'^HniimtmiiimiitimmtiitiittHiHuiuiiiiuttntUimtiiitiiiiiiiitiUiii r 6 ■ IsMMMAMT OF THE No. 6 Division Range Shelf....... Received z/-:.£&..A .1S7S. , BOOKSELLEI UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA. GIFT OF DANIEL C. OILMAN . a/r/Z' ' LECTURES ON THE MORAL GOVERNMENT OF GOD. BY NATHANIEL W. TAYLOR, D. D., LATE D WIGHT PPwOFESSOK OF DIDACTIC THEOLOGY IN YALE COLLEGE. " Of Law there can be no less acknowledged than that her seat is the bosom or God — her voice the harmony of the world." VOL. I. NEW YOEK; PUBLISHED BY CLARK, AUSTIN & SMITH, 3 PARK ROW & 3 ANN STREET. 1859. Entered, according to Act of Congress, in the year 1859, by Noah Porter, Samuel G. Buckingham, and Walter T. Hatch. In the Clerk's Office of the District Court of the United States for the Southern District of New York. NEW YORK: C. A. Alvord, Printer and Stereotyper, 15 Vandewater street. INTRODUCTION The Moral Government of God was the great thought of Dr. Taylor's intellect, and the favorite theme of his instructions in theology. It occupied his mind more than any and every other subject. lie was ever ready to enter upon the investi- gation of any truth that was nearly or remotely connected with this. He was never weary of grappling with such inquiries, whether they were suggested for the "first time by his own ingenuity, or had been discussed with greater or less success for centuries by speculative and earnest men. To vindicate the ways of God to man, was the object to which all his ener- gies were consecrated, and upon which were expended the ardor of his glowing soul and the force of his strong and steadfast will. Those secondary objects which the majority of men, even students and theologians, esteem important, were freely sacrificed to the accomplishment of this commanding purpose. To this the whole living man was consecrated with an activity and intensity which have not often been equaled. This object directed all his studies. All his investigations had their starting point from this central theme, and how- ever far he may seem to some to have wandered in the maze of scholastic distinctions or subtle refinements, he never lost the clue by which he returned to the subject of his great argument. Hence his interest in psychology. He studied man as an intellectual and moral being, that he might under- stand God's government over him. It was in the light of man's relations to God, that he sought to know what are his capacities, what his obligations, what his present condition, and IV INTRODUCTION. what liis future destiny. With the same intent he investi- gated with a passionate interest the nature of civil govern- ment, the authority of human law in all its varieties, and the principles by which the various forms of human society are organized and held together. He reasoned, that man being the subject of all these societies, duty being the obligation common to all, and law the expression of the authority by which they are sustained — they must furnish analogies to that moral government of God which comprehends the universe within its dominion. That he might understand this "civi- tas Dei" this "kingdom of God," he studied law, authority, and justice in their essential nature and constituent elements. Indeed, concerning theology itself, he would have adopted with few qualifications the definition given by Leibnitz, u Quce est quasi jurisjprudentia qitcedam specialis, sed eadem funda- mentalis ratione ceterarum. Est enim velut doctrina qucedam de jure publico quod obtinet in rej?ubUca Dei in homines."* Above all, he diligently and earnestly sought to find in the Scriptures a true and consistent system of principles in respect to the government of God ; and to develop such a system from the Scriptures as should be also consistent with the teachings of reason and conscience, he considered the great duty of the student and the teacher of theology. Iiis views of theology as the science which has this for its object, were elevated and even sublime. The enthusiastic language in which he was accustomed to express himself on this inspiring theme, will not soon be forgotten by those who have heard him speak. He tried every system of theology by this test : what are the principles concerning the moral government of God on which it rests, or what are the views of God's authority over man which it inculcates? If its principles were judged to be defective, vague, obscure or false — if the system did not i commend itself to the conscience' by asserting those truths to which the conscience responds, it was rejected wholly or * Diss, de Aete Combin., pp. 20, 21, ed. Erd. INTRODUCTION. V in part, whatever was the authority of the theologian or of the church whose name it bore. It was not, however, solely nor chiefly, from the relations of this subject to scientific theology, that he regarded it as of such commanding importance. His interest in this as in all other subjects, even in theology itself, was founded in a strong conviction of its practical usefulness. While he was a pastor, he wrote two sermons on the Moral Government of God, in order to vindicate the authority of His law, the justice of His retributions, and the necessity of an atonement. His interest in this subject was increased by the illustration of the practical importance of just and well settled principles in regard to it, which was developed in the Unitarian controversy. He con- stantly and earnestly insisted, that by the Christian preacher no subject needed to be so well understood, to enable him suc- cessfully to defend and enforce the great truths of the gospel. In his intercourse with his fellow-men and in the conduct of his own life, he manifested a loyalty to the King of Heaven, even in connection with the most trivial events, which lent a charm to all the manifestations of his character. In times of a^o- nizing sorrow, he would utter great truths concerning God's administration, its glory and goodness, which showed that his principles on these subjects were his daily sustenance and com- fort. One of the most impressive scenes of his last days was the utterance at parting with a friend, in tones of almost se- raphic ardor, of the ascription of the apostle, " Now unto the King eternal, immortal, invisible, the only wise God, be honor and glory forever and ever." The writers to whom Dr. Taylor was most indebted, and whose principles he sought to apply, to complete, and in some cases to correct, were Bishop Butler and Jonathan Edwards. Bishop Butler suggested the principles and the course of argument concerning the benevolence and equity of God's government, which were matured by him into a more exact system, and carried only to their legitimate conclusions. Presi- dent Edwards was often in his hands, and the careful reader of VI INTRODUCTION. these volumes will see the relation of many of the discussions, to the teachings of that prince of New England divines, and to the whole current of what is called New England theology. The works of all the New England divines were the familiar hand-books of his reading. He was also entirely at home with the writers on natural theology, for which the English church in other times was so distinguished. From all of these authors, and the bold and energetic workings of his own mind, he rea- soned out the system of principles and conclusions which is found in these volumes. These lectures were not delivered in precisely the same order and continuous succession in which they are now presented to the reader. They were given in different portions, as parts of a course of theological instruction, each in its assigned position, and were separated from each other by the discus- sion of other topics. It was thought expedient, however, to arrange them in a continuous series, so as to present a com- plete and connected view of all that he wrote on this fun- damental topic in theology. To' the lectures on moral gov- ernment, have been appended other essays and lectures on subjects that are naturally connected with this. The first section embraces the discussion of the essential nature of moral government, preliminary to any inquiries as to what is the actual government of the universe, as we dis- cover it by the light of nature. Section second treats of that government as it is made known by the light of nature, and discusses some of those questions of fact concerning the actual administration of the universe, which are appropriate to natural theology. The last four lectures of this section present a brief view of the necessity and evidences of reve- lation, so far as the light of nature and the lessons of human experience furnish the materials for an argument. Section third contains an extended discussion of the government of God as exhibited in revelation. Such a discussion should, in one view of the subject, according to the opinions expressed in the first section by the author, comprehend a complete system INTRODUCTION. Vii of revealed theology. It in fact gives us only his views of the nature of the Jewish Theocracy, as being a representation or visible manifestation of the unseen kingdom of God, and a careful examination of the law of God as it is revealed in this theocracy, and by the direct teachings of. the Scriptures. The opinions of the author in respect to some of the most important doctrines of the Scriptures, are however given with great distinctness, in connection with the treatment of his principal theme. Indeed, the most superficial reader of these lectures cannot fail to see in them all, from the beginning to the end — even the most abstract and metaphysical — a distinct and direct reference to the doctrines of atonement and justification. In the Appendix, will be found an essay on "Justice," which has a double interest, as a vigorous handling of the theme in its relations to civil society and the rights of man, and also in its bearings upon certain theological theories of the atonement. The essay on " the Providential Government and Purposes of God" is intimately related to the just and exact understanding of his moral government. The discussion of the question, " In what sense God can purpose opposite events," naturally arises in every attempt to vindicate the Holy One from responsibility for moral evil. The essay on " the Penalties of the Civil Law" is explained by its relation to the lecture, out of which it arises. The discussion of Miracles seems to be required by the lectures in the first volume that treat of the philosophical possibil- ity and truth of the Christian revelation. The Lectures and Appendix present the views of the author upon some of the most important questions involved in the nature and the evidences of natural and revealed theology. These views it seemed desirable to collect and arrange in a single work. The opinions expressed are given to the reader as the author believed and taught, and in the language in which he uttered them. His style was formed in the school of Butler and Ed- wards, and owes some of its peculiarities to the constant repe- tition of those definitions and distinctions, which he wished to impress upon the ear and to fix in the minds of the pupils Vlll INTRODUCTION. who heard him. His style was adapted to the ear, and not to the eye ; it was formed in and for the lecture-room, not for the printed page. Practiced critics and editors will easily under- stand how difficult it is to condense or correct such a style. It may be interesting to some of Dr. Taylor's friends and pupils to know, that the first lecture in the second volume was written only a few months before his death. It is almost the last word concerning the importance of a correct and vigorous theology which he was permitted to write, and may be viewed as his dying testimony on this most important theme. K P. Yale College, Jan. 19, 1859. CONTENTS SECTION I. WHAT IS A PERFECT MORAL GOVERNMENT ? OR, MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. LECTURE I. PAGE Can we determine the nature of a perfect Moral Government? — A perfect Moral Govern- ment denned. — The definition explained and vindicated in the following particulars : I. Moral Government is an influence on moral beings. II. Moral Government implies a moral Governor. III. Moral Government is designed so to control the action of moral beings, as to se- cure the great end of action on their part IV. The influence of a perfect Moral Government is the influence of authority 1 LECTURE II. V. A perfect Moral Government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of law.— The nature of such a law.— First, It is a decisive rule of action to subjects.— Sec- ondly, It must require benevolence as the best kind of action, and must forbid selfish- ness as the worst kind of action. — Viewed in relation to these objects, and to the agent who exercises them, these affections are supreme, intelligent, morally free, permanent, and predominant 16 LECTURE III. V. A perfect Moral Government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of law. — The nature of such a law further unfolded. — Third characteristic of the law so de- manded in a perfect Moral Government, viz. : it requires benevolence and forbids selfish- ness.— Relation of predominant to subordinate action.— Benevolence and selfishness de- fined. — These constitute the only kind of action possible to a moral being. — Manner in which the law requires and forbids subordinate action. — Benevolence and selfishness the only morally right and wrong actions ... - 47 LECTURE IV. V. A perfect Moral Government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of law. — The nature of law further unfolded. — 4. It must express the Lawgiver's prefer- ence of the action required, to its opposite, all things considered — 5. It implies, that the Lawgiver can be satisfied with obedience, and with nothing but obedience, on the part of the subject— 6. It expresses his highest approbation of obedience and his highest disap- probation of disobedience G9 CONTENTS. LECTURE V. PAGE Y. A perfect Moral Government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of law.— The nature of such a law further unfolded.— 7. The law of a perfect Moral Gov- ernment involves sanctions. — The relations of a Moral Governor to his kingdom more particularly considered.— Legal sanctions defined.— They establish or ratify the authority of the Moral Governor. — Thoy consist in natural good promised to obedience, and in natural evil threatened to disobedience. — They establish the Moral Governor's authority as its decisive proof. — They become decisive proof of the Moral Governor's authority by manifesting his benevolence in the form of his highest approbation of obedience, and highest disapprobation of disobedience.— It is not incredible that God in the Scriptures should express his highest approbation of obedience and his highest disapprobation of disobedience to His law 82 LECTURE VI. V. A perfect Moral Government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of law. — The nature of such a law further unfolded. — 7. The law of a perfect Moral Gov- ernment involves sanctions, (continued.) — 5th. Legal sanctions the necessary proof of the Moral Governor's authority as the necessary manifestations and proofs of his benev- olence in the form of his approbation of obedience and his highest disapprobation of dis- obedience. — This shown by proving (1,) that legal sanctions are in some respect neces- sary as the proof of the Moral Governor's authority ; (2,) that they are necessary for this purpose, as the necessary proofs of his benevolence ; and (3,) that they are necessary proofs of his benevolence in the form of his highest approbation of obedience and high- est disapprobation of disobedience. — The (1) and (2) of these arguments are treated in this lecture. — (1.) Legal Sanctions are necessary in some respect as proof of the Moral Governor's authority. — Argued from the import of the phrase legal sanctions ; from the nature of the law of a perfect Moral Government ; from the nature of a law or rule of action without sanctions ; from the fact that conformity and nonconformity to a rule without sanctions would subvert the Moral Governor's authority. — (2.) They are neces- sary as proofs of the Governor's authority as they are the necessary proofs of his benev- olence.— Eeason given why attempts to prove the benevolence of God from the light of nature are so unsuccessful 105 LECTURE VII. Y. A perfect Moral Government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of law.— The nature of the law further unfolded.— 7. The law of a perfect Moral Govern- ment involves sanctions.— 5th. The necessity of legal sanctions shown.— (3,) because they are the necessary proofs of his benevolence in the forms of his highest approbation of obedience and highest disapprobation of disobedience.— This is argued ; first, from the insufficiency of another mode of proving his benevolence ; second, from the nature of legal sanctions as already explained ; third, from the view of the sanctions of the supreme law of the state.— Remaeks : 1. Christianity is not a selfish system of religion ; 2. What it is to make light of the divine threatenings ; 3. They who deny the view now given of the sanctions of a perfect Moral Government cannot prove the benevolence of God 127 LECTURE VIII. Y. A perfect Moral Government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of law. — The nature of the law further unfolded. — Seventhly. The law of a perfect Moral Government involves the requisite sanctions of the Moral Governor's authority. — 6th. CONTENTS. XI Legal sanctions include the highest possible degree of natnral good, &c, and the highest possible degree of evil.— Objections.— Punishment ought to terminate with sin ; if all should disobey, all ought not to be punished; incredible and impossible that God should adopt a moral system with such liabilities.— Conclusion 160 SECTION II. THE MORAL GOVERNMENT OF GOD AS E^OWN BY THE LIGHT OF NATURE. LECTURE I. Thesis to be established in three leading propositions.— First, God administers a Moral Gov- ernment in some sense ; for, 1, men are moral beings ; 2, God has given them a law. — Shown from the manifestation of the tendencies of action to good and evil.— No oppos- ing evidence.— Perversion of a design does not disprove the reality of the design ; nor the fact that such perversion was foreseen; nor that the perversion is universal. — The perversion observed may bo temporary. — Tendency to wrong, not greater than to right action. — Cause of the certainty but not of the necessity of such perversion. — The only proper method of reasoning. — Conclusion 1 S4 LECTURE II. 3. First leading proposition continued.— God enforces conformity to his law by authority.— (a) He assumes the right to give a law.— (6) He dispenses good and evil as powerful in- ducements ;— for good and evil are the proper effects of right and wrong action ;— as self- complacency and remorse are enjoyed and suffered ; reflection can be avoided only in part; — (c) The providence of God in other ways works against evil and for good by dis- cipline, restraint, sickness, disappointment, death.— Forebodings of evil after death. 203 LECTURE III. Second leading proposition.— God's administration is equitable— proved by showing, 1. That God has given the best law, 2. That he distributes good and evil equitably.— In opposition to this proposition, the unequal distribution of good and evil has caused the chief diffi- culty.— Various theories resorted to. — Is the difficulty real ?— (a) Greater difficulties in denying God's equity than in admitting it.— (ft) No proof against it; for God is not in- equitable in treating men better than they deserve, nor in treating them worse. More rational to regard this distribution as explicable in some unknown way. God may be administering a moral government under a gracious economy. — (c) There is satisfactory proof for his equity— the arguments probable and cumulative 217 LECTURE IV. Second leading proposition continued, viz. : God administers an equitable moral govern- ment. — The possibility of a future state precludes all objections against the Divine equity. — No presumption against a future state. — No proof the soul is material. — No evidence that death destroys the soul.— Direct proofs of a future state.— Kind of evi- dence furnished. — No cause known which can destroy the soul. — Every thing which has begun continues to exist.— The present state unsuitable to the natural perfection of man. — Argument from man's moral nature decisive 230 Xll CONTENTS. LECTURE V. PAGE Second leading proposition continued, viz. : God administers an equitable moral govern- ment. — God administers his moral government under a gracious economy. — Explana- tion. — Proof 1. The manner in which he administers good and evil harmonizes with such an economy. — 2. Distribution of good and evil proves a design to recover. — (a) A virtu- ous life the happiest.— (b) Gifts of God tend to gratitude.— (c) Natural evils prove the same design. — (d) The present a state of discipline. — (e) The happiness of man in his own power. — {/) Without forgiveness, reclaiming influences vain. God's favor can be secured only on the terms which Christianity prescribes, whether Christianity is or is not from God 245 LECTURE VI. Second leading proposition continued, viz. : God administers an equitable moral govern- ment; also, God administers a moral government under a gracious economy.— Proof 3. "We must suppose God to administer his government in the way of exact retribution, or through an atonement. — One of these is true, or God is deficient in power, or malignant in intention. — Just conception of Benevolence in God. — What is Justice in God. — Infi- dels have false views of both.— Dispensations of God's Providence prove him not to ba weak. — The equity of a moral government can be consistent with mercy only through an atonement. — Alternative for the unbeliever 268 LECTURE VII. Third leading proposition : God governs with rightful authority. — This proved by his benev- olence. — Different opinions in respect to the method of proving his benevolence. — If it cannot be proved by the right of nature, it cannot be proved at all. — The Scriptures as- sert and assume that this benevolence is manifest by the light of nature 276 LECTURE VIII. Third leading proposition continued, viz. : God governs with rightful authority. — The be- nevolence of God may be proved, 1. From his natural attributes. — Nature of the argu- ment. — 2. From his works. — Preliminary definitions and explanations. — God is proved to be perfectly benevolent, by showing, {a) that the present system may be the best pos- sible; (b) that it is the best possible.— Prop, (a) considered.— Objection from existence of evil. — Evil is natural and moral. — Natural evil considered in the sufferings of infants, of animals, and of men as moral beings 2SS LECTURE IX. Third leading proposition continued, viz. : God governs with rightful authority. — God is be- nevolent, because the present system may be the best possible. — Objection from the exist- ence of moral eviL — There may be an impossibility, in the nature of things, that it should be prevented. Assuming that a moral system may be the best, 1. It may be impossible to prevent all sin under a moral system.— 2. If this is not true, it may be impossible un- der the best moral system 302 LECTURE X. Third leading proposition continued, viz.: God governs with rightful authority.— God is benevolent. — 2. The present system not only may be, but is the best possible to the Creator. — (a) It is better than none. — Happiness greater than misery in this life. — Ee- sults in a future world. — (b) It is the best possible. — No proof that a better could be CONTENTS. xiii adopted.— The present, in its nature and tendencies, is the best conceivable, and there- fore the be6t possible. — This argued under two heads; 1. From its general form as a moral system, in respect to the kind of beings and the kind of influence used.— 2. From its particular forms as a moral system, as involving influences from the nature and ten- dencies of moral action, from moral government, from an equitable moral government, and the same with a gracious economy. — Kemark 326 LECTURE XI. APPLICATION OF THE ARGUMENT FROM NATURE, TO PROVE THAT CHRISTIANITY IS FROM GOD. Nature of Divine Revelation. — Argument for its necessity.— Different views of the grounds of this. — I. Not necessary, because man cannot discover moral and religious truth ; but II. Necessary, 1. To make known the truth in the most perfect method, espe- cially by language.— Absurdity of objecting to this medium.— 2. To receive the prac- tical influence of such truth. — The experiment by the light of nature decisive, shown by the ancient philosophers. — Their views scanty, vacillating, erroneous. — Practical in- fluence feeble on themselves and others. — Prevalence of immorality. — Their teachings and example limited 350 LECTURE XII. Argument for necessity of revelation continued : Prop. 2 continued. — Revelation necessary to secure the practical influence of the truth. — Argued from the state of Pagan na- tions at present.— From the influence of Deism.— Deists greatly indebted to Christian- ity. — The influence of their systems is feeble, scanty and uncertain, denies the holiness and justice of God.— Their views of sin and repentance defective.— Their morality superficial. — Men are not made better by them. — Little zeal for reforming men by them.— Give no comfort in death.— Prop. 3. Revelation necessary to make known truth undiscoverable without it.— Conclusion 865 LECTURE XIII. DreECT Argument.— Question proposed.— Preliminary remarks.— 1. Question to be decided by human reason.— Limits of reason.— Perversion of reason.— 2. Rational to believe in divine origin of Christianity on low evidence. — Relation of Christianity to our character and life'. — Conclusions from this principle. — a. Unjust to demand high degree of evi- dence. — b. Shows the true cause of Infidelity. — c. The most promising method of con- vincing men of the truth. — rf. The reasonableness of faith in unlearned men. — 3. Com- mon facts and principles must be assumed by all parties as premises of argument- Illustrations.— How common premises may be fixed and agreed on.— Argument stated in four propositions. — First two have been previously proved 382 LECTURE XIV. Direct Aegixment continued.— Two remaining propositions considered.— Prop. 3. The im- portance of revelation renders it probable, if not certain, that God would give a revela- tion.— Opposed by some.— Their views discussed.— Man not competent to decide on the manner, &c, of revelation.— Recapitulation of argument on necessity of revelation. — Prop. 4. That which claims to be a revelation, is what it claims to be.— Conclusion. 403 THE MORAL GOVERNMENT OF GOD. SECTION I. WHAT IS A PERFECT MORAL GOVERNMENT! OK MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. LECTURE I. Can we determine the nature of a perfect Moral Government ?— A perfect Moral Government defined. — The definition explained and vindicated in the following particulars : I. Moral Government is an influence on moral beings. II. Moral Government implies a moral Governor. III. Moral Government is designed so to control the action of moral beings, as to secure th« great end of action on their part. IV. The influence of a perfect Moral Government is the influence of authority. Moral Government may be said in general terms to be the government of moral beings by the influence of authority. It may be distinguished into different kinds, as it is vested in different administrators, and is administered over different communities. The more prominent of these different kinds of moral government are the government of God over his moral creation, which is above every other — the government of the state or civil government, and the government of the family or parental government. We may suppose that both parental and civil governments, as manifestly indispensable in some form to man's present well-being, are alike the ordinances of a benevolent Deity, and subservient to the end of that higher system in which men are more directly the subjects of God's moral dominion. For the purpose however of distinguishing the different kinds of moral government, so far as to aid us in our present Vol. I.— 1 1 2 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. inquiry, we may suppose the family and the state each to ex- ist as a distinct and independent community, and to be under a jurisdiction peculiar and appropriate to itself. As members of these particular communities, men would be under a neces- sity of acting in one manner rather than in another, to secure the highest well-being of the whole. As bound by such a ne- cessity, and capable as moral beings of so acting as to defeat this great end, and to produce the opposite result in misery, they are the lit subjects of moral government, and actually as members of the family and the state, live under such a gov- ernment. Our first notion of moral government is obviously derived from that which is parental, and is extended and modified in that conception which we form of the government of the state. Since however, both are marred by undeniable imper- fection, we can appeal to neither as a perfect example of moral government. Nor can it be pretended that we have any ex- ample of a perfect moral government, which in the present world is fully unfolded to our inspection in all the detail of its administration, and in all the completeness of its issues. The most that can be claimed is, that there is such a govern- ment entered upon — one in the actual progress of administra- tion — one which, though not fully achieving its own perfect end, the highest conceivable well-being of all — is yet so dis- tinctly characterized by a strict adherence to the principles of equity, though modified in their application by a gracious economy, as clearly to reveal its absolute perfection. By a perfect moral government then, is here meant not a moral government which actually secures, but one which in its true nature and tendency is perfectly adapted to secure, and which unperverted would secure the great and true end of such a government, even the highest conceivable well-being of its subjects. We may suppose such a government to exist, and the end which it is designed and fitted to accomplish, to be partially or wholly defeated, solely through perversion by its subjects. Such perversion however, would in no degree obscure, but necessarily imply the absolute perfection of the system. Nor if we suppose, that on account of the foreseen perversion of a perfect system, it would be better in relation to actual results to adopt another system, still the adoption of the latter could be justified only on the ground of the foreseen THE ESSENTIAL ELEMENTS. 