, however, of direct evidence to this effect, our 
 estimate of the amount of pressure exercised by a deliberate 
 human agency in determining the policy of Delphi must rest 
 mainly on our antecedent view of what is likely to have been 
 the case, where the interests involved were of such wide 
 importance. 1 
 
 1 For this view of the subject, see Hiillmann, Wwrdigung des Delphischen 
 Orakels ; Gotte, Das Delphische Orakel, and Mr. Justice Bowen's Essay on 
 " Delphi." August Mommsen (Delphika) takes a somewhat similar view, and
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 453 
 
 For indeed the political influence of the Delphian oracle, 
 however inspired or guided, the value to Hellas of this one 
 unquestioned centre of national counsel and national unity, 
 has always formed one of the most impressive topics with 
 which the historian of Greece has had to deal. And I shall 
 pass this part of my subject rapidly by, as already familiar to 
 most readers, and shall not repeat at length the well-known 
 stories, the god's persistent command to expel the Peisistratids 
 from Athens, his partiality for Sparta, as shown both in en- 
 couragement and warning, 1 or the attempts, successful 2 and 
 unsuccessful, 3 to bribe his priestess. Nor shall I do more than 
 allude to the encouragement of colonisation, counsel of great 
 wisdom, which the god lost no opportunity of enforcing both 
 on the Dorian and Ionian stocks. He sent the Cretans to 
 Sicily, 4 and Alcmaeon to the Echinades ; 5 he ordered the foun- 
 dation of Byzantium 6 " over against the city of the blind ; " he 
 sent Archias to Ortygia to found Syracuse, 7 the Boeotians to 
 Heraclea at Pratos, 8 and the Spartans to Heraclea in Thessaly. 9 
 And in the story which Herodotus 10 and Pindar n alike have 
 made renowned, he singled out Battus, anxious merely to 
 learn a cure for his stammer, but type of the man with a 
 destiny higher than he knows, to found at Gyrene " a 
 charioteering city upon the silvern bosom of the hill." And, 
 as has often been remarked, this function of colonisation had 
 a religious as well as a political import. The colonists, before 
 whose adventurous armaments Apollo, graven on many a gem, 
 still hovers over the sea, carried with them the civilising 
 
 calls the Pythia a " blosse Figurantin," but his erudition has added little to 
 the scanty store of texts on which Hiillmann, etc. , depend. I may mention 
 here that Hendess has collected most of the existing oracles (except those 
 quoted by Eusebius) in a tract, Oracula quae supersunt, etc., which is con- 
 venient for reference. 
 
 1 Herod, vi. 52 ; Thuc. i. 118, 123 ; ii. 54. Warnings, ap. Paus. iii. 8 ; ix. 
 32 ; Diod. Sic. xi. 50 ; xv. 54. Plut. Lys. 22 ; Agesil. 3. 
 
 2 Cleisthenes, Herod, v. 63, 66 ; Pleistoanax, Thuc. v. 16. 
 
 3 Cleomenes (Cobon and Perialla) Herod, vi. 66 ; Lysander ; Plut. Lys. 26 ; 
 Ephor. Fr. 127 ; Nep. Lys. 3. 
 
 4 Herod, vii. 170. 5 Thuc. ii. 102. 
 
 6 Strab. vii. 320 ; Tac. Ann. xii. 63 ; but see Herod, iv. 144. 
 
 7 Paus. v. 7. 8 Justin, xvi. 3. 9 Thuc. iii. 29. 
 10 Herod, iv. 155. u Pyth. iv.
 
 454 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 maxims of the "just-judging" 1 sanctuary as well as the brand 
 kindled on the world's central altar-stone from that pine-fed 2 
 and eternal fire. Yet more distinctly can we trace the response 
 of the god to each successive stage of ethical progress to which 
 the evolution of Greek thought attains. 
 
 The moralising Hesiod is honoured at Delphi in preference 
 to Homer himself. The Seven Wise Men, the next examples 
 of a deliberate effort after ethical rules, are connected closely 
 with the Pythian shrine. Above the portal is inscribed that 
 first condition of all moral progress, " Know Thyself; " nor does 
 the god refuse to encourage the sages whose inferior ethical 
 elevation suggests to them only such maxims as, " Most men 
 are bad, " or " Never go bail." 3 
 
 Solon and Lycurgus, the spiritual ancestors of the Athenian 
 and the Spartan types of virtue, receive the emphatic approval 
 of Delphi, and the " Theban eagle," the first great exponent of 
 the developed faith of Greece, already siding with the spirit 
 against the letter, and refusing to ascribe to a divinity any 
 immoral act, already preaching the rewards and punishments 
 of a future state in strains of impassioned revelation, this 
 great poet is dear above all men to Apollo during his life, and 
 is honoured for centuries after his death by the priest's nightly 
 summons, " Let Pindar the poet come in to the supper of the 
 god." * It is from Delphi that reverence for oaths, respect for 
 the life of slaves, of women, of suppliants, derive in great 
 measure their sanction and strength. 5 I need only allude to 
 the well-known story of Glaucus, who consulted the god to 
 know whether he should deny having received the gold in 
 deposit from his friend, and who was warned in lines which 
 sounded from end to end of Greece of the nameless Avenger 
 of the broken oath, whose wish was punished like a deed, 
 and whose family was blotted out. The numerous responses 
 
 1 Pyth. xi. 9. 
 
 2 Plut. de El apud Delphos. Cf. Aesch. Eum. 40 ; Choeph. 1036. 
 
 8 I say nothing, de El apud Delphos, about the mystic word which five 
 of the wise men, or perhaps all seven together, put up in wooden letters at 
 Delphi, for their wisdom has in this instance wholly transcended our inter- 
 pretation. 
 
 4 Paus. ix. 23. 5 Herod, ii. 134 ; vi. 139, etc.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 455 
 
 of M'hich this is the type brought home to men's minds the 
 notion of right and wrong, of reward and punishment, with a 
 force and impressiveness which was still new to the Grecian 
 world. 
 
 More surprising, perhaps, at so early a stage of moral 
 thought, is the catholicity of the Delphian god, his indulgence 
 towards ceremonial differences or ceremonial offences, his 
 reference of casuistical problems to the test of the inward 
 lightness of the heart. 1 It was the Pythian Apollo who 
 replied to the inquiry, "How best are we to worship the gods?" 
 by the philosophic answer, " After the custom of your country," 2 
 and who, if those customs varied, would only bid men choose 
 " the best." It was Apollo who rebuked the pompous sacrifice 
 of the rich Magnesian by declaring his preference for the cake 
 and frankincense which the pious Achaean offered in humble- 
 ness of heart. 3 It was Apollo who warned the Greeks not to 
 make superstition an excuse for cruelty, who testified, by his 
 commanding interference, his compassion for human infirmi- 
 ties, for the irresistible heaviness of sleep, 4 for the thoughtless- 
 ness of childhood, 5 for the bewilderment of the whirling brain. 6 
 Yet the impression which the Delphian oracles make on 
 the modern reader will depend less on isolated anecdotes like 
 these than on something of the style and temper which appears 
 especially in those responses which Herodotus has preserved, 
 something of that delightful mingling of navvettwitla greatness, 
 
 1 See, for instance, the story of the young man and the brigands, Ael. Hint. 
 Var. iii. 4. 3. 
 
 2 Xen. Mem. iv. 3. ij re yap TLvOia. v6/j,cf TroXews avaipet TTOIOWTO.S evffejS&s &y 
 TTOutv. The Pythia often urged the maintenance or renewal of ancestral rites. 
 Paus. viii. 24, etc. 
 
 3 Theopomp. Fr. 283 ; cf. Sopater, Prolegg. in Aristid. Panath. p. 740, 
 eCaSt /not x0i#s Mfiavos, K.T.\. (Wolff, de Noviss. p. 5 ; Lob. Agl. 1006), and 
 compare the story of Poseidon (Pint, de Prof, in Virt. 12), who first re- 
 proached Stilpon in a dream for the cheapness of his offerings, but on learning 
 that he could afford nothing better, smiled, and promised to send abundant 
 anchovies. For the Delphian god's respect for honest poverty, see Plin. 
 H. N. vii. 47. 4 Evenius. Herod, ix. 93. 
 
 5 Paus viii. 23. This is the case of the Arcadian children who hung the 
 goddess in play. 
 
 6 Paus. vi. 9 ; Plut. Romul. 28 (Cleomedes). For further instances of the 
 inculcation of mercy, see Thuc. ii. 102 ; Athen. xi. p. 504.
 
 456 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 which was the world's irrecoverable bloom. What scholar has 
 not smiled over the god's answer 1 to the colonists who had 
 gone to a barren island in mistake for Libya, and came back 
 complaining that Libya was unfit to live in ? He told them 
 that " if they who had never visited the sheep-bearing Libya 
 knew it better than he who had, he greatly admired their 
 cleverness." Who has not felt the majesty of the lines which 
 usher in the test-oracle of Croesus with the lofty assertion of 
 the omniscience of heaven ? 2 lines which deeply impressed the 
 Greek mind, and whose graven record, two thousand years 
 afterwards, was among the last relics which were found among 
 the ruins of Delphi. 3 
 
 It is Herodotus, if any one, who has caught for us the 
 expression on the living face of Hellas. It is Herodotus whose 
 pencil has perpetuated that flying moment of young uncon- 
 sciousness when evil itself seemed as if it could leave no stain 
 on her expanding soul, when all her faults were reparable, and 
 all her wounds benign, when we can still feel that in her 
 upward progress all these and more might be forgiven and 
 pass harmless away 
 
 for the time 
 Was May-time, and as yet no sin was dreamed. 
 
 And through all this vivid and golden scene the Pythian 
 Apollo " the god," as he is termed with a sort of familar affec- 
 tion is the never-failing counsellor and friend. His provi- 
 dence is all the divinity which the growing nation needs. His 
 wisdom is not inscrutable and absolute, but it is near and kind ; 
 it is like the counsel of a young father to his eager boy. To 
 strip the oracles from Herodotus's history would be to deprive 
 it of its deepest unity and its most characteristic charm. 
 
 1 Herod, iv. 157. There seems some analogy between this story and the Norse 
 legend of second-sight, which narrates how " Mgimund shut up three Finns 
 in a hut for three nights that they might visit Iceland and inform him of the 
 lie of the country where he was to settle. Their bodies became rigid, they 
 sent their souls on the errand, and awakening after three days, they gave a 
 description of the Vatnsdael." Prim. Cult. i. 396. 
 
 2 Herod, i. 47. 
 
 2 Cyriac of Ancona, in the sixteenth century, found a slab of marble with 
 the couplet olda. T' iyJi, etc., inscribed on it. See Foucart, p. 139.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 457 
 
 And in that culminating struggle with the barbarians, when 
 the young nation rose, as it were, to knightly manhood through 
 one great ordeal, how moving I had almost said how human 
 was the attitude of the god ! We may wish, indeed, that he 
 had taken a firmer tone, that he had not trembled before the 
 oncoming host, nor needed men's utmost supplications before 
 he would give a word of hope. But this is a later view ; it is 
 the view of Oenomaus and Eusebius, rather than of Aeschylus 
 or Herodotus. 1 To the contemporary Greeks it seemed no 
 shame nor wonder that the national protector, benignant but 
 not omnipotent, should tremble with the fortunes of the 
 nation, that all his strength should scarcely suffice for a conflict 
 in which every fibre of the forces of Hellas was strained, " as 
 though men fought upon the earth and gods in upper air." 
 
 And seldom indeed has history shown a scene so strangely 
 dramatic, never has poetry entered so deeply into human fates, 
 as in that council at Athens 2 when the question of absolute 
 surrender or desperate resistance turned on the interpretation 
 which was to be given to the dark utterance of the god. It was 
 an epithet which saved civilisation ; it was the one word which 
 blessed the famous islet instead of cursing it altogether, which 
 gave courage for that most fateful battle which the world has 
 known 
 
 "Thou, holy Salamis, sons of men shalt slay, 
 Or on earth's scattering or ingathering day." 
 
 After the great crisis of the Persian war Apollo is at rest. 3 
 In the tragedians he has risen high above the attitude of a 
 struggling tribal god. Worshippers surround him, as in the 
 Ion, in the spirit of glad self -dedication and holy service ; his 
 priestess speaks as in the opening of the Eumenides, where 
 the settled majesty of godhead breathes through the awful 
 calm. And now, more magnificent though more transitory than 
 the poet's song, a famous symbolical picture embodies for the 
 
 1 Herod, vii. 139 seems hardly meant to blame the god, though it praises 
 the Athenians for hoping against hope. 
 
 8 Herod, vii. 143. 
 
 8 It is noticeable that the god three times defended his own shrine, 
 against Xerxes (Herod, viii. 36), Jason of Pherae (Xen. Hell. vi. 4), Brennus 
 (Paus. x. 23).
 
 458 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 remaining generations of Greeks the culminant conception of 
 the religion of Apollo's shrine. 
 
 " ISTot all the treasures," as Homer has it, " which the stone 
 threshold of the Far-darter holds safe within" would now be so 
 precious to us as the power of looking for one hour on the 
 greatest work of the greatest painter of antiquity, the picture 
 by Polygnotus in the Hall of the Cnidians at Delphi, of the 
 descent of Odysseus among the dead. 1 For as it was with the 
 oracle of Teiresias that the roll of responses began, so it is the 
 picture of that same scene which shows us, even through the 
 meagre description of Pausanias, how great a space had been 
 traversed between the horizon and the zenith of the Hellenic 
 faith. " The ethical painter," as Aristotle calls him, 2 the 
 man on whose works it ennobled a city to gaze, the painter 
 whose figures were superior to nature as the characters of 
 Homer were greater than the greatness of men, had spent on this 
 altar-piece, if I may so term it, of. the Hellenic race his truest 
 devotion and his utmost skill. The world to which he intro- 
 duces us is Homer's shadow-world, but it reminds us also of a 
 very different scene. It recalls the visions of that Sacred Field 
 on whose walls an unknown painter has set down with so start- 
 ling a reality the faith of medieval Christendom as to death 
 and the hereafter. 
 
 In place of Death with her vampire aspect and wiry wings, 
 we have the fiend Eurynomus, " painted of the blue-black 
 colour of flesh-flies," and battening on the corpses of the slain. 
 In place of the kings and ladies, who tell us in the rude Pisan 
 epigraph how 
 
 Ischermo di savere e di richezza 
 Di nobiltate ancora e di prodezza 
 Vale niente ai colpi de costei, 
 
 it is Theseus and Sisyphus and Eriphyle who teach us that 
 
 1 For this picture see Paus. x. 28-31 ; also Welcker (Klelne Schriften), 
 and W. W. Lloyd in the Classical Museum, who both give Riepenhausen's 
 restoration. While differing from much in Welcker's view of the picture, I have 
 followed him in supposing that a vase figured in his AUe Denkmaler, vol. iii. 
 plate 29, represents at any rate the figure and expression of Polygnotus's 
 Odysseus. The rest of my description can, I think, be justified from Pausanias. 
 
 2 Ar. Pol. viii. 8 ; Poet. ii. 2.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 459 
 
 might and wealth and wisdom "against those blows are of no 
 avail." And Tityus. whose scarce imaginable outrage in the 
 
 i/ ' O O 
 
 Pythian valley upon the mother of Apollo herself carries back 
 his crime and his penalty into an immeasurable past, Tityus 
 lay huge and prone upon the pictured field, but the image of 
 him (and whether this were by chance or art Pausanias could 
 not sav) seemed melting into cloud and nothingness through 
 
 v f o O o 
 
 the infinity of his woe. But there also were heroes and heroines 
 of a loftier fate, Memnon and Sarpedon, Tyro and Penthesilea, 
 in attitudes that told of " calm pleasures and majestic pains ; " 
 Achilles, with Patroclus at his right hand, and near 
 Achilles Protesilaus, fit mate in valour and in constancy 
 for that type of generous friendship and passionate woe. 
 And there was Odysseus, still a breathing man, but with 
 no trace of terror in his earnest and solemn gaze, demand- 
 ing from Teiresias, as Dante from Virgil, all that that strange 
 world could show; while near him a woman's figure stood, 
 his mother Anticleia, waiting to call to him in those 
 words which in Homer's song seem to strike at once to the 
 very innermost of all love and all regret. And where the 
 medieval painter had set hermits praying as the type of souls 
 made safe through their piety and their knowledge of the divine, 
 the Greek had told the same parable after another fashion. For 
 in Polygnotus' picture it was Tellis and Cleoboia, a young man 
 and a maid, who were crossing Acheron together with hearts at 
 peace ; and amid all those legendary heroes these figures alone 
 were real and true, and of a youth and a maiden who not long 
 since had passed away, and they were at peace because they 
 had themselves been initiated, and Cleoboia had taught the 
 mysteries of Demeter to her people and her father's house. 
 And was there, we may ask, in that great company, any heathen 
 form which we may liken, however distantly, to the Figure 
 who, throned among the clouds on the glowing Pisan wall 
 marshals the blessed to their home in light ? Almost in the 
 centre, as it would seem, of Polygnotus' picture was introduced 
 a mysterious personality who found no place in Homer's poem, 
 a name round which had grown a web of hopes and emotions 
 which no hand can disentangle now, "The minstrel sire of 
 song, Orpheus the well-beloved, was there."
 
 460 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 It may be that the myth of Orpheus was at first nothing more 
 than another version of the world-old story of the Sun ; that his 
 descent and resurrection were but the symbols of the night and 
 the day ; that Eurydice was but an emblem of the lovely rose- 
 clouds which sink back from his touch into the darkness of 
 evening only to enfold him brightlier in the dawn. But be this 
 as it may, the name of Orpheus 1 had become the centre of the 
 most aspiring and the deepest thoughts of Greece ; the lyre 
 which he held, the willow-tree on which in the picture his 
 hand was laid, were symbols of mystic meaning, and he himself 
 was the type of the man "who has descended and ascended "- 
 who walks the earth with a heart that turns continually towards 
 his treasure in a world unseen. 
 
 When this great picture was painted, the sanctuary and the 
 religion of Delphi might well seem indestructible and eternal. 
 But the name of Orpheus, introduced here perhaps for the 
 first time into the centre of the Apolline faith, brings with it 
 a hint of that spirit of mysticism which has acted as a solvent, 
 sometimes more powerful even than criticism, as the sun in 
 the fable of Aesop was more powerful than the wind, upon the 
 dogmas of every religion in turn. And it suggests a forward 
 glance to an oracle given at Delphi on a later day, 2 and cited by 
 Porphyry to illustrate the necessary evanescence and imperfec- 
 tion of whatsoever image of spiritual things can be made visible 
 on earth. A time shall come when even Delphi's mission shall 
 have been fulfilled ; and the god himself has predicted without 
 despair the destruction of his holiest shrine 
 
 " Ay, if ye bear it, if ye endure to know 
 
 That Delphi's self with all things gone must go, 
 Hear with strong heart the unfaltering song divine 
 Peal from the laurelled porch and shadowy shrine. 
 High in Jove's home the battling winds are torn, 
 From battling winds the bolts of Jove are born ; 
 These as he will on trees and towers he flings, 
 And quells the heart of lions or of kings ; 
 
 1 See, for instance, Maury, Religions de la Gr&ce, chap, xviii. Aelius Lam- 
 pridius (Alex. Sev. Vita, 29) says "In Larario et Apollonium et Christum, 
 Abraham et Orpheum, et hujusmodi deos habebat." 
 
 2 Eus. Pr. Ev. vi. 3.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 46 r 
 
 A thousand crags those flying flames confound, 
 A thousand navies in the deep are drowned, 
 And ocean's roaring billows, cloven apart, 
 Bear the bright death to Amphitrite's heart. 
 And thus, even thus, on some long-destined day, 
 Shall Delphi's beauty shrivel and burn away, 
 Shall Delphi's fame and fane from earth expire 
 At that bright bidding of celestial fire." 
 
 The ruin lias been accomplished. All is gone, save such cyclopean 
 walls as date from days before Apollo, such ineffaceable memo- 
 ries as Nature herself has kept of the vanished shrine. 1 Only 
 the Corycian cave still shows, with its gleaming stalagmites, as 
 though the nymphs to whom it was hallowed were sleeping 
 there yet in stone ; the Phaedriades or Shining Crags still flash 
 the sunlight from their streams that scatter into air; and 
 dwellers at Castri still swear that they have heard the rushing 
 Thyiades keep their rout upon Parnassus' brow. 
 
 III. 
 
 Even while Polygnotus was painting the Lesche of the 
 Cnidians at Delphi a man was talking in the Athenian market- 
 place, from whose powerful individuality, the most impressive 
 which Greece had ever known, were destined to flow streams 
 of influence which should transform every department of belief 
 and thought. In tracing the history of oracles we shall feel 
 the influence of Socrates mainly in two directions; in his 
 assertion of a personal and spiritual relation between man and the 
 unseen world, an oracle not without us but within ; and in his 
 origination of the idea of science, of a habit of mind which should 
 refuse to accept any explanation of phenomena which failed to 
 confer the power of predicting those phenomena or producing 
 them anew. We shall find that, instead of the old acceptance of 
 the responses as heaven-sent mysteries, and the old demands for 
 prophetic knowledge or for guidance in the affairs of life, men are 
 
 1 See Mr. Aubrey de Vere's Picturesque Sketches in Greece, and Turkey for a 
 striking description of Delphian scenery. Other details will be found in 
 Foucart, pp. 113, 114; and cf. Paus. x. 33.
 
 462 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 more and more concerned with the questions : How can oracles be 
 practically produced ? and what relation between God and man 
 do they imply ? But first of all, the oracle which concerned 
 Socrates himself, which declared him to be the wisest of man- 
 kind, is certainly one of the most noticeable ever uttered at 
 Delphi. The fact that the man on whom the god had bestowed 
 this extreme laudation, a laudation paralleled only by the 
 mythical w^ords addressed to Lycurgus, should a few years 
 afterwards have been put to death for impiety, is surely one of 
 a deeper significance than has been often observed. It forms 
 an overt and impressive instance of that divergence between 
 the law and the prophets, between the letter and the spirit, 
 which is sure to occur in the history of all religions, and on the 
 manner of whose settlement the destiny of each religion in turn 
 depends. In this case the conditions of the conflict are striking 
 and unusual. 1 Socrates is accused of failing to honour the 
 gods of the State, and of introducing new gods under the name 
 of demons, or spirits, as we must translate the word, since the 
 title of demon has acquired in the mouths of the Fathers a bad 
 signification. He replies that he does honour the gods of the 
 State, as he understands them, and that the spirit who speaks 
 with him is an agency which he cannot disavow. 
 
 The first count of the indictment brings into prominence an 
 obvious defect in the Greek religion, the absence of any 
 inspired text to which the orthodox could refer. Homer and 
 Hesiod, men like ourselves, were the acknowledged authors 
 of the theology of Greece; and when Homer and Hesiod 
 were respectfully received, but interpreted with rationalising 
 freedom, it was hard to know by what canons to judge the 
 interpreter. The second count opens questions which go 
 deeper still. It was indeed true, though how far Anytus and 
 Meletus perceived it we cannot now know, that the demon of 
 Socrates indicated a recurrence to a wholly different conception 
 of the unseen world, a conception before which Zeus and 
 Apollo, heaven-god and sun-god, were one day to disappear. 
 But who, except Apollo himself, was to pronounce on such 
 
 1 On the trial of Socrates and kindred points see, besides Plato (Apol., 
 Phaed., Euthyphr.) and Xenophon (Mem., ApoL), Diog. Laert. ii. 40, Diod. 
 Sic. xiv. 37, Plut. de genio Socratis.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 463 
 
 a question ? It was lie who was for the Hellenic race the 
 source of continuous revelation; his utterances were a sanc- 
 tion or a condemnation from which there was no appeal. And 
 in this debate his verdict for the defendant had been already 
 given. We have heard of Christian theologians who are " more 
 orthodox than the Evangelists." In this case the Athenian 
 jurymen showed themselves more jealous for the gods' honour 
 than were the gods themselves. 
 
 To us, indeed, Socrates stands as the example of the truest 
 religious conservatism, of the temper of mind which is able 
 to cast its own original convictions in an ancestral mould, 
 and to find the last outcome of speculation in the humility of a 
 trustful faith. No man, as is well known, ever professed a more 
 childlike confidence in the Delphian god than he, and many a 
 reader through many a century has been moved to a smile 
 which was not far from tears at his account of his own mixture 
 of conscientious belief and blank bewilderment when the infal- 
 lible deity pronounced that Socrates was the wisest of mankind. 
 
 A spirit balanced like that of Socrates could hardly recur, 
 and the impulse given to philosophical inquiry was certain to 
 lead to many questionings as to the true authority of the 
 Delphic precepts. But before we enter upon such contro- 
 versies, let us trace through some further phases the influence 
 of the oracles on public and private life. 
 
 For it does not appear that Delphi ceased to give utter- 
 ances on the public affairs of Greece so long as Greece had 
 public affairs worthy the notice of a god. Oracles occur, 
 with a less natural look than when we met them in Herodotus, 
 inserted as a kind of unearthly evidence in the speeches 
 of Aeschines and Demosthenes. 1 Hyperides confidently re- 
 commends his audience to check the account which a mes- 
 senger had brought of an oracle of Amphiaraus by despatching 
 another messenger with the same question to Delphi. 2 Oracles, 
 as we are informed, foretold the battle of Leuctra, 3 the battle 
 of Chaeronea, 4 the destruction of Thebes by Alexander. 5 Alex- 
 ander himself consulted Zeus Ammon not only on his own 
 
 1 e.g. Dem. Meid. 53 : r$ 5-/j/xy rGav ' &.Qt]voJitAv 6 TOV Aids arj/j.aLi'ei, etc. 
 - Hyper. Euxen. p. 8. 3 Paus. ix. 14. 
 
 4 Plut. Dem. 19. 5 Diod. xvii. 10.
 
 464 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 parentage but as to the sources of the Nile, and an ingenuous 
 author regrets that, instead of seeking information on this 
 purely geographical problem, which divided with Homer's 
 birthplace the curiosity of antiquity, Alexander did not 
 employ his prestige and his opportunities to get the question 
 of the origin of evil set at rest for ever. 1 We hear of oracles 
 given to Epaminondas, 2 to the orator Callistratus, 3 and to 
 Philip of Maceclon. 4 To Cicero the god gave advice which 
 that sensitive statesman would have done well to follow, to 
 take his own character and not the opinion of the multitude 
 as his guide in life. 5 
 
 Nero, too, consulted the Delphian oracle, which pleased 
 him by telling him to "beware of seventy-three," 6 for he 
 supposed that he was to reign till he reached that year. The 
 god, however, alluded to the age of his successor Galba. After- 
 wards Nero, grown to an overweening presumption which 
 could brook no rival worship, and become, as we may say, 
 Antapollo as well as Antichrist, murdered certain men and 
 cast them into the cleft of Delphi, thus extinguishing for a 
 time the oracular power. 7 Plutarch, who was a contemporary 
 of Nero's, describes in several essays this lowest point of 
 oracular fortunes. Not Delphi alone, but the great majority 
 of Greek oracles, were at that time hushed, a silence which 
 Plutarch ascribes partly to the tranquillity and depopulation 
 of Greece, partly to a casual deficiency of Demons, the im- 
 manent spirits who gave inspiration to the shrines, but who 
 are themselves liable to change of circumstances, or even to 
 death. 8 
 
 Whatever may have been the cause of this oracular eclipse, 
 it was of no long duration. The oracle of Delphi seems to 
 have been restored in the reign of Trajan, and in Hadrian's 
 
 1 Max. Tyr. Diss. 25. 2 Paus. viii. 11. 8 Lycurg. Leocr. 160. 
 
 s Diod. xvi. 91. 5 Plut. Cic. 5. Suet. Nero, 38. 
 