3 perversion in fact of the former, and would therefore imply its absolute perfection. We may further suppose that an abso- lutely perfect system of moral government would be adopted by an infinitely perfect Being, notwithstanding he should fore- see some degree of actual perversion and counteraction of its tendencies ; for it might still be true, that he should also fore- see that the actual results of such a system w r ould be far bet- ter than those of an imperfect system, even the best possible which he can secure. Can we then know what are the essential elements of a perfect moral government — those elements which must consti- tute such a government in the hands of an infinitely perfect Being, the knowledge of which must be of the highest con- cern to us, as the subjects of such a government? I answer, that there is no subject which mankind generally better under- stand ; none which they are under a more imperious necessity of understanding than moral government in some of its exist- ing forms ; none of whose reality they have a more constant and sure conviction ; none of whose nature in all essential re- spects they have a more adequate comprehension. There can- not be an existing state of man, as related to man, there can- not be a social state (and without this man can exist to no im- portant purpose), from which the idea of a moral government and the full conviction of its reality and necessity can be sepa- rated. This conviction begins almost with our existence, even so early as when the mother by some look or action first im- presses the mind of the child with the necessity of submitting his will to her will. Thus the condition of human infancy places us from the beginning in society, and naturally and necessarily introduces subjection to superior wisdom, power and goodness. From the dawn of the intellect, our parents jn-escribe things to be done, and forbid things not to be done, approving and disapproving, rewarding and punishing accord- ing to our doings. Thus they early assume authority over us, aiming at one comprehensive result in all our doings — that of bringing our will into conformity with theirs. Now why is this, and who does not know why it is ? It is because no family could subsist, much less be prosperous and happy without it. No matter how powerful may be the mo- tives in other forms of exhibition, to promote the harmony and well-being of the domestic circle — no matter how strong the 4 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. mutual affections which prevail, nor how wise and good the counsels and advice which are given, it would all be naught, were there no law, no authority, no calling to account, no retribution, that is, no moral government. Why is this? Let the appeal be made to any parent who has the heart of a parent. Why is it, that he governs his children by authority; why assume this prerogative as unquestionable? Is it, that he takes pleasure in so doing for its own sake ? Is it, that he loves for its own sake, to restrain their liberty, to cross their inclinations and often to inflict suffering? Or, is it because he knows their incompetence to govern themselves as well as lie can govern them — because he knows their ignorance, their passion, their waywardness, and because he knows, that he should be wanting in affection and a due parental oversight and guardianship, if he did not do, what he so surely knows to be for the best? In a word, is it not because he knows the necessity to the well-being of 'the family ', of maintaining, do what else he. may, parental authority f What parent, what child, what human being does not understand the nature, the design, and the necessity of moral government ? Who does not know all this, as it results from the nature of the human mind, as surely as he knows the necessity of food and of common air, which arises from the nature of the human body? If we pass from the family to the state, we iind the same familiar and well-known thing, having a wider range, and a higher end ; though more rigorously maintained in its adminis- tration, and more fully developed in its nature and essential characteristics. Born, as most men are under some form of civil government, they learn what it is for some ruling power to exercise authority over many, as the necessary means of a nation's welfare. Here we find for the most part a great vari- ety of statutes and enactments, having respect to the overt doings of men, but all based on one fundamental law; all implying its existence, and its supreme obligation, — the law of subjection to the powers that be. We find a sovereign Will — a Moral Governor — and the great fact assumed, conceded, and acted upon— the absolute necessity of authoritative law — of a supreme unquestionable right to govern. We find a necessity of it to the existence and well-being of the state — yea, to the prevention of utter anarchy and wretchedness — which no one in his senses can doubt, dispute or deny. Sup- NECESSARY TO TITE STATE. 5 pose what else we may, either in respect to him who governs or those who are governed ; the authority of law must be recognized and maintained, or all is lost. Whatever sacrifice may be involved — whatever may be lost or gained, this one thing — this indispensable means of the public weal must be maintained. And who does not understand the nature, the de- sign, the necessity of civil government ? Who does not know, that without it human society could not exist — much less attain any tolerable degree of prosperity and enjoyment? What could be done without the fundamental law, claiming submis- sion to authority — and what would this law be without author- ity sustained by sanctions — without judges, courts, trials, ex- ecutive officers, sentences passed and executed, and a sovereign will, from which the whole emanates.* I might exhibit the same thing, as it shows itself and its necessity, in lower and feebler forms, in all the relations of life. In our friendships, how much depends on the discharge of certain duties ; how are we held under responsibility, and failing here, how are we judged unworthy, and cast away. In neighborhood intercourse, in private circles, in the forms of politeness, and even in street civilities, who does not know, what it is to be responsible to the will of another, who does not know that in these matters there is a law, that a record is kept, that offenders are marked, that there is a tribunal, a judgment and a retribution ? Indeed were there two, and only two vol- untary beings in the universe, in all respects equals and exist- ing together for their mutual well-being, the will of one in certain respects, would be law to the will of the other, involv- ing the right to enforce it, and with power involving an actual enforcement, by appropriate sanctions. It is the right of one in many cases, to have his will done by another ; and, wherever this right exists, especially with power to enforce it, we have an exemplification of the essential characteristics of moral government, whether this right extends to an individual, a family, an empire or a universe. We all know then, what moral government is, and that men cannot exist in society without it. In that form of it called civil government, the lowest culprit in his prison knows its * In a representative government, I need hardly say, that the sovereign will is that of the people manifested through their representatives. b MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. general nature, its principles, its end, and its absolute neces- sity to this end, as well as the judge who condemns him. Not one of us,if we could not rely on its protection, would dare to go through the streets of our city. Without moral government, we should no sooner venture into human society than venture into a den of wolves. These things are enough to show how necessary moral government is to man, and how well too the thing itself is understood by man. But if neither parental nor civil government furnishes a perfect specimen of moral government, how can one know in what its perfection consists ; or what such a government would be in the hands of a Being of infinite perfection ? I answer that we are able to trace with entire accuracy the essential imperfections of every human specimen, and thus to determine what is essential to constitute a perfect moral gov- ernment. Knowing the end of a moral government, what is fitted to defeat it, and to a greater or less extent, what is adapted to that end and necessary to it, we can to tin's extent decide, what is not and what is, essential to the perfection of such a system. Man may not be qualified to give absolute perfection to such a system, but it does not follow that he can- not conceive of its perfection. Suppose that an absolutely perfect watch has never been made, and never can be by man, does it therefore follow, that it is not easy to conceive of such perfection as within the reach of the power and skill which man does not possess ; or that man himself cannot specify the very changes in the materials or the structure, which would give it absolute perfection? What is supposable in such a case, we claim to be true in that under consideration. We are so well acquainted with the subject, that we know wherein the imper- fection in the work of man consists, and can trace it to its cause. We know so well, what are the true object and end of a moral government, we know so well that by some things that end must be defeated, and we know so well that other things are perfectly adapted to secure that end ; we know so well wherein all human forms of moral government are imperfect, and so well that such deficiencies could not mar a moral government in the hands of an infinitely perfect Being ; we know so well what are the principles of moral action, and what are the means most perfectly fitted to influence moral beings — in short, we know so many things, that we can be at no loss IS AN INFLUENCE ON MORAL BEINGS. 7 to decide what a moral government must be in all essential respects, when administered by a perfect God. I am not saying, that we can tell all that God will or will not do in such an administration, but that we can decide what he will and will not do, in certain important and essential respects. I hope to show you, that there is truth on this sub- ject which man can know, and from which, in its bearings on his immortal interests he cannot escape, and that while there is such a God as Jehovah is clearly revealed, we are not doomed to look out on his ways and his doings as on chaos and dark- ness, but that, with an effulgence as broad as his own creation, and as clear as the light which is poured over it, he shows an end and a system of means worthy of such an author — a moral creation, comprising beings made in his own image, with ten- dencies and sure results that will " answer the great idea of him who made it." I assume, then, what I shall hereafter attempt to prove, and what is properly assumed for the purpose of explanation, that a moral system, or a community of moral beings, as dis- tinguished from any other system not moral, is the best means of the best end, and that a perfect moral government over such a community is the necessary means of accomplishing this end, and is therefore dictated and demanded by perfect benevolence. I now propose to define and explain what I intend by a perfect moral government; and to justify the definition. By a perfect moral government I intend — The influence of the authority, or of the rightful authority of a moral governor on moral beings, designed so to control their action as to secure the great end of action on their part, through the medium of law. In explaining and justifying this definition, I propose to consider the several parts of it, more or less extensively, as the case may seem to require. I. A moral government is an influence on moral beings, or, on beings capable of moral action. While this will be readily admitted, there are some things involved in it, which demand consideration. One is, that the influence of moral government being an influence on moral beings and designed to control moral action, is as diverse in its nature from the influence of physical causes, as moral 8 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. action is from a physical effect ; or as a moral cause is from a physical cause. It is an influence, which is designed aud fitted to give, not the necessity, but merely the certainty of its effect; and which leaves the moral liberty of the subject unimpaired. Hence, it is not essential to this influence that it actually secure the kind of action which it is fitted to secure. A perfect moral government may exist with all its influence, and yet be wholly counteracted in its designed effect on its subjects, since it is obvious that such a government may be maintained over subjects in revolt as well as over subjects who are loyal. Rebellion against government, cannot exist when there is no government. A perfect moral government then, as a government over moral beings, in respect to any cause of action giving the necessity of action, leaves every subject as free to perform the action which it aims to prevent, as to per- form that which it aims to secure. II. A perfect moral government implies a moral gov- ernor. In this respect a moral government differs from a moral sys- tem, as a species differs from a genus. A moral system may be conceived to exist either with or without a moral governor. We can conceive of moral beings, who should act under the direct influence of motives, so far as these reach the mind in the perceived nature, tendencies and consequences of action, though there were no influence of a superior being sustaining the relation of a ruler or moral governor. The direct influence of motives, as these are thus apprehended by the mind, and that influence which results from the character and relation of a moral governor, though different, may yet coexist ; and either may be supposed to exist without the other. The former without the latter would simply imply a moral system without a moral government. The latter with or without the former, would imply a moral system in that particular form which includes a moral government. The peculiar influ- ence therefore, which arises from the character and relation of a moral governor, whether other influences combine with it or not, is the essential constituting influence of moral govern- ment. So far as moral beings act under the peculiar influen- ces of a moral governor, so far and no farther, do they act under the influence of moral government. III. The influence of a perfect moral government is designed PROMOTES THE GREAT END OF ACTION". 9 so to control the action of moral beings, as to secure the great end of action on their part. It will be admitted that this influence is designed to control the action of moral beings in relation to some end which depends on their action in a community of such beings, and which is the best end, and in this sense the great end of such action. What then, is this end ? I answer — It is the produc- tion of well-being, even the highest well-being of all, and the prevention of misery, even the highest misery of all. A moral being is capable of performing two and only two kinds of moral action, and as a subject of moral government, is under an absolute necessity of performing one or the other in all action. He cannot, as a moral being, be inactive. His nature and relations necessarily exclude alike inaction and all neu- trality of action, or action in which he does not act morally. — Again, the nature — the peculiar powers and properties of a moral being — show that he is qualified to perform, what no other being is qualified to perform — that kind of action, which tends to produce the best conceivable end of all action, the highest conceivable well-being of all sentient beings, both of himself and of all others. It is this nature of a moral being, which gives to his existence its peculiar value — its pre-eminent worth, com- pared with the nature of any other being. It is this, which, as a creature, raises man to companionship with his Creator and with creatures the most exalted, and brings him under obliga- tion to act with them in principle, in purpose and in all sub- ordinate and executive doings, for the accomplishment of the great end of all action here on earth, and amid the scenes of eternity. Exalted thus by his nature as a moral being, he is by the same nature qualified to act in a manner which tends to defeat the great end of his creation, and to bring on himself and on all other beings, unmingled and perfect misery. And, what adds inconceivable importance to such a being is, that he cannot avoid, as we have said, acting in one or the other of these two modes of acting now specified. Even in every sub- ordinate action, he acts from principle, he acts with or in the form of, a supreme elective preference. These existing to- gether are often called his action ; and its tendency as moral action is the tendency of his action in its principle ; or rather, l* 10 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. the tendency of the action in principle is its true tendency.* To neglect to act in that mode which is fitted to secure the great and true end of all action on his part, viz., the highest well-being of all — is not only to sacrifice and defeat that end, but it is necessarily to act in that mode, which in its true ten- dency is fitted to produce the opposite result — the highest misery of all. Every thing of real significance in the being of a moral agent, viewed in relation to himself and to other beings, every thing virtuous and praiseworthy in the use of his exalted pow- ers, every thing vicious and blamable in the abuse of them, every thing that is dignified and honorable, every thing that is mean and disgraceful, every thing that affords inward peace and triumph, every thing that brings remorse and despair — every good and every evil to himself and to others — all, all depends on action. The highest happiness and the highest misery of all, all that blesses and all that curses, life and death, are in the power of action. Such issues, according to the true nature and tendencies of things, depend on the action of moral beings. Here, then, the design of a perfect moral government is manifest. The design of the pendulum of a clock to control and direct its motion, so as to mark the divisions of time as the true end of the machine, is not more obvious than is the design of a perfect moral government so to control the action of moral beings, as to secure the great end of action on their part, viz., the production of the highest well-being of all, and the prevention of the highest misery of all. IY. The influence of a perfect moral government is the influence of authority. By the influence of authority, I mean that influence which results from that right to command, which is founded in com- petence and disposition to govern in the best manner, and which imposes an obligation to obey. In other words, it is the influence of a right to command which imposes an ob- * A man may, in subordinate action, love his children, and seek their temporal welfare. But if in so doing, he prefers as he may, this welfare of his children, or any other limited good, to the highest well-being of all, then his action as a whole tends to destroy the highest well-being of all, and to produce their highest misery. For such action is essentially constituted by a principle, which would produce this twofold result, rather than sacrifice the welfare of the children. IS THE INFLUENCE OF AUTHORITY. 11 ligation to obey, as this right results from competence and disposition to give and maintain the best law. Intelligent voluntary beings never act voluntarily without acting from a regard to their own well-being. Instead however, of re- lying wholly, or even partially on their own wisdom or judgment, in respect to the best mode of action, or the mode in which they ought to act, they may rely partially or even wholly on the decision of superior wisdom and superior good- ness. It is true, that the subjects of a moral government may possess such knowledge of the nature and tendency of action on their part, as to know, irrespectively of any decision of the moral governor, that their own highest well-being as well as that of all others can be secured only by conformity to the law of his government. In this way natural good and evil as directly known to result from the nature and tendency of different kinds of action, may concur with the influence of au- thority to secure their conformity to the law. But in that con- formity to law which is secured by the single influence of natural good and evil as motives, there is no recognition of the moral governor's authority. The influence of authority is not the direct influence of natural good and evil reaching the mind through the known nature and tendency of action. It is that influence which results from one's having a right to command by virtue of the superior power, wisdom and goodness, which qualify him to govern in the best manner. So far as this in- fluence reaches moral beings, whether resisted or unresisted by them, they are under the influence of moral government. Where this influence does not exist, there is nothing which can be called moral government. Of the truth of the present position, the slightest attention to the subject will satisfy us. If we suppose a parent or a civil ruler to be without that right to command which imposes an obligation to obey, we cannot regard him as having author- ity, or as administering a moral government — or at most only in pretense. Nor can we suppose one to possess this right and exercise it through the medium of law, without admitting the existence of that which is called a moral government. It is then, this influence — the influence that results from the right to command which imposes an obligation to obey, which is an essential element of moral government. This is the in- fluence of authority. 12 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. The nature of this influence will be more manifest if we look at the basis or source of the right, viz., the competence and disposition of one to govern in the best manner. These qualifications vest him with the right to govern, as they fur- nish or constitute the evidence or proof that he will govern in the best manner, or that his law is the best law, and will be sustained as a decisive rule of action to subjects. Such a gov- ernor ought to be obeyed. Moral obligation is the binding influence of that necessitv, which a moral bein^ is under of performing that action which is decisively proved to be the best action, or to be best fitted to the great end of all action on his part, viz., the highest well-being of all, both of others and of himself. Xow the competence and disposition of the moral governor to give and maintain the best law, is decisive proof that the law which he gives is the best law, and that the action which he requires is the best fitted to the great end of all action, and as such is the best and necessary means of the best end. These qualifications of the moral governor there- fore, as decisive proof that he will govern in the best manner, become a ground of obligation on the part of subjects to obey his law. It is true that the subject, in submitting to the influence of authority, acts from a desire of the highest well-being of others and of himself, as truly as he would, were he influenced by the knowledge of the nature and tendency of action irrespect- ively of the influence of authority. The two influences may and often do coexist. Still, they are different influences. If the nature and tendency of action, as directly apprehended by the mind, or learned by experience, may be one kind of evidence, the character of an infinitely perfect lawgiver may be another kind of evidence that the action required is the best kind of action. If evidence from both sources exists, then the highest evidence supposable in the case exists. If, however, we suppose the evidence from the character of the lawgiver only exists, this is sufficient and decisive evidence that the action required by his law is the best action, and ought to be done. That this evidence is peculiarly fitted to impress the human mind, when compared with any other, we may have occasion to show hereafter. Be this as it may, the exclusive competence and disposition of the moral governor to give and maintain the best law being fully evinced, consti- THE RIGHT OF THE GOVERNOR. 13 tute sufficient and decisive proof that the law requires the best kind of action. This fact being established, the necessity of the action required to the great end of all action, viz., the highest well-being of all, is also established. This necessity of the action required, results in the obligation of the agent to perform the action. Without the manifest necessity of the action to the great end of all action, nothing can be conceived to be true of it which can bind the agent to its performance. With the necessity of the action to this end, nothing can be conceived to set aside his obligation to its performance. So far therefore, as there is any thing in respect to the character or the relation of a moral governor, which creates obligation to obedience on the part of subjects, it is the manifestation of his competence and disposition to govern in the best manner, as a proof that he will so govern. In opposition to the view now maintained, the right to gov- ern is supposed by some to rest on other grounds than com- petence and disposition to govern in the best manner. Thus, the right, in certain cases, is supposed to rest on some peculiar relation. For example, the right of the parent to govern his children, is supposed to rest simply on the relation of the pa- rent. This is obviously mistaking the evidence of the right for the basis of the right. Every such general doctrine or truth as that now referred to, must be determined by some general principle. The general principle, that parents will govern their children better than others will govern them, is justly inferred from the parental relation, and is therefore, the true basis or ground of the parents' right. This is obvious ; for if we reverse the principle — if w T e adopt the principle that others than parents will govern children better than pa- rents, the right to govern them would rest in other hands. Again, it is often maintained that the right of a Creator to govern his creatures, rests simply on his relation as their Crea- tor. The error in this case must be obvious to every one who distinguishes this single relation from the moral character of a Creator. If we suppose him, then, to be a selfish or malig- nant being, having only the designs of such a being to accom- plish by the conduct of his creatures, how could the mere act of creation give him the right to govern ? He could not possess even the right to create beings for his own selfish purposes ; how then, could submission to the will of such a Creator be the 14: MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. duty of his creatures ?* It is true that the act of creation may by its effects be supposed to evince the goodness of the Creator, and so become evidence of his qualification to govern in the best manner, and the ground of his rightful authority. But the act of creation may also by its effects be supposed to evince the malignity of the Creator, or to leave his designs and his character in concealment and in doubt. The act of creation does not necessarily involve his goodness. The act of creation therefore, simply considered, cannot be an ade- quate basis for the right to govern. To sustain the right of civil jurisdiction, various expedients have been resorted to, all of which confirm the view now main- tained. Thus " the divine right of kings" has been a favorite doctrine ; and to exhibit and enforce the right to rule, civil rulers have assumed the exalted titles of " sacred majesty," " God's vice-regent," " God's anointed," " God's representative ;" have claimed descent from gods, and exacted divine worship, and have pretended to have secret intercourse with some di- vinity, or to be gods themselves. All this clearly betrays the principle now maintained, as that which in the view of those who govern and of those who are governed, is the true basis of the right to govern. Some evidently rest the right to govern by law simply on the power to execute its sanctions. This theory obviously places the entire influence of moral government in the influ- ence of natural good and of natural evil, as the one is prom- ised to obedience and the other threatened to disobedience ; viewed only as motives to persuade to the one and dissuade from the other. According to this view, might gives right, and the veriest tyrant with power to execute the sanctions of law, combined with the most fell malignity, has a righteous claim for the unqualified submission of his subjects. On this scheme there can be no fixed standard, no permanent and es- sential elements of right and wrong moral action. All moral distinctions are subverted, and any being having the power, would have the right to fill the universe with misery. This monstrous theory of moral government is the legitimate con- sequence of the selfishness of this selfish world, looking only at natural good and evil in the form of legal reward and * Cicero says, that all religious and pious affection must cease, if love and be- nevolence be denied to God. — De Nat. Deorum L, 144. THE RIGHT OF TIIE GOVERNOR. 15 penalty, as the only motives to secure obedience and prevent disobedience to law. No account is made of the essential ele- ment of a moral government, the influence of authority. The right to govern, which results from competence and disposition to govern in ttie best maimer — the right which imposes an ob- ligation to obey, is unknown, and obedience and disobedience to a moral governor as having this right, are impossible. EEMAEK. In view of the nature of rightful authority, how desirable it is that men should be placed under this influence. WHAT IS A PERFECT MORAL GOVERNMENT? LECTURE II. V. A perfect Moral Government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of law. — The nature of such a law. First, It is a decisive rule of action to subjects. Secondly, It must require benevolence as the best kind of action, and must forbid selfishness as the worst kind of action. Viewed in relation to these objects, and to the agent who exercises them, these affections are supreme, intelligent, morally free, permanent, and predominant. I have said that a moral government is — I. An influence on moral beings ; II. That it implies a moral governor ; III. That it is designed so to control the action of moral beings, as to secure the great end of action on their part ; IY. That it is the influence of authority. I now proceed to say — Y. That a perfect moral government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of law. Here the question arises, what is law — the law of a perfect moral government f Generally speaking, the law of a perfect moral government, is the will of the moral governor concerning the action of his subjects, promulgated as an authoritative and perfect rule of action to them. In this general answer to the question, there would be perhaps a universal agreement in opinion, while in respect to its particular import, there might be diversity. Hence the question demands an answer in several important particulars. I proceed, then, to say — That the law of a perfect moral government, is the promul- gated will of the moral governor, as a decisive rule of action to his subjects, requiring benevolence on their part as the best hind of action, and as the sum of obedience, forbidding selfish- ness on their part as the worst hind of action and the sum of disobedience, expressing his preference of the action required to its opposite all things considered, his satisfaction with obedience and with nothing but obedience on the part of subjects, and his THE LAW A DECISIVE RULE. 17 highest approbation of obedience and highest disapprobation of disobedience; and including the appropriate sanctions of the moral governor's authority. This definition of the law of a perfect moral government, I shall attempt to support in the following particular propo- sitions : 1. The law of a perfect moral government is the promulgated will of the moral governor as a decisive rule of action to his subjects. The will of the moral governor must be promul- gated, that it may be known by the subject, since there can be no obligation on the part of the latter to. obey the will of the former, if it cannot be known. At the same time, the will of the lawgiver being clearly promulgated, ignorance of the law becomes voluntary, and can be no excuse for disobedi- ence. This will must be promulgated as a decisive ride of action to subjects. Beings who have the prerogative of decid- ing the question of duty for themselves irrespectively of the decision or will of another, are not under law to another. A rule of action propounded to others for consideration, leaving the question of duty wholly to their judgment of the nature and tendency of action, is not a law. Law differs widely from wholesome counsel or good advice ; and one of its essential characteristics is, that it is a rule of action, determining what ought to be done. Without this conception of a rule of action, that of law cannot be formed. Law, therefore, instead of leav- ing the question of duty to the judgment of its subjects, to be founded on other evidence, is an authoritative decision of the question, from which there is no appeal. This conception of law is founded in the truth of things. The right to command which imposes an obligation to obey, results from competence and disposition to give and maintain the best law. When a rightful sovereign therefore, in the form of promulgated law decides what the subject ought to do, the right of the subject to rejudge the decision, or to decide for himself, is wholly superseded. Whatever other rights real or imaginary, the subject may be supposed to possess in other circumstances, as a subject of law, he can possess none which is inconsistent with this right of the sovereign. The right to rule vests in him, because its exercise by him is neces- sary to the general good. As the subject then, can possess no right inconsistent with the general good, so he can possess 18 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. none inconsistent with that right of the sovereign, which is demanded by the general good. He cannot therefore even raise the question of duty, without usurping a right which he has not — nay more, without invading a right which pertains exclusively to the sovereign — one of the most sacred and invi- olable of all rights, the right of deciding that action or conduct of subjects,on which the highest well-being of each and of all depends. To suppose otherwise,is to divest the law of a right- ful sovereign of its peculiar and essential characteristic as a rule of action, and to degrade it to the level of mere advice. It is to commit the question of what ought to be done by the subject, to the incompetent judgment and self-will of one who is bound to conform his decision to that of unerring wisdom and goodness. It is to suppose, that the subject of the best law is not bound to obey it, but has a right to disobey it, and to make war on the general good. Law then, the law of a perfect moral government, decides — settles the question of duty on the part of its subjects, by superseding absolutely and wholly the right of decision on their part. 2. The law of a perfect moral government must require be- nevolence as the best kind of action, and forbid selfishness as the worst kind of action on the part of moral beings. The general proposition, that benevolence is the best kind of action, and selfishness the worst kind of action conceivable on the part of moral beings, can scarcely be supposed to need the support of formal argument. In this general view of the two kinds of action however, the mind, we think, but imper- fectly appreciates the intrinsic worth of the one as moral worth, and the intrinsic evil of the other as moral evil. A thorough and sucessful analysis of the essential elements which constitute the one the best, and the other the worst kind of action on the part of moral beings, will, I think, greatly serve to heighten our estimate of the moral worth, excellence, and rectitude of the one, and of the moral evil, pravity, and turpitude of the other, and thus reveal more dis- tinctly to our admiration the attractive lineaments and clus- tering beauties of the one, and to our abhorrence the repulsive aspect and manifold deformities of the other. It is proposed then, for the purpose of showing that a per- fect moral government must require benevolence, and forbid selfishness on the part of its subjects, to show, by unfolding MORAL PREFERENCES SUPREME. 19 some of the essential elements of these only two kinds of moral action, that the one is the best and the other the worst kind of action conceivable on the part of a moral being, inas- much as one is perfectly or in the highest degree fitted to prevent the highest misery, and to produce the highest well- being of all other sentient beings, and of the agent himself; and the other is perfectly or in the highest degree fitted to prevent the highest well-being, and to produce the highest misery of all other sentient beings, and of the agent himself. I propose to consider these different acts of a moral being : (1.) As they are related to other sentient beings than the agent / and, (2.) As they are related to the agent himself. Let us, then, contemplate these acts — (1.) As they are related to other sentient beings than the agent. I here remark — In the first place, that each of these acts is a supreme affec- tion ; in other words, it is an elective preference of its object as supreme. By this, I mean to distinguish each of these acts, not only from the other characteristics flbove specified, and from all involuntary or constitutional preferences, but even from all subordinate and executive preferences which are voluntary or elective. Benevolence then, as the act of a moral being, is an elec- tive preference of the highest well-being of all other sentient beings as his supreme object. Selfishness, as the act of a moral being, is an elective preference of the world,* as his supreme object. To explain further, every elective preference of an object as supreme, is a choice between those objects and those only which can come into competition as objects of election or choice, and also a preference of every object which is implied in or necessary to the existence of the supreme ob- ject. Now, with the object of the benevolent preference, viz., the highest good of all other sentient beings, the highest good of the agent can never come into competition as an ob- * By the term world, I here mean every possible good, which as an object of choice by a moral being, can come into competition with the highest well-being, and with what is necessary to or implied in the highest well-being of all other sentient boings. 20 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. ject of election or choice, for the highest well-being of the agent depends on the highest well-being, or rather on his choice of the highest well-being of all other beings. But with the exception of his own highest well-being, and with what is necessary to or involved in it (e. g., his own virtue, which cannot be an object of choice*,) every other good to thdagent, including the non-existence of evil in many forms, even all worldly good can come into competition with the highest well-being of all other beings as an object of prefer- ence. The benevolent preference then, is not, and cannot be a preference to the highest well-being of all other beings, to the agent's own highest well-being, nor of his own highest well-being to the highest well-being of all other beings. It is a preference of the highest well-being of all other beings, to all other good, including the non-existence of all evil, which can come into competition with their highest well-being as an object of choice. In this preference therefore, the agent pre- fers the highest well-being of all other beings to any and every good, including the non-existence of all evil, which can be preferred by him to their highest well-being. It is, of course, not indeed an uninterested, but a disinterested affection, it being its true nature and tendency as a benevolent prefer- ence, to sacrifice all good, and to submit to and incur all evil, on his part, which can be necessary to secure the high- est well-being of all other beings. Nor does it stop here. A moral being, in preferring the highest well-being of all other sentient beings as his supreme object, prefers every thing to its opposite, which is necessary to or implied in the existence of this object of his preference. Particularly he prefers to its opposite, every thing in their condition and circumstances which is necessary to the existence of this object, especially the perfect virtue of all other moral beings, as the known neces- sary means of their highest well-being. He also prefers to their opposites, the non-existence of the highest misery, and of all misery or unhappiness on the part of all others, with the non- existence of all causes and means of these evils ; especially he thus prefers the non-existence of the vice or wickedness of all * One's own virtue maybe the object of a constitutional preference to its oppo- site, but not of an elective preference or choice, since this would imply the absurdity of choosing his choice. MORAL P REFERENCES SUPREME. 21 other moral beings, as the cause or means of their highest misery. Thus we see the perfect adaptation of benevolence, considered as an elective preference of the highest well-being of all other beings as supreme, to secure this object, unclogged by any regard of the agent to his own highest well-being, and to any less happiness on his part, and involving a preference to its opposite of every thing else which can be necessary to, or implied in the existence of the object of his preference, the highest well-being of all other sentient beings. We shall now see, that from the nature of selfishness as an elective preference of its object as supreme, the facts are far otherwise. With the object of the sellish preference, viz., the world, as the supreme object, the highest well-being of the agent, the highest well-being of all other sentient beings, and the non-existence of the highest misery of all such beings, are necessarily in competition as objects of choice. The agent in preferring the world as his supreme object, necessarily pre- fers the non-existence of his own highest well-being to the non- existence of the highest well-being, and the existence of the highest misery of all other sentient beings, to the absence or non-existence of the object of his selfish preference. Nor is this all. A moral being in preferring the world as his supreme object, necessarily prefers every thing else to its opposite, which can be necessary to, or implied in the attainment of his supreme object. He therefore prefers to its opposite every thing in the condition and circumstances of all other sentient beings, which can be necessary to the attainment of his ob- ject ; particularly the non-existence of the perfect virtue, and the existence of the perfect vice or wickedness of all other moral beings, together with the non-existence of all other causes or means of their happiness, and the existence of all other causes or means of their unhappiness or misery, to the absence, or non-existence of his supreme object. It is of course the true tendency of the selfish preference on the part of a moral being, to destroy all good — all happiness and the means of it, and to produce all evil — all misery and the means of it — on the part of all other sentient beings, which may be necessary to secure the object of the preference. This view of selfishness as a principle of action on the part of a moral being, is abundantly recognized in the language of common life, particularly in that of the Scriptures. (Yid. Jas. 22 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. iv. 4.)* It places its object — the world — above every other object in its affections ; and will therefore destroy the highest good and produce the highest misery of all other beings, if necessary to the accomplishment of its object. Though it may not always reveal itself in the form of malice or hate, still it lives and acts in the mind with constant and reckless neglect and contempt, and therefore with practical opposition and hostility to all other good than its own object. It is, of course, as a principle of action, nothing but a principle of malevolence, in the only true and essential form of malevolence. Such is it in its essential nature ; nor is it less odious and destructive be- cause, though it assume not the mere terrific form of infuriate malice or hate in its overt doings, it carries on its work with heartless indifference and open scorn for the highest good, and the highest misery of all other beings. Thus, each of these two kinds of moral action — benevolence and selfishness — considered simply as an elective preference of its object as supreme, places that object in choice, in affection and in purpose, above every other object, which can come into competition with it as an object to be sought. It involves, of course, an unqualified determination — a full purpose of heart — to sacrifice any good, the sacrifice of which, and to produce any evil, the production of which, may be necessary for the accom- plishment of its object. At the same time, no state of mind on the part of a moral being is of such sure and infallible tendency as a cause, to go out into the full production of its effect, as the elective preference of an object as supreme. ]STor does a moral being aim at or seek any object as supreme, except in either the benevolent or the selfish preference. All other acts of will, on the part of such a being fix on their objects in sub- servience to the accomplishment of his supreme object; and therefore terminate in these objects. It is only in the elective preference of an object as supreme, that, a moral being so fixes his will upon, and so directs his affections to that object — so concentrates thought, and desire, and feeling upon it, as to be unqualifiedly willing — even fully determined, to sacrifice any and every good, and to incur any and every evil which may be necessary to the attainment of that object. But this he * " The friendship of the world is enmity against God." " The minding of the flesh is enmity against God." MORAL PREFERENCES INTELLIGENT. 23 does in each elective preference of an object as supreme, Be- nevolence then, as an elective preference of its object as supreme, is in one respect the action and the only action of a moral being, which is perfectly fitted to prevent the highest misery, and in its stead, to produce the highest well-being of all other sentient beings ; and selfishness, as an elective pref- erence of its object as supreme, is, in one respect, the action and the only action of a moral being, which is perfectly fitted to prevent the highest well-being, and to produce the highest misery of all other sentient beings. Benevolence, then, as an elective act, and as related to other beings, is the best kind of action in this respect, and selfishness as an elective act, and as related to other beings, is in this respect, the worst kind of action conceivable on the part of a moral being. I remark — In the second place ; that each of these moral acts is an intelligent preference of its object as supreme. By this, I mean, that in each of these elective preferences, the mind acts with an intellectual apprehension of the objects of its choice. In either case, the will and the affections are fixed on an object as supreme, not with ignorance, but with knowledge; — not amid the darkness of error, but under the light of truth. The agent, whether he acts for weal or for woe, knows what he is doing. lie has apprehended the tw r o great objects of moral choice, their nature, relations and tendencies. All that knowl- edge or truth can do, is done. He knows the object at which he aims, in distinction from that at which he does not aim. The end at which he aims — the end to be accomplished, is clearly to be distinguished from the end not to be accom- plished ; and is ever held in distinct vision before him. Thus every conceivable security is furnished, that his supreme ob- ject will never be mistaken ; — that his supreme object, or any thing involved in or necessary to its existence, will not be forgotten or lost sight of; nor in any way neglected by being unthought of or out of mind ; nor that the opposite object will be sought in its stead. What higher or more invaluable security than this, can be given, that the benevolent prefer- ence will act for, and thus accomplish its object — and what higher or more fearful security than this, that the selfish pref- erence will act for, and thus secure its object? How salutary and excellent the intellectual element in the one; how de- 24 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. structive and fatal the same element in the other ! And further — by this intellectual element — this adequate, and con- stant, and sure apprehension of the object of the preference, the mind is prepared to decide at once, to a vast extent, with its prior knowledge of subordinate, executive actions, the fit- ness of such action to promote or to defeat its supreme object. How is this decision, in a vast majority of cases, made with the quickness of instinct ; and on this account, is the fitness of the benevolent preference to good, and the fitness of the selfish preference to evil, increased ! Thus it may be said, that all that is valuable in being wise to do good, is combined ^in the one, and all that is destructive in being wise to do evil, is com- bined in the other, as each is an intelligent preference. Indeed, were it not so, the mind could have no supreme object or end. It would have no steady aim, and could be guided by nothing. It would be like a ship in the darkest tempest, without helm or compass ; while this constant intellectual apprehension and aim clears away every cloud, lights up the star of direction, and like the unerring needle, ascertains and guides the course. Being thus an intelligent act — combining the perfect employ- ment of the intellect for its own purpose, how is the fitness of each moral preference to secure its object, perfected in another respect? It is the benignant tendency and fitness of the be- nevolent preference, active with unqualified and unerring aim for its object in the light of truth; and it is the malignant tendency and fitness of the selfish preference, active with un- qualified and unerring aim for its object, under the same light ! One is the act of a moral being, with the knowledge of good and evil, aiming to prevent misery, even the highest misery, and to produce the highest good of all other beings ; the other is the act of a moral being with the knowledge of good and evil, aiming to destroy the highest good, and to produce the high- est misery of all other beings ! As intelligent action then, be- nevolence, in another respect, is the best kind of action, and selfishness the worst kind of action conceivable on the part of a moral being. I remark — In the third place, that each of the elective preferences un- der consideration, is a morally free action. A moral being has power to make either of these preferences in the circum- stances in which he acts, instead of the other; and is also MORAL ACTS PREVENT THEIR OPPOSITES. 25 under an absolute necessity of making the one or the other. By making one therefore, he prevents the other in the only possible way of preventing it. Now each of these elective preferences has its peculiar tendency — the one its beneficial tendency, the other its destructive tendency — considered sim- ply as an elective preference of its object as supreme ; and so it would be, though the actual opposite of each preference were nothing more than its own non-existence. But the actual opposite of each is not its own non-existence. A morally free being is not merely under the necessity of mak- ing one of these preferences or not making it, that is, of mak- ing one or making no preference. If he does not make the one, he does and must make the other. Make which he may, he does more than make it — he prevents the opposite prefer- ence which otherwise must be made. Moral agency must serve one of two masters, when by serving one his designs are accomplished, while the same service, preventing all ser- vice to the other, defeats his designs. In this view, free agency is the grand, not to say the most momentous element in the nature of a moral being, as related to the happiness and misery of other beings. By giving ex- istence to one positive cause, whether of immense good or im- mense evil to them — to one of which such a bein^ must eak louder than words. The act of dis- obedience says, in a manner the most unequivocal, the law is not to be obeyed — the authority of the moral governor is to be disregarded, and himself esteemed worthy only of unquali- fied contempt. The transgressor does what he can therefore, to bring into contempt, and thus to prostrate, and if nothing be done to counteract the true tendency of his act, he does what must effectually prostrate all law and all authority. Who would or could respect a king, who either from weak- ness, approbation, or policy, should acquiesce in the open rebellion of a single subject, trampling on his law and con- fronting his authority with undisguised contempt ? Suppose every subject thus to defy his authority, and the triumphant shout of rebellion to go throughout his empire, what is there of law, authority, or government remaining ? Nothing. And the reason is, that the act of transgression is a declaration and a proof that the lawgiver, his law, and authority, are unwor- thy of regard. It places the foot of rebellion on all that can Vol. I.— 4 74 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. be called authority, and all that is authority in the dust, with the acquiescence of the moral governor. The proof is decisive; the conclusion is not merely authorized but required, either that he is incompetent or indisposed to uphold the best law, or both ; and of course that he has no right to reign, and is entitled to no submission. The principle is the same in respect to a single instance of disobedience, considered as tes- timony. It gives the same testimony. It establishes the same fact — that so far as authority is concerned, there is none. For what is done once may be done again ; what is done by one may be done by all. The governor's acquiescence is the result either of weakness, of timidity, of indifference, of appro- bation, or of a selfish policy, and a single act of transgression acquiesced in by him proves this. Such an act therefore, in the very nature of the case subverts all authority. We may indeed imagine that a moral governor should maintain his place on his throne by dint of power. We may suppose him to express due disapprobation of all other transgressors but one. But if he fails to do this in respect to one transgressor and so treats him with favor, under a merely legal system, his authority is gone — subverted. He shows the partialities of favoritism, and these subvert authority if any thing can. They show him to be wanting in principle, and therefore wholly destitute of that character which gives the right to rule ; they show that he is as truly the friend of the disobedient as of the obedient — that he does not regard obedience to the best law as the indispensable means of the best end, and disobedience to it as the sure means of the worst end. Thus disobedience, without his disapprobation, subverts his authority, and he acquiesces in the result. What right has he to reign ? It may here be said, that under human governments, acts of disobedience often occur without detection, and that even subjects who are convicted as offenders are often pardoned, and yet the authority of law is not subverted. This may be admitted. But why is not the authority of law in these cases subverted ? Is it because the principle now stated is not true ? Or is it because every such government does what it can and shows itself determined to do what it can, consistently with its own weakness and imperfection, to counteract the tendency of transgression, by upholding its authority in the punishment of the guilty and the protection of the innocent ? The latter NECESSITY FOR PARDONING PREROGATIVE. 75 is the reason. In proof of it, let us suppose a civil ruler to possess knowledge and power fully adequate to detect and to punish without error and mistake, every offender against the fundamental law of the state, could he refuse to do it — could he refuse and be known to refuse to arrest the traitor and bring him to punishment, and yet sustain his authority in the view of his subjects ? Could treason be thus left to walk abroad in the face of day, untouched, uncounteracted in its tendency, and the authority of the king not be subverted ? "What sort of justice and what sort of authority could belong to such a ruler, suffering rebellion thus to trample on law ? lie would be virtually employing his power to protect the traitor, and so become his accomplice in crime. In respect to the pardoning prerogative in human governments, whence is it ? It rests solely on the ground of fallibility in the ad- ministration of justice. If we suppose the infallibility of omniscience, giving absolute security that the innocent shall not be punished instead of the guilty, the pardoning preroga- tive under civil law would be, or ought to be, unknown. There could be no pretense for it ; for what sort of justice would that be, which should punish some or many offenders and not punish another known to be equally guilty ? The act of remitting penalty in respect to a convict under a merely legal system, must either rest on the presumption of his inno- cence, or be an outrage on law. Thus every human govern- ment, though necessarily imperfect in the hands of an imperfect administrator, distinctly recognizes the principle of doing all it can do to sustain its authority, by counteracting the tend- ency of transgression to destroy it. By thus doing all it can do for this purpose, it shows that it would do more if it could, and thus avoid the very imperfections that mar its administra- tion. It shows that, in its own estimation, the transgression of law in its true tendency is the subversion of all law and of all authority, by doing all it can do to counteract this tendency. It thus recognizes, and therefore fully establishes, that very principle of a perfect moral government which it is supposed to disprove. If it should here be said, that in many instances human gov- ernments do not do what they can nor show that they are dis- posed to do what they can, to sustain their authority in the sense now maintained, and that still their authority is recog- ib MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. nized, I answer that in this view of a human government, all that can be called authority is in truth mere appearance. Language is used in these, as it is in many other cases, as if that which it denotes had an actual existence, when it has not. It is merely the language of appearance, and the thing when duly reflected upon, is seen to be a mere quasi authority — a thing imagined or supposed. Authority is recognized in words, and even in unreflecting thought and action; as when we speak of the rising and setting of the sun, or of the sweet- ness of sugar, or the coldness of ice, as properties of these things which resemble our sensations. As in these cases so in the present case, by reflection, the error is easily and surely detected and the ojyposite truth fully recognized. If in such cases rulers and subjects seem to recognize authority, it is at most only a recognition of something for the reality, which is not ; while even this subserves the purpose of preventing the evils of revolution and of anarchy. While the act of transgression then in its true nature and tendency subverts the authority of the moral governor, I now proceed to show that the transgressor cannot in any way, either by doing or by suffering prevent the actual effect. The whole force and influence of his act to destroy the authority of the moral governor, may be said to lie in the fact that the subject has violated the claim for his obedience. It follows therefore, that there is no way in which he can prevent the actual subversion of all authority, except by satisfying the unsatisfied claim for obedience. Can he then by any thing which he can either do or suffer, satisfy this claim ? Can he annihilate the act of transgression, or change it into an act of obedience, or cause it to be true, that he has not transgressed ? This is impossible. Can repentance or future obedience satisfy this claim ? Repentance or future obedience can at most only satisfy the claim in future. Were it otherwise, what would the law be ? It would be in language and in import, not obey, but sin and repent, transgress and reform. This would be al- lowing present transgression on condition of future obedience. Can works of supererogation ? These are out of the question, the continued demands of law being co-extensive with the powers of the subject. Can voluntary suffering? But volun- tary suffering is not the thing which the law claims of the sub- ject. The lawgiver threatens to inflict suffering, but no be- OBEDIENCE ONLY SATISFIES THE LAW. 77 nevolent lawgiver ever claimed voluntary suffering as the duty of a subject. Voluntary suffering then cannot satisfy the claim. The law has but one claim on the subject, and that is, for his obedience. The lawgiver proposes nothing, aims at nothing, desires nothing, except his obedience and his happi- ness. How can misery be a substitute for happiness in the estimate of a benevolent lawgiver? To suppose this is to sup- pose him to say, " I am as willing that you should transgress and be miserable, as obey and be happy." Besides, the most that the transgressor can be supposed to accomplish either by doing or suffering, is to evince his present regard for the law. But he is bound to do or to suffer whatever can do this ; it can therefore, only satisfy a present claim. Can punishment? But punishment is not the act of the transgressor, but of the lawgiver. It is not inflicted by him as a substitute for obedi- ence. It is not an act of the lawgiver declaring himself as well satisfied that his subjects should disobey and be pun- ished, as obey and be blessed. It is an act of the lawgiver designed, not to reform the subject and bring him to honor the law, not to retrieve all the evils of transgression and so to be an equivalent for the happiness it has destroyed, but to pre- vent simply one of the evils of transgression, viz., the subver- sion of law. It is simply the lawgiver's act, upholding his law and authority. What then on the part of the transgressor can satisfy the unsatisfied claim for his obedience ? Nothing. By the act of transgression he has proclaimed that the law is un- worthy of regard, and may be trampled in the dust by every subject ; and this testimony is decisive of the fact, it is prima facie evidence and uncounteracted by opposing evidence from the governor himself, authorizes and demands the belief, that the moral governor acquiesces in rebellion, that his law has ceased as truly as had a repeal of it issued from his own lips, and that he no more reigns with authority, than were he driven an insulted and degraded exile from his throne. The conclusion then on this topic is, that the law of a per- fect moral governor is in its very nature an unqualified claim for obedience on the part of every subject, and that whatever it may threaten, it claims of the subject nothing but obedi- ence. It knows of no substitute or equivalent for disobe- dience on his part, nor yet on the part of the lawgiver him- self; and therefore necessarily implies, that the lawgiver can T8 MOEAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. be satisfied with nothing but obedience on the part of the subject. 