 7 Dio Cass. Ixiii. 14. Suetonius and Dio Cassius do not know why Nero 
 destroyed Delphi ; but some such view as that given in the text seems the 
 only conceivable one. 
 
 8 Plut. de Defect, orac. 11. We may compare the way in which Heliogabalus 
 put an end to the oracle of the celestial goddess of the Carthaginians, by 
 insisting on marrying her statue, on the ground that she was the Moon and 
 he was the Sun. Herodian, v. 6.
 
 GREEK ORACLES, 465 
 
 days a characteristic story shows that it had again become a 
 centre of distant inquirers. The main preoccupation of that 
 imperial scholar was the determination of Homer's birthplace, 
 and he put the question in person to the Pythian priestess. 
 The question had naturally been asked before, and an old 
 reply, purporting to have been given to Homer himself, had 
 already been engraved on Homer's statue in the sacred pre- 
 cinct. But on the inquiry of the sumptuous emperor the 
 priestess changed her tone, described Homer as " an immortal 
 siren/' and very handsomely made him out to be the grandson 
 both of Nestor and of Odysseus. 1 It was Hadrian, too, who 
 dropped a laurel-leaf at Antioch into Daphne's stream, and 
 when he drew it out there was writ thereon a promise of his 
 imperial power. He choked up the fountain, that no man 
 might draw from its prophecy such a hope again. 2 But 
 Hadrian's strangest achievement was to found an oracle him- 
 self. The worshippers of Antinous at Antinoe were taught to 
 expect answers from the deified boy : " They imagine," says the 
 scornful Origen, " that there breathes from Antinous a breath 
 divine." 3 
 
 For some time after Hadrian we hear little of Delphi. 
 But, on the other hand, stories of oracles of varied character 
 come to us from all parts of the Roman world. The bull Apis, 
 " trampling the unshowered grass with lowings loud," refused 
 food from the hand of Germanicus, and thus predicted his 
 approaching death. 4 Germanicus, too, drew the same dark 
 presage from the oracle at Colophon of the Clarian Apollo. 5 
 And few oracular answers have been more impressively re- 
 counted than that which was given to Vespasian by the god 
 Carmel, upon Carmel, while the Eoman's dreams of empire 
 were still hidden in his heart. " Whatsoever it be, Vespasian, 
 that thou preparest now, whether to build a house or to 
 enlarge thy fields, or to get thee servants for thy need, there is 
 
 1 Anth. Pal. xiv. 102 : (Lyvwcrrov //.' fp^ets yeveijs xal Trarpidos afys 
 
 anfipoffiov Setp^voj, etc. 
 
 2 Sozomen, Hist. Ecd. v. 19. 
 
 3 Orig. ad. Cels. ap. Wolff, de Novlss. p. 43, where see other citations. 
 
 4 Plin. viii. 46. 
 
 6 Tac. Ann. ii. 54. 
 
 2G
 
 466 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 given unto tliee a mighty home, and far-reaching borders, and a 
 multitude of men." l 
 
 The same strange mingling of classic and Hebrew memories, 
 which the name of Carmel in this connection suggests, meets 
 us when we find the god Bel at Apamea, that same Baal " by 
 whom the prophets prophesied and walked after things that 
 do not profit " in Jeremiah's day, answering a Eoman emperor 
 in words drawn from Homer's song. For it was thus that the 
 struggling Macrinus received the signal of his last and irre- 
 trievable defeat : 2 
 
 " Ah, king outworn ! young warriors press thee sore, 
 And age is on thee, and thou thyself no more. " 
 
 In the private oracles, too, of these post-classical times there is 
 sometimes a touch of romance which reminds us how much 
 human emotion there has been in generations which we pass 
 rapidly by ; how earnest and great a thing many a man's mission 
 has seemed to him, which to us is merged in the dulness 
 and littleness of a declining age. There is something of this 
 pathos in the Pythia's message to the wandering preacher, 3 
 " Do as thou now doest, until thou reach the end of the world," 
 and in the dream which came to the weary statesman in Apollo 
 Grannus' shrine, 4 and bade him write at the end of his life's 
 long labour Homer's words 
 
 " But Hector Zeus took forth and bare him far 
 From dust, and dying, and the storm of war. " 
 
 And in the records of these last centuries of paganism we 
 notice that the established oracles, the orthodox forms of inquiry, 
 are no longer enough to satisfy the eagerness of men. In that 
 upheaval of the human spirit which bore to the surface so much 
 of falsehood and so much of truth, the religion of Mithra, 
 
 1 Tac. Hist. ii. 78. Suetonius, Vesp. 5, speaks of Carmel's oracle, though it 
 seems that the answer was given after a simple extispicium. 
 
 2 Dio Cass. Ixxviii. 40 ; Horn. II. viii. 103. Capitolinus, in his life of 
 Macrinus (c. 3), shows incidentally that under the Antonines it was customary 
 for the Roman proconsul of Africa to consult the oracle of the Dea Caelestis 
 Carthaginiensium. 
 
 3 Dio Chrysostom, vepl (j>vyTJs, p. 255. 
 
 4 Dio Cassius, ad fin.; Horn. II. xi. 163.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 467 
 
 the religion of Serapis, the religion of Christ, questions are 
 asked from whatever source, glimpses are sought through 
 whatsoever in nature has been deemed transparent to the 
 influences of an encompassing Power. It was in this age 1 
 that at Hierapolis the "clear round stone of the onyx kind," 
 which Damascius describes, showed in its mirroring depths 
 letters which changed and came, or sometimes emitted that 
 "thin and thrilling sound," 2 which was interpreted into the 
 message of a slowly-uttering Power. It was in this age that 
 Chosroes drew his divinations from the nickering of an eternal 
 tire. 3 It was in this age that the luminous meteor would fall 
 from the temple of Urauian Venus upon Lebanon into her 
 sacred lake beneath, and declare her presence and promise her 
 consenting grace. 4 It was in this age that sealed letters con- 
 taining numbered questions were sent to the temple of the sun 
 at Hierapolis, and answers were returned in order, while the 
 seals remained still intact. 5 It was in this age that the famous 
 oracle which predicted the death of Valens was obtained by 
 certain men who sat round a table and noted letters of the 
 alphabet which were spelt out for them by some automatic 
 agency after a fashion which from the description of Ammianus 
 we cannot precisely determine. 6 This oracle, construed into a 
 menace against a Christian Emperor, gave rise to a persecution 
 of paganism of so severe a character that, inasmuch as philoso- 
 phers were believed especially to affect the forbidden practice, 
 the very repute or aspect of a philosopher, as Sozomen tells us, 7 
 
 1 The following examples of later oracles are not precisely synchronous. 
 They illustrate the character of a long period, and the date at which we 
 happen to hear of each has depended largely on accident. 
 
 2 Damasc. ap. Phot. 348, (f>uvriv XeTrroO ffvpiff/j-aTos. See also Paus. vii. 21. 
 
 3 Procop. Bell. Pers. ii. 24. The practice of divining from sacrificial flame 
 or smoke was of course an old one, though rarely connected with any regular 
 seat of oracle. Cf. Herod, viii. 134. The irvpe'iov in the x u pl v ' Adiappiydvuv 
 which Chosroes consulted was a fire worshipped in itself, and sought for 
 oracular purposes. 
 
 4 Zcsimus, Ann. i. 57. 
 
 5 Macrob. Sat. i. 23. Fontenelle's criticism (ffistoire des Oracles) on the 
 answer given to Trajan is worth reading along with the passage of Macrobius 
 as an example of Voltairian mockery, equally convincing and unjust. Cf. 
 Amm. Marcell. xiv. 7 for a variety of this form of response. 
 
 6 Amm. Marcell. xxix. 2, and xxxi. 1. 
 
 7 Sozomen. vi. 35.
 
 468 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 was enough to bring a man under the notice of the police. This 
 theological rancour will the less surprise us, if we believe with 
 some modern criticism that St. Paul himself, under the 
 pseudonym of Simon Magus, had not escaped the charge, at 
 the hands of a polemical Father, of causing the furniture of his 
 house to move without contact, in obedience to his unholy 
 will. 1 
 
 Finally, to conclude this strange list with an example which 
 may by many minds be considered as typical of the rest, it 
 was in this age that, at the Nymphaeum at Apollonia in Epirus, 
 an Ignis Fatuus 2 gave by its waving approach and recession 
 the responses which a credulous people sought, except that 
 this Will-o'-the-Wisp, with unexpected diffidence, refused to 
 answer questions which had to do with marriage or with death. 
 
 Further examples are not needed to prove what the express 
 statement of Tertullian and others testifies, 3 that the world was 
 still " crowded with oracles " in the first centuries of our era. 
 We must now retrace our steps and inquire with what eyes the 
 post-Socratic philosophers regarded a phenomenon so opposed 
 to ordinary notions of enlightenment or progress. 
 
 Plato's theory of inspiration is too vast and far-reaching for 
 discussion here. It must be enough to say that, although oracles 
 seemed to him to constitute but a small part of the revelation 
 offered by God to man, he yet maintained to the full their 
 utility, and appeared to assume their truth. In his ideal polity 
 the oracles of the Delphian god were to possess as high an 
 authority, and to be as frequently consulted, as in conservative 
 Lacedaemon, and the express decision of heaven was to be 
 
 1 Pseudo-Clemens, Homil. ii. 32. 638, TO. ev oldg. CKe^-rj u>s avrofj-ara <f>fpo- 
 pfva. 7r/>6s virijpfffLav [3\tireff6ai vote?. Cf. Renan, Les Ap6tres, p. 153, note, 
 etc. 
 
 2 There can, I think, be little doubt that such was the true character of the 
 flame which Dio Cassius (xli. 45) describes : irpbs d rds eirixvcreis r&v 6fj.j3pui> 
 ^7ren/ Kal ts Vifsos i^alperai, etc. Maury's explanation (ii. 446) is slightly 
 different. The fluctuations of the flame on Etna (Paus. iii. 23) were an 
 instance of a common volcanic phenomenon. 
 
 8 Tertullian, de Anima, 46 : Nam et oraculis hoc genus stipatus est orbis, etc. 
 Cf . Plin. Hist. Nat. viii. 29 : Nee non et hodie multifariam ab oraculis medicina 
 petitur. Pliny's oracular remedy for hydrophobia (viii. 42) is not now phar- 
 macopoaal.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 469 
 
 invoked in matters of practical 1 as well as of ceremonial 2 
 import. 
 
 Aristotle, who possessed, and no man had a better right to 
 it, a religion all his own, and to which he never converted 
 anybody, delivered himself on the subject of oracular dreams 
 with all his sagacious ambiguity. " It is neither easy," he said, 
 "to despise such things, nor yet to believe them." 3 
 
 The schools of philosophy which were dominant in Greece 
 after the death of Aristotle occupied themselves only in a 
 secondary way with the question of oracles. The Stoics and 
 Academics were disposed to uphold their validity on conserva- 
 tive principles, utilising them as the most moral part of the 
 old creed, the point from which its junction with philosophy 
 was most easily made. Cicero's treatise on divination contains 
 a summary of the conservative view, and it is to be remarked 
 that Cratippus and other Peripatetics disavowed the grosser 
 forms of divination, and believed only in dreams and in the 
 utterances of inspired frenzy. 4 
 
 Epicureans and Cynics, on the other hand, felt no such need 
 of maintaining connection with the ancient orthodoxy, and 
 allowed free play to their wit in dealing with the oracular 
 tradition, or even considered it as a duty to disembarrass man- 
 kind of this among other superstitions. The sceptic Lucian is 
 perhaps of too purely mocking a temper to allow us to ascribe 
 to him much earnestness of purpose in the amusing burlesques 5 
 in which he depicts the difficulty which Apollo feels in com- 
 posing his official hexameters, or his annoyance at being obliged 
 to hurry to his post of inspiration whenever the priestess 
 chooses "to chew the bay-leaf and drink of the sacred spring." 6 
 
 1 Leges, vi. 914. 2 Leges, v. 428 ; Epinomis, 362. 
 
 8 Ar. Div. per Som. i 1 . He goes on to suggest that dreams, though not 
 BeoirefiiTTa, may be 5at/j.uvia. 
 
 4 See Cic. de Div. i. 3. 
 
 5 Jupiter Tragoedus; Bis Accusalus, etc. I need not remind the reader that 
 such scoffing treatment of oracles does not now appear for the first time. The 
 parodies in Aristophanes hit off the pompous oracular obscurity as happily as 
 Lucian's. A recent German writer, on the other hand (Hoffmann, Orakelwesen), 
 maintains, by precept and example, that no style can be more appropriate to 
 serious topics. 
 
 6 Bis Accusatus, 2. I may remark that although narcotics are often used 
 to produce abnormal utterance (Lane's Egyptians, ii. 33 ; Maury, ii. 479),
 
 470 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 The indignation of Oenomaus, a cynic of Hadrian's age, 
 is of a more genuine character, and there is much sarcastic 
 humour in his account of his own visit to the oracle of Apollo 
 at Colophon ; how the first response which he obtained might 
 have been taken at random from a book of elegant extracts, 
 and had also, to his great disgust, been delivered in the self- 
 same words to a commercial traveller immediately before him ; 
 how, to his second question, " Who will teach me wisdom ? " 
 the god returned an answer of almost meaningless imbecility ; 
 and how, when he finally asked, " Where shall I go now ? " the 
 god told him, "to draw a long bow and knock over untold 
 green-feeding ganders." l " And who in the world," exclaims 
 the indignant philosopher, "will tell me what these untold 
 ganders may mean ? " 
 
 Anecdotes like this may seem to warn us that our subject 
 is drawing to a close. And to students of these declining schools 
 of Greek philosophy, it may well appear that the Greek spirit 
 had burnt itself out ; that all creeds and all speculations were 
 being enfeebled into an eclecticism or a scepticism, both of them 
 equally shallow and unreal. But this was not to be. It was 
 destined that every seed which the great age of Greece had 
 planted should germinate and grow ; and a school was now to 
 arise which should take hold, as it were, of the universe by a 
 forgotten clew, and should give fuller meaning and wider 
 acceptance to some of the most remarkable, though hitherto 
 least noticed, utterances of earlier men. We must go back as 
 far as Hesiod to understand the Neoplatonists. 
 
 For it is in Hesiod's celebrated story of the Ages of the 
 World 2 that we find the first Greek conception, obscure 
 though its details be, of a hierarchy of spiritual beings who fill 
 
 this mastication of a laurel-leaf or bay-leaf cannot be considered as more than 
 a symbolical survival of such a practice. The drinking of water (Iambi. Myst. 
 Aeg. 72 ; Anacreon xiii.), or even of blood (Paus. ii. 24), would be equally in- 
 operative for this purpose ; and though Pliny says that the water in Apollo's 
 cave at Colophon shortened the drinker's life (Hist. Nat. ii. 106), it is difficult 
 to imagine what natural salt could produce hallucination. 
 
 1 Eus. Pr. Ev. v. 23 
 
 eK T(U'\jcrTpo(f>oio \aas fffavdovrjs ids avjjp 
 X^cas evapl^eiv /SoAcucrw, affirerovs, Trony/Jopovs. 
 
 3 Hes. Opp. 109 sqq.
 
 GREEK OR A CLES. 471 
 
 the unseen world, and can discern and influence our own. The 
 souls of heroes, he says, become happy spirits who dwell aloof 
 from our sorrow ; the souls of men of the golden age become 
 
 f O O 
 
 good and guardian spirits, who flit over the earth and watch 
 the just and unjust deeds of men; and the souls of men of 
 the silver age become an inferior class of spirits, themselves 
 mortal, yet deserving honour from mankind. 1 The same strain 
 of thought appears in Thales, who defines demons as spiritual 
 existences, heroes, as the souls of men separated from the body. 2 
 Pythagoras held much the same view, and, as we shall see 
 below, believed that in a certain sense these spirits were 
 occasionally to be seen or felt. 3 Heraclitus held "that all 
 things were full of souls and spirits," 4 and Empedocles has 
 described in lines of startling power 5 the wanderings through 
 the universe of a lost and homeless soul. Lastly, Plato, in the 
 Epinomis 6 brings these theories into direct connection with 
 our subject by asserting that some of these spirits can read the 
 minds of living men, and are still liable to be grieved by our 
 wrong-doing, 7 while many of them appear to us in sleep by 
 visions, and are made known by voices and oracles, in our health 
 or sickness, and are about us at our dying hour. Some are even 
 visible occasionally in waking reality, and then again disappear, 
 and cause perplexity by their obscure self-manifestation. 8 
 
 Opinions like these, existing in a corner of the vast 
 
 1 It is uncertain where Hesiod places the abode of this class of spirits ; the 
 MSS. read ewi-xBovioi, Gaisford (with Tzetzes) and Wolff, de Daemonibus, 
 
 VTTOX&OVIOI. 
 
 * Athenag. legal, pro Christo, 21 ; cf. Plut. de Plac. Phil. i. 8. 
 
 s Porph. vit. Pyth. 384 ; reff. ap. Wolff. For obsession, see Pseudo- 
 Zaleucus, ap. Stob. Flor. xliv. 20. 
 
 * Diog. Laert. ix. 6. 5 Plut. de Iside, 26. 
 
 6 I believe, with Grote, etc., that the Epinomis is Plato's ; at any rate it was 
 generally accepted as such in antiquity, which is enough for the present purpose. 
 
 7 Epinomis, 361. fj.ere-x.ovra. ^ <ppovfi<rews 6avfj.a<rrijs, are ytvovs 6vra 
 evfutOovs re Koi fjU>rnM>i>os, yiyvdiffKeiv ^ev %vfj.iraffav r-r\v Tj/J-ertpav avrd diavoiav 
 \tyw/j.ev, Kal rov re Ka\t>v TJ/JLUV Kal dyaObv a^a 6av/J.affrus dffirafraOai Kal rbv 
 ff<f>65pa Kanbv fuffflv, are XiyTnjs pere-xovra ijd-ij, K.r.\. 
 
 8 Kal TOVT' elvai r6re fj.ev 6pufj.evov &\\ore Se airoKpv<j>6ev &Sij\ov yiyvop.evov, 
 Oavfw. tear' d/j.vSpav 6\f/iv irapexo/jifvov. The precise meaning of dfivdpa fl^w is 
 not clear without further knowledge of the phenomena which Plato had in 
 his mind. Comp. the d\a/j,irfj Kal d/j.vSpdv fuyv, wffirep a.va6\>iu.a<Tiv, which is all 
 that reincarnated demons can look for (Plut. de Defect. 10).
 
 472 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 structure of Platonic thought, passed, as it seems, for centuries 
 with little notice. Almost as unnoticed was the gradual 
 development of the creed known as Orphic, which seems to 
 have begun with making itself master of the ancient myste- 
 ries, and only slowly spread through the profane world its 
 doctrine that this life is a purgation, that this body is a 
 sepulchre, 1 and that the Divinity, who surrounds us like an 
 ocean, is the hope and home of the soul. But a time came 
 when, under the impulse of a great religious movement, these 
 currents of belief, which had so long run underground, broke 
 into sight again in an unlooked-for direction. These tenets, 
 and many more, were dwelt upon and expanded with new 
 conviction by that remarkable series of men who furnish to 
 the history of Greek thought so singular a concluding chapter. 
 And no part, perhaps, of the Neoplatonic system shows more 
 clearly than their treatment of oracles how profound a change 
 the Greek religion has undergone beneath all its apparent con- 
 tinuity. It so happens that the Neoplatonic philosopher who 
 has written most on our present subject, was also a man whose 
 spiritual history affords a striking, perhaps an unique, epitome 
 of the several stages through which the faith of Greece had up 
 to that time passed. A Syrian of noble descent, 2 powerful 
 intelligence, and upright character, Porphyry brought to the 
 study of the Greek religion little that was distinctively 
 Semitic, unless we so term the ardour of his religious impulses, 
 and his profound conviction that the one thing needful for 
 man lay in the truest knowledge attainable as to his relation 
 to the divine. Educated by Longinus, the last representative 
 of expiring classicism, the Syrian youth absorbed all, and pro- 
 bably more than all, his master's faith. Homer became to 
 him what the Bible was to Luther ; and he spent some years 
 in producing the most perfect edition of the Iliad and 
 
 1 See, for instance, Plato, Crat. 264. doKovcn fdvToi /ML naXiara. 6<r6ai ol 
 d.fi.<pl ' Qp<pta TOUTO rb 6vofia (<rw/j.a quasi ffijfj.a) us 5'iK-qv Sidoucrys TTJS ^VXTJS &v drj 
 
 2 G. Wolff, Porph. de Phil, etc., has collected a mass of authorities on 
 Porphyry's life, and has ably discussed the sequence of his writings. But 
 beyond this tract I have found hardly anything written on this part of my 
 subject, on which I have dwelt the more fully, inasmuch as it seems 
 hitherto to have attracted so little attention from scholars.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 473 
 
 Odyssey which had yet appeared, in order that no fragment 
 of the inspired text might fail to render its full meaning. 
 But, as it seems, in the performance of this task, his 
 faith received the same shock which had been fatal to 
 the early piety of Greece. The behaviour of the gods in 
 Homer was too bad to be condoned. He discerned, what is 
 probably the truth, that there must be some explanation of these 
 enormities which is not visible on the surface, and that nothing 
 short of some profound mistake could claim acceptance for 
 such legends as those of Zeus and Kronos, of Kronos and 
 Uranus, amid so much else that is majestic and pure. 1 Many 
 philologists would answer now that the mistake, the disease 
 of language, lay in the expression in terms of human appetite 
 and passion of the impersonal sequences of the great phenomena 
 of Nature ; that the most monstrous tales of mythology mean 
 nothing worse or more surprising than that day follows night, 
 and night again succeeds to day. To Porphyry such explana- 
 tions were of course impossible. In default of Sanskrit he 
 betook himself to allegory. The truth which must be some- 
 where in Homer, but which plainly was not in the natural 
 sense of the words, must therefore be discoverable in a non- 
 natural sense. The cave of the nymphs, for instance, which 
 Homer describes as in Ithaca, is not in Ithaca. Homer must, 
 therefore, have meant by the cave something quite other than 
 a cave ; must have meant, in fact, to signify by its inside the 
 temporary, by its outside the eternal world. But this stage in 
 Porphyry's development was not of long duration. As Ms 
 conscience had revolted from Homer taken literally, so his 
 intelligence revolted from such a fashion of interpretation as 
 this. But yet he was not prepared to abandon the Greek 
 religion. That religion, he thought, must possess some autho- 
 rity, some sacred book, some standard of faith, capable of being 
 brought into harmony with the philosophy which, equally with 
 the religion itself, was the tradition and inheritance of the race. 
 And such a rule of faith, if to be found anywhere, must be 
 found in the direct communications of the gods to men. Scat- 
 
 1 The impossibility of extracting a spiritual religion from Homer is charac- 
 teristically expressed by Proclus (ad. Tim. 20), who calls Homer dirdtieiav re 
 voepav Kal faty ij>i\6<TO({>oi> oi>x oI6$ re irapadovvai.
 
 474 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 tered and fragmentary though these were, it must be possible 
 to extract from them a consistent system. 1 This is what he 
 endeavoured to do in his work, " On the Philosophy to be drawn 
 from Oracles," a book of which large fragments remain to us 
 imbedded in Eusebius's treatise "On the Preparation for the 
 Gospel." 
 
 Perhaps the best guarantee of the good faith in which 
 Porphyry undertook this task lies in the fact that he afterwards 
 recognised that he had been unsuccessful. He acknowledged, 
 in terms on which his antagonist Eusebius has gladly seized, 
 that the mystery as to the authors of the responses was too 
 profound, the responses themselves were too unsatisfactory, to 
 admit of the construction from them of a definite and lofty 
 faith. Yet there is one point on which, though his inferences 
 undergo much modification, his testimony remains practically 
 the same. 2 This testimony, based, as he implies and his 
 biographers assert, on personal experience, 3 is mainly concerned 
 with the phenomena of possession or inspiration by an unseen 
 power. These phenomena, so deeply involved in the conception 
 of oracles, and which we must now discuss, are familiar to the 
 ethnologist in almost every region of the globe. The savage, 
 readily investing any unusual or striking object in nature with 
 a spirit of its own, is likely to suppose further that a spirit's 
 temporary presence may be the cause of any unusual act or 
 condition of a human being. Even so slight an abnormality as 
 the act of sneezing has generally been held to indicate the 
 operation or the invasion of a god. And when we come to 
 graver departures from ordinary wellbeing nightmare, con- 
 sumption, epilepsy, or madness the notion that a disease-spirit 
 has entered the sufferer becomes more and more obvious. 
 Ravings which possess no applicability to surrounding facts 
 are naturally held to be the utterances of some remote intelli- 
 
 1 ws &i> K fiovov fiffiatov rets t\iridas TOV (ruOfji'ai dpvo/j.evos (Eus. Pr. Ev. iv. 6) 
 is the strong expression which Porphyry gives to his sense of the importance of 
 this inquiry. 
 
 2 There is one sentence in the epistle to Anebo which would suggest a con- 
 trary view, but the later De Abstinentia, etc., seem to me to justify the 
 statement in the text. 
 
 3 See, for instance, Eus. Pr. Ev. iv. 6 : /udXiora yap <piKo<r6<jx>}v oCros T&V K.a.0' 
 i)/j.3.s doKei /cat dai/MJi Kal oh (prjcri Oeols
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 475 
 
 gence. Such ravings, when they have once become an object 
 of reverence, may be artificially reproduced by drugs or other 
 stimuli, and we may thus arrive at the belief in inspiration by 
 an easy road. 1 
 
 There are traces in Greece of something of this reverence 
 for disease, but they are faint and few ; and the Greek ideal of 
 soundness in mind and body, the Greek reverence for beauty 
 and strength, seem to have characterised the race from a very 
 early period. It is possible indeed that the first tradition of 
 
 " Blind Thamyris and blind Mseonides, 
 And Teiresias and Phineus, prophets old," 
 
 may have represented a primitive idea that the " celestial light 
 shone inward" when the orbs of vision were darkened. But the 
 legends which have reached us scarcely connect Homer's blind- 
 ness with his song, and ascribe the three prophets' loss of sight to 
 their own vanity or imprudence. In nymph-possession, which, 
 in spite of Pausanias's statement, is perhaps an older pheno- 
 menon than ApoUine possession, we find delirium honoured, 
 but it is a delirium proceeding rather from the inhalation of 
 noxious vapours than from actual disease. 2 And in the choice 
 of the Pythian priestess while we find that care is taken that 
 no complication shall be introduced into the process of oracular 
 inquiry by her youth or good looks, 3 there is little evidence 
 to show that any preference was given to epileptics. 4 Still less 
 
 1 On this subject see Prim. Cult. chap. xiv. ; Lubbock, Origin of Civilisa- 
 tion, pp. 252-5, etc. The Homeric phrase (rrvyepbs 5t oi Hxp a 8a.lfj.wv (Od. v. 
 396) seems to be the Greek expression which comes nearest to the doctrine of 
 disease-spirits. 
 
 2 See Maury, ii. 475. Nymph-oracles were especially common in Boeotia, 
 where there were many caves and springs. Paus. ix. 2, etc. The passage 
 from Hippocrates, De Morbo Sacro, cited by Maury, ii. 470, is interesting from 
 its precise parallelism with savage beliefs, but cannot be pressed as an autho- 
 rity for primitive tradition. 
 
 8 Diod. Sic. xvi. 27. 
 
 4 Maury (ii. 514) cites Plut. de Defect, orac. 46, and Schol. Ar. Pint. 39, in de- 
 fence of the view that a hysterical subject was chosen as Pythia. But Plutarch 
 expressly says (de Defect. 50) that it was necessary that the Pythia should be 
 free from perturbation when called on to prophesy, and the Scholion on Aristo- 
 phanes is equally indecent and unphysiological. Moreover, Plutarch speaks 
 of the custom of pouring cold water over the priestess in order to ascertain by 
 her healthy way of shuddering that she was sound in body and mind. This
 
 476 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 can we trace any such reason of choice in other oracular 
 sanctuaries. We find here, in fact, the same uncertainty which 
 hangs over the principle of selection of the god's mouthpiece 
 in other shahmauistic countries, where the medicine-man 
 or angekok is sometimes described as haggard and nervous, 
 sometimes as in no way distinguishable from his less gifted 
 neighbours. 
 
 Nor, on the other hand, do we find in Greece much trace of 
 that other kind of possession of which the Hebrew prophets 
 are our great example, where a peculiar loftiness of mind and 
 character seem to point the prophet out as a fitting exponent 
 of the will of heaven, and a sudden impulse gives vent in words, 
 almost unconscious, to thoughts which seem no less than divine. 
 The majestic picture of Amphiaraus in the Seven against 
 Thebes, the tragic personality of Cassandra in the Agamemnon, 
 are the nearest parallels which Greece offers to an Elijah or 
 a Jeremiah. These, however, are mythical characters ; and so 
 little was the gift of prophecy associated with moral greatness 
 in later days, that while Plato attributes it to the action of the 
 divinity, Aristotle feels at liberty to refer it to bile. 1 
 
 It were much to be wished that some systematic discus- 
 sion of the subject had reached us from classical times. But 
 none seems to have been composed, at any rate none has come 
 down to us, till Plutarch's inquiry as to the causes of the 
 general cessation of oracles in his age. 2 Plutarch's temper is 
 conservative and orthodox, but we find, nevertheless, that he 
 has begun to doubt whether Apollo is in every case the inspir- 
 ing spirit. On the contrary, he thinks that sometimes this is 
 plainly not the case, as in one instance where the Pythia, 
 forced to prophesy while under the possession of a dumb and 
 evil spirit, went into convulsions and soon afterwards died. 
 
 same test was applied to goats, etc., when about to be sacrificed. There is no 
 doubt evidence (cf. Maury, ii. 461) that the faculty of divination was sup- 
 posed to be hereditary in certain families (perhaps even in certain localities, 
 Herod, i. 78), but I cannot find that members of such families were sought for 
 as priests in oracular seats. 
 
 1 Plat. Ion. 5. Ar. Probl. xxx. I cannot dwell here on Plat. Phaedr. 153, 
 and similar passages, which suggest a theory of inspiration which would carry 
 us far beyond the present topic. 
 
 2 Plut. de Defect, orac.; de Pyth. ; de El apud Delphos.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 477 
 
 And he recurs to a doctrine, rendered orthodox, as we have 
 already seen, by its appearance in Hesiod, but little dwelt on 
 in classical times, a doctrine which peoples the invisible world 
 with a hierarchy of spirits of differing character and power. 
 These spirits, he believes, give oracles, whose character therefore 
 varies with the character and condition of the inspiring spirit ; 
 and of this it is hard to judge except iuferentially, since spirits 
 are apt to assume the names of gods on whom they in some 
 way depend, though they may by no means resemble them in 
 character or power. Xay, spirits are not necessarily immortal, 
 and the death of a resident spirit may have the effect of closing 
 an oracular shrine. The death of Pan himself was announced 
 by a flying voice to Thamus, a sailor, " about the isles 
 Echinades ; " he was told to tell it at Palodes, and when the 
 ship reached Palodes there was a dead calm. He cried out 
 that Pan was dead, and there was a wailing in all the air. 1 
 
 In Plutarch, too, we perceive a growing disposition to dwell 
 on a class of manifestations of which we have heard little since 
 Homer's time, evocations of the visible spirits of the dead. 2 
 Certain places, it seems, were consecrated by immemorial 
 belief to this solemn ceremony. At Cumae, 3 at Phigalea, 4 at 
 Heraclea, 5 on the river Acheron, by the lake Avernus, 6 men 
 strove to recall for a moment the souls who had passed away, 
 sometimes, as Periander sought Melissa, 7 in need of the 
 accustomed wifely counsel; sometimes, as Pausanias sought 
 Cleonice, 8 goaded by passionate remorse ; or sometimes with 
 no care to question, with no need to confess or to be forgiven, 
 but as, in one form of the legend, Orpheus sought Eurydice, 9 
 
 1 This quasi-human character of Pan (Herod, ii. 146 ; Find. Fr. 68 ; Hyg. 
 Fab. 224), coupled with the indefinite majesty which his name suggested, 
 seems to have been very impressive to the later Greeks. An oracle quoted 
 by Porphyry (ap. Eus. Pr. Ev. ) etfxo/twu pporbs yeyds Ilavl crtV^vros 6e$, K.T.\., is 
 curiously parallel to some Christian hymns in its triumphant sense of human 
 kinship with the divinity. 
 
 3 Quaest. Horn. ; de Defect. Orac. ; de Ser. Num. Vind. 
 
 8 Diod. Sic. iv. 22 ; Ephor. ap. Strab. v. 244. 4 Paus. iii. 17. 
 
 * Plut. Cim. 6. 
 
 6 Liv. xxiv. 12, etc. The origin of this veKvo/j-avre'tov was probably Greek. 
 See reff. ap. Maury, ii. 467. 
 
 7 Diod. iv. 22 ; Herod, v. 92 gives a rather different story. 
 
 8 Plut. dm. 6. Paus. iii. 17. Paus. ix. 30.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 travelling to the Thesprotian Aornus, in the hope that her 
 spirit would rise and look on him once again, and waiting for 
 one who came not, and dying in a vain appeal. 
 
 But on such stories as these Plutarch will not dogmatically 
 judge ; he remarks only, and the remark was more novel then 
 than now, that we know as yet no limit to the communications 
 of soul with soul. 
 
 This transitional position of Plutarch may prepare us for 
 the still wider divergence from ancient orthodoxy which we 
 find in Porphyry. Porphyry is indeed anxious to claim for 
 oracular utterances as high an authority as possible ; and he 
 continues to ascribe many of them to Apollo himself. But he 
 no longer restricts the phenomena of possession and inspira- 
 tion within the traditional limits as regards either their time, 
 their place, or their author. He maintains that these pheno- 
 mena may be reproduced according to certain rules at almost 
 any place and time, and that the spirits who cause them are of 
 very multifarious character. I shall give his view at some 
 length, as it forms by far the most careful inquiry into the 
 nature of Greek oracles which has come down to us from 
 an age in which they existed still ; and it happens also that 
 while the grace of Plutarch's style has made his essays on 
 the same subject familiar to all, the post-classical date and 
 style of Porphyry and Eusebius have prevented their more 
 serious treatises from attracting much attention from English 
 scholars. 
 
 According to Porphyry, then, the oracular or communica- 
 ting demon or spirit, we must adopt spirit as the word of 
 wider meaning, manifests himself in several ways. Sometimes 
 he speaks through the mouth of the entranced " recipient," l 
 sometimes he shows himself in an immaterial, or even in a 
 material form, apparently according to his own rank in the 
 
 i is the word generally used for the human intermediary 
 between the god or spirit and the inquirers. See Lob. Agl. p. 108, on the 
 corresponding word Kara/3oAiK<5s for the spirit who is thus received for a 
 time into a human being's organism. Cf. also Firmicus Maternus de errore 
 prof, relig. 13: " Serapis vocatus et intra corpus hominis conlatus talia 
 respondit ; " and the phrase ^7/caro%^tras r SapdiriSi (Inscr. Smyrn. 3163, 
 ap. Wolff, deNov.)
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 4 79 
 
 invisible world. 1 The recipient falls into a state of trance, 
 mixed sometimes with exhausting agitation or struggle, 2 as in 
 the case of the Pythia. And the importance attached to a 
 right choice of time and circumstances for the induction of this 
 trance reminds us of Plutarch's story, already mentioned, of the 
 death of a Pythian priestess compelled to prophesy when pos- 
 sessed by an evil spirit. Another inconvenience in choosing 
 a wrong time seems to have been that false answers were then 
 given by the spirit, who, however, would warn the auditors 
 that he could not give information, 3 or even that he would 
 certainly tell falsehoods, 4 on that particular occasion. Porphyry 
 attributes this occasional falsity to some defect in the surround- 
 ing conditions, 5 which confuses the spirit, and prevents him 
 from speaking truly. For on descending into our atmosphere 
 the spirits become subject to the laws and influences which 
 rule mankind, and are not therefore entirely free agents. 6 
 When a confusion of this kind occurs, the prudent inquirer 
 should defer his researches, a rule with which inexperienced 
 investigators fail to comply. 7 
 
 Let us suppose, however, that a favourable day has been 
 secured, and also, not less important, a 8 " guileless inter- 
 
 1 Porphyry calls these inferior spirits Sai^via. v\iKa, and Proclus (ad 
 Tim. 142) defines the distinction thus : T&V Saipbvuv ol u-ev ev rrj ffvardcrei 
 TT\OV rb Trvpiov i=x ovTfS bparol 6vres ovotv i%ov<nv dvTiTvirus, ol 5t Kal yijs 
 fj.eTfi\r)<j)6Tes vTroiriirTov<n T% a<f>ri. It is only the spirits who partake of earthly 
 nature who are capable of being touched. These spirits may be of a rank 
 inferior to mankind ; Proclus, ad Tim. 24, calls them ^u%as dTroTvxovffas p.ev 
 TOV dvOpuTriKOv vov, 7r/)6s 5 TO, $Qo, c^ovcro.? 8id6e<nv. 
 
 2 ov fopei fj.e TOV doxyos i) rdXaiva Kapdia (Procl. in Rempublicam, 380) is 
 the exclamation of a spirit whose recipient can no longer sustain his presence. 
 
 3 Eus. Pr. Ev. vi. 5, ffri/j.epov oik eirtouce \tyeiv frffrpuv bSbv Ipriv. 
 
 4 Ibid. K\ele ftirfv Kdpros re \6yuv \f/evdriyopa X^w : "Try no longer to enchain 
 me with your words ; I shall tell you falsehoods." 
 
 8 i) K<na<rraau TOV irepitx ovr< >s- Eus. Pr. Ev. vi. 5, KOI TO irepitx v dvayKafrv 
 ^/{vdrj ylvfffdai TO. navTela, ov TOVS Trapoiras eKovTas irpoaTidtvai. TO i/'eOSos. . . . 
 irt(j>T]vev dpa, adds Porphyry with satisfaction, irodev iro\\a.Kis TO 
 
 ' Porph. ap. Philoponum, de Mundi Great, iv. 20, with the comments of 
 Philoponus, whose main objection to these theories lies in their interference 
 with the freedom of the will. 
 
 7 Pr. Ev. vi. 5, oi 5k ^vovfft Kal \tyeiv dvayKdfrovtn did TT^V dfiaOlav. 
 
 8 Ibid. v. 8, Kcanrfvev d/j.(f>l Kdpijvov d/j,u/j.Tf]Toio
 
 480 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 mediary." Some confined space would then be selected for 
 the expected manifestations, " so that the influence should not 
 be too widely diffused." l This place seems sometimes to have 
 been made dark,- a circumstance which has not escaped the 
 satire of the Christian controversialist, 2 whose derision is still 
 further excited by the " barbarous yells and singing " 3 with 
 which the unseen visitant was allured, a characteristic, it 
 may be noticed in passing, of shahmanistic practices, where- 
 ever they have been found to prevail. During these proceed- 
 ings the human agent appears to have fallen into an abnormal 
 slumber, which extinguished for the time his own identity, 
 and allowed the spirit to speak through his lips, " to contrive 
 a voice for himself through a mortal instrument." 4 In such 
 speeches, of which several are preserved to us, the informing 
 spirit alludes to the human being through whom he is speaking 
 in the third person, as " the mortal " or " the recipient ; " of 
 himself he speaks in the first person, or occasionally in the 
 third person, as " the god " or " the king." 5 
 
 The controlling spirits do not, however, always content 
 themselves with this vicarious utterance. They appear some- 
 times, as already indicated, in visible and tangible form. Of 
 this phase of the proceedings, however, Eusebius has preserved 
 to us but scanty notices. His mind is preoccupied with the 
 presumption and bizarrerie of the spirits, who sometimes 
 profess themselves to be (for instance) the sun and moon ; 
 sometimes insist on being called by barbarous names, and 
 talking a barbarous jargon. 6 The precise nature of such 
 appearances had been, it seems, in dispute since the days of 
 Pythagoras, who conjectured that the apparition was an 
 
 1 *cal dfjia &iro<TTT)plfoi>Tes afrrb fvravda ?v nvi ffTept 
 
 SiaxelffOai, Iamb, de Myst. iii. 14. The maxims of lamblichus in these 
 matters are in complete conformity with those of Porphyry. 
 
 2 Eus. Pr. Ev. iv. 1, Kal rb OKOTOS d ov fj-itcpa ffvvepyeiv rrj Ka.8' eavrovs 
 
 8 Ibid. v. 12, &<r^fwa re Kal fiapfiapois -fix 01 * Te Ka ' <t>^"ais KijKovjjifroi,. 
 
 4 Ibid. v. 8, auXoO 5' e*c fSpoT^oio <pi\t]v ereKvuffaro <f>ti)vf>v. 
 
 5 <f>u>s, j3porbs, doxtfc. Pr. Ev. v. 9, Xtfere \onrov &.VO.KTO., pporbs Oebv OVK^TI 
 Xwpei. 
 
 8 Pr. Ev. v. 10 (quoting Porph. ad Aneb. ), ri d Kal TO, &<rr)fjia. ftov\erai ovofjura 
 K<d T&V dffrifj.uv ra J3dpj3a.pa irpb ruv mur<f oiKeiuv, etc.
 
 GREEK OR A CLES. 
 
 emanation from the spirit, but not, strictly speaking, the spirit 
 itself. 1 
 
 In the Neoplatonic view, these spirits entered by a process 
 of " introduction " - into a material body temporarily prepared 
 for them ; or sometimes it was said that " the pure name was 
 compressed into a sacred Form." 3 Those spirits who have 
 already been accustomed to appear were best instructed as to 
 how to appear again ; but some of them were inclined to 
 mischief, especially if the persons present showed a careless 
 temper. 4 
 
 After a time the spirit becomes anxious to depart ; but is 
 not always able to quit the intermediary as promptly as it 
 desires. We possess several oracles uttered under these cir- 
 
 1 Pythag. ap. Aen. ; Gaz. ap. Theophr. p. 61, Boisson. irbrepov Oeol r) Sat/j-oves 
 7} TotjTUv a.irbppoi.a.1, Kal Trorepov SCU/XWP efs aXXos tlvai 5oKwv T) TroXXo: /ecu atpuv 
 avrwv Bi.a<f>epovTes, oi /Afv TJ/mepoi, oi 5' dypioi, Kal ol n^v eviore TaXrjOTJ \eyovres ol 
 6' 6Xws Kifi$ri\oi .... reXos irpo'lerai dai/u.ovos diroppoiav elvaL TO cpdafj.a. 
 
 2 fia-Kptiris. See Lob. Arjl. p. 730. 
 
 3 Pr. Ev. v. 8: iepdici TVTTOLS 
 
 ffwOXifiofJ-frov Trvpos dyvov. 
 
 I may just notice here the connection between this idea of the entrance of a 
 spirit into a quasi-human form built up for the occasion, and that recrud- 
 escence of idol-worship which marks one phase of Neoplatonism. In an age 
 when such primitive practices as ' ' carrying the dried corpse of a parent round 
 the fields that he might see the state of the crops" (Spencer's Sociology, 154), 
 were no longer possible, this new method of giving temporary materiality to 
 disembodied intelligences suggested afresh that it might be practicable so to 
 prepare an image as that a spirit would be content to live there permanently. 
 An oracle in Pausanias (ix. 38) curiously illustrates this view of statues. The 
 land of the Orchomenians was infested by a spirit which sat on a stone. The 
 Pythia ordered them to make a brazen image of the spectre and fasten it with 
 iron to the stone. The spirit would still be there, but he would now be per- 
 manently fixed down, and, being enclosed in a statue, he would no longer 
 form an obnoxious spectacle. 
 
 4 Pr. Ev. v. 8, #os iron)ffa.p.evoi rrjs eavrCiv irapovfftas evfiaOtcrrepov <j>oiTu<rai 
 Kal /MoXiffra eav Kal <f>6<rei dyadol Tvyx<ivuffiv, ol 5, K&V H6os ?x ufft r v "fapa- 
 ylveffBai, fiXd/Byi' TIV& TrpoOv/JLovvrai iroielv, Kal fJ-d\iffTa tav dfJ.e\t(rrep6v rts doKy 
 dvaffrptfaffOai ev rots irpdy/Mffi. This notion of a congruity between the in- 
 quirer and the responding spirit is curiously illustrated by a story of 
 Caracalla (Dio Cass. Ixxvii.), who tyvxayuyrjffe fttv fiXXos rt TWOS Kal rty rou 
 irarpbs rov re Ko/u./j.6dov tyvxfyv elire 5' oZv ovdels avrif ovdtv, TrXrjv TOV Ko/j.jjASov. 
 
 "E077 yap ravra' (3a2ve SiKrjs affffov, 6eol ty alrouffi Seftripy. No ghost would 
 address Caracalla except the ghost of Commodus, who spoke to denounce to 
 him his doom. 
 
 2 H
 
 482 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 cumstances, and giving directions which we can but imperfectly 
 understand. It appears that the recipient, for what reason we 
 are left to conjecture, was in some way bound with withes and 
 enveloped in fine linen, which had to be cut and unwrapped at 
 the end of the ceremony. 1 The human agent had then to be 
 set on his feet and taken from the corner where he had been 
 outstretched, and a singular collaboration seems to have taken 
 place, the spirit giving his orders to the bystanders by a voice 
 issuing from the recipient's still senseless form. 2 At last the 
 spirit departs, and the recipient is set free. 
 
 Eusebius, in a passage marked by strong common sense, 3 has 
 pointed out some obvious objections to oracles obtained in this 
 fashion. Some of these so-called " recipients," it appears, had been 
 put to the torture and had made damaging confessions. Further 
 penalties had induced them to explain how their fraud was 
 carried out. The darkness and secrecy of the proceedings were 
 in any case suspicious ; and the futility of the answers obtained, 
 or their evident adaptation to the wishes of the inquirers, 
 pointed too plainly to their human origin. The actual 
 method of producing certain phenomena has exercised the 
 ingenuity of other Fathers. Thus figures could be show r n in a 
 bowl of water by using a moveable bottom, or lights could be 
 made to fly about in a dark room by releasing a vulture with 
 flaming tow tied to its claws. 4 
 
 But in spite of these contemptuous criticisms the Christian 
 Fathers, as is well known, were disposed to believe in the 
 genuineness of these communications, and showed much anxiety 
 to induce the oracles, which often admitted the greatness and 
 wisdom, to acknowledge also the divinity, of Christ. 5 
 
 1 Pr. Ev. v. 8 : Tratieo di) ireptypuv ddpuv, avcarave d 
 
 Ba/j-vwv K\tiuv TroXibv rtiirov, -fjd' aifb yvtwv 
 NeiXanji* 666vr)v xepcrlf <m|3a/>ws diraeipas. 
 
 And again, when the bystanders delay the release, the spirit exclaims 
 crlvdovos afjurtraffov vecpfXi^v, \vff6v re 5o%^o. 
 
 2 Pr. Ev. v. 8 : v\f/lwpupov alpe rapffbv, fox ftv&v ^ K M U X < ^' / - And again, 
 
 &pare (pwra yalr)det> avaffTriffavres ercupoi, etc. 
 
 3 Pr. Ev. iv. 2. 
 
 4 Pseudo-Origen, Philosophumena, p. 73. 
 
 8 Pr. Ev. iv. iii. 7. Aug. de Civit. Dei, xix. 23. Lact. Instil, iv. 13.*
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 483 
 
 Eusebius himself, in another work, 1 adduces a letter of 
 Constantino's describing an oracle said to have been uttered 
 direct!} 7 by Apollo " from a certain dark hole," in which 
 the god asserted that he could no longer speak the truth on 
 account of the number of saints who were now on the earth. 
 But this has so little the air of an Apolline manifestation that 
 it is suspected that a Christian man had crept into a cave and 
 delivered this unauthorised response with a polemical object. 2 
 
 Into so obscure, so undignified a region of mingled fraud 
 and mystery does it seem that, by the admission of friends and 
 foes alike, the oracles of Greece had by this time fallen. Com- 
 pared with what had been stripped away, that which was left 
 may seem to us like the narrow vault of the Delian sanctuary 
 compared with the ruined glories of that temple-covered isle. 
 There was not, indeed, in Porphyry's view anything incon- 
 sistent with the occasional presence and counsel of a lofty and 
 a guardian spirit. There was nothing which need make him 
 doubt that the Greeks had been led upwards through their long 
 history by some providential power. Nay, he himself cites, as 
 we shall see, recent oracles higher in tone than any which have 
 preceded them. Yet as compared with the early ardour of that 
 imaginative belief which peopled heaven with gods and earth 
 with heroes, we feel that we are now sent back to " beggarly 
 elements ; " that the task of sifting truth from falsehood amid 
 so much deception and incompetence on the part both of visible 
 and invisible agencies, 3 of erecting a consistent creed on such 
 mean and shifting foundations, might well rebut even the patient 
 ardour of this most untiring of " seekers after God." And 
 when we see him recognising all this with painful clearness, 
 giving vent, in that letter to Anebo which is so striking an 
 example of absolute candour in an unscrupulous and polemic 
 
 1 Vit. Const, ii. 50 ; cf. Wolff, de Noviss. p. 4. 
 
 2 The well-known story, Tpriy6pt.os T$ 2a.Ta.vg. EiVeXtfe Greg. Nyss. 548 
 (and to be found in all lives of Gregory Thaumatiirgus), illustrates this Chris- 
 tian rivalry with pagan oracles or apparitions. 
 
 3 The disappointing falsity of the manifesting spirits who pretended to be 
 the souls of departed friends, etc., is often alluded to ; e.g. in the ad Aneb- 
 onem : ol 5 elvai [jv ^u6fi> rlffevrat rt> vwf)Koov ytvos dira.Tir)\rjs <f>\jfffus, iravrb- 
 /Jiop<}>6v re /cat iro\frrpowov, viroKpit>6fj.fvov Kcd 6eoi>s ical dai/j.ovas Ka 
 TfOvr)K6rtai>, etc.
 
 484 GREEK ORACLES. ' 
 
 age, to his despair at the obscurity which seems to deepen as 
 he proceeds, we cannot but wonder that we do not see him 
 turn to take refuge in the new religion with its offers of certainty 
 and peace. 
 
 Why, we shall often ask, should men so much in earnest as 
 the Neoplatonists have taken, with the gospel before them, the 
 side they took ? Why should they have preferred to infuse 
 another allegory into the old myths which had endured so 
 much ? to force the Pythian Apollo, so simple-hearted through 
 all his official ambiguity, to strain his hexameters into the 
 ineffable yearnings of a theosophic age ? For we seem to see the 
 issues so clearly ! when we take up Augustine instead of Pro- 
 clus we feel so instantly that we have changed to the winning 
 side! But to Greek minds and the glory of the Syrian 
 Porphyry was that, of all barbarians, he became the most 
 intensely Greek the struggle presented itself in a very 
 different fashion. They were fighting not for an effete mytho- 
 logy, but for the whole Past of Greece ; nay, as it seemed in 
 a certain sense, for the civilisation of the world. The repulse 
 of Xerxes had stirred in the Greeks the consciousness of their 
 uniqueness as compared with the barbarism on every side. 
 And now, when Hellenism was visibly dying away, there awoke 
 in the remaining Greeks a still more momentous conception, 
 the conception of the uniqueness and preciousness of Greek life 
 not only in space but in duration, as compared not only with 
 its barbarian compeers, but with the probable future of the 
 world. It was no longer against the Great King, but against 
 Time itself, that the unequal battle must be waged. And while 
 Time's impersonal touch was slowly laid upon all the glory 
 which had been, a more personal foe was seen advancing from 
 the same East from whose onset Greece already had escaped, 
 " but so as by fire." Christ, like Xerxes, came against the 
 Greek spirit ^vpiryyeve^ appa BtcoKcov, driving a Syrian car ; 
 the tide of conquest was rolling back again, and the East was 
 claiming an empire such as the West had never won. 
 
 We, indeed, knowing all the flower of European Christianity 
 in Dante's age, all its ripening fruit in our own, may see that this 
 time from the East light came ; we may trust and claim that we 
 are living now among the scattered forerunners of such types of
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 485 
 
 beauty and of goodness as Athens never knew. But if so much 
 even of our own ideal is in the future still, how must it have 
 been to those whose longest outlook could not "overpass the 
 dreary centuries of barbarism and decay ? So vast a spiritual 
 revolution must needs bring to souls of differing temper very 
 different fates. Happy were they who, like Augustine and 
 Origen, could frankly desert the old things and rejoice that all 
 things were become new. Happy too were those few saintly 
 souls an Antoninus or a 1'lotinus whose lofty calm no 
 spiritual revolution seemed able to reach or mar. But the 
 pathetic destiny was that of men like Julian or Porphyry, 
 men who were disqualified from leading the race onward into a 
 noble future merely because they so well knew and loved an 
 only less noble past. 
 
 And yet it is not for long that we can take Porphyry as an 
 example of a man wandering in the twilight between " dying 
 lights and dawning," between an outworn and an untried faith. 
 The last chapter in the history of oracles is strangely connected 
 with the last stage of the spiritual history of this upward- 
 striving man. 
 
 For it was now that Porphyry was to encounter an influence, 
 a doctrine, an aim, more enchanting than Homer's mythology, 
 profouncler than Apollo's oracles, more Christian, I had almost 
 written, than Christianity itself. More Christian at least than 
 such Christianity as had chiefly met Porphyry's eyes ; more 
 Christian than the violence of bishops, the wrangles of heretics, 
 the fanaticism of slaves, was that single-hearted and endless 
 effort after the union of the soul with God which filled every 
 moment of the life of Plotinus, and which gave to his living 
 example a potency and a charm which his writings never can 
 renew. 1 " Without father, without mother, without descent," 
 a figure appearing solitary as Melchisedek on the scene of 
 history, charged with a single blessing and lost in the un- 
 known, we may yet see in this chief of mystics the heir of 
 
 1 Eunapius (vit. Porph. ) manages to touch the heart, in spite of his affecta- 
 tions, when he describes the friendship between Porphyry and Plotinus. Of 
 Porphyry's first visit to Rome he says : -rty fjLeylffrrjv "Pufnji> t'SejV 
 . . . fireiSi] ra-x^TO- s avryv d0t'/cero Ka.1 T 
 6/J.i\icu>, irdvTuv tireXdOero TWV &\\uv, K.T.\.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 Plato, and affirm that it is he who has completed the cycle of 
 Greek civilisation by adding to that long gallery of types 
 of artist and warrior, philosopher and poet, the stainless image 
 of the saint. 
 
 It may be that the holiness which he aimed at is not for 
 man. It may be that ecstasy comes best unsought, and that 
 the still small voice is heard seldomer in the silence of the 
 wilderness than through the thunder of human toil and amid 
 human passion's fire. 
 
 But those were days of untried capacities, of unbounded 
 hopes. In the Neoplatonist lecture-room, as at the Christian 
 love-feast, it seemed that religion had no need to compromise, 
 that all this complex human spirit could be absorbed and 
 transfigured in one desire. 
 