6. The law of a perfect moral government expresses the law- giver's highest approbation of obedience, and highest disappro- bation of disobedience. First. It expresses his highest approbation of obedience. By highest approbation, I mean not higher approbation than he may feel toward some other object, which cannot come into competition with this as an object of approbation. A perfect moral governor would feel as high approbation of the end of right moral action, as of right moral action itself. But by highest approbation, I mean, as high as he can feel toward any object, and higher than any which he can feel toward any of all the objects which can come into competition as objects of ap- probation. The law of a perfect moral governor expresses as we have seen, his preference of the action required to its opposite, all things considered. This preference is of course an elective preference. It involves not only an act of will, but also affec- tion, love, approbation of its object as it is in its own nature and tendency ; and that degree of approbation which is suited to the worth and excellence of the object. Obedience to the perfect law of a perfect being is as we have seen the indis- pensable means of the best end, even of the highest happiness of the individual subject and of all others. As such a means of such an end, it is as excellent and valuable, as much to be loved, desired, approved and sought as the end itself. At the same time, these objects — obedience and the highest happi- ness of all, can never come into competition as objects of ap- probation. A perfect moral governor therefore, must regard obedience to his law with as high approbation as that with which he can regard any other object, even the highest happi- ness of all. Such approbation is necessarily involved in the very preference which he expresses in his law, otherwise the preference expressed in his law is not what it must be — a preference of obedience as it is in its true nature and tend- ency — the necessary means of the best end. Can he then feel so high a degree of approbation of any other object, which can come into competition with obedience as an object of approbation, as that which he feels for obedience ? This is impossible and absurd. To suppose it, is to suppose, that per- TIIE LAW EXPRESSES APPROBATION. 79 feet benevolence should feel as high approbation or love for that which is neither the highest happiness of all nor the necessary means of it, as it feels for these objects — which is to suppose that to be benevolence which is not benevolence. Again; the only object, which, under a moral government, can be conceived to exist and to come into competition with obedience as an object of approbation to. a moral governor, must be some supposable degree of happiness with exemption from some supposable degree of misery or suffering, in case of disobedience. It is admitted that a benevolent being approves of happiness, and of exemption from suffering in themselves considered. But no happiness, and no exemption from suffer- ing which are conceivable in case of disobedience, or con- nected with it or depending on it, can be so highly approved by a benevolent ruler as obedience to a perfect law. Suppose what else we may, so long as obedience does not exist, the ne- cessary means of the best end does not exist, nor the best end itself. Of course nothing exists or can exist without obedi- ence, of which a benevolent ruler can so highly approve and love as obedience to his law. The expression of his preference in his law therefore, being an expression of his approbation of obedience as it is, is an expression of his highest appro- bation of obedience. This reasoning might be further enforced by considering obedience in its particular relations as the means of the high- est well-being of all. Such it is, not merely in its direct ten- dencies to produce the highest happiness of the obedient and of all others, but also in all its indirect tendencies. Not however to specify these, I only advert to one of them al- ready stated — its tendency to support the authority of the moral governor. The obedience of his subjects is the testi- mony and the homage of every intellect and every heart, to his perfect qualification to reign ; and pre-eminently enthrones him in rightful dominion. This is " the column of true ma- jesty" in kings. When obedience exists, all exists that a per- fect moral governor can propose or desire in respect to himself and his subjects. And this he tells them in the preference — the will given forth in his law. "What other object can he so highly approve ? Secondly. The law of a perfect moral governor expresses his highest disapprobation of disobedience. By the highest dis- 80 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. approbation, I mean as high as he can feel toward any object, and higher than any which he can feel toward any of all the objects which can come into competition as objects of disap- probation. This is necessarily involved in the preference ex- pressed in his law. This preference of the action required to its opposite involves aversion, hatred, disapprobation toward the opposite as it is in its true nature and tendency. It in- volves a degree of disapprobation, which is suited to the de- gree of turpitude and odiousness in disobedience. ISTow dis- obedience to the law of a perfect moral government, in its true nature and tendency, is the sure means of the worst end even of the highest misery of the subject and of all others. As such a means of such an end, it is as odious as fit to be abhor- red and disapproved as the end itself. These objects however, disobedience and the highest misery of all, can never come into competition as objects of disapprobation. A perfect moral governor therefore, must regard disobedience with as high disapprobation as that with which he can regard the highest misery of all. Such disapprobation of disobedience is involved in the very preference expressed in his law. For this prefer; ence involves aversion, hatred, disapprobation of disobedience as it is in its true nature and tendency, that is as the means of the highest misery of all. Can he then feel so high a de- gree of disapprobation toward any other object which can come into competition with disobedience as an object of dis- approbation, as he must feel toward disobedience? This is impossible. To suppose it is to suppose, that a being of per- fect benevolence should feel as high disapprobation toward that which is neither the highest misery of all nor the means of it, as he feels toward these objects ; which is to suppose a perfectly benevolent being, who is not perfectly benevolent. This view of the subject is confirmed by considering the specific tendency of disobedience to destroy the authority of the governor. It not only tends as a kind of action to pro- duce the highest misery of all, but as we have seen, it tends to subvert the authority of law and government, and thus to demolish the necessary and only security and safeguard against this fearful issue. Intent on its work of ruin, it storms and rases to the foundation the only citadel of defense and protec- tion, that it may extend its desolations unhindered and unmo- lested. It thus destroys the last hope and refuge of benevo- NO EVIL SO GREAT AS TRANSGRESSION. 81 lence itself; forcing it to yield its authority and its designs to the ravages of fell malignity. What object so tit to be abhor- red ? What can be called law, which does not express supreme abhorrence of transgression ? What lawgiver can be entitled to respect, who does not express in his law the highest disap- probation of this deed of death — -this worst of evils as a cause — an evil equaled only by its appropriate effect, the absolute wretchedness of all? Thus, when disobedience exists, all ex- ists that a perfect moral governor can deprecate, disapprove and abhor as the cause of evil and the source of woe. It is hostility and defeat to his entire and only design. It crosses and frustrates his only will — his whole will as given forth in his law. What other object can he so highly disapprove and abhor ? 4* 6 LECTURE V. V. A perfect Moral Government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of laiv. — The nature of such a law further unfolded.— 7. The law of a perfect Moral Government involves sanctions.— The relations of a Moral Governor to his kingdom more particularly considered. — Legal sanctions denned. — They establish or ratify the authority of the Moral Governor.— They consist in natural good promised to obedience, and in natural evil threatened to disobedience. — They establish the Moral Governor's authority as its decisive proof. — They become decisive proof of the Moral Governors authority by manifesting his benevolenee in the form of his high- est approbation of obedience, and highest disapprobation of disobedience.— It is not incredible that God in the Scriptures, should express his highest approbation of obedience and his highest disapprobation of disobedience to His law. In preceding lectures, after defining a perfect moral govern- ment in general terms, I entered on the inquiry, What is the law of a perfect moral government f In answer to this in- quiry, I attempted to show that such a law is a decisive rule of action to subjects / that it must require "benevolence as the best "kind of action, and forbid selfishness as the worst kind of action conceivable on the part of subjects / that it requires be- nevolence as the sum of obedience, and forbids selfishness as the sum of disobedience on t/ie part of subjects ; that it expresses the lawgiver's preference of the action required to its opposite, all things considered; that it implies that the lawgiver can be satisfied with obedience and with nothing but obedience on the part of subjects ; that it expresses the lawgiver y s highest appro- bation of obedience, and highest disapprobation of disobedience on the part of subjects. Continuing these remarks concerning the nature of law, I proceed to say, Seventhly : That the law of a perfect moral government involves sanctions. In treating of this important and much controverted part of our subject, I propose to unfold the nature, the necessity, and the equity of legal sanctions in relation to the authority of the moral governor. Before however entering directly on these topics, I deem it important to consider more particularly than I have done, the relation which the moral governor sus- tains to his kingdom, the qualifications for the office, especially the moral character which he must possess and manifest as THE PECULIAR RELATION OF THE GOVERNOR. 83 the ground of his authority, and also the mode of manifesting his qualifications to his subjects. Assuming then what is now properly assumed, that a per- fect moral government is the best means of the best end, and therefore dictated and demanded by benevolence, I remark — That a moral governor sustains a peculiar relation to his kingdom — a relation distinguished from every other by its peculiar object or end, and also by its peculiar function. Every relation of every moral being toward other moral be- ings which is dictated and demanded by benevolence, has its peculiar object or end, and hence also its peculiar function, or what are called in most cases its peculiar duties, including those acts or doings, or some general comprehensive mode of acting necessary to the accomplishment of the peculiar object or end of the relation. Accordingly, benevolence in a moral governor, while it aims at the highest happiness of all, is also committed to another great object or end which is peculiar to his relation, viz., to secure to the extent of his power, right moral action, and to prevent wrong moral action on the part of his subjects, ~by means peculiar to the relation of a moral governor. I say that benevolence is committed — pledged — in its very nature, and from the nature of this relation, to accom- plish, as far as possible, this end by these means. Under a system of moral government, as I have before said, all — all depends on action. On the right and wrong moral action of its subjects depend its issues in happiness or misery. The weal or woe of the moral kingdom depends therefore, on what the moral governor does or fails to do, to secure right and to prevent wrong moral action on the part of his subjects. To secure right moral action with its results in happiness, and to prevent wrong moral action with its results in misery, by the peculiar influence of a perfect moral government, must be the grand object or end, and compared with any thing which can come into competition with it, must be the supreme object or end of a perfect moral governor. lie may care for and promote individual well-being, only so far as this shall be consistent with securing the greatest amount possible to him of right moral action, as the means of the highest happiness of his kingdom by the peculiar influence of a perfect moral govern- ment. But to the accomplishment of this end by this means, every thing which interferes with it must be sacrificed ; and 84 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. every tiling which is necessary to the accomplishment of this end by this means must be done, or the great end of benevo- lence must be defeated. To accomplish this particular end then — to secure the greatest amount of right moral action which he can secure, as that which is necessary to the highest well-being of all, by that influence which is peculiar to his relation as a moral governor, is the entire function of his office. A moral governor therefore from the very nature of his relation as a benevolent being, is under the necessity not merely of aiming to produce the highest happiness of his kingdom, but of aiming to produce it bv securing the greatest amount of right moral action. Nor is he as some vainly ima- gine, under the necessity merely of aiming to produce the highest well-being of his kingdom by securing the greatest amount of right moral action which he can secure ; but he is under the necessity of aiming to produce the highest amount of right moral action which he can secure by the peculiar in- fluence of a -perfect moral government. What then is the peculiar influence of a perfect moral gov- ernment f It is we have already seen, the single influence of authority — of that right to command which imposes an obli- gation to obey. This is that peculiar essential influence of a perfect moral government, without which such a government can have no existence. If right moral action can take place under other influences, it cannot take place as obedience to a moral governor without the influence of his authority on the subject. Other influences may be combined with this influ- ence, not to say must be combined with it, from the very condition of all moral beings. But such other influences are entirely distinct from this influence, and though necessary to its existence, they are no part of it. They may exist without this influence ; but when this influence does not exist, moral government does not exist. Eight moral action clone under the direct influence of natural good and evil as merely so much motive and without any regard to the will of another, is not done in submission to authority, and therefore is not obedience to a moral governor. "Wrong moral action not done in rejection of authority, is not disobedience to a moral governor. The only influence by which one acting simply in the relation of a moral governor can control, or attempt to control the conduct of others as his subjects, is the single in- ON WHAT AUTHORITY DEPENDS. 85 fluence of authority. To suppose a moral governor therefore without authority, is to suppose a moral governor without the least governing influence, and is the absurdity of supposing one to possess an influence which he does not possess — of sup- posing a moral governor who is not a moral governor. "When therefore there is no authority, there can be neither obedience nor disobedience to a moral governor — neither a moral gov- ernment nor a moral governor. Authority then — the right to command which imposes an obligation to obey — is the pecu- liar, essential, constituting influence of moral government; so that where this influence exists moral government exists ; and where this influence does not exist moral government does not exist. Again ; the authority of the moral governor — that right to command which imposes an obligation to obey — depends on his competence and disposition to govern in the best manner; that is, on his knowledge and power as qualifying him, and on his benevolence as disposing him to govern in the best manner, and on the decisive manifestations of these qualifica- tions and this character to his subjects. That the moral governor's authority depends on the knowl- edge and power which qualify him to govern in the best manner, and on the full manifestation of these qualification? for his office, is too obvious to be denied. These qualifications not manifested to the conviction of his subjects, would be in respect to constituting any part of the ground of his authority, as though they were not ; and who can suppose that ignorance and imbecility can give that right to command which imposes an obligation to obey ? The qualifications of knowledge and power admit of differ- ent modes of manifestation in different cases — modes which are peculiar to these attributes, when compared with that of manifesting a perfect moral character. In that Being who possesses omniscience and almighty power, these attributes are abundantly manifested by his works of creation. Essen- tial however, as the existence and the full manifestation of these qualifications are to the authority of the moral governor, it is in no respect necessary or important to my present pur- pose to dwell on either, since the existence and the manifes- tation of them in a moral governor in no respect depend on legal sanctions. Legal sanctions, whatever may be their 86 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. nature, their relations or their necessity, can neither impart the requisite attributes of knowledge and power, nor be neces- sary to prove their existence. At the same time, if we sup- pose the moral governor to furnish the most abundant proof of his qualifications in respect to knowledge and power, this fact does not imply that he possesses the shadow of authority; for his authority depends not merely on his knowledge and power but also on his benevolence, and the full proof or mani- festation of it to his subjects. If then legal sanctions have any influence in establishing his authority, it must be some influence on, or in relation to, the great question of his be- nevolence. That I may hereafter exhibit what I consider just and adequate views of legal sanctions, I now invite further and particular attention to benevolence on the part of the moral governor and its manifestation as one essential ground of his authority. It is then undeniable, that benevolence is one thing in the character, or rather that it is itself the character of the moral governor, which, in connection with the requisite knowledge and power, constitutes the essential ground of his authority. When it is once decided on sufficient evidence, that he pos- sesses that knowledge and power which qualify him to govern in the best manner — so far as such qualification depends on these attributes — and if this be not decided, the fact of his authority cannot be established ; then the fact, and the only fact which remains to be proved for the purpose of fully estab- lishing his authority, is the fact of his perfect moral character — his benevolence. In this fact is involved another. The moral governor who is truly or perfectly benevolent, must feel the highest appro- bation of right moral action, and the highest disapprobation of wrong moral action on the part of his subjects. These par- ticular emotions in view of the true nature and tendency of right and wrong moral action, are inseparable from the nature of benevolence in every mind. Again ; benevolence in the specific form of it now stated as the character of the moral governor, must from the very nature and design of his relation, be supremely concerned and absolutely committed to secure so far as he is able, right moral action in every instance, and to prevent wrong moral BENEVOLENCE INVOLVES THESE FEELINGS. 87 action in every instance by the influence of his authority. To accomplish this end by this means, is the great object of be- nevolence in a moral governor — the object by which this august relation is distinguished from every other relation. Benevolence on the part of a moral governor acting in this single relation, can be conceived to aim at no other object. The relation can be conceived to involve no other peculiar function than the accomplishment of this end by this means. We say then, that the grand, peculiar function of a moral governor is, by the influence of his authority, to aim to secure right, and to prevent wrong moral action on the part of his subjects. But if he who occupies the throne does not aim to secure right moral action, w T ith the highest approbation of it as the means of the highest well-being of all, and to prevent wrong moral action, with the highest disapprobation of it as the means of the highest misery of all, then he is not benevo- lent — he does not possess the character which is requisite to his right to reign — he has no authority. Besides, there is nothing in benevolence itself, on account of which it can be requisite to the moral governor's authority, except that it involves these feelings of highest approbation of right, and highest disapprobation of wrong moral action. Sup- pose benevolence to be any thing which it can be supposed to be, without involving the feelings of highest approbation of right and highest disapprobation of wrong moral action, and what is it but downright selfishness, showing no smile of favor for that which is the means of the highest welfare of all, and no frown of wrath for that which is the means of the highest misery of all ? What is it but selfishness in the form of malignity, welcoming and conniving at crime and wretch- edness, to subserve some private interest or purpose of its own? And what is there in such a character, to give to its possessor the right to control at will the conduct of others ? Or soften the character as you will, if it does not involve the feelings of highest approbation of right and highest disappro- bation of wrong moral action, its possessor can have no will in respect to right and wrong moral action in accordance with their true nature and tendency — no preference of the one to the other as the one is the means of the highest happiness of all, and the other the means of the highest misery of all. Law as a rule of action, cannot with truth express such a will or pref- 8o MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. erence. Its language is the utterance of falsehood. The law- giver has no such will, no such preference as the very nature of law involves, and the very language of law expresses. Whatever then the thing may be, by whatever name it may be called — whatever amount of good it may impart in other relations ; in a moral governor it is worthy only of execration and contempt. Call it benevolence if you will, but as the at- tribute of a moral governor, if it does not involve the high- est approbation of right, and the highest disapprobation of wrong moral action, it can give him no right to reign — no authority. Benevolence — benevolence in the form of the highest approbation of right and highest disapprobation of wrong moral action, is essential to the authority of the moral governor. ]STor is this all. The manifestation of benevolence in the form of the highest approbation of right and highest disappro- bation of wrong moral action, is also essential to the moral governor's authority. The grand and peculiar object or end of a perfect moral governor, is to secure right and prevent wrong moral action on the part of his subjects, by the influence of his authority. But his subjects cannot be reached by this influence and act under it, or rather the influence itself cannot exist, except as it results from a full manifestation of that character of the gov- ernor which is a requisite ground of his authority, even per- fect benevolence with its feelings of highest approbation of right and highest disapprobation of wrong moral action. In- deed these feelings are as we have seen, those very elements of his perfect moral character, which constitute it an essen- tial ground of his authority. It is obvious therefore, that the full and decisive manifestation of these feelings to the view of his subjects, is as necessary to his authority as the ex- istence of the feelings themselves, or of the character which involves them. To suppose Mm to authorize a doubt in the minds of his subjects of this character and these feelings, is to suppose him to authorize a denial of his authority. For what right to command can he possess in the view of subjects, while he leaves it with them an unsettled question, whether he feels the highest approbation of right, and highest disapprobation of wrong moral action. "We may view this topic under other aspects. Responsibil- FOR WHAT IS THE GOVERNOR RESPONSIBLE. 89 ity for actual results in the weal and woe of liis kingdom be- longs to the moral governor, so far as these results depend on his maintaining the influence of his authority. His business — . the grand function of his office, so to speak, is to secure, as far as may be, right moral action as the means of the highest well- being of all, and to prevent as far as may be, wrong moral action as the means of the highest misery of all, by the single influence of his authority. If the result in happiness fails, or if through wrong moral action the highest misery of all fol- lows, in consequence of his failure to sustain and use the influ- ence of his authority, the responsibility is emphatically his own. The highest happiness of all, and the prevention of the highest misery of all, so far as they depend on the existence and influence of his authority, are committed to his keeping. He is responsible for these high interests of his kingdom, so far as they depend on the influence of his authority. His con- cern is to maintain this influence unimpaired and perfect, be the sacrifice what it may. Nothing of equal value can come in- to competition with the maintenance of his authority. When it is once decided that a perfect moral government is the best means of the best end, then it is also decided, that the main- tenance of the moral governor's authority is the best means of the best end. His only alternative therefore, is, either to be- tray his trust, and thus to forfeit his character and his throne, or to manifest those feelings toAvard right and wrong moral action, which are the essential ground of his authority. Or thus, the moral governor from the nature of his relation, is to be looked to and confided in, as the faithful guardian of the welfare of his kingdom by the influence of his authority. To secure to his kingdom the highest happiness by this influence, and to be confided in accordingly, is the sole purpose and end of his high prerogative. Is he worthy, and does he show him- self to be worthy of this confidence in the view of his sub- jects? If so, then he must manifest those feelings toward right and wrong moral action, which as a perfect being he must possess, and the manifestation of which is essential to his authority. How else can his subjects confide in that guardian- ship, which is to be extended to his kingdom only through the influence of his authority? What confidence can be reposed in one, who, for aught that appears to the contrary, is indiffer- ent to the conduct of his subjects, on which the happiness or 90 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. misery of his kingdom depends, or who is or may prove him- self to be, so far as any evidence to the contrary exists, the friend and patron of wrong moral action ? And yet this is the only just view of his character. Failing to furnish decisive proof of his highest approbation of right, and of his highest disapprobation of wrong moral action, he furnishes not the shadow of proof, that he would express these feelings, even should the expression of them be necessary to prevent the universal wrong-doing, and with it the universal and perfect misery of his kingdom forevermore. I do not say, that the expression of these feelings is necessary to prevent this result in his kingdom. He however, in the case supposed, can fur- nish no proof to the contrary by what he does as a moral governor. His own declaration cannot be proof, for as yet his benevolence is not proved. Of course his veracity is not proved, and is therefore justly questioned. There can there- fore be no possible proof, in the view of his subjects in the supposed case, that the supposed result would not follow ; and no possible proof that the moral governor, foreseeing the re- sult, would in any instance express the specified feelings to- ward right and wrong moral action, were it necessary to pre- vent the direful catastrophe; no proof, that he would manifest the highest approbation of right moral action in a single in- stance, or the highest disapprobation of wrong moral action in a single instance, were it necessary to prevent his kingdom from becoming a pandemonium of sin and misery. He proves himself to be a selfish being; and there is not the shadow of reason to conclude, that he would not consent to and so be- come the responsible author of, the unmitigated and endless woes of his kingdom, rather than express the feelings requisite to prevent them, through legal sanctions. What authority or right to reign can such a being possess ? Or thus, a being who has the right to reign as a moral governor, is a benevo- lent being, and has of course the necessary feelings of a benev- olent being toward right and wrong moral action, the feelings of highest approbation of the one, and of the highest disappro- bation of the other. Having this character with its necessary emotions toward right and wrong moral action, he will furnish the requisite manifestation or proof of this material fact ; since otherwise he can possess no authority in the view of his sub- jects; that is, cannot use the necessary means of the great THE LAWGIVER MUST SHOW HIS PEELINGS. 91 end of benevolence, or of the highest happiness of his king- dom, which benevolence requires him to use. Benevolence no more requires him to aim at this end, than it requires him to use the necessary means of it — than it requires him to mani- fest his highest approbation of right and highest disapproba- tion of wrong moral action. Or thus : to suppose a perfect moral governor not to manifest the highest approbation of obedience to the best law, and the highest disapprobation of disobedience to the best law, is a palpable absurdity. It is to suppose him to use the influence of his authority, an influence which depends wholly on the manifestation of these feelings, and yet that he does not manifest the feelings on which the in- fluence thus depends; that is, it is to suppose him to use an influence which can have no existence and which of course he does not use. Does the moral governor then establish and sustain his authority ? This question depends on another ; does he fully manifest his highest approbation of right, and highest disap- probation of wrong moral action; does he show that he re- gards the one kind of action as the means of the highest well- being of all, and as such, as valuable as the end itself, and the other as the means of the highest misery of all, and as such, as evil as the end itself? This is the grand problem. I say then repeating the question, does the moral governor show that he regards right moral action with supreme approbation, and wrong moral action with supreme disapprobation f Does he so prove it as not to authorize a doubt of it ? If he does not, then there is no proof of his benevolence and therefore no proof of his authority. There is proof to the contrary. Failing as the responsible guardian of the welfare of his king- dom fully to manifest these feelings toward right and wrong moral action — the highest approbation of the one as the means of the highest welfare of all, and the highest disapprobation of the other as the means of the highest misery of all — he de- cisively evinces the opposite character, and can make no claim or pretense to authority. I remark once more, that the requisite manifestation and proof of the moral governor's benevolence, in the form of his highest approbation of right, and his highest disapprobation of wrong moral action, and in this way the requisite proof of his authority, must depend not merely on what he does in other 02 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. relations^ hut also on what he does in this relation. From in- adequate views of the relation of a moral governor and the peculiar function of his office, it seems not to be an uncommon opinion, that he may by acts and doings in other relations, fully establish his character for benevolence ; that, from his character thus established, may be inferred his appropriate feelings toward right and WTong moral action; and that in this way his authority or right to rule, so far as it depends on this character and these feelings, may also be fully established. On this fundamental point it is readily conceded, that to the establishment of his authority as a moral governor, his character as manifested in all his other relations must be unim- peached and unimpeachable. It is indispensable to this pur- pose, that his acts and his doings in all his other relations, should not only be free from every thing which w r ould evince the selfish principle, but consist in or include all the positive acts of beneficence which are demanded by his other relations. Otherwise he would furnish decisive proof against his benevo- lence, and of course against his authority. But it is now maintained, that these things — even the most decisive proofs of benevolence possible in his other relations merely — cannot prove his benevolence, and so establish his authority as a moral governor. They may furnish a degree of presumptive evidence — nay, the best evidence supposable in the case — of that character which entitles him to assume the relation of a moral governor. But no matter what proofs of his benevo- lence he may furnish in his other relations, they are not suffi- cient proofs of his benevolence, if in this relation he does not perform that appropriate function of his office which benevo- lence requires him to perform. To what purpose is it, that a being furnishes every possible proof of his benevolence in some or in many relations, if in another relation he utterly fails to perform the duties or functions wmich in this relation benevolence requires him to perform ? All his conduct in other relations be it ever so unexceptionable, may he the dic- tate of the selfish principle ; while his failure to perform the duties or functions of this relation, is decisive j>roof that it is the dictate of the selfish principle. Now the moral governor sustains a peculiar relation — a relation widely different from every other, and involving a peculiar responsibility and a peculiar function. He is the BENEVOLENCE MUST SHOW ITS FEELINGS. 93 responsible guardian of a kingdom's welfare, as its weal or woe depends on what lie does, to bring his subjects under the influence of his authority. The grand and peculiar function of his relation or office is to bring this influence to bear on his subjects, that by it he may secure right and prevent wrong moral action, the one being the means of the highest well- being of all, and the other the means of the highest misery of all. The question of his benevolence therefore, depends not merely on what he does or has done in other relations, but also on what he does in this relation. Does he as the moral governor, perform the peculiar function of his office ? — does he create the influence of his authority by what he does in this relation? If not — if he does not bring his subjects under this influence, so that they in acting must either submit to it or resist it, then he is recreant to the grand and only function of his office, and betrays the trust which he pretends to as- sume. He thus shows himself not to be benevolent, and of course to possess no authority. Benevolence therefore, re- quires him to manifest his benevolence by what he does in the relation of a moral governor, and in this way to establish his authority. Ivor is this all. Benevolence requires him also to manifest in his relation as a moral governor, his benevolence in that form which is peculiar and appropriate to this relation, viz., in its necessary feelings toward right and wrong moral action on the part of subjects. The happiness or misery of his king- dom depends on his showing himself to feel toward right and wrong moral action, as a benevolent being must feel. If he CD J CD does not show these feelings, he shows himself not to be be- nevolent. As we have seen, all that there is in the nature of benevolence which qualifies him to rule and can give him the right to rule, is, that it involves these feelings and will mani- fest them, for the accomplishment of the great end of benevo- lence. If benevolence has any peculiar feelings toward hap- piness and misery, it must have peculiar feelings toward right moral action as the means of the highest happiness of all, and toward wrong moral action as the means of the highest mis- ery of all. If benevolence requires the moral governor to make a full and decisive manifestation of his feelings toward the highest happiness of all and the highest misery of all, then it requires him also to manifest not less decisively its peculiar 94 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. feelings toward right moral action, as the means of the high- est happiness of all, and toward wrong moral action as the means of the highest misery of all. But if he does not mani- fest his benevolence in its peculiar and necessary feelings toward right and wrong moral action, by what he does in his relation as a moral governor, he cannot manifest it at all ; and the proof from this is decisive, that he is not benevolent, and can have no right to rule ; nay more, that he is not willing to use the best and only proper means of securing the highest happiness of all and preventing the highest misery of all, and therefore is a selfish being and in moral character, nothing better than a fiend. Thus plain is it, that a moral governor is under an absolute necessity of maintaining his authority in the view of his sub- jects, if he maintains it at all, by what he does in the relation of a moral governor ; in other words, by manifesting in this relation his benevolence, in the form of his highest approba- tion of right moral action, and his highest disapprobation of wrong moral action on the part of his subjects. If he would use the peculiar and essential influence of a perfect moral government, the influence of authority — if he would establish his right to reign, he must appear before his kingdom as the unchangeable friend and patron of right moral action, and the uncompromising enemy and avenger of wrong moral action, showing that he loves the one as he loves the highest happi- ness of his kingdom, and that he hates the other as he hates the highest misery of his kingdom. He must appear in all the excellence and loveliness and majesty of this character, without a cloud or a spot to obscure its splendor. The glory of his rightful dominion must be as the sun shining in his strength. In view of what has now been said concerning the relation of the moral governor to his kingdom, his qualifications for the office, and especially concerning the moral character which he must possess and manifest as the ground of his authority, I now proceed to the direct consideration of legal sanctions. My object is, to ascertain their nature, to show their necessity to the existence of law and moral government, and to unfold their equity in respect to the degrees of natural good and evil which are requisite to their design. For the purpose of presenting what I deem just and adequate views of the subject, I propose to define, in somewhat general terms, LEGAL SANCTIONS DEFINED. 95 the phrase legal sanctions, or sanctions of law, and to explain and defend the several parts of the definition. Legal sanctions then — by which I mean the sanctions of the law of a perfect moral government — consist in that natural good promised to obedience, and in that natural evil threatened to disobedience by the moral governor, which establish or ratify his authority as the decisive or necessary proof of it, by mani- festing his benevolence in the form of his highest approbation of obedience and his highest disapprobation of disobedience, and which for this purpose include the highest possible degree of natural good in each case of obedience, and the highest pos- sible degree of natural evil in each case of disobedience. This definition may be fully comprised in the following par- ticular propositions : 1st. Legal sanctions establish or ratify the authority of the moral governor. 2d. They consist in natural good promised to obedience, and in natural evil threatened to disobedience, by the moral governor. 3d. They establish or ratify the moral governor's authority, as the decisive proof of it. 4th. They become the decisive proof of his authority, by manifesting his benevolence in the form of his highest appro- bation of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobe- dience. 5th. They are the necessary proof of his authority, as being the necessary manifestations and proof of his benevolence, in the necessary form of his highest approbation of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobedience. 6th. They include the highest possible degree of natural good in each case of obedience, and the highest possible de- gree of natural evil in each case of disobedience. These several particular propositions I propose to explain and to vindicate. 1st, Legal sanctions establish or ratify the authority of the moral governor. If legal sanctions are tilings of any signifi- cance, they sustain this particular relation to law — they estab- lish or ratify it as an authoritative rule of action to subjects. To speak of law as an authoritative rule of action, is only to say, that it is a rule of action given by one who has authority or that right to command which imposes an obligation to obey. 96 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. That which gives to the law of a moral government its binding force, or which constitutes its whole influence or char- acter as a decisive rule of action, considered as the will of one which ought to be obeyed because it is his will, is the author- ity of the lawgiver or moral governor. Whether we speak of legal sanctions as establishing the authority of law, or estab lishing law as an authoritative rule of action, all that we can mean is, not that they constitute but determine or establish the fact, that it is the law of one who has the right to com- mand — who has authority. The authority of law therefore — its binding force or influence upon the subject, if established at all, must be established by establishing the authority of him whose law it is — by showing that he has that right to com- mand which imposes an obligation to obey. This being done, all is done which can give force to law, or invest it in the view of subjects, with that characteristic which constitutes it an authoritative and decisive rule of action to them. Nothing can be, nothing can need to be established or sanctioned, for the purpose of giving to law all the binding force which law can have, except, that he who assumes the right to rule actu- ally possesses and shows himself to possess the right. The peculiar influence of legal sanctions then, is to establish or rat- ify, in the view of his subjects the authority of the moral governor. 2d. Legal sanctions consist in natural good promised to obe- dience, and in natural evil threatened to disobedience by the moral governor. By this I mean, that in respect to the matter of them, they consist exclusively in such natural good and evil. Whatever natural good and evil are as sanctions, and what- ever else may be necessary to their being sanctions of law, they are the only things which are or can be sanctions of law. All men concur in calling natural good and natural evil an- nexed to law in the manner now specified, legal sanctions. Nor can this language be applied to any thing else, with the least propriety or truth. Other things which are not legal sanctions may be necessary on the part of the moral governor, that he may establish his authority by natural good and nat- ural evil as legal sanctions. Other things may be necessary to this purpose, because the want of them would be proof against his authority, and thus prevent the promised good and threat- ened evil from sanctioning his authority, however adapted in LEGAL SANCTIONS, NATURAL GOOD AND EVIL. 97 themselves to the purpose. The impossibility that the moral governor should establish or sustain his authority by other means than by annexing natural good and evil to his law as sanctions, I shall attempt to show hereafter. lie cannot do this as we have already seen, merely by furnishing the requi- site evidence of his qualifications to reign in respect to knowl- edge and power. If in addition to this w T e suppose, that by giving the best rule of action, and by a blameless and kind de- portment in all other relations than that of a moral governor, he does what he can without natural good and evil as legal sanctions, to establish and sustain his authority, still none of these things nor all of them combined can be legal sanctions ; in other words, they cannot sanction his authority. Indeed this supposition is wholly inadmissible, for all these things may be done, and be justly believed to be done by a selfish being who of course can possess no authority. His authority could not be established by these things. When all this is done, more must be done, or there can be no legal sanctions. The best evidence of his authority must be furnished of which the nature of the case admits. But such evidence cannot be furnished without the promise to obedience of a proper de- gree of natural good, and the threatening to disobedience of a proper degree of natural evil. This is the evidence and the only evidence, which wdien any tiling else supposable has been done, determines — settles the question of his authority beyond reasonable doubt. The sanctioning influence then, whatever it is, pertains exclusively to natural good promised to obe- dience as a reward, and natural evil threatened to disobedience as a penalty. What is true in the nature of things however, may more fully appear hereafter. I now appeal to the uni- versal conceptions of mankind, as evinced by the only author- ized use of language. On this ground I claim, that neither the act of prescribing the best rule of action nor a blameless and kind deportment, nor both combined, nor any thing else except natural good as the reward of obedience, and natural evil as the penalty of disobedience, can with the least propriety or truth be called legal sanctions. The authority of the moral governor then, cannot be either wholly or partially sanctioned by other things than natural good as a legal reward, and nat- ural evil as a legal penalty. If his authority is not fully and exclusively sanctioned by these, it is not sanctioned at all. Vol. I.— 5 1 98 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. Legal sanctions then in the matter of them, consist exclusively in natural good promised by the moral governor to obedience, and in natural evil threatened to disobedience. 3d. Legal sanctions, or natural good and evil as legal sanc- tions, establish or ratify the moral governor's authority as the decisive proof of it. The word sanction denotes a particular kind of evidence or proof, viz., that which is the decisive and neces- sary proof of that of which it is the sanction. I shall now speak of it only as decisive proof, proposing to consider its necessity hereafter. In some cases of moral evidence it is justly deemed too weak to authorize belief, at least for practi- cal purposes. This may be owing to its intrinsic insufficiency, or to its being opposed to contrary evidence of the same kind. In some cases of opposing evidence of this kind, we speak of the balance of evidence or probability as in favor of what we believe. In some such cases of belief, the degree of our assent or the strength of our conviction, is not such as to exclude all doubt, or is at least less than it would be, were there no op- posing evidence. What we believe is not fully or decisively established — there is not that ground for unqualified belief which there would be, were the evidence wholly un counter- acted by evidence on the other side. By decisive proof I mean, not merely a slight balance of probability, nor merely what may be called sufficient proof; but I mean that which implies the absence of all opposing evidence or of all ground for doubt or hesitation, and which in its own nature, there being no opposing evidence, fully confirms and in this sense establishes or ratifies that of which it is the proof. Now to every one tolerably acquainted with the use of lan- guage, it must be obvious, that nothing can be truly and prop- erly called a sanction, except under the idea of it as a proof; nor unless it implies, in the circumstances or case in which it is a sanction, the absence of all opposing evidence or proof, nor unless it is conceived to be a decisive proof, a proof which in its nature so establishes or ratifies that of which it is the sanction, as to remove all reasonable doubt. To illustrate by an example. The sanction of a treaty with this country, is the consent of the President and Senate. This consent is not only a proof of the reality or validity of a treaty, but a proof which implies the absence of all opposing evidence or proof, and which in its own nature establishes or ratifies, to the exclu- LEGAL SANCTIONS, A PROOF OF AUTHORITY. 99 sion of all doubt, the reality or validity of the instrument or writing called a treaty. It is under this view of it as essential to a sanction, that such consent is called a sanction. In accordance with this view of the nature of a sanction in one respect, I maintain that legal sanctions are the decisive proof oi the authority of a moral governor. Or thus I main- tain, that natural good and evil as legal sanctions, are that kind of evidence or proof of the moral governor's authority, which implies the absence of all opposing evidence, and which being in its own nature the best evidence of which the nature of the case admits, establishes or ratifies his authority beyond all reasonable doubt or hesitation. I do not say that natural good and evil, be the degree of them what it may, are legal sanctions in a case in which there is evidence from any other source against the moral governor's authority. On the con- trary I maintain, that they cannot be legal sanctions, except in a case in which there is no such opposing evidence, and that therefore, as legal sanctions, they imply the absence of all evi- dence against the moral governor's authority. It is under this idea or notion of them as legal sanctions that they exclude all doubt of his authority, while in their own nature and tendency when thus uncounteracted by opposing evidence, they establish or ratify his authority. With this explanation in view, I now ask, what can be more obvious in the use of language, than that natural good and evil considered as legal sanctions, are universally conceived of as the decisive proof of the law- giver's authority ? If as legal sanctions they prove nothing, then they sanction nothing ; and how then, or in what possi- ble meaning can they be called sanctions? If as sanctions they prove or establish any thing, it must be as we have seen, the authority of the moral governor. And how can they establish or ratify this, that is, confirm it beyond all reason- able doubt, except as implying the absence of all opposing evidence, and as being in their own nature decisive proof 'of his authority? Ith. Legal sanctions or natural good and evil as legal sanc- tions, oecome decisive pr oof of the moral governor's authority, by manifesting his benevolence in the form qf his highest approba- tion of obedience and his highest disapprobation of disobedience. Our object is now to show how or in ivhat manner natural good and evil become decisive proof of the moral governor's author- 100 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. ity. This cannot be, as we have before shown, by proving his qualifications for the office in respect to knowledge and power. These qualifications and the requisite proof of them must be presupposed. Nor can it be, except in a case in which there is opposing or counteracting evidence of any kind whatever. For what we claim and all that we claim is, that natural good and evil are legal sanctions, by being such in their true nature and tendency, as to be decisive proof of his authority, when in their influence as evidence, they are uncounteracted by oppos- ing evidence. In this case, we say that they become decisive proof of his authority, by manifesting his benevolence in the form of his highest approbation of obedience, and of his highest disapprobation of disobedience. While natural good and evil constitute the matter of legal sanctions, they do not, considered simply as natural good and evil, become or constitute legal sanctions. Natural good prof- fered or conferred, and natural evil threatened or inflicted, may sustain very different relations ; and it is in respect to these different relations, that we conceive and speak of them as very different things. Natural good under one relation we call payment, and under another hire, wages and the like. We call it reward also, as conceived of under very different rela- tions. The word reward is often applied to the consequence of wickedness. Natural evil under one relation — that is, when inflicted with the design of reforming an offender, we call chas- tisement, discipline, and sometimes punishment; while evil inflicted with no such design is also often called punishment. What then, is the precise nature of a legal reward and of a legal penalty or punishment f What is the peculiar relation of natural good and evil as sanctions of law f And here, ac- cording to what has been already said, it is obvious, that to be- come sanctions of law, they must sustain some relation to law ; and not only so, but in this particular relation to law, they must tend to secure or render effectual, by establishing or rati- fying the peculiar and appropriate influence of law, which as we have seen, is its authority or the authority of the lawgiver. Here then we have a sure criterion by which to determine what causes natural good promised to obedience, and natural evil threatened to disobedience to be legal sanctions; viz., that they tend to secure and render effectual the peculiar influence of law — the authority of the lawgiver or moral governor — by LEGAL SANCTIONS MANIFEST BENEVOLENCE. 101 establishing or ratifying this authority. What we now claim is, that they have this tendency as decisive proof of his author- ity, by manifesting his highest approbation of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobedience. It will not be denied, that natural good promised as the re- ward of obedience, is a decisive manifestation of approbation of obedience, by him who promises it ; nor, that natural evil threatened as the penalty of disobedience, is a decisive mani- festation of disapprobation of disobedience, by him .who threatens it. The promise and the threatening would be all which the case would admit of, prior to any acts of obedience or disobedience. If now we suppose the fulfillment of the promise in every case of obedience, and the execution of the threatening in every case of disobedience, the most impressive manifestation of the feelings specified is made which is con- ceivable. And yet the promise of reward, and the threaten- ing of penalty prior to all acts of obedience and of disobedi- ence, being all the evidence of which the nature of the case admits, are as truly decisive proof 'of the feelings specified, as would be the actual conferring of the reward in the case of obedience, and the actual inflicting of the penalty in the case of disobedience. In either case, the feeling of approbation of obedience, and the feeling of disapprobation of disobedience would be fully and decisively proved to be real. Nor is this all. The degree of natural good promised or conferred as the reward, and the degree of natural evil threat- ened or inflicted as the penalty, would be, in all just estima- tion, the criteria and measure of the degree of the feelings of which they would be the manifestations. When therefore, the natural good conferred in such a case on the obedient subject is such in degree as to manifest on the part of him who confers it, the highest approbation of obedience, and the natural evil inflicted on the disobedient subject, manifests on the part of him who inflicts it the highest disapprobation of disobedience, then supposing no counteracting evidence, the authority of the moral governor is established or ratified. He thus manifests the feelings which are essential to his character as a perfect moral governor. He thus decisively proves the fact, and the only fact which needs to be proved in the case, viz., that he possesses that moral character which invests him with the right to govern — that is, with authority. Having 102 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. already evinced, by their proper evidence, Ills qualifications in respect to knowledge and power for his responsible office, and having furnished by his deportment, his acts and doings, no evidence against his perfect moral character, he now proves what only remains to be proved — that he has the feelings and the character, and will act the part, of a benevolent moral governor. By thus showing through the medium of natural good and evil, his highest approbation of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobedience, he shows that he re- gards obedience to the best law as it is, the best kind of action, and disobedience to the best law as the worst kind of action — the one, as that which, in its true nature and tendency, is the means of the highest well-being of all, and the other as that which in its true nature and tendency is the means of the highest misery of all. These are the feelings and the only feelings of benevolence toward right and wrong moral action. This decisive manifestation of them through the requisite de- gree of natural good as a reward, and the requisite degree of natural evil as a penalty, is therefore decisive proof of benev- olence, and of course, decisive proof of authority. Indeed, suppose what other mode of manifesting these feelings and this character we may, if any such mode were supposable, how feeble and unimpressive it must be, compared with that which would be made through that degree of natural good as a reward, and of natural evil as a penalty, which should be the expression of these feelings 1 How would any other evince that weakness of heart which would provoke contempt, when compared with the power and majesty of emotions which, for the sake of the highest universal good, express themselves in such results of happiness to the obedient, and of misery to the disobedient ! Thus natural good and evil as legal sanctions, become de- cisive proof of the moral governor's authority, by manifesting his benevolence in the form of his highest approbation of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobedience. They reveal his moral character, holding forth, in defiance of doubt, his perfect benevolence, in its essential emotions of love of right and abhorrence of wrong moral action. They show the full strength of his will, fixed on securing so far as may be, the best means of the best end, and on preventing so far as may be, the sure means of the worst end. Thus they bring SCRIPTURAL SANCTION, NOT STRANGE. 