 Counsels of perfection are the aliment of strenuous souls, 
 and henceforth, in each successive book of Porphyry's, we see 
 him rising higher, resting more confidently in those joys and 
 aspirations which are the heritage of all high religions, and the 
 substance of the communion of saints. 
 
 And gradually, as he dwells more habitually in the thought 
 of the supreme and ineffable Deity, the idea of a visible or 
 tangible communion with any Being less august becomes 
 repugnant to his mind. For what purpose should he draw to 
 him those unknown intelligences from the ocean of environing 
 souls ? " For on those things which he desires to know there is 
 no prophet nor diviner who can declare to him the truth, but 
 himself only, by communion with God, who is enshrined indeed 
 in his heart." 1 " By a sacred silence we do Him honour, and by 
 pure thoughts of what he is." 2 " Holding Him fast, and being 
 made like unto Him, let us present ourselves, a holy sacrifice, 
 for our offering unto God." 3 
 
 And in his letter to the well-loved wife of his old age, 
 than which we find no higher expression of the true Platonic 
 love (so often degraded and misnamed) no nobler charge and 
 
 1 De Abstln. ii. 54. 
 
 2 Ibid. ii. 34, Sia S ffiyris Ka.6a.pas icai TWV irepl avrov Ka.6a.pSjv evvoi&v 6prf- 
 
 3 Ibid. ii. 34, Sel &pa ffvva<f>0vTas KOA. 6/JWiudfrTa.s O.UT<$ TT?C avruv a 
 dvffiav Ifpav Trpoaa.ya.yeiv r<p Off.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 487 
 
 counsel of man to woman in all the stores which antiquity has 
 bequeathed, in this last utterance we find him risen above 
 all doubt and controversy, and rapt in the contemplation of 
 that Being whom "no prayers can move and no sacrifice 
 honour, nor the abundance of offerings find favour in his sight ; 
 only the inspired thought fixed firmly on Him has cognisance 
 of God indeed." 1 It may seem that as we enter on this region 
 we have left oracles behind. But it is not so. The two last 
 oracles which I shall cite, and which are among the most 
 remarkable of all, are closely connected with this last period of 
 Porphyry's life. The first of them is found, by no chance 
 we may be sure, on a leaf of the manuscript which contains 
 his letter to Marcella. It is introduced to us by an unknown 
 writer as "an oracle concerning the Eternal God.'" 2 
 
 God ineffable, etenial Sire, 
 
 Throned on the whirling spheres, the astral fire, 
 
 Hid in whose heart thy whole creation lies, 
 
 The whole world's wonder mirrored in thine eyes, 
 
 List thou thy children's voice, who draw anear, 
 
 Thou hast begotten us, thou too must hear ! 
 
 Each life thy life her Fount, her Ocean knows, 
 
 Fed while it fosters, filling as it flows ; 
 
 Wrapt in thy light the star-set cycles roll, 
 
 And worlds within thee stir into a soul ; 
 
 But stars and souls shall keep their watch and way, 
 
 Nor change the going of thy lonely day. 
 
 Some sons of thine, our Father, King of kings, 
 Rest in the sheen and shelter of thy wings, 
 Some to strange hearts the unspoken message bear, 
 Sped on thy strength through the haunts and homes of air, 
 Some where thine honour dwelleth hope and wait, 
 Sigh for thy courts and gather at thy gate ; 
 These from afar to thee their praises bring, 
 Of thee, albeit they have not seen thee, sing ; 
 
 1 rb &6fov <f>p6vr)(j.a /caXws ijdpafffj.frot' ffwdTrrerai T<j5 6c$. See the Ad Mar- 
 cellam passim. 
 
 2 This oracle was very probably actually delivered in a shrine, as the utter- 
 ances of this period were often tinged with Neoplatonism. I have followed 
 Wolff's emendations, and must refer the reader to his Porph. Fragm. p. 144, 
 and especially TaisAddit. IV. de Daemonibus, p. 225, in support of the substantial 
 accuracy of my rendering. It is impossible to reproduce all the theology 
 which this hymn contains ; I have tried to bring out the force of the most 
 central and weighty expressions, such as decdois dxeroiai ri6i]vCiv vow araXavrov. 
 The oracle will also be found in Steuchus, de Perenni Philosophies,, iii. 14 ; 
 Orelli, Opusc. (jr. vett. sentent. i. 319 ; and Mai's edition of the Ad Marcellam.
 
 4 88 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 Of thee the Father wise, the Mother mild, 
 Thee in all children the eternal Child, 
 Thee the first Number and harmonious Whole, 
 Form in all forms, and of all souls the Soul. 
 
 The second oracle above alluded to, the last which I shall 
 quote, was given, as Porphyry tells us, at Delphi to his friend 
 Amelius, who inquired, " Where was now Plotinus's soul?" 1 
 
 Whatever be the source of this poem, it stands out to us as 
 one of the most earnest utterances of antiquity, though it has 
 little of classical perfection of form. Nowhere, indeed, is the 
 contest more apparent between the intensity of the emotions 
 which are struggling for utterance and the narrow limits of 
 human speech, which was composed to deal with the things 
 that are known and visible, and not with those that are incon- 
 ceivable and unseen. 
 
 Little, indeed, it is which the author of this oracle could 
 express, less which the translator can render; but there is 
 enough to show once more the potency of an elect soul, what a 
 train of light she may leave behind her as she departs on her 
 unknown way ; when for those who have lived in her presence, 
 but can scarcely mourn her translation, the rapture of love 
 fades into the rapture of worship. Plotinus was " the eagle 
 soaring above the tomb of Plato;" no wonder that the eyes 
 which followed his flight must soon be blinded with the sun. 
 
 Pure spirit once a man pure spirits now 
 Greet thee rejoicing, and of these art thou ; 
 Not vainly was thy whole soul alway bent 
 With one same battle and one the same intent 
 Through eddying cloud and earth's bewildering roar 
 To win her bright way to that stainless shore. 
 Ay, 'mid the salt spume of this troublous sea, 
 This death in life, this sick perplexity, 
 Oft on thy struggle through the obscure unrest 
 A revelation opened from the Blest 
 
 1 Porph. vit. Plot. 22. It is seldom that the genuineness of an oracle can be 
 established on grounds which would satisfy the critical historian. But this 
 oracle has better external evidence than most others. Of Porphyry's own 
 good faith there is no question, and though we know less of the character 
 of his fellow-philosopher Amelius, it seems unlikely that he would have 
 wished to deceive Porphyry on an occasion so solemn as the death of their 
 beloved master, or even that he could have deceived him as to so considerable 
 an undertaking as a journey to Delphi.
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 489 
 
 Showed close at hand the goal thy hope would win, 
 
 Heaven's kingdom round thee and thy God within. 1 
 
 So sure a help the eternal Guardians gave, 
 
 From life's confusion so were strong to save, 
 
 Upheld thy wandering steps that sought the day 
 
 And set them stedfast 011 the heavenly way. 
 
 Xor quite even here on thy broad brows was shed 
 
 The sleep which shrouds the living, who are dead ; 
 
 Once by God's grace was from thine eyes unfurled 
 
 This veil that screens the immense and whirling world, 
 
 Once, while the spheres around thee in music ran, 
 
 Was very Beauty manifest to man ; 
 
 Ah, once to have seen her, once to have known her there, 
 
 For speech too sweet, for earth too heavenly fair ! 
 
 But now the tomb where long thy soul had lain 
 
 Bursts, and thy tabernacle is rent in twain ; 
 
 Now from about thee, in thy new home above, 
 
 Has perished all but life, and all but love, 
 
 And on all lives and on all loves outpoured 
 
 Free grace and full, a spirit from the Lord, 
 
 High in that heaven whose windless vaults enfold 
 
 Just men made perfect, and an age all gold. 
 
 Thine own Pythagoras is with thee there, 
 
 And sacred Plato in that sacred air, 
 
 And whoso followed, and all high hearts that knew 
 
 In death's despite what deathless Love can do. 
 
 To God's right hand they have scaled the starry way 
 
 Pure spirits these, thy spirit pure as they. 
 
 Ah, saint ! how many and many an anguish past, 
 
 To how fair haven art thou come at last ! 
 
 On thy meek head what Powers their blessing pour, 
 
 Filled full with life, and rich for evermore ! 
 
 This, so far as we know, was the last utterance of the 
 Pythian priestess. Once more, indeed, a century afterwards, 
 a voice was heard at Delphi. But that voice seems rather 
 to have been, in Plutarch's phrase, "a cry floating of itself over 
 solitary places," than the deliverance of any recognised priestess, 
 or from any abiding shrine. For no shrine was standing more. 
 The words which answered the Emperor Julian's search were 
 but the whisper of desolation, the last and loveliest expression 
 of a sanctity that had passed away. A strange coincidence ! 
 that from that Delphian valley, whence, as the legend ran, had 
 
 1 {(/HIVI) yovv rtf ID^urLvif CTKOTTOS eyyvOi valuv' r^Xoj yap avry Ka.1 
 fy rb evudrjvai /ecu TreXdcrat Tip ^TT! iraai 6e<j>. 'En>xe 8t Terpam iroi>, frre a\ 
 CLVT$, TOV ffKoirov TOVTov tvfpyeia df>prfr({> (cat ov 5wafJ.ei. (Porph. vit. Plot.) 
 
 2 I
 
 490 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 sounded the first of all hexameters, 1 the call, as in the child- 
 hood of the world, to " birds to bring their feathers and bees 
 their wax " to build by Castaly the nest-like habitation of the 
 young new-entering god, from that same ruined place where 
 " to earth had fallen the glorious dwelling," from the dry 
 channel where " the water-springs that spake were quenched 
 and dead," should issue in unknown fashion the last frag- 
 ment of Greek poetry which has moved the hearts of men, 
 the last Greek hexameters which retain the ancient cadence, 
 the majestic, melancholy flow ! 2 
 
 Stranger still, and of deeper meaning, is the fate which has 
 ordained that Delphi, born with the birth of Greece, symbolis- 
 ing in her teaching such light and truth as the ancient world 
 might know, silenced once only in her long career, and silenced 
 not by Christ, but by Antichrist, should have proclaimed in 
 her last triumphant oracle the canonisation of the last of the. 
 Greeks, should have responded with her last sigh and echo to 
 the appeal of the last of the Romans. 
 
 And here I shall leave the story of Greek oracles. It may 
 be, indeed, that some strange and solitary divinities the god 
 Jaribolus at Palmyra, 3 the god Marnas at Gaza, 4 the god Besa at 
 Abydos 5 still uttered from time to time some perishing pro- 
 phecy, some despairing protest against the new victorious faith. 
 But that such oracles there still were is proved rather from Chris- 
 tian legislation than from heathen records. On these laws I will 
 not dwell, nor recount how far the Christian emperors fell from 
 their divine ideal when they punished by pillage, 6 by torture, 7 
 
 epa. r' olwvol Kripov re /uAtTTcu. Plut. de Pyth. xvii.; and reff. 
 ap. Hendess, Orac. Graec. p. 36. 
 
 2 eitrare r<JJ ftacriXiji, xanal irt<re daida\os afi\a' 
 oi>K4n 3>or/3oj i-Xft KaXv^av, 01) /JMVTida 8a.<t>vr]v, 
 ov irayav \a\tovcraf airier jSero KO.I \d\ov vdup. 
 
 Ge. Cedren. Hist. Comp. i. 304 ; and see Mr Swinburne's poem, "The Last 
 Oracle." The Pleistos is now called Xero-Potamo. 
 
 * Inscr. Gr. 4483 ap. Wolff, de Noviss. p. 27. There is, however, no proof 
 of Jaribolian utterance later than A. D. 242. 
 
 4 Marc. Diac. vlt. Porph. Episc. ap. Acta Sanctoriim, and Wolff, de JVo 
 p. 26. Circ. A.D. 400. 
 
 5 Amm. Marc. xix. 12 (A.D. 359). 
 
 6 Cod. Theod. xvi. 10 (Theodosius i.) 
 
 7 Amm. Marc. xxi. 12 (Constantius).
 
 GREEK ORACLES. 49 1 
 
 and by death 1 the poor unlearned " villagers," whose only crime 
 it was that they still found in the faith of their fathers the 
 substance of things hoped for, and an evidence of things not 
 seen. Such stains will mar the noblest revolutions, but must 
 not blind us to the fact that a spiritual revolution follows only 
 on a spiritual need. The end of the oracles was determined 
 not from without, but from within. They had passed through 
 all their stages. Fetishism, Shahmanism, Nature-worship, 
 Polytheism, even Monotheism and Mysticism, had found in 
 turn a home in their immemorial shrines. Their utterances 
 had reflected every method in which man has sought com- 
 munion with the Unseen, from systematic experiment to 
 intuitive ecstasy. They had completed the cycle of their 
 scripture from its Theogony to its Apocalypse ; it was time 
 that a stronger wave of revelation should roll over the world, 
 and that what was best and truest in the old religion should 
 be absorbed into and identified with the new. 
 
 And if there be some who feel that the youth, the naivettf, 
 the unquestioning conviction, must perish not from one religion 
 only, but from all ; that the more truly we conceive of God, the 
 more unimaginable He becomes to us, and the more infinite, and 
 the more withdrawn ; that we can no longer " commune with 
 Him from oak or rock as a young man communes with a 
 maid;" to such men the story of the many pathways by 
 which mankind has striven to become cognisant of the Un- 
 seen may have an aspect of hope as well as of despondency. 
 
 For before we despair of a question as unanswerable we 
 must know that it has been rightly asked. And there are 
 problems which can become clearly defined to us only by the 
 aid of premature and imperfect solutions. There are many 
 things which we should never have known had not inquiring 
 men before us so often deemed vainly that they knew. 
 
 Suspense of judgment, indeed, in matters of such moment, 
 is so irksome an attitude of mind, that we need not wonder if 
 
 1 Cod. Justin, ix. 18 (Constantius) ; Theod. leg. Novell, iii. (Theodosivts n.). 
 These laws identify paganism as far as possible with magic, and, by a singular 
 inversion, Augustine quotes Virgil's authority (Aen. iv. 492) in defence of the 
 persecution of his own faith. See Maury, Magie, etc., p. 127. The last struggle 
 of expiring paganism was in defence of the oracular temple of Serapis at 
 Alexandria, A.D. 389.
 
 492 GREEK ORACLES. 
 
 confidence of view on the one side is met by a corresponding 
 confidence on the other; if the trust felt by the mass of man- 
 kind in the adequacy of one or other of the answers to these 
 problems which have been already obtained is rebutted by the 
 decisive assertion that all these answers have been proved futile 
 and that it is idle to look for more. 
 
 Yet such was not the temper of those among the Greeks 
 who felt, as profoundly perhaps as we, the darkness and the 
 mystery of human fates. To them it seemed no useless or 
 unworthy thing to ponder on these chief concerns of man with 
 that patient earnestness which has unlocked so many problems 
 whose solution once seemed destined to be for ever unknown. 
 " For thus will God," as Sophocles says in one of those passages 
 (Fr. 707) whose high serenity seems to answer our perplexities 
 as well as his own 
 
 " Thus then will God to wise men riddling show 
 Such hidden lore as not the wise can know ; 
 Fools in a moment deem his meaning plain, 
 His lessons lightly learn, and learn in vain." 
 
 And even now, in the face of philosophies of materialism 
 and of negation so far more powerful than any which Sophocles 
 had to meet, there are yet some minds into which, after all, a 
 doubt may steal, whether we have indeed so fully explained 
 away the beliefs of the world's past, whether we can indeed 
 so assuredly define the beliefs of its future, or whether it may 
 not still befit us to track with fresh feet the ancient mazes, to 
 renew the world-old desire, and to set no despairing limit to 
 the knowledge or the hopes of man. 
 
 F. W. H. M. 
 
 $TCBS : 
 THOMAS AND ARCHIBALD COXSTABLK, PRINTERS TO HER MAJESTV.
 
 A CATALOGUE OF WORKS 
 
 IN 
 
 GENERAL LITERATURE 
 
 PUBLISHED BY 
 
 MESSRS. LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO. 
 
 39 PATERNOSTER ROW, LONDON, E.G. 
 
 MESSRS. LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO. 
 
 Issue the undermentioned Lists of their Publications, which may be had post free on 
 
 application : 
 
 i. MONTHLY LIST OF NEW WORKS AND 6. CATALOGUE OF SCHOOL BOOKS AND 
 
 NEW EDITIONS. 
 
 EDUCATIONAL WORKS. 
 
 2. QUARTERLY LIST OF ANNOUNCE- y . CATALOGUE OF BOOKS FOR ELE- 
 
 MENTS AND NEW WORKS. 
 
 3. NOTES ON BOOKS ; BEING AN ANALYSIS 
 
 OF THE WORKS PUBLISHED DURING 
 EACH QUARTER. 
 
 4. CATALOGUE OF SCIENTIFIC WORKS. 
 
 MENTARY SCHOOLS AND PUPIL 
 TEACHERS. 
 
 8. CATALOGUE OF THEOLOGICAL WORKS 
 BY DIVINES AND MEMBERS OF THE 
 CHURCH OF ENGLAND. 
 
 5. CATALOGUE OF MEDICAL AND SURGICAL g. CATALOGUE OF WORKS IN GENERAL 
 WORKS. LITERATURE. 
 
 ABBEY ami OVERTON.The Eng- 
 lish Church in the Eighteenth 
 Century. By CHARLES J. ABBEY 
 and JOHN H. OVERTON. Cr. 8vo. js. 6d. 
 
 ABBOTT (Evelyn, 
 WORKS BY. 
 
 M.A., LL.D.} 
 
 A Skeleton Outline of Greek 
 History. Chronologically Ar- 
 ranged. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 A History of Greece. 
 
 Part I. From the Earliest Times to the 
 Ionian Revolt. Crown 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 Part II. 500-445 B.C. IDS. 6d. 
 
 Hellenica. A Collection of Essays 
 
 on Greek Poetry, Philosophy, History, 
 and Religion. Edited by EVELYN ABBOTT, 
 M.A., LL.D. 8vo. i6s. 
 
 A GLAND andMANSOME.AHand- 
 book in Outline of the Politi- 
 cal History of England to 
 1890. Chronologically Arranged. 
 By A. H. DYKE ACLAND, M.P., and 
 CYRIL RANSOME, M.A. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 ACTON. Modern Cookery. By 
 
 ELIZA ACTON. With 150 Woodcuts. 
 Fcp. 8vo. 4J. 6d. 
 
 A. K. H. B. WORKS BY THE VERY 
 
 REVEREND A. K. H. BO YD, D.D. 
 
 Twenty-five Years of St. Andrews. 
 
 1865-1890. 2vols. 8vO. Vol. I. 8VO. 125. 
 
 [Ready]. Vol. II. [In Preparation. 
 
 Autumn Holidays of a Country Parson. 
 
 y.6d. 
 Changed Aspects of Unchanged Truths. 
 
 3^. 6</. 
 Commonplace Philosopher, y. 6d. 
 
 [Continued on next page.
 
 A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS IN GENERAL LITERATURE 
 
 A.K.H.B.THE ESSAYS AND CON- 
 TRIBUTIONS OF continued. 
 
 Counsel and Comfort from a City Pulpit. 
 
 3-r. 6d. 
 
 Critical Essays of a Country Parson. y.6d. \ 
 East Coast Days and Memories. 3-r. 6d. ' 
 Graver Thoughts of a Country Parson. ; 
 
 Three Series. y. bd. each. 
 Landscapes, Churches, and Moralities. 
 
 y. 6d. 
 
 Leisure Hours in Town. 3^ 6d. 
 Lessons of Middle Age. 3-r. 6d. 
 Our Little Life. Two Series. 3^. 6d. each. 
 Our Homely Comedy; and Tragedy. y.6d. 
 Present Day Thoughts. 35. 6d. 
 Recreations of a Country Parson. Three 
 
 Series. y. 6d. each. Also 1st series, 6d. 
 Seaside Musings, y. 6d. 
 Sunday Afternoons in the Parish Church 
 
 of a Scottish University City. 3.?. 6d. 
 1 To Meet the Day ' through the Christian 
 
 year : being a Text of Scripture, with an 
 
 Original Meditation and a Short Selection 
 
 in Verse for Every Day. 4^. 6d. 
 
 AMOS. A Primer of the English 
 Constitution and Government. 
 
 By SHELDON AMOS. Crown Svo. 6s. 
 
 Annual Register (The). A Review 
 
 of Public Events at Home and Abroad, 
 for the year 1891. Svo. iSs. 
 
 %* Volumes of the ' Annual Register' for the 
 years 1863-1890 can still be had. 
 
 ANSTEY (F.) WORKS BY. 
 
 / The Black Poodle, and other 
 
 Stories. Crown Svo. 2s. bds. ; 2s. 6d. cl. 
 
 Voces Populi. Reprinted from 
 
 / Punch. 1st Series. With 20 Illustrations 
 
 byj. BERNARD PARTRIDGE. Fcp. 410. $s. 
 
 2nd Series. [/ the Press. 
 
 The Travelling Companions. 
 
 / Reprinted from Punch. With Illustrations 
 by J. BERNARD PARTRIDGE. Post 410. $s. 
 
 ARISTOTLE. THE WORKS OF. 
 The Politics: G. Bekker's Greek 
 
 Text of Books I. III. IV. (VII.), with an 
 English Translation by W. E. BOLLAND, 
 M.A. ; and short Introductory Essays by 
 A. LANG, M.A. Crown Svo. Js. 6d. 
 
 The Politics : Introductory Essays. 
 
 /By ANDREW LANG. (From Bolland and 
 Lang's 'Politics'.) Crown Svo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 The Ethics: Greek Text, Illustrated 
 
 with Essays and Notes. By Sir ALEXAN- 
 DER GRANT, Bart. 2 vols. Svo. 32^. 
 
 The Nicomachean Ethics: Newly 
 
 Translated into English. By ROBERT 
 WILLIAMS. Crown Svo. 75. 6d. 
 
 ARMSTRONG (G. F. Savage-) 
 
 WORKS BY. 
 Poems : Lyrical and Dramatic. Fcp. 
 
 Svo. 6s. 
 King Saul. (The Tragedy of Israel, 
 
 Part I.) Fcp. Svo. 5-r. 
 
 King David. (The Tragedy of 
 
 Israel, Part II.) Fcp. Svo. 65. 
 
 King Solomon. (The Tragedy of 
 
 Israel, Part III.) Fcp. Svo. 6s. 
 
 Ugone : A Tragedy. Fcp. Svo. 6s. 
 A Garland from Greece ; Poems. 
 
 Fcp. Svo. js. 6d. 
 
 Stories of Wicklow ; Poems. 
 
 Fcp. Svo. js. 6d . 
 
 Mephistopheles in Broadcloth: 
 
 a Satire. Fcp. Svo. 4-r. 
 
 One in the Infinite ; a Poem. 
 
 Crown Svo. "js. 6d. 
 
 The Life and Letters of Edmund 
 J. Armstrong. Fcp. Svo. -js. 6d. 
 ARMSTRONG (E. J.) WORKS BY. 
 Poetical Works. Fcp. Svo. $s. 
 Essays and Sketches. Fcp. Svo. 5*. 
 
 ARMSTRONG. Elizabeth Far- 
 
 nese : the Termagant of Spain. 
 By EDWARD ARMSTRONG, Queen's Col- 
 lege, Oxford. Svo. i6s. 
 
 ARNOLD (Sir Edwin, K.C.I. E.) 
 
 WORKS BY. 
 The Light of the World; or, 
 
 the Great Consummation. A Poem. 
 Crown Svo. Js. 6d. net. 
 
 Seas and Lands. Reprinted letters 
 
 from the ' Daily Telegraph '. With 
 71 Illustrations. Crown 8vo. js. 6d. 
 
 Potiphar's Wife, and other Poems. 
 
 Crown Svo. $s. net. 
 ARNOLD (Dr. T.) WORKS BY. 
 
 Introductory Lectures on Mo- 
 dern History. Svo. -js. 6d. 
 
 Miscellaneous Works. Svo. js.6d. 
 
 ASHLEY. English EconomicHis- 
 
 tory and Theory. By W. J. 
 
 ASHLEY, M.A. Part I. The Middle 
 Ages. 55. 
 
 Atelier (The) du Lys ; or, An Art 
 
 Student in the Reign of Terror. By the 
 Author of ' Mademoiselle Mori '. Crown 
 Svo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 BY THE SAME AUTHOR. 
 
 Mademoiselle Mori: a Tale of 
 
 Modern Rome. Crown Svo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 That Child. Illustrated by GORDON 
 BROWNE. Crown Svo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 [Continued on next page.
 
 PUBLISHED BY MESSRS. LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO. 
 
 Atelier (The) du Lys WORKS BY 
 
 THE A UTHOR OF continued. 
 Under a Cloud. Cr. 8vo. 2s. 6d. 
 The Fiddler of Lugau. With 
 
 Illustrations by W. RALSTON. Crown 
 8vo. 2s. 6</. 
 
 A Child of the Revolution. 
 
 With Illustrations by C. J. STAMLAND. 
 Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 Hester's Venture : a Novel. Cr. 
 
 8vo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 In the Olden Time : a Tale of the 
 
 Peasant War in Germany. Cr. 8vo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 The Younger Sister : a Tale. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 BACON. THE WORKS AND LIFE 
 OF. 
 
 Complete Works. Edited by R. 
 L. ELLIS, J. SPEDDING, and D. D. 
 HEATH. 7 vols. 8vo. ^3 135. 6d. 
 
 Letters and Life, including all 
 his Occasional Works. Edited 
 
 by J. SPEDDING. 7 vols. 8vo. ,4 41. 
 
 The Kssays ; with Annotations. 
 By RICHARD WHATELY, D.D., 8vo. 
 i or. 6d. 
 
 The Essays ; with Introduction, 
 Notes, and Index. By E. A. ABBOTT, 
 D.D. 2 vols. fcp. 8vo. price 6s. Text 
 and Index only, without Introduction 
 and Notes, in i vol. Fcp. 8vo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 The BADMINTON LIBRARY, 
 
 Edited by the DUKE OF BEAUFORT, K.G., 
 assisted by ALFRED E. T. WATSON. 
 
 Hunting. By the DUKE OF BEAU- 
 FORT, K.G., and MOWBRAY MORRIS. 
 \Vith 53 Illus. by J. Sturgess, J. Charlton, 
 and A. M. Biddulph. Cr. 8vo. icw. 6d. 
 
 Fishing. By H. CHOLMONDELEY- 
 
 PENNELL. 
 Vol. I. Salmon, Trout, and Grayling. 
 
 With 158 Illustrations. Cr. 8vo. los. 6d. 
 Vol. II. Pike and other Coarse Fish. 
 
 With 132 Illustrations. Cr. 8vo. IDJ. 6d. 
 
 Racing and Steeplechasing. By 
 
 the EARL OF SUFFOLK AND BERKSHIRE, 
 W. G. CRAVEN, &c. With 56 Illustra- 
 tions by J. Sturgess. Cr. 8vo. icw. 6d. 
 
 Shooting. By LORD WALSINGHAM 
 and Sir RALPH PAYNE-GALLWEY, Bart. 
 
 Vol. I. Field and Covert. With 105 
 Illustrations. Cr. 8vu. lor. 6J. 
 
 Vol. II. Moor and Marsh. With 65 Illus- 
 trations. Cr. 8vo. lew. 6d. 
 
 Cycling. By VISCOUNT BURY 
 (Earl of Albemarle), K.C.M.G., and G. 
 LACY HILLIER. With 19 Plates and 70 
 Woodcuts, &c., by Viscount Bury, Joseph 
 Pennell, &c. Crown 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 The BADMINTON LIBRARY- 
 
 continued. 
 
 Athletics and Football. By 
 
 MONTAGUE SHEARMAN. With 6 full- 
 page Illustrations and 45 Woodcuts, &c., by 
 Stanley Berkeley, and from Photographs 
 by G. Mitchell. Crown 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 Boating. By W B. WOODGATE. 
 
 With lofull-pagelllustrationsand 39 wood- 
 cuts, &c., in the Text. Cr. 8vo. los. (>d. 
 
 Cricket. By A. G. STEEL and the 
 Hon. R. H. LYTTELTON, With 1 1 full-page 
 Illustrations and 52 Woodcuts, &c., in the 
 Text, by Lucien Davis. Cr. 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 Driving. By the DUKE OF BEAU- 
 FORT. With 1 1 Plates and 54 Woodcuts, 
 &c., by J. Sturgess and G. D. Giles. 
 Crown 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 Fencing, Boxing, and Wrest- 
 ling. By WALTER H. POLLOCK, 
 F. C. GROVE. C. PREVOST, E. B. Mi- 
 CHELL, and WALTER ARMSTRONG. With 
 1 8 Plates and 24 Woodcuts, &c. Crown 
 Svo. los. 6d. 
 
 Golf. By HORACE HUTCHINSON, the 
 Rt. Hon. A. J. BALFOUR, M.P., ANDREW 
 LANG, Sir W. G. SIMPSON, Bart., &c. 
 With 19 Plates and 69 Woodcuts, &c. 
 Crown 8vo. IQS-. 6d. 
 
 Tennis, Lawn Tennis, Rackets, 
 and Fives. By J. M. and C. G. 
 
 HEATHCOTE, E. O. PLEYDELL-BOU- 
 VERIF, and A. C. AINGER. With 12 
 Plates and 67 Woodcuts, &c. Crown 
 Svo. los. 6af. 
 
 Riding and Polo. By Captain 
 ROBERT WEIR, Riding Master, R.H.G., 
 and J. MORAY BROWN, the DUKE OF 
 BEAUFORT, K.G., the EARL of SUFFOLK 
 and BERKSHIRE, &c. With 18 Plates and 
 41 Woodcuts, &c. Crown Svo. los. fxl. 
 
 Skating, Curling, Tobogganing, 
 and other Ice Sports. By J. M. 
 
 HEATHCOTE, C. G. TEBBUTT, T. MAX- 
 WELL WITHAM, the Kev. JOHN KERR, 
 ORMOND HAKE, and Colonel BUCK. 
 With 12 Plates and 272 Woodcuts. Cr. 
 Svo. ioj. 6d. 
 
 Mountaineering. By C. T. DENT, 
 
 Sir F. POLLOCK, Bart., W. M. CONWAY, 
 DOUGLAS FRESHFIELD, C. E. MATHEWS, 
 C. PILKINGTON, and other Writers. 
 With Illustrations by H. G. WILLINK. 
 
 B AGE HOT (Walter}. WORKS BY. 
 
 Biographical Studies. 8vo. i2s. 
 Economic Studies. 8vo. 105. 6d. 
 Literary Studies. 2 vols. 8vo. 285-. 
 The Postulates of English Po- 
 litical Economy. Cr. 8vo. 2s. 6d.
 
 A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS IN GENERAL LITERATURE 
 
 BAGWELL. Ireland under the, 
 Tudors. By RICHARD BAG- , 
 
 WELL. (3 vols.) Vo!s. I. and II. 
 From the first invasion of the Northmen 
 to the year 1578. 8vo. 32^. Vol. III. 
 1578-1603. 8vo. i&r. 
 
 BAIN (Alexander}. WORKS BY. 
 
 Mental and Moral Science. Cr. 
 
 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 Senses and the Intellect. 8vo. 15*. 
 Emotions and the Will. 8vo. 1 5*. 
 Logic, Deductive, and Inductive. 
 
 PART I., 4J. PART II., 6s. 6d. 
 Practical Essays. Cr. 8vo. 2s. 
 
 BAKER (Sir S. W.). WORKS BY. 
 Eight Years in Ceylon. With 6 
 
 Illustrations. Crown 8vo. y. 6d. 
 
 The Rifle and the Hound in Cey- 
 lon. 6 Illustrations. Cr. 8vo. y. 6d. 
 
 BALDWIN. Where Town and 
 Country Meet; a Novel. By Mrs. 
 ALFRED BALDWIN. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 BALL (The Rt. Hon. J. T.). WORKS. 
 The Reformed Church of Ire- 
 land. (1537-1889). 8vo. 7*. 6d. 
 Historical Review of the Legis- 
 lative Systems Operative in 
 Ireland, from the Invasion of 
 Henry the Second to the Union (1172- 
 1800). 8vo. 6s. 
 
 BARING-GOULD (Rev. S.). WORKS 
 BY. 
 
 ^ Curious Myths of the Middle 
 
 Ages. Crown 8vo. y. 6d. 
 Origin and Development of Re- 
 ligious Belief. 2 vols. 7^. 
 BEACONSFIELD (The Earl of}. 
 
 WORKS BY. 
 Novels and Tales. The Hughen- 
 
 den Edition. With 2 Portraits and II 
 
 Vignettes. 1 1 vols. Crown 8vo. 42^. 
 
 Endymion. Henrietta Temple. 
 
 Lothiar. Contarini, Fleming, &c. 
 
 Coningsby. Alroy, Ixion, &c. 
 
 Tancred. Sybil. The Young Duke, &c. 
 
 Venetia. Vivian Grey. 
 
 Novels and Tales. Cheap Edition. 
 
 Complete in 1 1 vols. Crown 8vo. is. 
 each, boards ; is. 6d. each, cloth. 
 
 BECKER (Professor). WORKS BY. 
 
 Gallus ; or, Roman Scenes in the 
 
 Time of Augustus. Post 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 Charicles ; or, Illustrations of the 
 
 Private Life of the Ancient Greeks. Post 
 8vo. 7s. 6d. 
 
 BELL (A//*. Hufjlt}. WORKS BY. 
 Chamber Comedies : a Collection 
 
 / of Plays and M oriologues for the Drawing 
 Room. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 Nursery Comedies : Twelve Tiny 
 
 Plays for Children. Fcap. 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 BLAKE. Tables for the Conver- 
 sion of 5 per Cent. Interest 
 from T V to 7 per Cent. By J. 
 
 BLAKE, of the London Joint Stock Bank, 
 Limited. Svo. 12s. 6d. 
 
 Book (The) of Wedding Days. 
 
 Arranged on the Plan of a Birthday Book. 
 With 96 Illustrated Borders, Frontispiece, 
 and Title-page by WALTER CRANE; and 
 Quotations for each Day. Compiled and 
 Arranged by K. E. J. REID, MAY Ross, 
 and MABEL BAMFIELD. 410. 2 is. 
 
 BR ASSET (Lady}. WORKS BY. 
 A Voyage in the ' Sunbeam,' our 
 Home on the Ocean for 
 Eleven Months. 
 
 Library Edition. With 8 Maps and 
 
 Charts, and 118 Illustrations, Svo. 21 s. 
 Cabinet Edition. With Map and 66 
 
 Illustrations, Crown Svo. "js. 6d. 
 'Silver Library' Edition. With 66 
 
 Illustrations. Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 Popular Edition. With 60 Illustrations, 
 
 4to. 6d. sewed, is. cloth. 
 School Edition. With 37 Illustrations, 
 
 Fcp. 2s. cloth, or 35. white parchment. 
 
 Sunshine and Storm in the East. 
 
 Library Edition. With 2 Maps and 
 114 Illustrations, Svo. 2IS. 
 
 Cabinet Edition. With 2 Maps and 
 114 Illustrations, Crown Svo. 75. 6d. 
 
 Popular Edition. With 103 Illustra- 
 tions, 410. 6d. sewed, is. cloth. 
 
 In the Trades, the Tropics, and 
 the ' Roaring Forties '. 
 
 Cabinet Edition. \Vith Map and 220 
 Illustrations, Crown Svo. "js. 6d. 
 
 Popular Edition. With 183 Illustra- 
 tions, 410. 6d. sewed, is. cloth. 
 
 The Last Voyage to India and 
 Australia in the 'Sunbeam'. 
 
 With Charts and Maps, and 40 Illustrations 
 in Monotone (20 full-page), and nearly 200 
 Illustrations in the Text from Drawings 
 by R. T. PRITCHETT. Svo. 2 is. 
 
 Three Voyages in the 'Sun- 
 beam*. Popular Edition. With 
 
 346 Illustrations, 410. 2s. 6<f. 
 
 BRA Y. The Philosophy of Neces- 
 sity ; or, Law in Mind as in Matter. 
 By CHARLES BRAY. Crown Svo. 55.
 
 PUBLISHED BY MESSRS. LONGMANS, GREEN, CO. 
 
 BRIGHT. A History of England. 
 
 By the Rev. J. FRANCK BRIGHT. D.D., 
 Master of University College, Oxford. 
 4 vols. Crown 8vo. 
 
 Period I. Mediaeval Monarchy: The De- 
 parture of the Romans to Richard III. 
 From A.D. 449 to 1485. 45. 6d. 
 
 Period II. Personal Monarchy : Henry VII. 
 to James II. From 1485 to 1688. 55. 
 
 Period III. Constitutional Monarchy: i 
 William and Mary to William IV. From I 
 1689 to 1837. 75. 6d. 
 
 Period IV. The Growth of Democracy : 
 Victoria. From 1837 to 1880. 6s. 
 
 BRYDEN. Kloof and Karroo : j 
 
 Sport, Legend, and Natural History in j 
 Cape Colony. By H. A. BRYDEN. With J 
 17 Illustrations. 8vo. IDS. 6d. 
 
 BUCKLE. History of Civilisation 
 in England and France, 
 Spain and Scotland. By HENRY 
 
 THOMAS BUCKLE. 3 vols. Cr. 8vo. 245. 
 BULL (Thomas). WORKS BY. 
 
 Hints to Mothers on the 
 Management of their Health 
 
 during the Period of Pregnancy. Fcp. 8vo. 
 is. 6d. 
 
 The Maternal Management of 
 Children in Health and Dis- 
 ease. Fcp. 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 BUTLER (Saimtel). WORKS BY. 
 Op. I. Erewhon. Crown 8vo. $s. 
 Op. 2. The Fair Haven. A Work 
 
 in defence of the Miraculous Element in 
 our Lord's Ministry. Crown 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 Op. 3. Life and Habit. An Essay 
 
 after a Completer View of Evolution. 
 Crown 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 Op. 4. Evolution, Old and New. 
 
 Crown 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 Op. 5. Unconscious Memory. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 Cp. 6. Alps and Sanctuaries of j 
 Piedmont and Canton Ticino. | 
 Illustrated. Pott 410. los. 6d. 
 
 Op. 7. Selections from Ops. 1-6. 
 
 With Remarks on Mr. ROMANES' 'Mental 
 Evolution in Animals '. Cr. 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 Op. 8. Luck, or Cunning, as the 
 Main Means of Organic 
 Modification ? Cr. 8vo. TS. 6d. 
 
 Op. 9. Ex Voto. An Account of 
 
 the Sacro Monte or New Jerusalem at 
 Varallo-Sesia. IDS. 6d. 
 
 Holbein's* La Danse'. A Note on 
 
 a Drawing called ' La Danse'. 35. 
 
 GARLYLE. Thomas Carlyle : a 
 
 History of His Life. By J. A. FROUDE. 
 I 795- I 835, 2 vols. Crown 8vo. js. 
 1834-188:, 2 vols. Crown 8vo. 75. 
 
 Last Words of Thomas Carlyle 
 
 Wotton Reinfred Excursion (Futile 
 enough) to Paris Letters to Varnhagen 
 von Ense, &c. Crown 8vo. 6s. 6d. net. 
 
 CASE. Physical Realism : being 
 
 an Analytical Philosophy from the Physical 
 Objects of Science to the Physical Data 
 of Sense. By THOMAS CASE, M.A., 
 Fellowand Senior Tutor, C.C.C. 8vo. 155. 
 
 CHETWYND. Racing Remini- 
 scences and Experiences of 
 the Turf. By Sir GEORGE CHET- 
 WYND, Bart. 2 vols. 8vo. 2is. 
 
 CHETWYND-STA PYLTON.-Chet- 
 wynds of Ingestre (The) : 
 
 being a History of that Family from a 
 very early Date. By H. E. CHETWYND- 
 STAPYLTON. With numerous Portraits 
 and Illustrations. 8vo. 14?. 
 
 CHILD. Church and State under 
 the Tudors. By GILBERT W. 
 CHILD, M.A. 8vo. 155. 
 
 CHILTON. The History of a 
 Failure, and other Tales. By E. 
 C HILTON. Fcp. 8vo. 3-r. 6<f. 
 
 GHISHOLM. Handbook of Com- 
 mercial Geography. By G. G. 
 
 CHISHOLM. New edition. With 29 Maps. 
 8vo. i os. net. 
 
 CHURCH. Sir Richard Church, 
 C.B., G.C.H. Commander-in- 
 Chief of the Greeks in the W r ar of Inde- 
 pendence : a Memoir. By STANLEY 
 LANF.-POOLE. With 2 Plans. 8vo. 55. 
 
 CLERKE. Familiar Studies in 
 Homer. By AGNES M. CLERKE. 
 
 Crown 8vo. "js. 6d. 
 
 CLODD.Tht Story of Creation : 
 
 a Plain Account of Evolution. By ED- 
 WARD CLODD. With 77 Illustrations. 
 Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 CLUTTERBUCK (W. J.}. WORKS 
 BY. 
 
 The Skipper in Arctic Seas. 
 
 With 39 Illustrations. Cr. 8vo. IDS. 6d. 
 
 About Ceylon and Borneo : 
 
 being an Account of Two Visits to Ceylon, 
 one to Borneo, and How we Fell Out on 
 our Homeward Journey. With 47 Illus- 
 trations. Crown 8vo. los. 6d.
 
 A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS IN GENERAL LITERATURE 
 
 COLENSO.The Pentateuch and 
 Book of Joshua Critically 
 Examined. By J. W. COLENSO, 
 
 D.D., late Bishop of Natal. Cr. 8vo. 6s. 
 
 COMYN. Atherstone Priory : a 
 
 Tale. By L. N. COMYN. Cr. 8vo. 2s. 6d. 
 CONINGTON (Jolm}. WORKS BY. 
 The -ineid of Virgil. Translated 
 
 into English Verse. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 The Poems of Virgil. Translated 
 
 into English Prose. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 COX. A General History of 
 Greece, from the Earliest Period 
 to the Death of Alexander the Great ; 
 with a sketch of the subsequent History 
 to the Present Time. By the Rev. Sir 
 G. W. Cox, Bart., M.A. With n Maps 
 and Plans. Crown 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 CRAKE (Rev. A. D.}. WORKS BY. 
 & Historical Tales. Crown 8vo. 5 
 
 vols. 2s. 6d. each. 
 
 Edwy the Fair; or, The First Chronicle 
 
 of ^Escendune. 
 Alfgar the Dane ; or, the Second 
 
 Chronicle of ^Escendune. 
 The Rival Heirs : being the Third and 
 
 Last Chronicle of ^Escendune. 
 The House of Walderne. A Tale of the 
 
 Cloister and the Forest in the Days of 
 
 the Barons' Wars. 
 Brian Fitz-Count. A Story of Walling- 
 
 ford Castle and Dorchester Abbey. 
 
 History of the Church under 
 the Roman Empire, A.D. 
 30-476. Crown 8vo. 7$. 6d. 
 
 GREALOCK. Deer-Stalking in 
 the Highlands of Scotland. By 
 
 the late Lieutenant-General H. H. CREA- 
 LOCK. Edited by his brother, Major- 
 General JOHN NORTH CREALOCK. With 
 36 full-page Plates reproduced in autotype, 
 and numerous Illustrations in the Text. 
 Royal 4to. Six guineas net. 
 
 CREIGHTON. History of the 
 Papacy during the Reforma- 
 tion. BY MANDELL CREIGHTON, 
 
 D.D., LL.D., Bishop of Peterborough. 
 8vo. Vols. I. and II., 1378-1464, 325. ; 
 Vols. III. and IV. , 1464-1518, 245. 
 
 CRUMP (A.). WORKS BY. 
 
 A Short Enquiry into the For- 
 mation of Political Opinion, 
 
 from the reign of the Great Families to 
 the Advent of Democracy. 8vo. 7s. 6d. 
 
 CRUMP (A.). WORKS EY.cont. 
 An Investigation into the Causes 
 of the Great Fall in Prices 
 
 which took place coincidently with the 
 Demonetisation of Silver bv Germany. 
 8vo. 6s. 
 
 CUDWORTH.An Introduction 
 to Cudworth's Treatise con- 
 cerning Eternal and Immu- 
 table Morality. By W. R. 
 
 SCOTT. Crown 8vo. 3s. 
 
 CURZON. Persia and the Per- 
 sian Question. By the Hon. 
 
 GEORGE N. CUR/.ON, M.P., late Fellow 
 of All Souls College, Oxford, Author of 
 'Russia in Central Asia'. With 9 Maps, 
 96 Illustrations, Appendices, and an Index. 
 2 vols. 8vo. 42.?. 
 
 DAXTE.'La. Commedia di Dante. 
 
 A New Text, carefully Revised with 
 the aid of the most recent Editions and 
 Collations. Small 8vo. 6s. 
 
 DA VIDSON ( W. L.}. WORKS BY. 
 The Logic of Definition Ex- 
 plained and Applied. Cr. 8vo. 6s. 
 Leading and Important English 
 Words Explained and Ex- 
 emplified. Fcp. 8vo. 3-y. 6d. 
 
 Dead Shot (The) ; or, Sportman's 
 Complete Guide. Being a Treatise on the 
 Use of the Gun, with Rudimentary and 
 Finishing Lessons on the Art of Shooting 
 Game of all kinds, also Game Driving, 
 Wild - Fowl and Pigeon Shooting, Dog 
 Breaking, &c. By MARKSMAN. Sixth 
 Edition, Revised and Enlarged. Crown 
 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 DEL AND (Mrs.}. WORKS BY. 
 John Ward, Preacher : a Story. 
 
 Crown Svo. 2s. boards, 2s. 6d. cloth. 
 Sidney : a Novel. Crown 8vo. 6s. , 
 The Old Garden, and other Verses. 
 
 Fcp. Svo. 55. 
 
 DELA SAUSSAYE.A Manual of 
 the Science of Religion. By 
 
 Professor CHANTEPIE DE LA SAUSSAYE. 
 Translated by Mrs. COLYER FERGUSSON 
 (nee MAX MULLF.R). Revised by the 
 Author. Crown Svo. 12s. 6d . 
 
 DE REDCLIFFKThe Life of the 
 Right Hon. Stratford Can- 
 ning: Viscount Stratford De 
 Redcliffe. By STANLEY LANB- 
 
 POOLE. Crown Svo. js. 6d.
 
 PUBLISHED BY MESSRS. LONGMANS, GREEN, A CO. 
 
 DE SALIS (Mrs.}. WORKS BY. 
 
 Cakes and Confections a la 
 Mode. Fcp. 8vo. 1 5-. 6d. 
 
 Dressed Game and Poultry a 
 la Mode. Fcp. 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 Dressed Vegetables a la Mode. 
 
 Fcp. 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 Drinks a la Mode. Fcp. 8vo. is.6d. 
 Entrees a la Mode. Fcp. 8vo. 
 
 is. 6d. I 
 
 Floral Decorations. Suggestions 
 
 and Descriptions. Fcap. 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 New- Laid Eggs : Hints for Ama- 
 teur Poultry Rearers. Fcp. 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 Oystersala Mode. Fcp. 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 Puddings and Pastry a la Mode. 
 
 Fcp. 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 Savouries a la Mode. Fcp. 8vo. 
 
 is. 6d. 
 
 Soups and Dressed Fish a la 
 Mode. Fcp. 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 Sweets and Supper Dishes a la 
 Mode. Fcp. 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 Tempting Dishes for Small 
 Incomes. Fcp. 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 Wrinkles and Notions for every 
 Household. Crown 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 DE TOCQUEVILLE. Democracy 
 in America. By ALEXIS DE 
 
 TOCQUEVILLF.. 2 vols. Crown 8vo. i6s. 
 
 Dorothy Wallis : an Autobiography. 
 With Preface by WALTER BESANT. Crown 
 8vo. 6s. 
 
 DOUGALL. Beggars All : a Novel. 
 
 By L. DOUGALL. Crown 8vo. 3-r. 6d. 
 
 DOWELL.A History of Taxa- 
 tion and Taxes in England 
 
 from the Earliest Times to the Year 1885. 
 By STEPHEN DOWELL. (4 vols. 8vo.) 
 Vols. I. and II. The History of Taxation, 
 215. Vols. III. and IV. The History of 
 Taxes, 215. 
 
 DOYLE (A. Gonan). WORKS BY. 
 Micah Clarke. A tale of Mon- 
 
 mouth's Rebellion. With Frontispiece 
 and Vignette. Crown 8vo. 3$. 6d. 
 
 The Captain of the Polestar; 
 
 and other Tales. Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 DRANE.The History of St. 
 Dominic. By AUGUSTA THEO- 
 DORA DRANE. 32 Illustrations. 8vo. 151. 
 
 Dublin University Press Series 
 (The) : a Series of Works under- 
 taken by the Provost and Senior Fellows 
 of Trinity College, Dublin. 
 
 Abbott's (T. K.) Codex Rescriptus Dub- 
 linensis of St. Matthew. 410. 2 is. 
 
 - Evangeliorum Versio Ante- 
 hieronymiana ex Codice Usseriano 
 
 (Dublinensi). 2 vols. Crown 8vo. 2is. 
 
 Short Notes on St. Paul's 
 
 Epistles to the Romans, Corinthians, 
 Galatians, Ephesians, and Philippians. 
 Fcp. 8vo. 4-r. 
 
 Allman's (G. J.) Greek Geometry from 
 Thales to Euclid. 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 Burnside (W. S.) and Panton's (A. W.) 
 Theory of Equations. 8vo. 125. 6d. 
 
 Casey's (John) Sequel to Euclid's Ele- 
 ments. Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 - Analytical Geometry of the 
 Conic Sections. Crown 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 Davies' (J. F. ) Eumenides of ^schylus. 
 With Metrical English Translation. 8vo. 
 75. 
 
 Dublin Translations into Greek and 
 Latin Verse. Edited by R. Y. Tyrrell. 
 8vo. 65. 
 
 Graves' (R. P.) Life of Sir William 
 Hamilton. 3 vols. 155. each. 
 
 Addendum to the Life of Sir 
 William Rowan Hamilton, LL.D., 
 D.C.L. 8vo. 6d. sewed. 
 
 Griffin (R. W.) on Parabola, Ellipse, 
 and Hyperbola. Crown 8vo. 65. 
 
 Hobart's (W. K.) Medical Language of 
 St. Luke. 8vo. i6s. 
 
 Leslie's (T. E. Cliffe) Essays in Politi- 
 cal Economy. 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 Macalister's (A.) Zoology and Mor- 
 phology of Vertebrata. 8vo. IDS. 6d. 
 
 MacCullagh's (James) Mathematical 
 and other Tracts. 8vo. 155. 
 
 Maguire's (T.) Parmenides of Plato, 
 Text, with Introduction, Analysis, &c. 
 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 Monck's (W. H. S.) Introduction to 
 Logic. Crown 8vo. 55. 
 
 Roberts' (R. A.) Examples on the Ana- 
 lytic Geometry of Plane Conies. Cr. 
 8vo. 55. 
 
 Southey's (R.) Correspondence with 
 Caroline Bowles. Edited by E. Dow- 
 den. 8vo. 145. 
 
 [Continued on next page.
 
 A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS IN GENERAL LITERATURE 
 
 Dublin University Press Series 
 (The). continued. 
 
 Stubbs' (J. W.) History of the University 
 of Dublin, from its Foundation to the End 
 of the Eighteenth Century. 8vo. 125. 6d. 
 
 Thornhill's (W. J.) The^neid of Virgil, 
 freely translated into English Blank 
 Verse. Crown 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 Tyrrell's (R. Y.) Cicero's Correspon- 
 dence. Vols. I. II. III. 8vo. each 12s. 
 - The Acharnians of Aristo- 
 X> phanes, translated into English Verse. 
 Crown 8vo. is. 
 
 Webb's (T. E.) Goethe's Faust, Trans- 
 lation and Notes. 8vo. 125. 6d. 
 
 The Veil of I sis : a Series ot 
 
 Essays on Idealism. 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 Wilkins' (G.) The Growth of the Ho- 
 
 merle Poems. 8vo. 6s. 
 
 Epochs of Modern History. 
 
 Edited by C. COLBECK, M.A. 19 vols. 
 Fcp. 8vo. with Maps, 2s. 6d. each. 
 *.* List will be sent on application. 
 
 Epochs of Church History. Ed- 
 ited by MANDELL CREIGHTON, D.D., 
 Bishop of Peterborough. 15 vols. Fcp. 
 8vo. 25. 6d. each. 
 %* List will be sent on application. 
 
 Epochs of Ancient History. 
 
 Edited by the Rev. Sir G. W. Cox, 
 
 Bart., M.A., and by C. SANKEY, M.A. 
 
 10 volumes, Fcp. 8vo. with Maps, 2s. 6d. 
 
 each. 
 
 %* List will be sent on application. 
 
 Epochs of American History. 
 
 Edited by Dr. ALBERT BUSHNELL HART, 
 Assistant Professor of History in Harvard 
 College. 
 
 THWAITES (R. G.}. The Colo- 
 hies (1492-1763). Fcp. 8vo. 
 
 35. 6d. 
 
 *+* Others in preparation. 
 
 Epochs of English History. 
 
 Complete in One Volume, with 27 Tables 
 and Pedigrees, and 23 Maps. Fcp. 8vo. 
 
 5*. 
 
 *,* For details of Parts see Longmans & Co.'s 
 Catalogue of School Books. 
 
 EWALD (Heinricli). WORKS BY. 
 
 The Antiquities of Israel. Trans- 
 lated from the German by H. S. SOLLY, 
 M.A. 8vo. 125. 6d. 
 
 The History of Israel. Trans- 
 lated from the German. 8 vols. 8vo. 
 Vols. I. and II. 245. Vols. III. and IV. 
 215. Vol. V. i8s. Vol. VI. i6s. Vol. 
 VII. 2is. Vol. VIII., with Index to the 
 Complete Work, 185. 
 
 FALKENER. Games, Ancient 
 and Oriental, and how to play 
 them. Being the Games of the 
 
 Ancient Egyptians, the Hiera Gramme of 
 the Greeks, the Ludus Latrunculorum of 
 the Romans, ami the Oriental Games of 
 Chess, Draughts, Backgammon, and Magic 
 Squares. By EDWARD FALKENER. With 
 numerous Photographs, Diagrams, &c. 8vo. 
 
 2IS. 
 
 FARNELL.Grz&s. Lyric Poetry: 
 
 a Complete Collection of the Surviving 
 Passages from the Greek Song- Writers. 
 Arranged with Prefatory Articles, Intro- 
 ductory Matter, and Commentary. By 
 GEORGE S. FARNELL, M.A. With 5 
 Plates. 8vo. i6s. 
 
 FARRAR( Yen. Archdeacon}. WORKS 
 BY. 
 
 Darkness and Dawn ; or, Scenes 
 
 in the Days of Nero. An Historic Tale. 
 Crown 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 Language and Languages. A 
 
 Revised Edition of Chapters on Language 
 and Families of Speech. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 FITZPATRICK. Secret Service 
 under Pitt. By W. J. FITZPATRICK, 
 F.S.A., Author of 'Correspondence of 
 Daniel O'Connell '. 8vo. 14^. 
 