103 out, in full and vivid manifestation, the glories of Him who occupies the throne. Removing all ground of doubt in re- spect to that character which gives him the right to command, they tend to secure the full force and efficacy of his authority in the confidential homage and unqualified submission of his subjects, and, with these, the perfect blessedness of his king- dom. EE MAKE. It is not to be thought strange or incredible, that the sanc- tions of the law of God, as these are presented in the Scrip- tures, should express his highest approbation of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobedience. Without here affirming that such sanctions are necessary to establish his authority as the perfect moral governor of his moral kingdom, I now ask, who can show that they are not necessary for this purpose ? Who can show that the legal sanctions, which as w r e have seen, would fully establish his authority, are not necessary to establish it ? If this cannot be shown, then let it not be thought incredible that such sanctions are annexed to the law of that Being who reigns over the moral universe. The incredibility of this is further diminished, if we reflect that a system of moral government which includes these sanc- tions, includes the highest degree of influence to secure right and to prevent wrong moral action, which can be conceived to be essential to a moral government. Suppose what other sys- tem of moral government we may, it cannot involve much of the influence to secure right and prevent wrong moral action which this system involves. If any other system would in- volve decisive proof of the perfect qualifications of the moral governor in respect to knowledge and power, of the excellence of his law as a rule of action, and of his absolute perfection in moral character, so does this. But besides all this, and more than all this, the system now r maintained presents mo- tives in natural good and evil which admit of no parallel, and which bind the will to right moral action, not indeed by physical force, but by the most imperious necessity by which it can be bound — the necessity of right moral action to secure perfect happiness, and to avoid perfect misery forever. And more still. In proof .that the action required ought to be done, and that its opposite ought not to be done, it reveals 104 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. through these sanctions, the will of an infinitely perfect being, unveiling his infinite benevolence in its highest approbation of obedience, and its highest disapprobation of disobedience. Thus there is no truth and no evidence of truth, which can be employed to secure right moral action, and which can be supposed to be essential to a perfect moral government, which the system now maintained does not employ, and employ in the most impressive manner. There is no such truth in re- spect to God, and the creatures of God formed in his image, which is fitted to secure the great end of their being, which is not made known in its full power to impress and control. Pre-eminently by this system is God revealed — God, the depths of whose wisdom none can fathom — God, the thunder of whose power who can understand — God, in the enrapturing glories of his goodness, smiling his approbation of right moral action, and recoiling from wrong moral action in wrathful abhorrence! What majesty and awful love! More cannot be conceived. The universe of truth, of evidence, of motive, is exhausted to give every essential perfection which can be conceived to this system of moral government, and to bind the will of moral beings to secure their own perfection in char- acter and in happiness. Who then shall count it strange, that God should place his moral creation under such an influence ? Who knows — who can prove — that this degree of influence is not necessary to the best results in happiness, and therefore demanded by infinite goodness ? Who knows — who can prove — that the highest blessedness of the moral universe — not to add also, the prevention of the perfect misery of all — does not require this manifestation of God through the medium of legal sanctions, that all may see and know- what a friend he is to right moral action, and what an enemy he is to wrong moral action ? Who knows — who can prove — that the Book, which declares that an infinitely perfect Being employs such an influ- ence for such a purpose, declares a falsehood ? LECTURE VI. V. A perfect Moral Government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of law. — The nature of such a law further unfolded.— 7. The law of a perfect Moral Government involves sanctions, (continued.)— 5th. Legal sanctions the necessary proof of the Moral Governor's authority, as the necessary manifestations and proofs of his benevolence in the form of his appro- bation of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobedience. — This shown by proving (1,) that legal sanctions are in some respect necessary as the proof of the Moral Governor's authority; (2,) that they are necessary for this purpose, as the necessary proofs of his benevo- lence; and (3,) that they are necessary proofs of his benevolence in the form of his highest approbation of obedience and highest disapprobation of disobedience. — The (1) and (2) of these arguments are treated in this lecture. — (1.) Legal Sanctions are necessary in some respect as proof of the Moral Governor's authority. — Argued from the import of the phrase legal sanctions; from the nature of the law of a perfect Moral Government; from the nature of a law or rule of action without sanctions; from the fact that conformity and nonconformity to a rule without sanctions would subvert the Moral Governor's authority. — (2.) They are necessary as proofs of the Governor's authority, as they are the necessary proofs of his benevolence. — Keason given why attempts to prove the benevolence of God from the light of nature are so unsuccessful. In the last lecture I proposed to show, that legal sanctions, or the sanctions of the law of a perfect moral government, con- sist in that natural good promised to obedience, and in that nat- ural evil threatened to disobedience by the moral governor, ivhich establish or ratify his authority as the decisive and necessary proof of it, by manifesting his benevolence in the form of his highest approbation of obedience, and his highest disappro- bation of disobedience, and which include the highest pos- sible degree of natural good in each case of obedience, and the highest possible degree of natural evil in each case of dis- obedience. This proposition was divided into several particular propo- sitions ; the four following of which I explained, and endeav- ored to support, viz. : 1st. That legal sanctions establish or ratify the authority of the moral governor. 2d. That they consist in the matter of them, exclusively in natural good promised to obedience, and in natural evil threat- ened to disobedience by the moral governor. 3d. That they establish or ratify the moral governor's author- ity as the decisive proof of it. •1th. That they become the decisive proof of it, by manifest- 5* 106 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. ing Ills benevolence in the form of his highest approbation of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobedience. I now propose in this and the following lectures to show the necessity of legal sanctions, and for this purpose, to explain and prove the fifth of the particular propositions before stated, viz. : 5th. That legal sanctions are the necessary proof of the moral governor's authority, as the necessary manifestations and proofs of his benevolence in the form of his highest approba- tion of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobedi- ence. This proposition I shall attempt to establish by showing — (1.) That legal sanctions are in some respect or under some relation, necessary as the proof of the moral governor's author- ity. (2.) That they are necessary for this purpose, as the neces- sary manifestations or proofs of his benevolence, and — (3.) That they are necessary for this purpose, as the neces- sary manifestations or proofs of his benevolence in the form of his highest approbation of obedience, and of his highest disap- probation of disobedience. (1.) Legal sanctions are necessary in some respect or tinder some relation, as the proof of the moral governor's authority. This will appeal 1 — In the first place, from the import of the phrase, legal sanc- tions. I have already remarked, that the word sanction de- notes a particular kind of evidence or proof, viz., that which is the decisive and necessary proof of that of which it is the sanc- tion. I have attempted to show that it denotes a decisive proof — that is, a proof which implies the absence of all oppos- ing proof or evidence, and fully establishes or ratifies that of which it is the sanction. I now propose to show, that it de- notes a necessary proof of that of which it is the sanction. By this I mean, that it is that, without which there is not only no proof of that of which it is the sanction, but proof to the con- trary. On this point, I appeal to the example already referred to. Without the consent of the President and Senate, there is and can be not only no proof of the reality or validity of a treaty between this nation and another, but there is decisive proof to the contrary. We may suppose the evidence of the fact in other respects to be what it may, still without the con- SANCTIONS AS PROOF OP AUTHORITY. 107 sent specified, no instrument purporting to be such a treaty can possess the least validity. On the contrary, the want of such consent is decisive proof of its validity. Thus plain is it, that the word sanction denotes that which is the necessary proof of that of which it is the sanction — necessary as being that without which there can be no proof of the fact or truth to be proved in the case, but must be proof to the contrary. Since then the genus, as logicians speak, is always included in the species, it follows, that legal sanctions, in the universal con- ceptions of men, are the necessary proof of that of which they are the sanctions. In the second place, the same thing is evident from the nature of the law of a perfect moral govern- ment. It is essential to the nature of such a law, that it be, and that it be fully proved to be, an expression of the law- giver's preference of obedience to disobedience, of his satisfac- tion with obedience and with nothing but obedience on the part of the subject, and of his highest approbation of obedience, and of his highest disapprobation of disobedience. But no possible proof without legal sanctions can be furnished, that it is an expression of such feelings. The moral governor may furnish all possible evidence of kind or benevolent feelings in all his other relations, he may prescribe the best rule of action in this relation, and all this may be prompted by other feel- ings than those of true benevolence ; may be prompted by the feelings and purposes of a purely selfish mind. There can be nothing in the case to warrant the conclusion that he is not ac- tuated by purely selfish designs ; nor that he has the feelings toward right and wrong moral action, which his law in words expresses, tlather, there is decisive proof to the contrary. As a perfect moral governor, he is as we have seen, under the ne- cessity of manifesting these feelings ; and as a benevolent being will manifest them. He cannot be a benevolent moral gover- nor without having these feelings, nor without making a full and decisive manifestation of them. Not to manifest them therefore, is proof decisive that they do not exist. Nor is this all. This manifestation of these feelings toward right and wrong moral action must be made, as we have also seen, if made at all, by what he does in the relation of a moral gov- ernor. But he can do nothing in this relation, except give the best rule of action, annex sanctions to the rule, and execute them as occasion shall occur in the conduct of subjects. Merely 108 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. to give the best rule of action will not make the requisite mani- festation. This act alone is entirely consistent with selfish designs on his part. It is not the best evidence of the feelings of benevolence toward right and wrong moral action, of which the nature of the case admits, and therefore not all the evidence which the case requires. It is only when the proof from legal sanctions is added that the evidence becomes all that the nature of the case admits of and requires, and is therefore decisive. I am not now saying that legal sanctions will fully prove the lawgiver's preference of obedience to disobedience. Nor am I now saying any thing of the mode in which natural good and evil in the form of sanctions become the proof of the expression of such a preference. I am only saying, that without legal sanctions there can be no proof of such a preference on the part of the moral governor, that whatever else may be neces- sary, natural good and evil as sanctions are necessary to evince the reality of those feelings which the language of law ex- presses, and that the want of such sanctions is full proof that such feelings on the part of the lawgiver do not exist ; and of course that what is called law in such a case, if any thing can be so called, is not law ; and therefore there is no lawgiver having authority. We may view this topic in another light. The law of a per- fect moral government is an authoritative rule of action. Can then a rule of action without natural good and evil as the sanctions of its authority, or which is the same thing, of the lawgiver's authority, be regarded as an authoritative rule of action ? Is it in this sense a law ? Plainly to pronmlge such a rule in the form of a command — to give it forth in the man- ner of one having the right to rule, claiming for it the majesty of law, and for himself the unqualified homage of his subjects, would be a burlesque on all legislation. Can a moral governor claim the submission of the will of every subject to his will, and furnish no evidence that he will reward obedience and punish disobedience ; or rather furnish decisive proof that he will do neither ! Do you call this a law — an authoritative rule of action? No misnomer can be more palpable — none more ridiculous. Is this performing the high function of his office '{ Is such a rule of action the only means which one standing before his kingdom as its rightful sovereign, and the supreme guardian of its welfare, must use to promote and protect the LAW WITHOUT SANCTIONS, NO AUTHORITY. 109 highest happiness of all? Such a rule would not only leave this great end, which he is bound to protect, unprotected, and show that it is wholly uncared for by him who is responsible for its protection, but it would be an invitation to wrong doing from the throne itself. For not to promise to reward obedience, and not to threaten to punish disobedience, is not only a pledge not to reward the one and not to punish the other, but virtually to threaten to punish obedience, and to promise to reward disobedience ; since not to reward is in a degree to punish obedience, and not to punish is in a degree to reward disobedience. Such a rule of action therefore, in- stead of having the nature and tendency of law, instead of being adapted to secure the highest happiness of all, would tend to secure the highest misery of all. Who does not know this ? Who would be governed, influenced at all, by a law without sanctions as an authoritative rule of action? Who would be concerned about doing or not doing the will of another, from whom to say the least, obedience has nothing to hope, and disobedience nothing to fear? He gives no secur- ity, furnishes no evidence that the obedient shall be protected and blessed and the disobedient be punished — none that lie will not reverse the treatment of the two classes, should his sinister and selfish designs demand it, or rather, he furnishes good reason to believe that he will reverse it. Who then could respect his character or his will, and regard him as entitled to exercise the prerogative of absolute dominion, who confide in him as the friend and protector of a kingdom's happiness, who submit to his will as law ? He may in words, express kind wishes, and in form propound the best rule of action. He may show kindness in every other relation. But as a moral gover- nor he shows none to his kingdom. He is recreant to the high function of his office. He betrays his trust as the guardian of universal happiness. He sinks the power and majesty of law into the weakness of ineffective wishes, and justly incurs the scorn and contempt due to unmasked hypocrisy. He thus de- feats the great and sole end of moral government, and tempts his subjects to war on each other and himself, without the shadow of restraint from law and authority. Again ; a rule of action without sanctions, viewed in the most favorable aspect, is justly considered as mere advice. But advice be the form of it what it may, is not law. The 110 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. difference between them demands consideration. Advice be it ever so wise and good, is a mere declaration of wliat is best to be done. It implies no will or preference on the part of the adviser of that which is advised to its opposite. It wonld still be advice, though attended with a preference of the opposite doing, and though prompted solely by sinister designs. Law is the most unequivocal expression of the unqualified, absolute will or preference of the lawgiver, that what is commanded should be done. Compliance with the one is discretionary on the part of him to whom it is given. He has the right un- questionable and perfect, to rejudge the decision of the giver, and is responsible to none for his individual judgment in the case. He violates no right of another merely by rejecting the counsel which is given. Compliance with the other admits not of a question, even in thought. Law decides — settles the question of what ought and ought not to be done, by supersed- ing the right of all further inquiry. Its violation is the viola- tion of a right the most sacred and inviolable of all rights — the right to control that, on which the highest happiness of each and of all depends. Advice whether complied with or not, involves in respect to him to whom it is given, not the least good or evil wdiich depends on the will of him who gives it. Law enforces compliance by results in good and evil to the subject which depend on the will of the lawgiver, and wmich, while as motives to right reason, they must be decisive and final for obedience, reveal the perfect character and per- fect w T ill of him from whom it emanates. Advice carries with it no binding influence from the character or will of him who gives it, to the will of him to whom it is given. Law, instead of leaving compliance with its claim to the mere option, to the uninfluenced will of the subject, binds his will to compli- ance — not indeed by physical force or necessity, but by that obligation which is imposed by the right to command, the strongest influence by which the will can be bound. This, as we have seen, is the grand, peculiar, essential influence of law — the influence of authority. But to prescribe a rule of action without sanctions, as the law of a moral government, is to give mere advice, which can possess no authority. It is to divest law of its peculiar and essential nature and influence, and to degrade it to a level with the counsels of imbecility, by com- mitting the question of what ought and ought not to be done "WITHOUT SANCTIONS LAWGIVER UNFIT. Ill to the judgment and will of an equal. It is for the moral gov- ernor to disclaim, in the most formal manner, all authority or right to rule. It is an open avowal that he has not the character which entitles him to exercise the prerogative of dominion — that he is a governor who neither has nor can have the least governing influence. Surely a rule of action, a law without sanctions, involving such a palpable dereliction of all claim or pretense to rightful authority, cannot be an authoritative rule of action — cannot be the law of a perfect moral government. In the third place, a law or rule of action without sanctions, is a decisive proof that the lawgiver, either by imbecility or by selfishness, or by both, is utterly disqualified to rule. As a proof on the question of his qualification to rule, it is al- together equivalent to refusing to reward obedience, and to punish disobedience, when they exist. In such a case, the moral governor cannot be supposed to be both competent and disposed to execute legal sanctions, for then he would execute them. He must then, either be both incompetent and indis- posed to execute them — in which case he would be disqualified to rule in every essential respect — or, he must be incompetent and yet disposed, or competent and indisposed, to execute them. Now, he is either able to confer a reward on the obedi- ent, in the form of protection and favor, or he is not. If he is not able to confer a reward, then he is the subject of an imbe- cility which is an utter disqualification for office. If he is able to confer a reward then, by conferring none, he manifests no approbation of obedience, when the public good demands that he should, and when, were he truly benevolent he would manifest it by rewarding the obedient. He stands before his kingdom therefore, convicted of indifference, or aversion to obedience — to the very thing on which the highest happiness of his kingdom depends. He thus shows himself to be, not a benevolent but a selfish being, and of course to be utterly disqualified to govern. Again ; he is either able to inflict a penalty on the disobedient, or he is not. If he is not, then he is disqualified to govern by his imbecility. If he is able, then by inflicting no penalty for disobedience, he manifests no dis- approbation of disobedience, when the public good demands that he should, and when were he truly benevolent, he would manifest it by the infliction of penalty. He stands before his 112 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. kingdom therefore, convicted of indifference to, or approbation of disobedience, the very thing which tends to produce the highest misery of his kingdom. He thus shows himself the unconcerned spectator of disobedience on the part of his sub- jects, or rather the open patron of disobedience, and the open enemy of the public good. He occupies the place of the only guardian of the public good, as this depends on his mani- festing his highest approbation of right and highest disap- probation of wrong moral action. Indifference to either is unmasked enmity to the public good. His disqualification to rule on either supposition, is decisively proved. He gives a law without sanctions, and the fact must be traced either to incompetence or indisposition to execute sanctions, or to both. In either case, he is proved to be disqualified to govern. Legal sanctions then, are in some respect necessary, as proof of the moral governor's authority or right to rule. In the fourth place, conformity and non-conformity to a law or rule of action without sanctions, alike disprove and subvert the moral governor's authority. Conformity to the rule in such a case would exist without a reward, and non-conformity without a penalty. Conformity to the rule takes place, in a case in which there is no proof of the governor's authority. The subject therefore, does not act in conforming to the rule, from respect to his authority, or under the influence of his authority. He conforms to the rule for some other reason, and under some other influence. The fact is undeniable and notorious. It cannot be otherwise. The act of conformity is not only no recognition of the moral governor's authority, but as done, and known to be clone exclusively under another in- fluence,^ is a distinct declaration, testimony, or proof on the part of the subject, that the moral governor has no authority. He acts just as he would act, for aught that appears to the contrary, were no rule of action prescribed. He thus disclaims all right in the author of the rule to govern him, and gives an open and decided testimony against his authority. Nor is this all. The moral governor, by conferring no reward, acquiesces in this disregard of his authority ; for did he promise and con- fer a reward, there would be no proof from the supposed act of conformity that it was not rendered from respect to his authority, but the contrary. Indeed, it would be impossible in such a case that the subject should conform to the rule and WITHOUT SANCTIONS, AUTHORITY SUBVERTED. 113 not be influenced by his authority. The moral governor therefore, by conferring no reward, acquiesces in the subject's disregard of his authority, and so confirms the testimony or proof from the act of the subject. Tims the act of conforming to the rule, contemplated as an unrewarded act, augments the proof, and shows, beyond all dotibt or denial, that the author of the rule has no right to reign. The same thing will appear, still more strikingly, from non- conformity to a rule of action without a penalty. The act of non-conformity or transgression is, in its true nature, an open proclamation by the transgressor, that the character of the governor does not entitle him to the submission claimed in his law. And the proof in this form of testimon}^ or declaration is decisive, provided the governor himself does not counteract it by opposing proof in the execution of penalty. What force or influence can there be or ought there to be, in the mere dictum, of one — call it law if you will ; what force or influence is there or ought there to be, in an expression of his will as his will, when there is nothing in his doings and nothing in his character to give it the least weight, or to entitle it to the least respect ? Now it is in exactly such a case that the sup- posed act of transgression, or as we may suppose, a universal revolt, occurs. What is it as an act, and what is it as a testi- mony? As an act, it is one of open defiance of the moral governor — of absolute contempt of his want of qualification to govern, and a decisive triumph of self-will over incompe- tence and usurpation. As a testimony, under what aspect does it present the supposed lawgiver except that of an utter dis- qualification to rule — as had infancy itself ascended the throne and given forth the law ? The law and the lawgiver would be, and ought to be, despised. Rebellion would place its foot on liis authority, and in a shout of triumph, seal its prostration. Nor is this all. The moral governor by inflicting no penalty, acquiesces in this contempt of himself and of his authori ij. He refuses to counteract the testimony furnished by the act of transgression to the fact that he has no right to reign. lie thus confirms the proof furnished by the act of transgression ; and so, the act as unpunished, utterly subverts his authority. Who does not know all this ? Who does not know, that rebel- lion unpunished legalizes rebellion — that it hides from every eye the reality of a perfect moral governor, and covers with 8 114 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. infamy him who pretends to exercise his prerogative ; that it annihilates all possible evidence of his authority, and puts all authority in the dust ? The proclamation of the rebel is, that the mandate from the throne is unworthy of regard, and the moral governor by his quiescent good wishes, confirms the proclamation, and authorizes rebellion throughout his empire. (2.) Legal sanctions are necessary to establish the authority of the moral governor, as the necessary manifestations or proof of his benevolence. If the relation of a moral governor is any thing, it is a relation distinguished from every other by its peculiar function. This peculiar function as we have seen, is to create and establish the influence of his authority, that by this influence, he may secure obedience to his will as the means of the highest happiness of all, and prevent disobedience to his will as the means of the highest misery of all. The in- fluence of his authority depends on his moral character, on his benevolence, and on the decisive manifestation or proof of his benevolence. He can as we have seen, possess no authority in the view of his subjects, unless it is made evident to them that he is a benevolent being, and feels toward right and wrong moral action on their part as a benevolent being must feel. The question then is, can he furnish the requisite proof of his benevolence, and of the necessary feelings of benevolence toward right and wrong moral action, and in this way estab- lish his authority, or right to rule, without annexing sanctions to his law ? Here it is readily admitted, that other things beside legal sanctions are or may be necessary, that the moral governor may establish his authority by legal sanctions. Supposing him to evince by the proper proofs, his qualifications in re- spect to knowledge and power, it may still be necessary to the purpose under consideration, that his deportment in all his other relations beside that of moral governor, should be free from all acts of unkindness or injustice — from every thing which would decisively evince the selfish principle ; and also, that it should be characterized by all those positive acts of beneficence which are demanded by his other relations ; since otherwise he would furnish decisive evidence against his be- nevolence, and so against his authority. It may be necessary for the same purpose, that he should prescribe the best rule THINGS NECESSARY BESIDES SANCTIONS. 115 of action. His blameless and kind deportment in his other relations may furnish beforehand a degree of presumptive evidence of the character which entitles him to assume the relation of a moral governor. These things, provided the re- quisite sanctions are annexed to his law, may be said to furnish additional evidence of his authority; because his benevolence and with it his authority, being in this case established by the requisite sanctions, it is reasonable to conclude that what may proceed from benevolence does proceed from benevolence. But it is now maintained, that none of these things, nor all of them together, nor any thing else, can without legal sanctions, prove his benevolence, and so establish his authority. The question of his benevolence, as we have before shown, de- pends, not on what he does or has done in his other relations, but on what he does in the relation of a moral governor. If he would establish his right to rule, he must act benevolently in this relation as well as in other relations. Benevolence im- poses on him a momentous function which is peculiar to this relation, the fulfillment of which is absolutely indispensable as the proof of his benevolence. Whatever his conduct in his other relations may have been or now is, if he fails to fulfill the peculiar and momentous function of his present relation, this failure is decisive proof that he is not a benevolent but a selfish being. Benevolence therefore, requires him to mani- fest his benevolence by what he does in his relation as a moral governor. It requires him to fulfill the peculiar function of his office, which is, to create and establish the influence of his authority,by manifesting in his present relation his benevo- lence in its necessary feelings toward right and wrong moral action. If he would create and establish the influence of his authority, he must act the part of benevolence in his present relation; and if he would act the part of benevolence in his present relation, he must manifest the necessary feelings of benevolence toward the best and the worst kind of action on the part of his subjects, by what he does in his present rela- tion. All that there is in the nature of benevolence which gives him the right to rule, or on which this right does or can depend in the view of his subjects, is, that it necessarily in- volves certain peculiar feelings toward right and wrong moral action, and that it does and will make a full manifestation of them in the moral governor, for the purpose of securing the 110 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. one kind of action as the means of the highest happiness of all, and of preventing the other as the means of the highest misery of all. If then the moral governor does not in his relation as a moral governor, make a full and decisive mani- festation of these feelings of benevolence, he cannot prove his benevolence, cannot fulfill the grand and peculiar function of his office, and of course cannot establish his authority. To recur then to the question now before us ; can the moral governor in his present relation manifest in any way, the ne- cessary feelings of benevolence toward right and wrong moral action, and so establish his authority without legal sanctions? Can he do this by mere professions of the supposed feelings? Such professions may be made by the most insincere and false pretender to benevolence, or rather, would be made in most cases, by the veriest usurper and tyrant. Who that ever claimed the right of dominion over others, did not profess to aim at the general good, and to require submission to his will only to promote this high end ? I clo not say that such profes- sions are necessarily inconsistent with benevolence ; but I say, that in themselves they are utterly insufficient as proof of benev- olence : while the want of all proof from every other source, would, notwithstanding such professions, be decisive proof to the contrary. Mere professions of a principle of action in cases in which if it exist, it will show itself in action, and in which it does not thus show itself, are ever and justly regarded as insincere and false. To say in such a case to a sufferer, (depart in peace, be warmed, be fillecl,)and yet to give noth- ing, is proof decisive of the want of the benevolent principle. So in the case before us. If there are acts which the moral governor may perform which would fully prove his benevo- lence, and which therefore he would perform were he truly benevolent, then no possible reason can be conceived for his failure to show himself benevolent by the requisite acts, except that he does not possess the character. Who would concede the right to govern to such a mere pretender to benevolence ? Again ; there are strictly speaking but three acts which a being in the capacity or relation of a perfect moral governor can perform, viz., the act of prescribing the best rule of action ; the act of annexing the requisite sanctions to the rule; and the act of executing these sanctions in cases of obedience and dis- obedience. These acts may be viewed as comprising all that NOT ENOUGH, TO PRESCRIBE RULES. 