 FITZWYGRAM. -- Horses and 
 Stables. By Major-General Sir 
 F. FITZWYGRAM, Bart. With 19 pages 
 of Illustrations. 8vo. 55. 
 
 FORD. The Theory and Practice 
 of Archery. By the late HORACE 
 
 FORD. New Edition, thoroughly Re- 
 vised and Re-written by W. BUTT, M.A. 
 With a Preface by C. J. LONGMAN, M. A., 
 F.S.A. 8vo. 145. 
 
 FOUARD. The Christ the Son of 
 
 God : a Life of our Lord and Sa- 
 viour Jesus Christ. By the Abbe^ CON- 
 STANT FOUARD. With an Introduction 
 by Cardinal MANNING. 2 vols. Crown 
 8vo. 145. 
 
 FOX. The Early History of 
 Charles James Fox. By the 
 
 Right Hon. Sir G. O. TREVELYAN, Bart. 
 
 Library Edition, 8vo. i8s. 'r'\-,k"'~ 
 
 S Cabinet Edition, Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 FRANCIS. A Book on Angling; 
 
 or, Treatise on the Art of Fishing in 
 every branch ; including full Illustrated 
 List of Salmon Flies. By FRANCIS 
 FRANCIS. With Portrait and Coloured 
 Plates. Crown 8vo. 15$.
 
 PUBLISHED BY MESSRS. LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO. 
 
 FREEMAN. The Historical Geo- 
 graphy of Europe. By E. A 
 
 FREEMAN. With 65 Maps. 2 vols. 8vo. 
 3 is. 6d. 
 
 FROUDE (James A.}. WORKS BY. 
 The History of England, from 
 
 the Fall of Wolsey to the Defeat of the 
 Spanish Armada. 12 vols. Crown 8vo. 
 35. 6d. each. 
 
 The Divorce of Catherine of 
 Aragon ; the Story as told by the 
 
 Imperial Ambassadors resident at the 
 Court of Henry VIII. In nsnm Lai- 
 corum. 8vo. l6s. 
 
 Short Studies on Great Sub- 
 jects. Cabinet Edition, 4 vols. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 245. Cheap Edition, 4 vols. 
 Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. each. 
 
 Caesar : a Sketch. Crown 8vo. 3*. 
 
 6d. 
 
 The English in Ireland in the 
 Eighteenth Century. 3 vols. 
 
 Crown 8vo. iSs. 
 
 Oceana; or, England and her 
 Colonies. With 9 Illustrations 
 Crown 8vo. 2s. boards, 2s. 6d. cloth. 
 
 The English in the West Indies ; 
 
 or, the Bow of Ulysses. With 9 Illus- 
 trations. Crown 8vo. 2s. boards, as. 6d. 
 cloth. 
 
 The Two Chiefs of Dunboy ; 
 
 an Irish Romance of the Last Century. 
 Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Thomas Carlyle, a History of his 
 
 Life. 1795 to 1835. 2 vols. Crown 8vo. 
 75. 1834 to 1881. 2 vols. Crown 8vo. "js. 
 
 The Spanish Story of the Ar- 
 mada, and other Essays, Histo- 
 rical and Descriptive. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 G ALL WEY. Letters to Young 
 Shooters. (First Series.) On 
 the Choice and Use of a Gun. By Sir 
 RALPH PAYNE- GALLWEY, Bart. With 
 Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 GARDINER (Samuel Rawsori). 
 
 WORKS BY. 
 History of England, from the 
 
 Accession of James I. to the Outbreak 
 of the Civil War, 1603-1642. 10 vols. 
 Crown Svo. price 6s. each. 
 
 A History of the Great Civil 
 War, 1642-1649. (3 vols.) Vol. 
 
 I. 1642-1644. With 24 Maps. Svo. 
 (out of print). Vol. II. 1644- 164 '/. 
 With 21 Maps. Svo. 245. Vol. III. 
 1647-1649. With 8 Maps. Svo. 28j. 
 
 GARDINER (Samuel Rawson). 
 WORKS BY .continued. 
 
 The Student's History of Eng- 
 land. Vol. I. B.C. 55 A.D. 1509, 
 
 with 173 Illustrations. Crown Svo. 45. 
 Vol. II. 1509-1689, with 96 Illustrations. 
 Crown Svo. 45. Vol. III. (1689-1865). 
 With 109 Illustrations. Crown Svo. 45. 
 Complete in i vol. With 378 Illustra- 
 tions. Crown Svo. I2s. 
 
 A School Atlas of English His- 
 tory. With 66 Maps and 22 Plans 
 of Battles, &c. Fcap. 410. 5^. 
 
 GIJBERNE. Nigel Browning. By 
 
 AGNES GIBERNE. Crown Svo. 5J-. 
 
 GOETHE. Faust. A New Transla- 
 tion chiefly in Blank Verse ; with Intro- 
 duction and Notes. By JAMES ADEY 
 BIRDS. Crown Svo. 6s. 
 Faust. The Second Part. A New 
 Translation in Verse. By JAMES ADEY 
 BIRDS. Crown Svo. 6s. 
 
 GREEN. The Works of Thomas 
 Hill Green. Edited by R. L. 
 NETTLESHIP. (3 vols.) Vols. I. and II. 
 Philosophical Works. Svo. i6s. each. 
 Vol. III. Miscellanies. With Index to 
 the three Volumes and Memoir. Svo. 2is. 
 
 The Witness of God and Faith : 
 
 Two Lay Sermons. By T. H. GREEN. 
 Fcp. Svo. 25. 
 
 GREVILLE.A Journal of the 
 Reigns of King George IV., 
 King "William IV., and Queen 
 Victoria. By C. C. F. GREVILLB. 
 
 8 vols. Crown Svo. 6s. each. 
 
 GWILT. An Encyclopaedia of 
 Architecture. By JOSEPH GWILT, 
 
 F.S. A. Illustrated with more than 1700 
 Engravings on Wood. Svo. 52s. 6d. 
 
 HAGGARD. Life and its Author: 
 
 an Essay in Verse. By ELLA HAGGARD. 
 With a Memoir by H. RIDER HAGGARD, 
 and Portrait. Fcp. Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 HAGGARD (H. Rider). WORKS BY. 
 
 She. With 32 Illustrations by M. 
 GRKIFFENHAGEN and C. H. M. KERR. 
 Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Allan Quatermain. With 31 Illus- 
 trations by C. H. M. KERR. Crown Svo. 
 35. 6rf. 
 
 Maiwa's Revenge ; or, The War 
 
 of the Little Hand. Crown Svo. is. 
 boards; is. 6d. cloth. 
 
 Colonel Quaritch, V.C. A Novel. 
 
 Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 [Continued on next page.
 
 A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS IN GENERAL LITERATURE 
 
 HAGGARD (H. Rider.} WORKS BY. 
 
 continued. 
 Cleopatra. With 29 Full-page 
 
 Illustrations by M. Greiffenhagen and 
 R. Caton Woodville. Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Beatrice. A Novel. Cr. 8vo. 3^. 6d. 
 
 Eric Brighteyes. With 1 7 Plates 
 
 and 34 Illustrations in the Text by 
 LANCELOT SPEED. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 Nada the Lily. With 23 Illustra- 
 tions by C. H. M. KERR. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 HAGGARD and LANG. The 
 World's Desire. By H. RIDER 
 
 ^- HAGGARD and ANDREW LANG. Crown 
 Svo. 6s. 
 
 HALL I WELL - PHILLIPPS. A 
 Calendar of the Halliwell- 1 
 Phillipps' collection of Shake- 
 spearean Rarities. Enlarged 
 
 by ERNEST E. BAKER, F. S.A. Svo. | 
 IDS. 6d. 
 
 HARRISON. Myths of the Odys- 
 sey in Art and Literature. 
 
 Illustrated with Outline Drawings. By 
 JANE E. HARRISON. Svo. iSs. 
 
 HARRISON. The Contemporary 
 History of the French Revo- ' 
 
 lution, compiled from the 'Annual j 
 Register '. By F. BAYFORD HARRISON, j 
 Crown Svo. 3s. 6d. 
 
 HARRISON. Cookery for Busy 
 Lives and Small Incomes. By 
 
 MARY HARRISON. Fcp. Svo. is. 
 HARTE (Bret}. WORKS BY. 
 In the Carquinez Woods. Fcp. 
 
 Svo. is. boards ; is. 6d. cloth. 
 
 On the Frontier. i6mo. is. 
 By Shore and Sedge. i6mo. is. 
 
 HARTWIG (Dr.}. WORKS BY. 
 The Sea and its Living Wonders. 
 
 With 12 Plates and 303 Woodcuts. Svo. 
 7s. net. 
 
 The Tropical World. With 8 
 
 Plates and 172 Woodcuts. Svo. 75. net. 
 
 The Polar World. With 3 Maps, | 
 
 8 Plates and 85 Woodcuts. Svo. 75. net. 
 
 The Subterranean World. With 
 
 3 Maps and So Woodcuts. Svo. /s. net. 
 
 The Aerial World. With Map, 
 
 8 Plates and 60 Woodcuts. Svo. "js. net. 
 
 HA VELOCK. Memoirs of Sir 
 Henry Havelock, K.C.B. By 1 
 
 JOHN CLARK MARSHMAN. Crown Svo. 
 
 HEARN(W. Edward). WORKS BY. 
 The Government of England: 
 
 its Structure and its Development. Svo. 
 i6s. 
 
 The Aryan Household : its Struc- 
 ture and its Development. An Introduc- 
 tion to Comparative Jurisprudence. Svo. 
 1 6s. 
 
 HISTORIC TOWNS. Edited by 
 E. A. FREEMAN, D.C.L., and Rev. 
 WILLIAM HUNT, M.A. With Maps and 
 Plans. Crown Svo. 35. 6d. each. 
 
 Bristol. By Rev. W. HUNT. 
 Carlisle. ByRev.MANDELLCREiGH- 
 
 TON. 
 
 Cinque Ports. By MONTAGU 
 BURROWS. 
 
 Colchester. By Rev. E. L. CUTTS. 
 
 Exeter. By E. A. FREEMAN. 
 
 London. By Rev. W. J. LOFTIE. 
 
 Oxford. By Rev. C. W. BOASE. 
 
 Winchester. By Rev. G. W. KIT- 
 CHIN, D.D. 
 
 New York. By THEODORE ROOSE- 
 VELT. 
 
 Boston (U.S.). By HENRY CABOT 
 LODGE. 
 
 York. By Rev. JAMES RAINE. 
 
 HODGSON (Shadwwth H.}. WORKS 
 BY. 
 
 Time and Space : a Metaphysical 
 
 Essay. Svo. i6s. 
 
 The Theory of Practice : an 
 
 Ethical Enquiry. 2 vols. Svo. 245. 
 
 The Philosophy of Reflection: 
 
 2 VOls. SvO. 2 IS. 
 
 Outcast Essays and Verse 
 Translations. Essays : The 
 
 Genius of De Quincey De Quincey as 
 Political Economist The Supernatural 
 in English Poetry ; with Note on the 
 True Symbol of Christian Union Eng- 
 lish Verse. Verse Translations : Nineteen 
 Passages from Lucretius, Horace, Homer, 
 &c. Crown Svo. 8s. 6d. 
 
 HOOPER. Abraham Fabert : 
 
 Governor of Sedan, Marshall of France. 
 His Life and Times, 1599-1662. By 
 GEORGE HOOPER. With a Portrait. Svo. 
 IDS. 6d. 
 
 HO WITT. Visits to Remarkable 
 Places, Old Halls, Battle-Fields, 
 
 Scenes, illustrative of Striking Passages 
 in English History and Poetry. By 
 WILLIAM HOWITT. With So Illustra- 
 tions. Crown Svo. 3s. 6d.
 
 PUBLISHED BY MESSRS. LONGMANS, GREEN, <t- CO. 
 
 HULLAH (John}. WORKS BY. 
 
 Course of Lectures on the His- 
 tory of Modern Music. 8vo. 
 
 85. 6d. 
 
 Course of Lectures on the Tran- 
 sition Period of Musical His- 
 tory. Svo. los. 6d. 
 
 HUME. --The Philosophical Works 
 of David Hume. Edited by T. 
 
 H. GREEN and T. H. GROSE. 4 vols. 
 Svo. 565. Or Separately, Essays, 2 vols. 
 285. Treatise of Human Nature. 2 vols. 
 285. 
 
 HUTOHINSON. Famous Golf 
 Links. By HORACE G. HUTCHIN- 
 SON, ANDREW LANG, H. S. C. EVERARD, 
 T. RUTHERFORD CLARK, &c. With 
 numerous Illustrations by F. P. HOPKINS, 
 T. HODGES, H. S. KING, and from 
 Photographs. Crown Svo. 65. 
 
 HUTH.The Marriage of Near 
 Kin, considered with respect to 
 the Law of Nations, the Result of Ex- 
 perience, and the Teachings of Biology. 
 By ALFRED H. HUTH. Royal Svo. 2is. 
 
 INGELOW (Jean). WORKS BY. 
 Poetical Works. Vols. I. and II. 
 
 Fcp. Svo. 125. Vol. III. Fcp. Svo. 55. 
 
 Lyrical and other Poems. Se- 
 lected from the Writings of JEAN 
 INGELOW. Fcp. Svo. zs. 6d. cloth plain ; 
 35. cloth gilt. 
 
 Very Young and Quite Another 
 Story : Two Stories. Cr. Svo. 6s. 
 
 Investors' Review (The) (Quar- 
 terly). Edited by A. J. WILSON. Royal 
 Svo. $s. 
 
 JAMESON (Mrs.). WORKS BY. 
 Sacred and Legendary Art. With 
 
 19 Etchings and 187 Woodcuts. 2 vols. 
 Svo. 20J. net. 
 
 Legends of the Madonna. The 
 
 Virgin Mary as represented in Sacred 
 and Legendary Art. With 27 Etchings 
 and 165 Woodcuts. I vol. Svo. IDS. net. 
 
 Legends of the Monastic Orders. 
 
 With ii Etchings and 88 Woodcuts. I 
 vol. Svo. IDS. net. 
 
 History of Our Lord. His Types 
 
 and Precursors. Completed by Lady 
 EASTLAKE. With 31 Etchings and 281 
 Woodcuts. 2 vols. Svo. 205. net. 
 
 JEFFERIES (Richard). WORKS BY. 
 Field and Hedgerow : last Essays. 
 
 With Portrait. Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 The Story of My Heart: my 
 
 Autobiography. With Portrait and new 
 Preface by C. J. LONGMAN. Crown 
 Svo. 35. 6rf. 
 
 Red Deer. With 17 Illustrations 
 by J. CHAKLTOX and H. TUNALY. 
 Crown Svo. 3-r. 6d. 
 
 Wiltshire Labourers. With auto- 
 type reproduction <f bust of Richard 
 Jefferies. Crown Svo. 
 
 JENNINGS. Ecclesia Anglicana. 
 
 A History of the Church of Christ in 
 Kngland, from the Earliest to the Present 
 Times. By the Rev. ARTHUR CHARLES 
 JENNINGS, M.A. Crown Svo. 75. 6d. 
 
 JOHNSON. The Patentee's Man- 
 ual ; a Treatise on the Law and 
 
 Practice of Letters Patent. By J. JOHN- 
 SON and J. H. JOHNSON. Svo. los. 6d. 
 
 JORDAN (William Leighton).The 
 Standard of Value. By WILLIAM 
 LEIGHTON JORDAN. Svo. 65. 
 
 JUSTINIAN. The Institutes of 
 Justinian ; Latin Text, chiefly 
 
 that of Huschke, with English Introduc- 
 tion, Translation, Notes, and Summary. 
 By THOMAS C. SANDARS, M.A. Svo. 185. 
 
 KALISCH (M. M.}. WORKS BY. 
 Bible Studies. Part I. The Pro- 
 
 phecies of Balaam. Svo. IDS. 6d. Part 
 II. The Book of Jonah. Svo. IDS. 6d. 
 
 Commentary on the Old Testa- 
 ment ; with a New Translation. 
 Vol. I. Genesis, Svo. i8s. or adapted for 
 the General Reader, 125. Vol.11. Exodus, 
 155. or adapted for the General Reader, 
 I2s. Vol. III. Leviticus, Part I. 155. or 
 adapted for the General Reader, Si. 
 Vol. IV. Leviticus, Part II. 155. or 
 adapted for the General Reader, 8s. 
 
 KANT (Immanuel). WORKS BY. 
 
 Critique of Practical Reason, and 
 other Works on the Theory of 
 Ethics. Translated by T. K. Ab- 
 bott, B.D. With Memoir. Svo. I2s. 6d. 
 
 Introduction to Logic, and his 
 Essay on the Mistaken Sub- 
 tilty of the Four Figures. 
 
 Transit ed by T K. Abbott. Notes by 
 S. T. Coleridge. Svo. 6s. 
 
 KILLICK. Handbook to Mill's 
 System of Logic. By the Rev. 
 
 A. H. KILLICK, M.A. Crown Svo. 35. 6d.
 
 A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS IN GENERAL LITERATURE 
 
 KNIGHT (E. F.). WORKS BY. 
 The Cruise of the ' Alerte ' ; the 
 
 Narrative of a Search for Treasure on the 
 Desert Island of Trinidad. With 2 Maps 
 and 23 Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Save Me from my Friends: a 
 
 Novel. Crown 8vo. 65. 
 
 LADD (George T.}. WORKS BY. 
 
 Elements of Physiological Psy- 
 chology. 8vo. 2 is. 
 
 Outlines of Physiological Psy- 
 chology. A Text-book of Mental 
 Science for Academies and Colleges. 
 8vo. I2s. 
 
 LANG (Andrew}. WORKS BY. 
 Custom and Myth : Studies of 
 
 Early Usage and Belief. With 15 Illus- 
 trations. Crown 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 Ballads of Books. Edited by 
 ANDREW LANG. Fcp. 8vo. 6s. 
 
 Letters to 'Dead Authors. Fcp. 
 
 8vo. 2s. 6d. net. 
 
 Books and Bookmen. With 2 
 
 Coloured Plates and 17 Illustrations. 
 Fcp. 8vo. 2s. 6d. net. 
 
 ^ Old Friends. Fcp. 8vo. 2s. 6d. net. 
 
 Letters on Literature. Fcp. 8vo. 
 2s. 6d. net. 
 
 Grass of Parnassus. Fcp. 8vo. 
 
 -,* 2s. 6d. net. 
 
 Angling Sketches. With 20 Illus- 
 trations by W. G. Brown Murdoch. 
 Crown 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 The Blue Fairy Book. Edited by 
 
 ANDREW LANG. With 8 Plates and 130 
 Illustrations in the Text by H. J. Ford 
 and G. P. Jacomb Hood. Cr. 8vo. 6s. 
 
 The Red Fairy Book. Edited by 
 
 ANDREW LANG. With 4 Plates and 96 
 Illustrations in the Text by H. J. Ford 
 and Lancelot Speed. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 The Blue Poetry Book. Edited 
 
 by ANDREW LANG. With 12 Plates and 
 88 Illustrations in the Text by H. J. Ford 
 and Lancelot Speed. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 The Blue Poetry Book. School 
 
 Edition, without Illustrations. Fcp. 8vo. 
 2s. 6d. 
 
 The Green Fairy Book. Edited 
 
 by ANDREW LANG. With Illustrations by 
 H. J. Ford. Crown 8vo. 
 
 LA VISSE. General View of the 
 Political History of Europe. 
 
 By ERNEST LAVISSE, Professor at the 
 Sorbonne. Translated by CHARLES 
 GROSS, Ph.D. Crown 8vo. $s. 
 
 LECKY(W. E. H.}. WORKS BY. 
 
 History of England in the 
 Eighteenth Century. Library 
 
 Edition. 8vo. vols. I. & II. 1700-1760. 
 36s. Vols. III. & IV. 1760-1784. 36s. 
 Vols. V. &VI. 1784-1793. 365. Vols. 
 VII. & VIII. 1793-1800. 365. 
 Cabinet Edition. England. 7 vols. Crown 
 8vo. 6s. each. Ireland. 5 vols. Crown 
 8vo. 6s. each. [In Monthly Volumes 
 from January, 1892. 
 
 The Historyof European Morals 
 from Augustus to Charle- 
 magne. 2 vols. Crown 8vo. i6s. 
 
 History of the Rise and Influ- 
 ence of the Spirit of Rational- 
 ism in Europe. 2 vols. Crown 
 
 8vo. 1 6s. 
 
 Poems. Fcp. 8vo. $s. 
 
 LEES and CLUTTERBUCK.B. C. 
 1887, A Ramble in British 
 Columbia. By J. A. LEES and 
 
 W. J. CLUTTERBUCK. With Map and 
 75 Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 LEGER.A. History of Austro- 
 Hungary. From the Earliest 
 
 Time to the year 1889. By Louis LEGER. 
 With a Preface by E. A. FREEMAN, 
 D.C.L. Crown 8vo. IDS. 6d. 
 
 LEWES. The History of Philo- 
 sophy, from Thales to Comte. 
 By GEORGE HENRY LEWES. 2 vols. 
 8vo. 325. 
 
 LIDDELL.The Memoirs of the 
 Tenth Royal Hussars (Prince 
 of Wales' Own) : Historical and 
 Social. Collected and Arranged by 
 Colonel R. S. LIDDELL, late Command- 
 ing Tenth Royal Hussars. With Portraits 
 and Coloured Illustration. Imperial 8vo. 
 6 3 5. 
 
 LLOYD. The Science of Agricul- 
 ture. By F. J. LLOYD. 8vo. i2s. 
 
 LONGMAN (Frederick W.). WORKS 
 BY. 
 
 Chess Openings. Fcp. 8vo. zs. 6d. 
 
 Frederick the Great and the 
 
 Seven Years' War. Fcp. 8vo. 
 
 2S. 6d. 
 
 Longman's Magazine. Published 
 
 Monthly. Price Sixpence. 
 Vols, 1-19. 8vo. price 55. each.
 
 PUBLISHED BY MESSRS. LONGMANS, GREEX, d- CO. 
 
 Longmans' New Atlas. Political 
 
 and Physical. For the Use of Schools 
 and Private Persons. Consisting of 40 
 Quarto and 16 Octavo Maps and Dia- 
 grams, and 16 Plates of Views. Edited 
 by GEO. G. CHISHOLM, M.A., B.Sc. 
 Imp. 410. or Imp. 8vo. 125. 6d. 
 
 Richard Wiseman, 
 
 Surgeon and Sergeant-Surgeon to Charles 
 II. : a Biographical Study. By Surgeon 
 General Sir T. LONGMORE, C.B., F.R.C.S., 
 &c. With Portrait and Illustrations. Svo. 
 ioj. 6J. 
 
 LOU DO X (J. C.). WORKS BY. 
 Encyclopaedia of Gardening. 
 
 With 1000 Woodcuts. Svo. 2is. 
 
 Encyclopaedia of Agriculture ; 
 
 the Laying-out, Improvement, and 
 Management of Landed Property. With 
 IIOO Woodcuts. Svo. 2is. 
 
 Encyclopaedia of Plants ; the 
 
 Specific Character, &c. , of all Plants found 
 in Great Britain. With 12,000 Wood- 
 cuts. Svo. 42j t 
 
 LUBBOCK.The Origin of Civil- 
 isation and the Primitive Condi- 
 tion of Man. By Sir J. LuBBOCK, Bart., 
 M.P. With 5 Plates and 20 Illustrations 
 in the Text. Svo. iSs. 
 
 LYALL. The Autobiography of a 
 Slander. By EDNA LYALL, Author 
 
 of 'Donovan,' &c. Fcp. Svo. is. sewed. 
 
 LYDEKKER. Phases of Animal 
 Life, Past and Present. By R. 
 
 LYDEKKER, B.A. With 82 Illustrations. 
 Crown Svo. 6s. 
 
 LYDE. An Introduction to An- 
 cient History : being a Sketch of 
 
 the History of Egypt, Mesopotamia, 
 Greece, and Rome. With a Chapter on 
 the Development of the Roman Empire 
 into the Powers of Modern Europe. By 
 LIONEL W. LYDE, M.A. With 3 
 Coloured Maps. Crown Svo. 35. 
 
 LYONS. Christianity and Infalli- 
 bility Both or Neither. By the 
 Rev. DANIEL LYONS. Crown Svo. 55. 
 
 L YTTUN. Marah. By OWEN ME- 
 REDITH (the late Earl of Lytton). Fcp. 
 Svo. 6s. 6</. 
 
 MA CA ULA Y (Lord). WORKS OF. 
 
 Complete Works of Lord Ma- 
 caulay : 
 
 Library Edition, 8 vols. Svo. ^5 55. 
 Cabinet Edition, 16 vols. Post Svo. 4 165. 
 
 MA CA ULA Y (Lord). WORKS OF. 
 
 continued. 
 
 History of England from the 
 Accession of James the 
 Second : 
 
 Popular Edition, 2 vols. Crown Svo. 5-r. 
 Student's Edition, 2 vols. Crown Svo. i2s. 
 People's Edition, 4 vols. Crown Svo. 165. 
 Cabinet Edition, 8 vols. Post Svo. 485. 
 Library Edition, 5 vols. Svo. ^"4. 
 
 Critical and Historical Essays, 
 with Lays of Ancient Rome, 
 
 in i volume : 
 
 Popular Edition, Crown 8vo. 25. 6J. 
 Authorised Edition, Crown Svo. 25. 6d. or 
 ^35. 6d. gilt edges. 
 Silver Library Edition, Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Critical and Historical Essays : 
 
 Student's Edition, i vol. Crown Svo. 65. 
 People's Edition, 2 vols. Crown Svo. 85. 
 Trevelyan Edition, 2 vols. Crown Svo. 95. 
 Cabinet Edition, 4 vols. Post Svo. 24^. 
 Library Edition, 3 vols. Svo. 365. 
 
 Essays which may be had separately 
 price 6d. each sewed, 15. each cloth : 
 
 Addison and Waipole. 
 
 Frederick the Great. 
 
 Croker's Boswell's Johnson. 
 
 Hallam's Constitutional History. 
 
 Warren Hastings. ($d. sewed, 6d cloth.) 
 
 The Earl of Chatham (Two Essays). 
 
 Ranke and Gladstone. 
 
 Milton and Machiavelli. 
 
 Lord Bacon. 
 
 Lord Clive. 
 
 Lord Byron, and The Comic Dramatists of 
 the Restoration. 
 
 The Essay on Warren Hastings annotated 
 
 by S. HALES, is. 6d. 
 The Essay on Lord Clive annotated by H. 
 
 COURTHOPE BOWEN, M.A., 25. 6d. 
 
 Speeches : 
 
 People's Edition, Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Lays of Ancient Rome, &c. : 
 
 Illustrated by G. Scharf, Fcp. 410. 105. 6d. 
 Bijou Edition, i8mo. 
 
 25. 6rf. gilt top. 
 
 Popular Edition, 
 
 Fcp. 410. 6d. sewed, is. cloth. 
 Illustrated by J. R. Weguelin, Crown STO. 
 
 35. 6d. cloth extra, gilt edges. 
 Cabinet Edition, Post Svo. 35. 6J. 
 Annotated Edition, Fcp. Svo. 15. sewed, 
 
 15. 6d. cloth. 
 
 Miscellaneous Writings : 
 
 People's Edition, i vol. Crown Svo. 45. 6d. 
 Library Edition, 2 vols. Svo. 215. 
 
 [Continued on next page..
 
 A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS IN GENERAL LITERATURE. 
 
 MACAU LAY (Lord}. WORKS OF.- 
 continued. 
 
 Miscellaneous Writings and 
 Speeches : 
 
 Popular Edition, i vol. Crown 8vo. 25. 6d. 
 