117 lie does or can do in performing the function of this high rela- tion. In assuming this relation, he cannot reward obedience nor punish disobedience ; for neither obedience nor disobedi- ence can exist. The question then now before us is reduced to this: can he manifest the necessary feelings of benevolence toward right and wrong moral action by merely prescribing the best rule of action. We have already said enough to show that such a rule of action without sanctions,not only could not be an authoritative rule of action, but could not possess other essential characteristics of the law of a perfect moral govern- ment ; that it would be the mere advice of imbecility ; that it could not be regarded as the truthful expression of any benev- olent feeling whatever on the part of him who should give it, but would amount to an open, palpable disclaimer of all author- ity. I do not say, that the act of giving the best rule of action is not necessary, that the moral governor may by legal sanc- tions manifest or prove his benevolence. But I affirm, that the act itself without legal sanctions, is not proof of his benev- olence, lie does nothing in this case which a perfectly selfish being may not be believed to do. He does nothing to show that he feels toward right and wrong moral action, as a benev- olent being must feel ; nothing to show that he truly prefers the best kind of action to the worst, or the highest happiness of all to the highest misery of all ; nothing to show that he will befriend and bless the obedient rather than the disobedient, or that he will not confer good on the latter, and inflict evil on the former to the extent of his power. He commits himself in no respect as the friend and patron of right moral action, nor as the enemy and avenger of wronj? moral action. lie refuses to do it when benevolence recpiires him to do it, and when were he a benevolent being, he would do it. lie therefore proves himself not to be benevolent. Again ; if the manifestation of these feelings of the moral governor be made at all, it must be made by some act or acts, which are the appropriate and significant expressions of them, by some act or acts which shall be justly and universally re- garded as such expressions of them. We have already seen, that by promising natural good to obedience, and threatening natural evil to disobedience in some supposable degrees, the moral governor in a case in which there is no evidence to the contrary, would decisively and in the most impressive man- 118 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. ner conceivable, express the necessary feelings of benevolence toward right and wrong moral action, and so establish his authority. Such sanctions as we have spoken of, would be de- cisive evidence of these feelings, because they furnish the best evidence of them of which the nature of the case admits. I now say, that legal sanctions are the necessary evidence of these feelings on the part of the moral governor. What then is — what can be, truly or justly regarded as the decisive, un- ambiguous expression of his feelings of approbation of obedi- ence and his disapprobation of disobedience, except either, when giving his law, the promise to reward obedience and the threatening to punish disobedience ; or the actual conferring of a reward for obedience when it exists, and the actual inflict- ing of a penalty for disobedience when it exists. In giving his law, he cannot reward obedience nor punish disobedience, for there can be no obedience to be rewarded nor disobedience to be punished. If then he does not promise to reward the one, and threaten to punish the other, he does nothing and can do nothing, to manifest the necessary feelings toward the two kinds of action, nothing to show that it is not a matter of per- fect indifference to him whether his subjects obey or disobey his law. By annexing no sanctions to his law, he furnishes decisive proof that he wills no consequences in good or evil, no results in happiness or misery to his subjects as obedient or disobedient, and of course, that he is not willing to use the least influence in the form of motive, nor any influence arising from the expression of his approbation or disapprobation clearly and fully made, for the purpose of securing right and preventing wrong moral action, and thus securing the highest happiness of all, and preventing the highest misery of all. As a moral governor then, in such a case he can manifest no feelings, and of course no character, which entitles him to the least respect- ful consideration from his subjects. Whatever may be his claims or his professions or both, there can be no influence from his character to secure the one kind of moral action nor to prevent the other — none from his official prerogative or right to rule — none which would not result from the character of any other, even the most selfish being, who should make the same claims and the same professions — none in a word, to secure obedience and prevent disobedience to his will, because it is the will and proved to be the will of a perfect being. LEGAL SANCTIONS PROOFS OF BENE YOLENCE. 119 Were obedience to exist, lie would make no manifestation of such a will by conferring a reward. Were disobedience to ex- ist, he would manifest no such will by inflicting a legal pen- alty. What then, shall be said of his moral character? Where in the view of his subjects is the proof of his benevolence ? What becomes of the peculiar function of his office ? lie ut- terly refuses to do the very things, which his high relation as a moral governor, benevolence requires him to do, viz., to manifest his benevolence as a practical principle in its neces- sary forms of approbation of right and disapprobation of wrong moral action. lie utterly neglects to establish his right to rule. He refuses to bring that influence to bear on his sub- jects, which is indispensable to secure the highest happiness of all, and to prevent the highest misery of all — the influence of his authority. Instead therefore, of manifesting his benev- olence in its appropriate and necessary expressions, and so performing the peculiar function of his office by bringing this highest and best influence to control the moral conduct of his subjects, he betrays a character which entitles him only to exe cration,as a false and faithless protector of his kingdom's wel- fare. Legal sanctions then are necessary to evince the benevo- lence of a moral governor, and so to establish his authority. Further ; the same thing will appear if we examine some of the particular ways or modes in which it may be supposed that a moral governor may evince his benevolence, and so establish his authority without legal sanctions. — Vide Lect. VII., p. 128. It may be said or supposed,that a greater amount of obedience to the best rule of action might or would be se- cured, and with it a greater amount of happiness without legal sanctions than with them, and that in this way the benevolence of the moral governor and his consequent right to rule may be fully established. I answer, that by obedience in this case cannot be meant conformity to the rule involving submission to authority ; for according to the supposition, the so-called obedience must exist as the proof of the governor's benev- olence, and in this way as the proof of his authority. There can therefore be no manifestation of his character as the ground of his authority prior to the supposed obedience, and of course no obedience involving submission to his authority. On the contrary, he who should give the supposed rule of action, would as we have seen, instead of manifesting the character, 120 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. the manifestation of which is requisite to his authority, mani- fest the opposite character, and so disprove and subvert his authority. By obedience then in the present case, must be meant mere conformity to the rule of action, or right moral action performed solely under the influence of the perceived nature and tendencies of moral action, with out involving the least submission to, or respect for, authority. But to say that there might be a greater amount of right moral action without than with legal sanctions', is saying nothing to the purpose, since it may as well be said that there might not be. To say either, is merely to assert a natural possibility of things — a possibility which must always be admitted in cases of moral reasoning. The question is one of probability. And the prob- ability of a greater amount of right moral action is greater, other things being the same, under a greater degree of in- fluence to secure it, than under a less degree of such influ- ence ; while the degree of this influence is greater with legal sanctions than without them. Besides, our object in the pres- ent inquiry is not to determine the comparative excellence of different systems of influence. It is, to ascertain what is the nature of a perfect moral government under the general or universal admission, that there is such a thing administered by an infinitely perfect being over his moral creation, and that whatever else it is, it is the necessary means of the greatest amount of right moral action and of happiness. "We have said enough already, to show that without legal sanctions there cannot be a perfect moral government. To say then, that a greater amount of right moral action might be secured without legal sanctions than with them, is to say that such a result might be secured without a perfect moral government ; that is, that the result might be secured without the necessary means of securing it ; which is absurd. Thus if we view the present question as one of mere probability, all the probability in the case is, that there would be a greater amount of right moral action with legal sanctions than without them ; while the fact that there would be, is fully admitted in the concession that a perfect moral government is necessary to the greatest amount of right moral action. But there is yet another view of this important topic which demands consideration. If then it be conceded that a greater amount of right moral action and of happiness would take place under the supposed system, and NO PROOF POSSIBLE WITHOUT SANCTIONS. 121 that its adoption would therefore be demanded by benevo- lence, still the benevolence of the being who should adopt it, could never be proved. It has already been shown, that neither his deportment prior to his assuming the relation of a moral governor, nor the act of prescribing the best rule of action, could be regarded as proof of his benevolence. Nor could the least degree of proof on this point be furnished by any degree of right moral action and of happiness snpposable in the case. As I have already said, right moral action in such a case, must be performed solely under the influence of the perceived nature and tendencies of moral action. It can- not therefore be performed out of respect for the character of the lawgiver, and of course can furnish no testimony or proof of its excellence. There can be no connection between the right mural action and the character of the lawgiver. The former therefore can furnish no proof of the excellence of the latter. The amount of happiness consequent on such action can in no degree depend on the will of the lawgiver ; for to suppose this, would be to suppose a legal reward in a case in which there is no legal reward. No possible proof then exists or can exist in the case supposed, that he who assumes the re- lation of a moral governor, feels toward right and wrong moral action, as a benevolent being must feel. Were he a perfectly selfish being, it is altogether credible that he should do all that he is supposed to do. Nor is this all. But by failing to show in his relation of a moral governor, the feelings of a benevolent being toward right and wrong moral action,- he proves himself to be a selfish/being. If then he is, according to the present supposition a benevolent being, he is benevolent in a case in which his benevolence cannot be proved, in which he acts contrary to the plainest dictates of benevolence, and in which therefore, according to the laws of evidence, he must be re- garded as a selfish being. In such a case, there could of course be no authority ; nothing which could be called a moral government. I do not say that a benevolent being would not adopt the supposed system, if the greatest good required its adoption ; nor that it would riot be one kind of a moral system. But 1 say that it would not be a jjerfect moral government. Its influence would be simply that of the per- ceived nature and tendencies of moral action ; and nothing more and nothing less than were there no lawgiver supposed Vol. I.— 6 " 122 MOEAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. in the case. There could not be the shadow of that influence which results from the law, the authority and the character of a perfect moral governor. He who should assume the supposed relation without annexing sanctions to his law, would have, and would be entitled to have, no more and no other influence over the conduct of his subjects, than any individual among them who should propound the same rule of action. The great object and end of the relation is to secure the highest well- being of all, and to prevent the highest misery of all, by secur- ing right and preventing wrong moral action ; and the great and peculiar function of the relation is, to secure right moral action, and to prevent wrong moral action by the influence of his authority — an influence which depends on the manifesta- tion of that approbation of the one kind of action, and of that disapprobation of the other, which a benevolent being must feel. But without legal sanctions he manifests no such feel- ings, and thus proves himself to be a selfish being and desti- tute of all authority. Again ; it may be said, that a moral governor by promising a reward to obedience, though he threatens no penalty to dis- obedience, would prove his benevolence and so establish his authority. I answer, that the thing supposed is impossible. For how could the promise of a reward to obedience prove the benevolence of the lawgiver, while he left disobedience to go unpunished ? How could he show himself to feel as a benev- olent being must feel toward right moral action, without also showing himself to feel as a benevolent being must feel toward wrong moral action ? All the proof of such feeling toward right moral action furnished by the reward, would be wholly counteracted by manifesting no appropriate feeling toward wrong moral action ; or rather, to manifest no disapprobation of wrong moral action, would be to show indifference or appro- bation in respect to it ; and no being who feels either indiffer- ence to or approbation of wrong moral action, can feel as a benevolent being must feel toward either right or wrong moral action. But not to dwell longer on this topic. Make what supposition you will, if the moral governor confers no reward for obedience, he expresses no approbation of the only means of the best end, but rather disapprobation ; and if he inflicts no penalty for disobedience, he expresses no disappro- bation of the means of the worst end, but rather approbation. THE GOVERNOR SELFISH WITHOUT SANCTIONS. 123 In the one case, lie virtually punishes obedience by withhold- ing a reward ; in the other, he virtually rewards disobedience by withholding penalty. Suppose then what else we may, if, in the capacity of moral governor, he does not annex sanctions to his law, and if he does not reward obedience and punish disobedience, his conduct must be traced to the selfish prin- ciple in some form. It may be selfishness in the form of caprice, despotic humor, favoritism, a spirit of self-aggrandize- ment, the love of applause, or of a weak, indulgent tenderness which sacrifices public good to individual happiness. But it is selfishness still, and not benevolence ; for benevolence in a moral governor must feel, and must express, approbation of obedience and disapprobation of disobedience to the best law. Xot to express these feelings, is not to show the necessary and due regard to the only means of the highest happiness of all, and the necessary and due abhorrence of the sure means of the highest misery of all. Not to do it, is to establish the fact that the moral governor is not himself governed by the prin- ciple of perfect and immutable rectitude. Whom he will reward, and whom he will punish, however it may be supposed to be decided by other considerations, is not determined by the perfection of his character. So far as this basis for confi- dence is concerned, the good have as much to fear as the bad, and the bad as much to hope for as the good. Perfection in character is wanting in him who occupies the throne. Obedi- ence, as submission to authority — as that confidential homage and unqualified and joyous compliance in which the will of the subject goes along with the will of a perfect ruler of all, is impossible. There is no such ruler. The act of obedience, and the act of disobedience, alike in their true tendency and influence, disclaim and prostrate his authority, and the moral governor, doing nothing to counteract the effect, legalizes re- bellion from one end of his dominions to the other. REMARK. "We see why the attempts to prove the benevolence of God from the light of nature have been so often, not to say uni- formly, unsuccessful. The fact I think will not be denied, that the arguments of the soundest theism on this most inter- esting and momentous question have been, and still are, in the 124 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. view of many of the most acute and ingenuous minds, marred by manifest imperfection and weakness. Even many Christian divines confidently maintain that the moral perfection of God cannot be proved from the light of nature. My present design is not to trace minutely the defects of the arguments now re- ferred to, but rather to present what I deem a fundamental defect common to them all, and which fully accounts for their inconclusive and unsatisfactory character, viz., that in these arguments the most important relation of God to his moral creation has been wholly overlooked in its true and proper bear- ing on the conclusion. And here let me not be misunderstood. I do not say that this important relation of God has been de- nied. It has been fully believed by every sound theist. But I affirm that, in the best conducted arguments on the subject with which I am acquainted, that no such account has been made of the relation of God as the moral governor of men as the exigency of the argument demands. If what has been said in the present lecture be just, the question, whether a being who assumes the relation of a moral governor is benevo- lent, depends on another, viz., whether the sanctions of his law manifest his benevolence in its necessary approbation of right, and necessary disapprobation of wrong moral action. But in what treatise or work in natural theology has the argument for the divine benevolence been made to depend on the rela- tion of God to men as their moral governor — on the nature, principles and facts of this relation, and particularly on the sanctions annexed to his law? On the contrary, is not the uniform method of discussing the great question of God's moral character from the light of nature, after having proved his existence as Creator, and his natural attributes, to proceed directly to the proof of his moral attributes — that is, to the proof of his benevolence — without the least attempt to unfold the nature of his high relation to his creatures as their perfect moral governor ? But if God sustains this relation to men — and surely no sound theist will deny it — then manifestly it is the great, the paramount relation which he sustains to them — a relation to which every other must be subservient, even that of their Creator, and that of the providential Disposer of all events in respect to them. This relation of God to his creatures must therefore control and modify all the manifesta- tions of himself to them, and especially the manifestations of GOD'S BENEVOLENCE, HOW PROVED. 125 his moral character. How can we judge of the moral charac- ter of any being except from his works, his acts, and his do- ings, their nature, design, tendencies and results? And how can we judge of these without understanding and contempla- ting: the relation which the being sustains to other beings whom his acts and doings respect ? Suppose you were to wit- ness a parent inflicting chastisement upon his child in some of its necessary and severer forms, and yet were so ignorant of the parental relation as not to be able to comprehend, or so thoughtless as not to consider, the design of parental discipline; or suppose you were to see a surgeon amputating the limb of a patient, without a suspicion or a thought of the necessity of the operation to save the life of the latter; or to see the exe- cutioner of public justice inflicting the penalty of the law upon the murderer, wholly ignorant or making no account of the design of such infliction — how, in either case, could you regard the evil suffered as the dictate and proof of benevolence, or as other than the decisive proof of the opposite principle ? So, if God is acting in the relation of a perfect moral governor of his moral creation, and if all his acts and doings are con- trolled and modified by this relation, to what purpose, without appealing to this relation and to his acts and doings as dictated and modified by it, shall we attempt to prove his benevolence, or to judge for ourselves, or to lead others to judge of Ids moral character? On this supposition no wonder that all such attempts are vain. If we wo aid vindicate the ways of God to man, we must understand, and lead others to under- stand, his relation to man as a moral governor. To represent him as merely the Creator of men, and the providential Dis- poser of their allotments, and in these relations aiming only to produce the happiness and to prevent the misery of his creatures irrespective of their moral conduct, when he is act- ing in the paramount relation of their lawgiver, and adhering to every principle of strictest equity in his administration, is to pour darkness on all his works and ways, and therefore on his moral character; while to contemplate him in his true re- lation — the high and august relation of a perfect moral gov- ernor — would light up all the dark paths of his providence, and cause all his goodness to pass before us. That God is in fact administering a perfect moral govern- ment over this world, will be readily conceded by every be- 126 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. liever in divine revelation. It is true indeed that there is no ground for the pretense that he carries this system of govern- ment out to its full issues in the present life. Still it must be admitted by all who receive the Christian revelation, that God in his providence over men in this world, in no respect departs from or violates a single principle of a perfect moral govern- ment; but that on the contrary, he so adheres to every such principle in his administration, that its perfection can in no respect be impeached or denied. Why then is it incredible that his providence, were it rightly read in the lessons which it gives us, should show us that he is administering a perfect moral government over this world, if not in the form of a strictly legal economy with some delay of its just retributions not inconsistent with its nature, at least in what, as we think, is far more probable — in the form of an economy of grace ? If the word of God reveals him to us as our moral governor, exercising his rightful dominion through grace, why should it be thought strange that his works and ways of providence, well considered, should present him in the same exalted and glorious relation ? Or rather, how can it be supposed to be otherwise ? Can it be supposed, that in his works and ways of providence he contradicts the testimony concerning himself given in his word ? Does his written revelation exhibit him to our faith in one relation, and his acts and doings in another ? Is it credible, that his works when duly considered, should make no decisive manifestation of the character and the rela- tion which he sustains to his intelligent creation? What shall be concluded, if his works furnish no confirmation of his dec- larations ? What is this but contradicting in his word what he is doing in his providence? If the book of revelation reveals God administering over men a perfect moral govern- ment blended with an economy of grace, the book of nature — the book that tells us what he is oy what he does — if rightly read, must show him as the righteous Sovereign, and las the Eewarder of them that diligently seek Him. LECTURE VII. V. A perfect Moral Government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of law. — The nature of the law further unfolded. — 7. The law of a perfect Moral Government involves sanctions. — 5th. The necessity of legal sanctions shown. — (3,) because they are the necessary proofs of his benevolence in the forms of his highest approbation of obedience and highest dis- approbation of disobedience. — This is argued; first, from the insufficiency of another mode of proving Ins benevolence ; second, from the nature of legal sanctions as already explained ; third, from the view of the sanctions of the supreme law of the state. — Remarks: 1. Christianity is not a selfish system of religion ; 2. What it is to make light of the divine threatenings ; 3. They who deny the view now given of the sanctions of a perfect Moral Government, cannot prove the benevolence of God. In treating of the necessity of legal sanctions in the preced- ing lecture, I attempted to show, (1.) That they are necessary, in some respect or under some relation, as the proof of the moral governor's authority; and (2.) That they are necessary for this purpose, as being the requisite proof of his benevo- lence. I now proceed to show, as I proposed — (3.) That legal sanctions are necessary for this purpose, as the required manifestations or proofs of his benevolence in the form of his highest approbation of obedience, and of his highest disapprobation of disobedience. It has been shown that the moral governor is under the necessity of establishing by decisive proof, his authority, or right to reign ; that he cannot do this without proving his benevolence, and that he cannot prove his benevolence and so establish his authority, by any thing which he can do in his other relations, nor by any thing which he can do in this rela- tion, without annexing natural good and evil to his law as its sanctions. "What I now propose to show is, that he cannot prove his benevolence, without annexing sanctions to his law which shall manifest his highest approbation of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobedience; in other words, that natural good and evil cannot become legal sanctions — that is, cannot manifest the benevolence, and so establish the authority of the moral governor, in any other ivay or mode, except by manifesting his highest approbation of obedience, and his high- est disapprobation of disobedience. 128 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. I argue the truth of this proposition, In the first place, from the insufficiency of certain particular ways or modes in which natural good and evil are, or have been supposed to become legal sanctions, other than that now specified. Here I propose to examine such other modes than the one now specified, some one of which so far as I know, has been considered the proper mode. If natural good and evil can- not become legal sanctions in any of these modes, it is fairly inferred that they cannot in any other than that now maintain- ed. I remark then, That natural good promised or conferred as the mere dictate of individual kindness, cannot possess the nature of a legal reward; and that natural evil, threatened or inflicted as the mere dictate of individual unkindness, cannot possess the nature of a legal penalty. In such a case, the lawgiver in annexing the supposed sanctions to his law, and also in their execution, can have no benevolent regard for the public good, and of course no such regard for the establishment of his own authority as the necessary means of the public good. His whole object in conferring the natural good, and in inflicting the natural evil supposed, terminates in the happiness and unhappiness of individuals as such, and in his own selfish grati- fication. This implies an utter disregard of the highest happi- ness of all, and of the necessary means of this end. It shows him to be utterly regardless of the function of his high relation, and recreant to his high trust. Whatever other tendencies then his acts may be supposed to have, or whatever results they may be supposed to produce, they can have no tendency to establish his authority, and to secure by means of it the highest well-being of his kingdom. On the contrary, the sup- posed acts must be — the one in the form of favoritism or in- dulgent tenderness, and the other in that of resentment or revenge, the dictate of unqualified selfishness, and must there- fore decisively disprove his authority. Nor do natural good and evil employed merely as moral discipline, constitute legal sanctions. It is altogether credible, that a being perfectly benevolent should, prior to assuming the relation of the moral governor of other beings, confer on them much natural good, and inflict some natural evil, for the pur- pose of securing better results, when they come to act under his moral government, than he could otherwise secure. Such PUNISHMENT NOT CHASTISEMENT. 