 Student's Edition, in 1 vol. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 Cabinet Edition, including Indian Penal 
 Code, Lays of Ancient Rome, and Mis- 
 cellaneous Poems, 4 vols. Post 8vo. 245. 
 
 Selections from the Writings 
 of Lord Macaulay. Edited, 
 
 with Occasional Notes, by the Right Hon. 
 Sir G. (). TREVELYAN, Bart. Cr. 8vo. 6s. 
 
 The Life and Letters of Lord 
 Macaulay. By the Right Hon. 
 
 Sir G. O. TREVELYAX, Bart.: 
 Popular Edition, i vol. Crown 8vo. 2s. 6d. 
 Student's Edition, I vol. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 Cabinet Edition, 2 vols. Post 8vo. I2S. 
 Library Edition, 2 vols. 8vo. 365. 
 
 MACDONALD (Geo.). WORKS BY. 
 Unspoken Sermons. Three 
 
 Series. Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. each. 
 
 The Miracles of Our Lord. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 A Book of Strife, in the Form 
 of the Diary of an Old Soul : 
 
 Poems. I2ino. 6s. 
 
 MACFARREN (Sir G. A.}. WORKS 
 w' BY - 
 
 Lectures on Harmony. 8vo. 12*. 
 
 MA CKAIL. SelectEpigrams from 
 
 the Greek Anthology. Edited, 
 
 with a Revised Text, Introduction, Trans- 
 lation, and Notes, by J. W. MACKAIL, 
 M.A. 8vo. i6s. 
 
 MACLEOD (Henry D.). WORKS B Y. 
 The Elements of Banking. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 The Theory and Practice of 
 Banking. Vol. I. 8vo. i2s. 
 
 Vol. II. I4S. 
 
 The Theory of Credit. 8vo. 
 
 Vol. I. ^s. 6d. ; Vol. II. Part I. 4S. 6d. ; 
 Vol. II. Part II. IDS. 6d. 
 
 M c CULLOCH.The Dictionary of 
 Commerce and Commercial Navi- 
 gation of the late J. R. McCuixoCH. 
 8vo. with ii Maps and 30 Charts, 635. 
 
 MA C VINE. Sixty-Three Years' 
 Angling, from the Mountain 
 Streamlet to the Mighty Tay. By JOHN 
 MACVINE. Crown 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 MALMESBURY. Memoirs of an 
 Ex-Minister. By the Earl of 
 MALMESBURY. Crown 8vo. ^s. 6d. 
 
 MANNERING.With Axe and 
 Rope in the New Zealand 
 Alps. By GEORGE EDWARD MAN- 
 NERING. With 18 Illustrations. 8vo. 
 12s. 6<L 
 
 MANUALS OF CATHOLIC 
 PHILOSOPHY (Stony hurst 
 
 Series) : 
 
 Logic. By RICHARD F. CLARKE, 
 
 S.J. Crown 8vo. 55. 
 
 First Principles of Knowledge. 
 
 By JOHN RICKABY, S.J. Crown 8vo. 5s. 
 
 Moral Philosophy (Ethics and 
 Natural Law). By JOSEPH RICK- 
 ABY, S.J. Crown 8vo. 55. 
 
 General Metaphysics. By JOHN 
 
 RICKABY, S.J. Crown 8vo. 5s. 
 Psychology. By MICHAEL MAHER, 
 
 S.J. Crown 8vo. 6s. 6d. 
 
 Natural Theology. By BERNARD 
 
 BOEDDER, S.J. Crown 8vo. 6s. 6d. 
 
 Political Economy. By CHARLES 
 
 S. DF.VAS. Crown 8vo. 6s. 6d. 
 
 MARBOT.The Memoirs of the 
 Baron de Marbot. Translated 
 
 from the French. 2 vols. 8vo. 32J. 
 
 MARTINEA U (James). WORKS BY. 
 
 Hours of Thought on Sacred 
 Things. Two Volumes of Ser- 
 mons. 2 vols. Crown 8vo. 7 5 - 6d. each. 
 
 Endeavours after the Christian 
 Life. Discourses. Cr. 8vo. 7^. 6d. 
 
 The Seat of Authority in Re- 
 ligion. 8vo. i4s. 
 
 Essays, Reviews, and Ad- 
 dresses. 4 vols. Cr.8vo.7-r. 6</.each. 
 
 I. Personal : Poli- III. Theological: 
 tical. Philosophical. 
 
 II. Ecclesiastical : 
 Historical. 
 
 IV. Academical : 
 Religious. 
 
 Home Prayers, with Two Services 
 
 for Public Worship. Crown 8vo. 3-r. 6d. 
 
 MA TTHEWS(Brander). WORKS BY. 
 A Family Tree, and other Stories. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 Pen and Ink : Papers on Subjects 
 
 of more or less Importance. Cr. 8vo. $s. 
 
 With My Friends : Tales told in 
 
 Partnership. With an Introductory 
 Essay on the Art and Mystery of Colla- 
 boration. Crown 8vo. 6s.
 
 PUBLISHED BY MESSRS. LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO. 
 
 MAUNDER'S TREASURIES. 
 Biographical Treasury. With 
 
 Supplement brought down to 1889, by 
 Rev. JAS. WOOD. Fcp. 8vo. 6s. 
 
 Treasury of Natural History ; 
 
 or, Popular Dictionary of Zoology. Fcp. 
 8vo. with 900 Woodcuts, 6s. 
 
 Treasury of Geography, Physical, 
 
 Historical, Descriptive, and Political. 
 With 7 Maps and 16 Plates. Fcp. 8vo. gs. 
 
 Scientific and Literary Trea- 
 sury. Fcp. 8vo. 6.r. 
 
 Historical Treasury : Outlines of 
 
 Universal History, Separate Histories of 
 all Nations. Fcp. 8vo. 6s. 
 
 Treasury of Knowledge and 
 Library of Reference. Com- 
 prising an English Dictionary and Gram- 
 mar, Universal Gazetteer, Classical 
 Dictionary, Chronology, Law Dictionary, 
 &c. Fcp. 8vo. 6s. 
 
 The Treasury of Bible Know- 
 ledge. By the Rev. J. AYRE, M. A. 
 
 With 5 Maps, 15 Plates, and 300 Wood- 
 cuts. Fcp. 8vo. 6s. 
 
 The Treasury of Botany. 
 
 Edited by J. LINDLEY, F.R.S., and 
 T. MOORE, F.L.S. With 274 Woodcuts 
 and 20 Steel Plates. 2 vols. Fcp. 8vo. I2S. 
 
 MAXMULLER (F.). WORKS BY. 
 Selected Essays on Language, 
 Mythology and Religion. 
 
 2 vols. Crown 8vo. i6s. 
 
 The Science of Language, 
 
 Founded on Lectures delivered at the 
 Royal Institution in 1861 and 1863. 2 
 vols. Crown 8vo. 2is. 
 
 Three Lectures on the Science 
 of Language and its Place in 
 General Education, delivered 
 
 at the Oxford University Extension 
 Meeting, 1889. Crown 8vo. 35. 
 
 Hibbert Lectures on the Origin 
 and Growth of Religion, as 
 
 illustrated by the Religions of India. 
 Crown 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 Introduction to the Science of 
 Religion ; Four Lectures delivered 
 
 at the Royal Institution. Crown 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 Natural Religion. The Gifford 
 
 Lectures, delivered before the University 
 of Glasgow in 1888. Crown 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 Physical Religion. The Gifford 
 
 Lectures, delivered before the University 
 of Glasgow in 1890. Crown 8vo. IDS. 6rf. 
 
 MAX MULLER (F.). WORKS BY. 
 continued. 
 
 Anthropological Religion : The 
 
 Gifford Lectures delivered before the Uni- 
 versity of Glasgow in 1891. Cr.8vo.iOJ-.6o'. 
 
 The Science of Thought. 8vo. 
 
 2IS. 
 
 Three Introductory Lectures on 
 the Science of Thought. 8vo. 
 
 2S. 6ft. 
 
 Biographies of Words, and the 
 Home of the Aryas. Crown 
 
 8vo. 75. 6d. 
 
 India, what can it teach us? 
 
 Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 A Sanskrit Grammar for Be- 
 ginners. Abridged Edition. By 
 A. A. MACDONELL. Cr. 8vo. 6s. 
 
 MAY. The Constitutional His- 
 tory of England since the 
 
 Accession of George III. 1760-1870. 
 By the Right Hon. Sir THOMAS 
 ERSKINE MAY, K.C.B. 3 vols. Crown 
 8vo. i8s. 
 
 MEADE(L. T.}. WORKS BY. 
 Daddy's Boy. With Illustrations. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Deb and the Duchess. With 
 
 Illustrations by M. E. EDWARDS. Crown 
 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 The Beresford Prize. With Illus- 
 trations by M. E. EDWARDS. Crown 
 8vo. 55. 
 
 MEATH (The Earl of). WORKS BY. 
 Social Arrows : Reprinted Articles 
 
 on various Social Subjects. Cr. 8vo. $s. 
 
 Prosperity or Pauperism ? 
 
 Physical, Industrial, and Technical 
 Training. (Edited by the EARL OF 
 MEATH.) 8vo. 55. 
 
 MELVILLE (G.J. Why te). NOVELS 
 BY. Crown 8vo. is. each, boards; is. 
 
 (>d. each, cloth. 
 
 The Gladiators. ; Hoimby House. 
 The Interpreter. Kate Coventry. 
 
 Good for Nothing. Digby Grand. 
 The Queen's Maries. General Bounce. 
 
 MENDELSSOHN. The Letters of 
 Felix Mendelssohn. Translated 
 
 by Lady WALLACE. 2 vols. Crown 8vo. 
 
 IO5.
 
 1 6 
 
 A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS IN GENERAL LITERATURE 
 
 MERIVALE (The Very Rev. Chas.). 
 
 WORKS BY. 
 
 History of the Romans under 
 the Empire. Cabinet Edition, 
 
 8 vols. Crown 8vo. 485. 
 Popular Edition, 8 vols. Cr. 8vo. 35. 6d. each. 
 
 The Fall of the Roman Republic : 
 
 a Short History of the Last Century of 
 the Commonwealth. I2mo. 75. 6d. 
 
 General History of Rome from 
 
 B.C. 753 to A.D. 476. Cr. 8vo. 7-r. 6d. 
 
 The Roman Triumvirates. With 
 
 Maps. Fcp. 8vo. zs. 6d. 
 
 MILES. The Correspondence of 
 William Augustus Miles on 
 the French Revolution, 1789- 
 1817. Edited by the Rev. CHARLES 
 POPHAM MILES, M.A. 2 vols. 8vo. 325. 
 
 MILL. Analysis of the Pheno- 
 mena of the Human Mind. 
 
 By TAMES MILL. 2 vols. 3vo. 285. 
 MILL (John Stuart}. WORKS BY. 
 
 Principles of Political Economy. 
 
 Library Edition, 2 vols. 8vo. 305. 
 People's Edition, i vol. Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 A System of Logic. Cr . 8vo . 35. 6d. 
 On Liberty. Crown 8vo. is. $d. 
 On Representative Government. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 25. 
 
 Utilitarianism. 8vo. 5*. 
 Examination of Sir William 
 
 Hamilton's Philosophy. 8vo. 
 
 165. 
 Nature, the Utility of Religion, 
 
 and Theism. Three Essays. 8vo. 
 
 5*. 
 
 MOLESWORTH (Mrs.). WORKS BY. 
 Marrying and Giving in Mar- 
 riage : a Novel. Illustrated. Fcp. 
 
 8vo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 Silverthorns. Illustrated. Crown 
 
 8vo. 55. 
 
 The Palace in the Garden. Illus- 
 trated. Crown 8vo. 55. 
 The Third Miss St. Quentin. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 Neighbours. Illustrated. Crown 
 
 8vo. 6s. 
 
 The Story of a Spring Morning, 
 
 &c. Illustrated. Crown 8vo. 5$. 
 
 Stories of the Saints for Chil- 
 dren : the Black Letter Saints. 
 
 With Illustrations. Royal l6mo. 5-r. 
 
 MOORE. Dante and his Early 
 Biographers. By EDWARD 
 
 MOORE, D.D., Principal of St. Edmund 
 Hall, Oxford. Crown 8vo. 45. 6<f. 
 
 MULHALL. History of Prices 
 since the Year 1850. By 
 
 MICHAEL G. MULHALL. Cr. 8vo. 6s. 
 
 NANSEN.The First Crossing of 
 Greenland. By Dr. FRIDTJOF 
 
 NANSEN. With 5 Maps, 12 Plates, and 
 150 Illustrations in the Text. 2 vols. 
 8vo. 36^. Cheaper Edition, abridged. 
 With numerous Illustrations and a Map. 
 In I vol. crown 8vo. "js. 6d. 
 
 NAPIER. The Life of Sir Joseph 
 Napier, Bart., Ex-Lord Chan- 
 cellor of Ireland. By ALEX. 
 
 CHARLES EWALD, F.S.A. With Por- 
 trait. 8vo. 155. 
 
 NAPIER. The Lectures, Essays, 
 and Letters of the Right Hon. 
 Sir Joseph Napier, Bart., late 
 
 Lord Chancellor of Ireland. 8vo. I2S. 6d. 
 
 NESBIT. Leaves of Life : Verses. 
 
 By E. NESBIT. Crown 8vo. 5$. 
 
 Lays and Legends. By E. NESBIT 
 
 (Mrs. HUBERT BLAND). FIRST Series. 
 New and Cheaper Edition. Crown 8vo. 
 3J. 6d. SECOND Series. With Portrait. 
 Crown 8vo. $s. 
 
 NEWMAN. The Letters and Cor- 
 respondence of John Henry 
 Newman during his Life in the 
 
 ^r English Church. With a brief Autobio- 
 graphical Memoir. Arranged and Edited 
 by ANNE MOZLEY. With Portraits. 2 
 vols. 8vo. 3os. net. 
 
 NEWMAN (Cardinal). WORKS BY. 
 Apologia pro Vita Sua. Cabinet 
 
 Edition, Crown 8vo. 6s. Cheap Edition, 
 Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d. 
 
 Discourses to Mixed Congrega- 
 tions. Cabinet Edition, Crown 
 8vo. 6s. Cheap Edition, Cr. 8vo. y. 6d. 
 
 Sermons on Various Occasions. 
 
 Cabinet Edition. Crown 8vo. 6s. Cheap 
 Edition. 35. 6d. 
 
 The Idea of a University defined 
 and illustrated. Cabinet Edition, 
 Crown 8vo. js. Cheap Edition, Crown 
 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 [Continued on next page.
 
 PUBLISHED BY .MESSRS. LONGMANS, GREEX, rf- CO. 
 
 NEWMAN (Cardinal}. WORKS BY. , NEWMAN (Cardinal}. WORKS OF.- 
 continued. continued. 
 
 Historical Sketches. 3 vols. 
 
 Cabinet Edition. Crown 8vo. 6s. each. 
 Cheap Edition. 3 vols. 35. 6d. each. 
 
 The Arians of the Fourth Cen- 
 tury. Cabinet Edition, Crown 
 
 8vo. 65. Cheap Edition, Cr. 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Select Treatises of St. Athan- 
 asius in Controversy with the 
 
 Arians. Freely Translated. 2 vols. Cr. 
 Svo. i~,s. 
 
 Discussions and Arguments on 
 Various Subjects. Cabinet 
 
 Edition, Crown Svo. 6s. Cheap Edition, 
 Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 An Essay on the Development I 
 of Christian Doctrine. Cabinet 
 
 Edition, Crown Svo. 6s. Cheap Edition, 
 Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Certain Difficulties felt by An- 
 glicans in Catholic Teaching 
 Considered. Cabinet Edition, 
 
 Vol. I., Crown Svo. 75. 6d. ; Vol. II., Cr. 
 Svo. 55. 6d. Cheap Edition, 2 vols. Cr. 
 Svo. 3s. 6d. each. 
 
 The Via Media of the Anglican 
 Church, illustrated in Lectures, 
 Ac. 2 vols. Cabinet Edition. Cr. Svo. 6s. 
 each. Cheap Edition, 2 vols. 3s. 6d. each. 
 
 Essays, Critical and Historical. 
 
 Cabinet Edition, 2 vols. Crown Svo. 125. 
 Cheap Edition, 2 vols. Crown Svo. "js. 
 
 Essays on Biblical and on Ec- 
 clesiastical Miracles. Cabinet 
 
 Edition, Crown Svo. 6s. Cheap Edition, 
 Crown Svo. y. 6d. 
 
 Tracts, i. Dissertatiunculae. 2. On 
 the Text of the Seven Epistles of St. 
 Ignatius. 3. Doctrinal Causes of Arian- 
 ism. 4. Apollinarianism. 5. St. Cyril's 
 Formula. 6. Ordo de Tempore. "J. 
 Douay Version of Scripture. Crown Svo. 
 8s. 
 
 An Essay in Aid of a Grammar 
 of Assent. Cabinet Edition, } 
 
 Crown Svo. "js. 6d. Cheap Edition, ; 
 Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Present Position of Catholics in 
 England. Cabinet Edition, Cr. 
 
 Svn. -j-. 6</. Cheap Edition, Cr. Svo. j 
 
 3. 6d. 
 
 Callista: a Tale of the Third Cen- 
 tury. Cabinet Edition, Crown Svo. 6s. 
 Cheap Edition, Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Loss and Gain : a Tale. Cabinet 
 
 Edition, Crown Svo. 6s. Cheap Edition, 
 Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 The Dream of Gerontius. i6mo. 
 
 6d. sewed, is. cloth. 
 
 Verses on Various Occasions. 
 
 Cabinet Edition, Crown Svo. 6s. Cheap 
 Edition, Crown Svo. 35. bd. 
 
 Fabulae Quaedam ex Terentio 
 et Plauto ad usum Puerorum 
 accommodatae. With English 
 
 Notes and Translations to assist the re- 
 presentation. Cardinal Newman's Edi- 
 tion, Crown Svo. 6s. 
 
 %* For Cardinal Newman's other Works 
 see Messrs. Longmans & Co.'s Catalogue 
 of Church of England Theological Works. 
 
 NORTON (Charles L.}. WORKS BY. 
 
 Political Americanisms: a Glos- 
 sary of Terms and Phrases Current at 
 Different Periods in American Politics. 
 Fcp. Svo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 A Handbook of Florida. With 
 
 49 Maps and Plans. Fcp. Svo. 5s. 
 
 O'BRIEN.When we were Boys : 
 
 a Novel. By WILLIAM O'BRIEN, M.P. 
 Crown Svo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 OLIPHANT (Mrs.}. NOVELS BY. 
 Madam. Cr. 8vo. u.bds. ; is. 6d. cl. 
 In Trust. Cr. Svo. is. bds.; i*. 6d. cl. 
 
 OMAN. A History of Greece from 
 the Earliest Times to the 
 Macedonian Conquest. By C. 
 
 W. C. OMAN, M.A., F.S.A. With 
 Maps and Plans. Crown Svo. 45. 6d. 
 
 O'REILLY. Hurstleigh Dene: a 
 
 Tale. By Mrs. O'REILLY. Illustrated 
 by M. ELLEN EDWARDS. Cr. Svo. 55. 
 
 PAUL. Principles of the History 
 of Language. By HERMANN 
 
 PAUL. Translated by H. A. STRONG. 
 Svo. IDS. 6d. 
 
 PA YN (James) .No VELS B Y. 
 
 The Luck of the Darrells. Cr. 
 
 Svo. is. boards ; is. 6d. cloth. 
 
 Thicker than Water. Crown Svo. 
 
 is. boards ; is. 6d. cloth.
 
 18 
 
 A CA TALOGUE OF BOOKS IN GENERAL LITER A TURE 
 
 PEERING (Sir Philip}. WORKS BY. 
 Hard Knots in Shakespeare. 
 
 8vo. TS. 6d. 
 
 The 'Works and Days 'of Moses. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 35. 6rf. 
 
 PHILLIPPS- WOLLEY. Snap : a 
 
 Legend of the Lone Mountain. By C. 
 PHILLIPPS-WOLLEY. With 13 Illustra- 
 tions by H. G. WILLINK. Cr. 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 POLE. The Theory of the Mo- 
 dern Scientific Game of Whist. 
 
 By W. POLE, F.R.S. Fcp. 8vo. zs. 6d. 
 
 POLLOCK. The Seal of Fate: 
 
 a Novel. By Lady POLLOCK and W. 
 H. POLLOCK. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 POOLE. Cookery for the Diabetic. 
 
 By W. H. and Mrs. POOLE. With Pre- 
 face by Dr. PAVY. Fcp. 8vo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 PRAEGER. Wagner as I knew 
 him. By FERDINAND PRAEGER. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 7-r. 6d. 
 
 PRATT. To the Snows of Tibet 
 through China. By A. E. 
 
 PRATT, F.R.G.S. With 33 Illustrations 
 and a Map. 8vo. i8j. 
 
 PRENDERGAST. Ireland, from 
 the Restoration to the Revolu- 
 
 tion, 1660-1690. By JOHN P. PREN- 
 
 .^, 8vo. 55. 
 
 PROCTOR (R. A.). WORKS BY. 
 Old and New Astronomy. 12 
 
 Parts, 25. 6d. each. Supplementary Sec- 
 tion, is. Complete in i vol. 4to. 365. 
 
 [In course of publication. 
 
 The Orbs Around Us ; a Series of 
 
 Essays on the Moon and Planets, Meteors 
 and Comets. With Chart and Diagrams. 
 Crown Svo. 5s. 
 
 Other Worlds than Ours ; The 
 
 Plurality of Worlds Studied under the 
 Light of Recent Scientific Researches. 
 With 14 Illustrations. Crown Svo. 55. 
 
 The Moon ; her Motions, Aspects 
 
 Scenery, and Physical Condition. With 
 Plates, Charts, Woodcuts, &c. Cr. Svo. 55. 
 
 Universe of Stars; Presenting 
 
 Researches into and New Views respect- 
 ing the Constitution of the Heavens. 
 With 22 Charts and 22 Diagrams. Svo. 
 los. 6d. 
 
 PROCTOR (R. A.). WORKS BY. 
 continued. 
 
 Larger Star Atlas for the Library, 
 
 in 12 Circular Maps, with Introduction 
 and 2 Index Pages. Folio, 155. or Maps 
 only, i2s. 6d. 
 
 The Student's Atlas. In Twelve 
 
 Circular Maps on a Uniform Projection 
 and one Scale. Svo. 55. 
 
 New Star Atlas for the Library, 
 
 the School, and the Observatory, in 12 
 Circular Maps. Crown Svo. 55. 
 
 Light Science for LeisureHours. 
 
 Familiar Essays on Scientific Subjects. 
 3 vols. Crown Svo. 55. each. 
 
 Chance and Luck ; a Discussion of 
 
 the Laws of Luck, Coincidences, Wagers, 
 Lotteries, and the Fallacies of Gambling, 
 &c. Crown Svo. 2s. boards ; 2s. 6d. cloth. 
 
 Studies of Venus-Transits. With 
 
 7 Diagrams and 10 Plates. Svo. 55. 
 
 How to Play Whist: with the 
 Laws and Etiquette of Whist. 
 
 Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Home Whist: an Easy Guide to 
 
 Correct Play. i6mo. is. 
 
 The Stars in their Seasons. 
 
 An Easy Guide to a Knowledge of the 
 Star Groups, in 12 Maps. Roy. Svo. 55. 
 
 Star Primer. Showing the Starry 
 
 Sky Week by Week, in 24 Hourly Maps. 
 Crown 4to. 2s. 6d. 
 
 The Seasons pictured in 48 Sun- 
 Views of the Earth, and 24 
 
 Zodiacal Maps, &c. Demy 410. 55. 
 
 Strength and Happiness. With 
 
 9 Illustrations. Crown Svo. $s. 
 
 Strength : How to get Strong and 
 
 keep Strong, with Chapters on Rowing 
 and Swimming, Fat, Age, and the Waist. 
 With 9 Illustrations. Crown Svo. 2s. 
 
 Rough Ways Made Smooth. 
 
 Familiar Essays on Scientific Subjects. 
 Crown Svo. 55. 
 
 Our Place Among Infinities. A 
 
 Series of Essays contrasting our Little 
 Abode in Space and Time with the Infi- 
 nities around us. Crown Svo. 5s. 
 
 [Continued on next page.
 
 PUBLISHED BY MESSRS. LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO. 
 
 PROCTOR (R. A.). WORKS BY. 
 
 continued. 
 The Expanse of Heaven. Essays 
 
 on the Wonders of the Firmament. Cr. 
 
 8vo. 55. 
 
 The Great Pyramid, Observa- 
 tory, Tomb, and Temple. 
 
 With Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 55. 
 
 Pleasant Ways in Science. Cr. 
 
 8vo. 55. 
 
 Myths and Marvels of Astro- 
 nomy. Crown 8vo. $s. 
 
 Nature Studies. By GRANT ALLEN, 
 A. WILSON, T. FOSTER, E. CLODD, and 
 R. A. PROCTOR. Crown 8vo. 55. 
 
 Leisure Readings. By E. CLODD, 
 A. WILSON, T. FOSTER, A. C. RANYARD, 
 and R. A. PROCTOR. Crown 8vo. 55. 
 
 PRYCE. The Ancient British 
 Church : an Historical Essay. 
 By JOHN PRYCE, M.A. Crown 8vo. 65. 
 
 RANSOMS. The Rise of Consti- 
 tutional Government in Eng- 
 land : being a Series of Twenty 
 
 Lectures on the History of the English 
 Constitution delivered to a Popular 
 Audience. By CYRIL RANSOME, M.A. 
 Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 RAW LIN SON. The History of 
 Phoenicia. By GEORGE RAWLIN- 
 
 SON, M.A., Canon of Canterbury, &c. 
 With numerous Illustrations. 8vo. 245. 
 
 RIBOT. The Psychology of At- 
 tention. ByTH.RiBOT. Crown 
 
 8vo. 35. 
 
 RICH. A Dictionary of Roman 
 and Greek Antiquities. With 
 
 2000 Woodcuts. By A. RICH. Crown 
 Svo. 75. 6d. 
 
 RICHARDSON. National Health. 
 
 Abridged from 'The Health of Nations'. 
 A Review of the Works of Sir Edwin 
 Chadwick, K.C.B. By Dr. B. W. 
 RICHARDSON. Crown, 45. fid. 
 
 RILEY. Athos ; or, the Mountain 
 of the Monks. By ATHELSTAN RILEY, 
 M.A., F.R.G.S. With Map and 29 
 Illustrations. Svo. 2 is. 
 
 j.ij. 
 
 RILE K Old-Fashioned Roses : 
 Poems. By JAMES WHITCOMB 
 RILEY. iamo. 55. 
 
 RIVERS. The Miniature Fruit 
 Garden ; or, The Culture of Pyra- 
 midal and Bush Fruit Trees. By THOMAS 
 and T. F. RIVERS. With 32 Illustrations. 
 Crown Svo. 4^. 
 
 RIVERS. The Rose Amateur's 
 Guide. By THOMAS RIVERS. 
 Yep. Svo. 4-f. 6d. 
 
 ROBERTSON. The Kidnapped 
 
 Squatter, and other Australian 
 Tales. By A. ROBERTSON. Cr. Svo. 6s. 
 
 ROCKHILL.The Land of the 
 Lamas : Notes of a Journey 
 
 through China, Mangolia and Tibet. 
 With 2 Maps and 6 Illustrations. By 
 W. W. ROCKHILL. Svo. 155. 
 
 ROGET.A History of the 'Old 
 Water-Colour' Society (now 
 
 the Royal Society of Painters in Water- 
 Colours). With Biographical Notices of 
 its Older and all its Deceased Members 
 and Associates. By JOHN LEWIS ROGET, 
 M.A. 2 vols. Royal Svo. 425. 
 
 ROGET. Thesaurus of English 
 Words and Phrases. Classified 
 
 and Arranged so as to facilitate the Ex- 
 pression of Ideas. By PETER M. ROGET. 
 Crown Svo. los. 6d. 
 
 ROMANES. Darwin, and after 
 
 Darwin : an Exposition of the 
 
 Darwinian Theory and a Discussion of 
 Post-Darwinian Questions. By GEORGE 
 JOHN ROMANES, M.A., LL.D., F.R.S., 
 Author of ' Mental Evolution in Man,' 
 &c. Part I. The Darwinian Theory. 
 With Portrait of Darwin and 125 Illustra- 
 tions. Crown Svo. icw. 6d. 
 
 RONALDS. The Fly - Fisher's 
 Entomology. By A. RONALDS. 
 
 With 20 Coloured Plates. Svo. 145. 
 
 ROSSETTI.A Shadow of Dante : 
 
 being an Essay towards studying Himself, 
 his World, and his Pilgrimage. By MARIA 
 FRANCESCA ROSSETTI. With Illustra- 
 tions. Crown Svo. los. 6d. 
 
 ROUND. Geoffrey de Mande- 
 ville : a Study of the Anarchy. 
 By J. H. ROUND, M.A., Author of 'The 
 Early Life of Anne Boleyn : a Critical 
 Essay'. Svo. i6s. 
 
 RUSSELL. A Life of Lord John 
 Russell (Earl Russell, K.G.). 
 
 By SPENCER WALPOLE. With 2 Por- 
 traits. 2 vols. 8vo. 365. Cabinet Edition, 
 2 vols. Crown Svo. 125.
 
 A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS IN GENERAL LITERATURE 
 
 SEEBOHM (Frederic). WORKS BY. 
 The Oxford Reformers John 
 Colet, Erasmus, and Thomas 
 More ; a History of their Fellow- i 
 Work. 8vo. 145. 
 
 The English Village Commu- 
 nity Examined in its Relations to 
 
 the Manorial and Tribal Systems, &c. 13 > 
 Maps and Plates. 8vo. i6s. 
 
 The Era of the Protestant 
 Revolution. With Map. Fcp. I 
 
 8vo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 SEWELL. Stories and Tales. By ' 
 
 ELIZABETH M. SEWELL. Crown 8vo. I 
 15. 6d. each, cloth plain ; 2s. 6d. each, i 
 cloth extra, gilt edges : 
 
 Amy Herbert. Laneton Parsonage. 
 
 The Earl's Daughter. Ursula. 
 
 The Experience of Life. Gertrude. 
 
 AGlimpseoftheWorld. Ivors. 
 
 Cleve Hall. Home Life. 
 
 Katharine Ashton. After Life. 
 
 Margaret Percival. 
 
 SHAKESPEARE. - - Bowdler's 
 Family Shakespeare, i Vol. 
 
 8vo. With 36 Woodcuts, 145. or in 6 
 vols. Fcp. 8vo. 2 is. 
 
 Outlines of the Life of Shake- 
 speare. By J. O. HALLIWELL- 
 
 PHILLIPPS. With numerous Illustrations 
 and Fac-similes. 2 vols. Royal Svo.^l is. 
 
 A Calendar of the Halliwell- 
 Phillipps' Collection of Shake- 
 spearean Rarities Formerly 
 
 Preserved at Hollingbury Copse, Brighton. 
 Enlarged by ERNEST E. BAKER, F.S.A. 
 8vo. KM. 6d. 
 
 Shakespeare's True Life. By 
 
 JAMES WALTER. With 500 Illustrations. 
 Imp. 8vo. 215. 
 
 The Shakespeare Birthday 
 Book. By MARY F. DUNBAR. 
 32mo. 15. 6d. cloth. With Photographs, 
 32mo. 55. Drawing-Room Edition, with 
 Photographs, Fcp. 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 SI D& WICK. Distinction: and the 
 
 Criticism of Belief. By ALFRED SIDO 
 WICK. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 SILVER LIBRARY (The). 
 
 Crown 8vo. y. 6d. each volume. 
 
 Baker's (Sir S. W.) Eight Years in 
 Ceylon. With 6 Illustrations. y. &d. 
 
 Baker's (Sir S. W.) Rifle and Hound in 
 Ceylon. With 6 Illustrations. 35. 6d. 
 
 Baring-Gould's Curious M^ths of the 
 Middle Ages. y. 6d. 
 
 SILVER LIBRARY (The). 
 
 continued. 
 Baring-Gould's (Rev. S. ; Origin and 
 
 Development of Religious Belief. 2 
 
 vo!s. 75. 
 
 Brassey's (Lady) A Voyage in the 'Sun- 
 beam'. With 66 Illustrations, y. 6a. 
 Clodd's (E.) Story of Creation: a Plain 
 
 Account of Evolution. With 77 Illustra- 
 tions. 3.?. 6ff. 
 Conybeare (Rev. W. J. and Howson's 
 
 (Very Rev. J. S.) Life and Epistles of 
 
 St. Paul. 46 Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 
 
 35. 6rf. 
 Dougall's (L.) Beggars All : a Novel. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 Doyle's (A. Conan) Micah Clarke. A 
 
 Tale of Monmouth's Rebellion. y. dd. 
 Doyle's (A. Conan) The Captain of the 
 
 Polestar, and other Tales. Crown 8vo. 
 
 3J. 6d. 
 Froude's ( J. A. ) Short Studies on Great 
 
 Subjects. 4 vols. 3-r. 6J. each. 
 Froude's (J. A.) Caesar : a Sketch, y. 6d. 
 Froude's (J. A.) Thomas Carlyle : a 
 
 History of his Life. 1795-1835. 2 vols. 
 
 1834-1881. 2 vols. Is. each. 
 Froude's (J. A.) The Two Chiefs of 
 
 Dunboy : an Irish Romance of the Last 
 
 Century, y. 6d. 
 Gleig's (Rev. G. R. ) Life of the Duke 
 
 of Wellington. With Portrait. 3-r. 6d. 
 Haggard's (H. R.) She: A History of 
 
 Adventure. 32 Illustrations. 3.?. 6d. 
 Haggard's (H. R.) Allan Quatermain. 
 
 With 20 Illustrations. 3-r. 6d. 
 Haggard's (H. R.) Colonel Quaritch, 
 
 V.C. : a Tale of Country Life. 3-f. (>d. 
 Haggard's (H. R.) Cleopatra. With 29 
 
 Fall-page Illustrations. y. 6d. 
 Haggard's (H. R.) Beatrice. 35. 6d. 
 Howitt's (W.) Visits to Remarkable 
 
 Places. 80 Illustrations. y. 6d. 
 Jefferies' (R.) The Story of My Heart : 
 
 My Autobiography. With Portrait. y.f)d. 
 Jefferies' (R.) Field and Hedgerow. Last 
 
 Essays of. With Portrait. 3-r. 6d. 
 Jefferies' (R.) Red Deer. With 17 Illus- 
 trations by J. CHARLTON and H. 
 
 TUNALY. Crown 8vo. 3-r. 6d. 
 Knight's (E. F.) The Cruise of the 
 
 4 Alerte : ' the Narrative of a .Search for 
 
 Treasure on the Desert Island of Trinidad. 
 
 With 2 Maps and 23 Illustrations. Crown 
 
 8vo. 3*. 6d. 
 Lees (J. A.) and Clutterbuck's (W. J.), 
 
 B. C. 1887, A Ramble in British 
 
 Columbia. With Maps and 75 Illustra- 
 tions. 35. 6(/. 
 
 [Continued on next page.
 
 PUBLISHED BY MESSRS, LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO. 
 
 SILVER LIBRARY (The). 
 
 continued. 
 Macaulay's (Lord) Essays and Lays. 
 
 With Portrait and Illustration. 35. 6d. 
 Macleod's (H. D.) The Elements of 
 
 Banking. 3^. 6d. 
 Marshman's (J. C.) Memoirs of Sir 
 
 Henry Havelock. y. 6d. 
 Max Miiller's (F.) India, what can it 
 
 teach us ? Crown Svo. y. 6d. 
 Merivale's (Dean) History of the 
 
 Romans under the Empire. 8 vols. 
 
 3.?. 6d. each. 
 Mill's (J. S.) Principles of Political 
 
 Economy, y. 6d. 
 
 Mill's (J. S.) System of Logic 3-r. 6d. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Historical 
 
 Sketches. 3 vols. 35. 6d. each. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Apologia Pro 
 
 Vita Sua. y. 6</. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Callista : a Tale 
 
 of the Third Century. y. 6d. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Loss and Gain : 
 
 a Tale. 3^. 6</. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Essays, Critical 
 
 and Historical. 2 vols. "js. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) An Essay on the 
 
 Development of Christian Doctrine. 
 
 3J. 6V. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) The Arians of 
 
 the Fourth Century. y. 6J. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Verses on Various 
 
 Occasions. 3^. fxi. 
 
 Newman's (Cardinal) The Present Posi- 
 tion of Catholics in England. 3*. t>d. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Parochial and 
 
 Plain Sermons. 8 vols. 3-r. 6d. each. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Selection, adapted 
 
 to the Seasons of the Ecclesiastical Year, 
 
 from the ' Parochial and Plain Sermons '. 
 
 y. 6J. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Sermons bearing 
 
 upon Subjects of the Day. Edited 
 
 by the Rev. W. J. Copeland, B.D., late 
 
 Rector of Farnham, Essex. 3-r. 6d. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Difficulties felt by 
 
 Anglicans in Catholic Teaching Con- 
 sidered. 2 vols. 3^. 6d. each. 
 
 Newman's (Cardinal) The Idea of a 
 University Defined and Illustrated. 
 
 y. 6d. 
 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Biblical and 
 Ecclesiastical Miracles, y. 6</. 
 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Discussions and 
 Arguments on Various Subjects. 
 3^. 6d. 
 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Grammar of 
 Assent. y. 6d. 
 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Fifteen Sermons 
 Preached before the University of 
 Oxford. Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 SILVER LIBRARY (The).- 
 
 continued. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Lectures on the 
 
 Doctrine of Justification. Crown Svo. 
 . 35. 6d. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Sermons on 
 
 Various Occasions. Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) The Via Media 
 
 of the Anglican Church, illustrated in 
 
 Lectures, &c. 2 vols. y. 6J. each. 
 Newman's (Cardinal) Discourses to 
 
 Mixed Congregations. 35. 6d. 
 Phillipps-Wolley's (C.) Snap : a Legend 
 
 of the Lone Mountain. With 13 Illustra- 
 tions. 35. 6d. 
 Stanley's (Bishop) Familiar History of 
 
 Birds. 160 Illustrations. 3.5-. 6d. 
 Stevenson (R. L.) and Osbourne's (LI.) 
 
 The Wrong Box. Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 Weyman's (Stanley J.) The House of 
 
 the Wolf : a Romance. Cr. Svo. 35. 6d. 
 Wood's (Rev. J. G.) Petland Revisited. 
 
 With 33 Illustrations, y. 6d. 
 Wood's (Rev. J. G.) Strange Dwellings : 
 
 With 60 Illustrations. 3-r. 6</. 
 Wood's (Rev. J. G.) Out of Doors. 
 
 ii Illustrations. 3^. dd. 
 
 SMITH (R. Bosworth). Carthage 
 and the Carthagenians. By 
 
 R. BOSWORTH SMITH, M.A. Maps, 
 Plans, &c. Crown Svo. 6s. 
 
 Sophocles. Translated into English 
 Verse. By ROBERT WHITELAW, M.A. 
 Assistant-Master in Rugby School ; late 
 Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge. 
 Crown Svo. 85. 6d. 
 
 I STEEL (J. H.). WORKS BY. 
 
 A Treatise on the Diseases of 
 the Dog; being a Manual of 
 Canine Pathology. 88 Illustrations. 
 Svo. IO5. 6d. 
 
 A Treatise on the Diseases of 
 
 the Ox ; being a Manual of 
 Bovine Pathology. 2 Plates and 117 
 Woodcuts. Svo. 155. 
 
 A Treatise on the Diseases of 
 the Sheep ; being a Manual of 
 
 Ovine Pathology. With Coloured Plate 
 and 99 Woodcuts. 8vo. 1 2s. 
 
 ; STEPHEN. Essays in Ecclesi- 
 astical Biography. By the 
 
 Right Hon. Sir J. STKPHEN. Crown 
 Svo. 75. f>d. 
 
 STEPHENS. A History of the 
 French Revolution. By H. 
 
 MORSE STEPHENS, Balliol College, 
 Oxford. 3 vols. Svo. Vols. I. and II. 185. 
 each.
 
 A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS IN GENERAL LITERATURE 
 
 STE VENSON (RoU. Louis}. WORKS 
 BY. 
 
 A Child's Garden of Verses. 
 
 Small Fcp. Svo. 55. 
 
 A Child's Garland of Songs, 
 
 Gathered from ' A Child's Garden of 
 Verses'. By ROBERT Louis STEVEN- 
 SON, and set to Music by C. VILLIERS 
 STANFORD, Mus. Doc. 410. is. sewed, 
 y. 6d. cloth gilt. 
 
 The Dynamiter. Fcp. 8vo. I*. 
 
 sewed ; is. 6d. cloth. 
 
 Strange Case of Dr. Jekyll and 
 Mr. Hyde. Fcp. 8vo. i*. swd. : 
 
 is. 6d. cloth. 
 
 STEVENSON and OSBOURNE. 
 The Wrong Box. By ROBERT 
 Louis STEVENSON and LLOYD OS- 
 BOURNE. Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 STOCK. Deductive Logic. By 
 
 ST. GEORGE STOCK. Fcp. Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 1 STONEHENGE '.The Dog in 
 Health and Disease. By 
 
 'STONEHENGE'. With 84 Wood En- 
 gravings. Square Crown Svo. 7s. 6d. 
 
 STRONG, LOG EM A N, and 
 WHEELER. Introduction to 
 the Study of the History of 
 Language. By HERBERT A. 
 STRONG, M.A., LL.D. ; WILI.EM S. 
 LOGEMAN ; and BENJAMIN IDE 
 WHEELER. Svo. IDS. 6d. 
 
 SULLY (James}. WORKS BY. 
 
 The Human Mind : a Text- Book 
 
 of Psychology. 2 vols. Svo. zis. 
 
 Outlines of Psychology. With 
 
 Special Reference to the Theory of Edu- 
 cation. Svo. ioj. 
 
 The Teacher's Handbook of 
 Psychology, on the Basis of 
 
 ' Outlines of Psychology '. Cr. Svo. 5-r. 
 
 Supernatural Religion ; an In- 
 quiry into the Reality of Divine Reve- 
 lation. 3 vols. Svo. 365. 
 
 Reply (A) to Dr. Lightfoot's 
 Essays. By the Author of ' Super- 
 natural Religion '. Svo. 6s. 
 
 SWINBURNE. Picture Logic ; an 
 
 Attempt to Popularise the Science of 
 Reasoning. By A. J. SWINBURNE, B. A. 
 Post Svo. 5s. 
 
 SYMES (J. E.}. WORKS BY. 
 
 Prelude to Modern History: 
 
 being a Brief Sketch of the World's 
 History from the Third to the Ninth 
 Century. With 5 Maps. Crown Svo. 
 2s. 6d. 
 
 A Companion to School His- 
 tories of England. Crown 
 
 Svo. 25. 6d. 
 
 Political Economy. With Prob- 
 lems for Solution, and Hints for Sup- 
 plementary Reading. Crown Svo. 2s. 6d. 
 
 TAYLOR. A Student's Manual of 
 the History of India. By 
 
 Colonel MEADOWS TAYLOR, C.S.I., &c. 
 Crown Svo. 75. 6d. 
 
 THOMPSON (D. Grcenlecif). WORKS 
 BY. 
 
 The Problem of Evil : an Intro- 
 duction to the Practical Sciences. Svo. 
 los. 6d. 
 
 A System of Psychology. 2 vols. 
 
 Svo. 365. 
 
 The Religious Sentiments of 
 the Human Mind. 8vo. 7*. 6d. 
 
 Social Progress : an Essay. Svo. 
 75. 6d. 
 
 The Philosophy of Fiction in 
 Literature : an Essay. Cr. 8vo.6^. 
 
 Three in Norway. By Two of 
 
 THEM. With a Map and 59 Illustrations. 
 Cr. Svo. 2s. boards; 2s. 6d. cloth. 
 
 THOMSON. Outlines of the 
 Necessary Laws of Thought: 
 
 a Treatise on Pure and Applied Logic. 
 By the Most Rev. WILLIAM THOMSON, 
 D.D., late Lord Archbishop of York. 
 Post Svo. 6s. 
 
 TIREBUCK.Dorrie: a Novel. By 
 WILLIAM TIREBUCK. Crown SVG. 6s. 
 
 TOYNBEE. Lectures on the In- 
 dustrial Revolution of the 
 i8th Century in England. 
 
 By ARNOLD TOYNBEE. Svo. los. 6d. 
 
 TREVELYAN (Sir G. 0., Bart.}. 
 WORKS BY. 
 
 The Life and Letters of Lord 
 Macaulay. 
 
 POPULAR EDITION, Crown Svo. as. 6d. 
 STUDENT'S EDITION, Crown Svo. 6s. 
 CABINET EDITION, 2 vols. Cr. Svo. 125. 
 LIBRARY EDITION, 2 vols. Svo. 365. 
 
 [Continued on next page.
 
 PUBLISHED BV MESSRS. LONGMANS, GREEN, & CO. 
 
 TREVELYAX (Sir G. O., /*///.). 
 WORKS BY. continued. 
 
 The Early History of Charles 
 James Fox. Library Edition, 
 
 8vo. 185. Cabinet Edition, Cr. 8vo. 6s. 
 
 TROLLOPE(Anthony}. NOVELS BY. 
 The Warden. Crown 8vo. is. 
 
 boards; is. 6d. cloth. 
 
 Barchester Towers. Crown 8vo. 
 
 is. boards ; is. 6d. cloth. 
 
 VERNEY. Memoirs of the Ver- 
 ney Family during the Civil 
 War. Compiled from the Letters 
 
 and Illustrated by the Portraits at Clay- 
 don House, Bucks. By FRANCES PAR- 
 THKNOPE VERNEY. With a Preface by 
 S. R. GARDINER, M.A., LL.D. With 
 38 Portraits, Woodcuts and Facsimile. 
 2 vols. Royal 8vo. 4.2s. 
 
 VILLE.The Perplexed Farmer: 
 
 How is he to meet Alien Competition ? 
 By GEORGE VILLE. Translated from the 
 French by WlI.LTAM CROOKES, F.R.S., 
 V.P.C.S., &c. Crown 8vo. 5-r. 
 
 VIRGIL. Publi Vergili Maronis 
 Bucolica, Georgica, ALneis; 
 
 The Works of VIRGIL, Latin Text, with 
 English Commentary and Index. By 
 B. H. KENNEDY, D.D. Cr. 8vo. IDS. 6d. 
 
 The ^Eneid of Virgil. Translated 
 
 into English Verse. By JOHN CONING- 
 TON, M.A. Crown 8vo. 65. 
 
 The Poems of Virgil. Translated 
 
 into English Prose. By JOHN CONING- 
 TON, M.A. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 The Eclogues and Georgics of 
 Virgil. Translated from the 
 Latin by J. W. MACKAII., M.A., Fellow 
 of Balliol College, Oxford. Printed on 
 Dutch Hand-made Paper. Royal i6mo. 
 5*- 
 
 WAKEMAN and HASSALL. 
 Essays Introductory to the 
 Study of English Constitu- 
 tional History. By Resident 
 
 Members of the University of Oxford. 
 Edited by HENRY OFFLEY WAKEMAN, 
 M.A., and ARTHUR HASSALL, M.A. 
 Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 WALFORD. The Mischief of 
 Monica: a Novel. By L. B. 
 WALFORD. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 WALKER. The Correct Card ; or 
 
 How to Play at Whist ; a Whist Cate- 
 chism. By Major A. CAMPBELL- 
 WALKER, F.R.G.S. Fcp. 8vo. as. 6d. 
 
 WALPOLE. History of England 
 from the Conclusion of the 
 Great War in 1815 to 1858. 
 
 By SPENCER WALPOLE. Library Edition. 
 
 5 vols. Svo. ^"4 I os. Cabinet Edition. 
 
 6 vols. Crown Svo. 6s. each. 
 
 WELLINGTON. Life of the Duke 
 of Wellington. By the Rev. G. 
 
 R. GLEIG, M.A. Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 WELLS. Recent Economic 
 Changes and their Effect on the 
 
 Production and Distribution of Wealth 
 and the Well-being of Society. By 
 DAVID A. WELLS. Crown Svo. ics. 6d. 
 
 WENDT. Papers on Maritime 
 Legislation, with a Translation 
 of the German Mercantile Laws relating 
 to Maritime Commerce. By ERNEST 
 EMIL WENDT. Royal Svo. \ us. 6d. 
 
 WEST Half-hours with the Mil- 
 lionaires : Showing how much 
 
 harder it is to spend a million than to 
 make it. Edited by B. B. WEST. Crown 
 Svo. 6s. 
 
 WEYMAN. The House of the 
 Wolf: a Romance. By STANLEY 
 J. WEYMAN. Crown Svo. 35. 6d. 
 
 WHAT ELY (E. Jane). WORKS BY. 
 English Synonyms. Edited by 
 R. WHATELY, D.D. Fcp. Svo. 35. 
 
 Life and Correspondence of 
 Richard Whately, D.D., late 
 
 Archbishop of Dublin. With Portrait. 
 Crown Svo. IDS. 6d. 
 
 WHATELY (Archbishop). WORKS 
 BY. 
 
 Elements of Logic. Crown Svo. 
 
 45. 6d. 
 
 Elements of Rhetoric. Crown 
 
 8vo. 45. 6d. 
 
 Lessons on Reasoning. Fcp. 
 
 8vo. is. 6d. 
 
 Bacon's Essays, with Annotations. 
 8vo. I os. 6d. 
 
 Whist in Diagrams : a Supplement 
 
 to American Whist, Illustrated ; being a 
 Series of Hands played through, Illus- 
 trating the American leads, the new play, 
 the forms of Finesse, and celebrated coups 
 of Masters. With Explanation and 
 Analysis. By G. W. P. Fcp. Svo. 6s. 6d.
 
 41717 
 
 A CATALOGUE OF BOOKS IN GENERAL LITERATURE. 
 
 WILCOCKS. The Sea Fisherman, i 
 
 Comprising the Chief Methods of Hook ; 
 and Line Fishing in the British and other j 
 Seas, and Remarks on Nets, Boats, and i 
 Boating. By J. C. WILCOCKS. Pro- j 
 fusely Illustrated. Crown 8vo. 6s. 
 
 WILLIOH. Popular Tables for; 
 
 giving Information for ascertaining the j 
 value of Lifehold, Leasehold, and Church j 
 Property, the Public Funds, &c. By 
 CHARLES M. WILLICH. Edited by : 
 H. BENCE JONES. Crown 8vo. los. 6d. \ 
 
 WILLOUGHBY. East Africa and 
 its Big Game. By Capt. Sir j 
 JOHN C. WILLOUGHBY, Bart. Illus- j 
 trated by G. D. Giles and Mrs. Gordon j 
 Hake. Royal 8vo. 2 is. 
 
 WITT (Prof.}. WORKS BY. Trans- ! 
 lated by FRANCES YOUNGHUSBAND. 
 
 The Trojan War. Crown 8vo. 2s. 
 Myths of Hellas ; or, Greek Tales. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 31. 6d. 
 
 The Wanderings of Ulysses. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 35. (>d . 
 
 The Retreat of the Ten Thou- 
 sand ; being the story of Xeno- 
 phon's ' Anabasis '. With Illustrations. 
 Crown 8vo. y. 6d. 
 
 WOLFF (Henry W.). WORKS BY. 
 
 Rambles in the Black Forest. 
 
 Crown 8vo. 75. f>d. 
 
 The Watering Places of the 
 VosgCS. Crown 8vo. 4*. 6d. 
 
 The Country of the Vosges. 
 
 With a Map. 8vo. 1 2s. 
 WOOD (Rev. J. G.}. WORKS BY. 
 
 Homes Without Hands ; a De- 
 scription of the Habitations of Animals, 
 classed according to the Principle of Con- 
 struction. With 140 Illustrations. 8vo. 
 75. net. 
 
 Insects at Home; a Popular 
 
 Account of British Insects, their Struc- 
 ture, Habits, and Transformations. With 
 700 Illustrations. 8vo. js. net. 
 
 Insects Abroad; a Popular Account 
 
 of Foreign Insects, their Structure, 
 Habits, and Transformations. With 
 600 Illustrations. 8vo. js. net. 
 
 10,000/6/92. 
 
 WOOD (Rev. J G.). WORKS BY. 
 
 continued. 
 Bible Animals ; a Description of 
 
 every Living Creature mentioned in the 
 Scriptures. With 112 Illustrations. 8vo. 
 75. net. 
 
 Strange Dwellings ; a Description 
 
 of the Habitations of Animals, abridged 
 from ' Homes without Hands '. With 
 60 Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 35. 6d. 
 
 Out of Doors ; a Selection of 
 Original Articles on Practical Natural 
 History. With n Illustrations. Crown 
 8vo. 35. >d. 
 
 Petland Revisited. With 33 
 
 Illustrations. Crown 8vo. 35. 6<f. 
 
 WORDSWORTH. Annals of My 
 Early Life, 1806-46. By 
 
 CHARLES WORDSWORTH, D.C.L., 
 Bishop of St. Andrews. 8vo. i$s. 
 
 WYLIE. History of England 
 under Henry IV. By JAMES 
 
 HAMILTON WYLIE. 2 vols. Vol. I., 
 
 1399-1404. Crown 8vo. los. 6d. Vol. II. 
 
 [In the Press. 
 
 YO UA TT ( William}. WORKS B Y. 
 The Horse. Revised and enlarged. 
 8vo. Woodcuts, 75. 6d. 
 
 The Dog. Revised and enlarged. 
 8vo. Woodcuts, 65. 
 
 ZELLER (Dr. E.}. WORKS BY. 
 History of Eclecticism in Greek 
 Philosophy. Translated by 
 SAKAH F. ALLEYNE. Cr. 8vo. los. 6d. 
 
 The Stoics, Epicureans, and 
 Sceptics. Translated by the Rev. 
 O. J. REICHEL, M.A. Crown 8vo. 155. 
 
 Socrates and the Socratic 
 Schools. Translated by the Rev. 
 O. J. REICHEL, M.A. Cr. 8vo. IDS. 6d. 
 
 Plato and the Older Academy. 
 
 Translated by SARAH F. ALLEYNK and 
 ALFRED GOODWIN, B.A. Crown 8vo. 
 i8s. 
 
 The Pre-Socratic Schools: a 
 
 History of Greek Philosophy from the 
 Earliest Period to the time of Socrates. 
 Translated by SARAH F. ALLEYNE. 2 
 vols. Crown 8vo. 305. 
 
 Outlines of the History of Greek 
 Philosophy. Translated by 
 SARAH F. ALLEYNE and EVELYN 
 ABBOTT. Crown 8vo. IDS. >d. 
 
 THE ABERDEEN UNIVERSITY PRESS.
 
 A 000 670 350 
 
 CENTRAL UNIVERSITY LIBRARY 
 
 University of California 
 
 SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY 
 
 305 De Neve Drive - Parking Lot 17 Box 951388 
 
 LOS ANGELES, CALIFORNIA 90095-1388 
 
 Return this material to the library from which it was borrowed.