129 natural good and evil however, cannot constitute legal sanc- tions. It is also credible, if we suppose a legal economy to be connected, as it may be, with an economy of grace, that natu- ral good and evil should be employed to reform the transgres- sors of law. Such natural good and evil however, being merely disciplinary in their design and tendency, cannot constitute lejml sanctions. I admit indeed that natural evil inflicted for the purpose of reclaiming an offender, is often called punish- ment in the - popular use of the word. Hence such natural evil is often mistaken for penal evil, or for the penalty of the law. Such natural evil, as distinguished from legal penalty, is properly called chastisement. It implies not less than the legal penalty, that the subject is an offender, since otherwise its infliction for the purpose of reformation would be obviously absurd. It differs however essentially, under a perfect moral government, from the legal penalty. Chastisement aims ex- clusively at the reformation of the subject; legal penalty not at all. Chastisement is inflicted in love; legal penalty, in wrath. Chastisement, in its design and tendency, is a blessing to its subject; legal penalty, an unmitigated curse. Chastise- ment has a special respect to the individual's benefit ; legal penalty respects the good of the public. Hence chastisement cannot, under a perfect moral government, be the penalty of the law, it being a ridiculous anomaly to threaten a transgres- sor of law with the means of his reformation and of his deliv- erance from the legal penalty; in other words, to threaten a real, and to him the greatest blessing, as a legal penalty. Nor is the-' conferring of a legal reward by the moral gov- ernor, the payment of a debt, in the sense of that which is due for something received, which is not clue. The lawgiver re- ceives nothing in the obedience of his subjects but what is his due. Obedience is a matter of obligation on their part, and of rightful demand on his ; and surely he does not reward them for paying their own debt. By this I do not mean that the reward is not that which is due, at least on account of the relation which conferring it has to the public good, as one means of increasing the public good, and that it may not in this sense be properly said that the reward is reckoned of debt Kara to o(pi?.7][ia. This however cannot imply that the service claimed or rendered is not due to the lawgiver, and that the reward establishes the authority of the lawgiver simply by 6* 9 130 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. satisfying the claim of the obedient subject. Indeed, the act of satisfying the claim of the subject, be the ground of it what it may, may be prompted by selfishness as well as by benevo- lence, and can therefore furnish no proof of benevolence, and none of authority on the part of the lawgiver. Besides, on the supposition opposed, the lawgiver's authority could not be established, until obedience should exist and the reward be con- ferred. Of course, in the supposed act of obedience there could be no recognition of authority. In short, if the "promise and the conferring of a reward for obedience has no relation except to satisfy a claim of the subject, then it has no relation to the public good. It does not imply the least degree of approbation of obedience as the means of the public good, and instead of being proof of the lawgiver's benevolence, and so of his author- ity, it is proof to the contrary. ~Noy is the endurance of natural evil as a legal penalty the payment of a debt on the part of the transgressor, by which he satisfies the claim of the lawgiver, and thus establishes his authority. For what has the subject received for which he owes suffering as an equivalent ? Plainly, he cannot, in this sense, be said to owe suffering as a debt.* lie has neither done nor failed to do any thing for which suffering on his part can be rendering an equivalent. The language of a benevo- lent lawgiver is not, " I will be as well pleased and satisfied with disobedience and the endurance of its penalty, as with perfect obedience." Legal penalty is not a thing claimed by the lawgiver and rendered by the traSgressor, but a tiling threatened and inflicted by the lawgiver, and endured by the transgressor. Considered simply as so much suffering endured, it can have no tendency to manifest the benevolence of the lawgiver. Kor can it have such tendency except it be consid- ered as suffering inflicted by the act of the lawgiver, and as such, becoming an expression of the emotion which benevo- lence must feel toward transgression. Voluntary submission to it on the part of the subject, is in no respect necessary to it as a legal penalty. Its infliction is the act of the moral gov- ernor, and in no respect the act of the transgressor, by which * Sin, as an act of withholding obedience which is due, may be called a debt, as in Matt. vi. : 12 ; not however as something due which can be paid by suffering the legal penalty, nor by any thing else. SANCTION PRIMARILY NOT MOTIVES. 131 lie may satisfy any demand made on him by the lawgiver, and thus establish his authority. Nor do natural good and evil become legal sanctions, as being so much motive to secure right and prevent wrong moral action. By this I do not mean, that natural good and evil as the matter of legal sanctions, must not have the influ- ence of motives on the minds of subjects, that they may answer the end of legal sanctions. Nor do I mean that the direct in- fluence of natural good and evil as motives, is at all incon- sistent with that peculiar influence which we call moral gov- ernment, so that the two influences may not coexist. But I mean, that the influence of natural good and evil as such, or as so much motive merely, does not constitute them legal sanc- tions. In such influence merely, there is no influence of authority. The former may exist without the latter. If we suppose the subject to be under the influence of natural good and evil, as so much motive merely, he is not under the influ- ence of authority, and therefore not under the influence of moral government. If we suppose him to conform to the rule of action under the former influence merely, the act would not be done because the moral governor commands it, but done simply to obtain natural good and to avoid natural evil ; and of course done without the least regard to the will or character of him who prescribes the rule. Now the object of a perfect moral governor is not merely to secure right moral action, but to secure it in a given way by a peculiar influence — the influ- ence of his authority ; to secure it, I do not say exclusively, but really by this influence. It is to bring his subject to act from a respect to his will, as the will of a perfect being. Otherwise the act of conformity to the rule would not be an act of obedi- ence, as involving any recognition of his right to rule. Even supposing the act to be morally right — an act done in view of the true nature and tendency of moral action, still if done from this influence merely, it would no more involve any regard for the character of the lawgiver, as that which gives him the right to rule, than were the subject hired to perform the act by a fellow subject, Natural good and evil then, influencing the subject as merely so much motive, are not legal sanctions. Nor do natural good and evil become legal sanctions, on the ground that it is right or just to reward obedience and to punish disobedience, irrespective of the tendency of so doing 132 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. to produce happiness and to prevent misery. The contrary opinion is maintained by some at least in respect to penalty. It is said that it is right to pnnish the transgressor of law irre- spective of the general good — that it is ill-desert, and not the good of society, which is the ground of his just liability to punishment — that sin or transgression is an evil in itself and deserves punishment for its own sake, and without respect to its tendency to evil. Now in such statements as these, it is obvious that distinctions are made without a difference. It is readily admitted, then, that it is right to punish the trans- gressor of law ; that it is ill-desert, which is the ground of his just liability to punishment, and that sin or transgression is an evil in itself. But it is denied that these things are true, or can be conceived to be true, irrespective of the relation of punish- ment to some good end, or to the public good. The real and only question in the case then is, would it be right or just to punish the transgressor of law, if no good end could be promoted by his punishment? Or thus, would it be right or just to inflict suffering in a case in which not the least good in kind or degree could result, either to the sufferer or to any other being from its infliction ? To say that it would be, is to say that it would be right or just to inflict suffering purely for its own sake. Could a being of perfect benevolence do this ? Could any feeling short of unqualified malice prompt it ? "Would such an act sustain the authority of the moral governor ? But it will be said that there is inherent ill-desert in the trangression of a perfect law, and that on this account it is right or just to inflict punishment on the transgressor. But the ill-desert of trans- gression is either its relation to the law as tending to destroy its authority or the authority of the lawgiver and so to destroy the public good which depends on the authority of law, or it is not. If it is, and if punishment is justly inflicted on this ac- count and as the means of sustaining this authority, then it is inflicted in respect to a good end, even for the public good. If it is not, then plainly the transgression of law sustains no re- lation to law, on account of which it is right or just to punish it. It leaves the authority of the law or of the lawgiver unim- paired and in full force. It has done, and" can do no injury to the law or to the authority of the lawgiver. There is no evil to be prevented or to be redressed by punishment, no good to be accomplished in respect to the law. Why then punish the PUNISHMENT FOR THE PUBLIC GOOD. 133 transgressor? Is it said that the ill-desert of transgression is not its relation to law as tending to destroy its authority, but its inherent moral turpitude considered simply as wrong moral action ? Be it so ; but how can this be a good reason for in- flicting suffering on the transgressor merely for its own sake, or when no good end can be answered by its infliction? Is it said that it is fit, or proper, or right, or what ought to be done, and that we instinctively feel it to be so ? But why is it ? Right to inflict suffering purely for the sake of inflicting it ! Who are the beings that instinctively feel this to be right, and in what world do they dwell ? Of such a species of beings we have no knowledge, and with them if they exist, we utterly disclaim all fraternity. Is it then said that transgression is evil in itself, and that on this account and for its own sake, it de- serves punishment? This is only saying in another form the same thing. What then is the meaning of the language? There are, generally speaking, two things, and only two, each of which may be properly said to be evil in itself. The one is suffering, including unhappiness and misery, and the other is the direct means of suffering. Each is truly and properly said to be evil in itself in distinction from being evil as the indi- rect means of suffering. That suffering, i. e. unhappiness, pain, or misery, is evil in itself will not be denied. So that which is the direct means of suffering or of unhappiness, is properly said to be evil in itself though it be also the indirect means of it. Thus it is properly said, that ignorance or infamy is evil in itself. But neither of these things is evil in itself in the same sense in which unhappiness or suffering is. The transgression of a perfect law, sin, wrong moral action, is also evil in itself, not as being itself suffering, but as being in its own nature and true tendency,^ direct means of suffering. This is all that can be properly meant by calling transgression or sin evil in itself. Not being identical with suffering or unhappiness, it can be conceived to be evil,on\y as being in its own nature the direct means of suffering. But how can this fact be a good and sufficient reason for inflicting suffering on the transgressor by a moral governor, when no good can result from the inflic- tion ? It would be only to increase evil for evil's sake. And we say again, that nothing short of unqualified malice could inflict suffering in such a case. Or rather, we affirm that the most unqualified malice could not do it. The supposed act is 134 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. impossible in the nature of tilings. No being can find a motive to inflict suffering on others any more than on himself, when no good in his view either to himself, or to them, or to others, is connected with or depends on the act. The supposition in- volves the absurdity of choosing to act without a motive or a reason — the absurdity of an event without a reason. The sup- posed act bids defiance to even infernal malice. But it has been said, if the justice of punishment is founded in the utility of punishment, then it will follow, that if the public good would be best promoted by punishing the innocent instead of the trans- gressor, it would be right and just to punish the innocent, which is revolting to every sentiment of our moral nature. It is read- ily admitted, that to punish the innocent instead of the guilty, would, as things are in their essential nature and relations, be abhorrent to every true sentiment of right and equity. But here two questions arise ; why is it thus, and how would it be, were the nature and relations of things changed in the manner supposed? Why is it thus? Is it not because the truth is clearly seen and strongly felt by every mind, that the author- ity of law, and with it the public good depend on and require the punishment of the transgressor, and forbid the punishment of the obedient subject? Does not every one know, even the culprit at the bar, as well as the judge on the bench, that to assert, that a due regard to the authority of law and with it to the public good require the punishment of the transgressor, is the same thing as to assert that justice requires his punish- ment ? And now, if we suppose the essential nature of things to be so changed, that the authority of law and the public good as depending on it, would be destroyed, and absolute and uni- versal misery follow, unless the innocent were to be punished, would it not be right to make innocence, now become the true and necessary cause of such fearful results, the ground of pun- ishment? Could a benevolent moral governor voluntarily be- come the author of such utter ruin and wretchedness,by suffer- ing the innocent to escape punishment ? Plainly on the sup- position now made, the nature of things would be so changed, that innocence, obedience to law, would possess the same nature, aud sustain the same relations as the ground of punishment, which disobedience now sustains ; and if our moral nature ap- prove of the punishment of the latter, it must in the case supposed, approve of the punishment of the former. If it is SANCTIONS FROM JUST BENEYOLENCE. 135 dow right or just to punish the disobedient, it would then be so to punish the obedient — to punish for a thing having the same relative nature, though it should have another name. To deny it, is to make a supposition to be reasoned on, and then to disregard and overlook it in the reasoning. It is like sup- posing the nature of things to be so changed that two and two should be five, and then to deny that on this supposition two and tw^o would be five, or that twice two and two would be ten. Those philosophers then, who maintain the justice of punishment, irrespective of its relations to the public good or to any good — and the same thing is true mutatis mutandis — in respect to the justice of reward, evidently fail to analyze their own necessary ideas or conceptions of things. If the question be put, why is it right to punish transgression, they have no answer to give, but that it is right, or that it is right because it is right, or some equivalent answer equally trivial and irrelevant. If pressed further on the point, they tell us, that the idea of moral rectitude or rightness is a simple idea — an idea incapable of analysis and definition, and that the ques- tion is wholly unauthorized, why is an action morally right, or what is that in which its moral rectitude consists. This has already been considered. Nor do natural good and evil become legal sanctions, con- sidered as the dictate of justice as distinguished from benevo- lence; or, as annexed to law, apart from their subserviency to public good. This view of the subject, which is not perhaps essentially different from that just considered, instead of repre- senting benevolence as the primary attribute, and justice as one particular form of benevolence, represents them " as dis- tinct and primary characteristics" or attributes of a perfect moral governor.* Its advocates are obviously led to adopt it, from an inadequate and false conception of the nature of be- nevolence, as the comprehensive moral perfection of a perfect ruler. By benevolence, they obviously mean that species of sentimental kindness wdiich seeks the welfare of others as indi- viduals, without regard to the highest well-being of the whole. Such kindness is not the benevolence of a perfect moral gov- ernor. It not only does not involve or imply the attribute of justice, but would be palpably inconsistent with it. Benevo- * Chalmers' Natural Theology, Vol. II., c. vi. 136 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. lence, as the attribute of a perfect moral governor, is the supreme love of the highest happiness of his kingdom, or an elective preference of this object to every other that can come into competition with it as an object of preference. It becomes therefore, from its very nature in relation to the promotion of the highest happiness, a disposition or purpose to promote it, by every means necessary for its promotion. One of these is, the establishment and support of the authority of a perfect law, or of the lawgiver's authority, by legal sanctions. Benev- olence dictates and demands this, and in its very nature neces- sarily leads to a full and fixed determination or purpose to secure and employ this means of the general good, or highest well-being of all ; and as such a purpose is what we mean, and all that can be meant, by justice as the attribute of a perfect moral governor — call it by what name we will — righteousness, holiness, justice — it is a disposition or purpose, prompted by benevolence, to uphold the authority of the law, or of the law- giver, by legal sanctions as the necessary means of the general good. It is therefore one particular form or modification of benevolence, or a particular disposition or purpose, prompted by benevolence. Indeed, all we c all moral attributes in a per- fect moral being, except benevolence, are only forms or modifica- tions of benevolence in more particular dispositions or purposes. Thus veracity is a particular disposition or purpose, prompted by his benevolence, to speak truth ; pity, or compassion, is a particular disposition or purpose prompted by benevolence, to relieve suffering; mercy, as an attribute of a moral ruler, is a particular disposition or purpose, prompted by benevolence, to show favor to the guilty. Justice also, as the attribute of a moral ruler, is a particular disposition or purpose prompted by benevolence, to establish and maintain the authority of law by legal sanctions, which, under a merely legal system, is in all cases indispensable to the general good. It is true that general benevolence dictates and requires other things also, for other things are necessary to the general good. But it de- mands the support of the authority of the moral governor as one necessary, absolutely indispensable means of this end. Thus viewed as a benevolent disposition to uphold his author- ity^ the indispensable means of the general good, it consti- tutes, or rather assumes the particular form, which we call justice, as an attribute of a moral governor. Hence benevo- BENEVOLENCE AND JUSTICE COINCIDE. 137 lence, as the attribute of a perfect moral governor, never re- quires any thing which is inconsistent with what justice in a perfect moral governor dictates and demands ; for the support of the authority of law is always as truly exacted by benevo- lence as by justice. Kor does justice ever require any thing inconsistent with benevolence ; for the support of the authority of law by the requisite means of its support, is what justice demands, and this is always necessary to the general good, and therefore always dictated and demanded by benevolence. Be- nevolence, no less than justice requires, under a perfect moral government viewed as a merely legal system, the sacrifice of individual happiness in the case of the transgressor; so that justice in seeking his punishment, never claims what benevo- lence forbids. What justice demands in such a case, benevo- lence also demands. So if benevolence dictates and demands an atonement, which shall fully support the authority of law in the pardon of the transgressor, it claims nothing which justice as the attribute of a moral governor forbids.* The entire claim of justice is met, provided the authority of law be supported in case of transgression, whether this be done by the execution of penalty or by an atonement. There is therefore no antago- nism here — no clashing of different attributes in the moral governor — no violence done to benevolence, in answering the inflexible demand of justice; and none to the inflexible demand of justice, by conforming to any conceivable demand of benev- olence. Justice, and all the particular moral attributes of a perfect moral governor, may be distinguished not only from each other, but also from his benevolence. But while each particular attribute, so to speak, acts in subservience to benev- olence, all act in perfect harmony. Benevolence is the central sun which gives direction, and power, and results, to the whole constellation of the particular moral attributes of a perfect moral governor. If compassion demands relief for the suffer- ing, or if mercy dictates favor to the guilty, so does benevo- lence. If justice require legal sanctions, as it does under a merely legal system, benevolence also demands them as the necessary means of supporting the authority of the lawgiver, and as such, of promoting the general good. Such are some of the ways or modes — -and I know of no * Vide Appendix on Justice, Vol. II., p. 000. 138 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. other — iii which it lias been supposed that natural good and evil can become legal sanctions, instead of that which is now maintained to be the only mode. It is obvious however that the j cannot become legal sanctions in any of these modes. If this be so, it is a fair conclusion that they can become legal sanctions in no other than that now maintained; that is, except as manifestations of the moral governor's highest approbation of obedience, and highest disapprobation of dis- obedience. I argue the same thing — In the second place, from what has been already shown respecting the nature of legal sanctions. We have seen that the moral governor can establish his authority only by natural good and evil annexed to his law as sanctions. Whatever else may be necessary for this purpose besides natural good and evil as legal sanctions, the establishing or sanctioning influence is exclusively from natural good as the reward of obedience, and from natural evil as the penalty of disobedience. But he cannot establish his authority, as we have shown, without manifesting his highest approbation of obedience, and his high- est disapprobation of disobedience, and of course cannot estab- lish his authority by natural good and evil as legal sanctions, except as they manifest these feelings. Since then, natural good and evil are necessary as legal sanctions; since they can become such only as manifestations of the moral governor's approval or disapproval, it follows, that they are necessary as legal sanctions, solely because they are requisite for the pur- pose of such a manifestation. Or thus : it has been shown that the moral governor cannot establish his authority without manifesting his benevolence ; that he cannot do this by natural good and evil as legal sanc- tions, unless they manifest the necessary feelings of benevolence toward right and wrong moral action ; and that these are the highest approbation of the one, and the highest disapprobation of the other. As then the moral governor cannot establish his authority by natural good and evil as legal sanctions, unless they manifest his highest approbation of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobedience, it follows, that they are required as legal sanctions, solely because they are necessary for the purpose of such a manifestation. What has now been said will be more fully confirmed by SANCTIONS MUST MANIFEST THE LAWGIVER. 139 viewing the subject under some other aspects, and in some other connections. I proceed then to remark — In the third place, that it is utterly unsupposable and in- conceivable, that natural good and evil should become legal sanctions in any other mode, than as expressions or manifesta- tions of the moral governor's highest approbation of obedience, and highest disapprobation of disobedience. Every one knows, that promising natural good to obedience, in the form of law, and conferring it when obedience is ren- dered, is the appropriate and most significant possible expres- sion of approbation of obedience ; and that the threatening of natural evil to disobedience, in the form of law, and inflicting it when disobedience occurs, is the appropriate and most sig- nificant expression of disapprobation of disobedience. The degree of approbation in the one case, and of disapprobation in the other, are justly estimated and measured by the degree of natural good promised or conferred in the one case, and of natural evil threatened or inflicted in the other. JSTow, when these things are so — when, as we have seen, there is no other conceivable reason that a perfect moral governor should annex natural good and evil to his law as legal sanctions ; or rather, when to annex them for any other conceivable reason or pur- pose, would disprove his moral perfection and subvert his authority, what good or sufficient reason could he have for annexing natural good and evil to his law as legal sanctions, and to do this for the purpose of establishing his authority, except that they are necessary for this purpose, and because they are the only significant and true, and therefore necessary, expressions of his approval of obedience and disapproval of the opposite. Again ; if natural good and evil can become legal sanctions in any other mode than by expressing the moral governor's highest approbation of obedience, and highest disapprobation of disobedience, it must be either by not manifesting any degree of these feelings, or by manifesting some less degree of them than the highest. Can he then establish his authority by nat- ural good and evil as legal sanctions, without manifesting through them some degree of the feelings specified ? This is plainly impossible. For they can be proof of nothing on the part of a moral governor on which his authority depends, un- less they manifest on his part some degree of approbation of 140 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. obedience, and some degree of disapprobation of disobedience. As the appropriate and significant signs of these feelings, they necessarily express them. Even if they are considered as merely so mnch motive or inducement employed by him to secure obedience and to prevent disobedience, they necessarily imply a preference on his part for some reason or another — either a selfish or a benevolent preference — of obedience to dis- obedience, and of course some kind and degree of approbation of the one, and of disapprobation of the other. It is true in- deed, that if they express these feelings in their selfish form, they become proof against his authority. But it is also true, that if they are not regarded as expressions of these feelings in any form, they can imply no preference of one kind of action to the other, and therefore can prove nothing in respect to the will, can establish nothing in respect to the feelings and char- acter of the moral governor which can have the least bearing on the question of his authority, any more than were they the effects of an impersonal cause or physical agent. If then nat- ural good and evil annexed to law as sanctions, do not manifest some approbation of obedience, and some disapprobation of dis- obedience on the part of the moral governor, they can prove nothing which can have the remotest connection with estab- lishing his authority — nothing in respect to the purpose for which they are annexed to law. They can sanction nothing — they can prove nothing which can give him the right to reign, and therefore cannot be legal sanctions. Again; it has been already shown that the moral governor can make no decisive expression, and therefore can furnish no decisive proof of his benevolence, except by natural good and evil as legal sanctions ; nor by these, except as they express his approbation of obedience, and his disapprobation of disobedi- ence. If therefore he does not make such manifestation, he furnishes no proof of his benevolence, and of course none of his authority. On the contrary, his failure to manifest these feel- ings by this means, decisively proves that he is not a benevo- lent but a selfish being, and utterly disproves his authority. Who would concede to another the right to govern — the right to impose his will as an authoritative rule of action, who should refuse to furnish the least proof of his approbation of right, and his disapprobation of wrong moral action, and who should thus furnish decisive proof of that selfishness which, to SANCTIONS EXPRESS HIS STRONGEST FEELINGS. 14.1 subserve its purposes, is as ready to befriend and patronize wrong as right moral action — to sacrifice as to promote the highest happiness of his kingdom? Plainly the moral governor cannot establish his authority by natural good and evil as legal sanctions, without manifesting through them some degree of approbation of right, and some degree of disapprobation of wrong moral action. To recur now to the other side of the alternatives ; can the moral governor establish his authority by annexing to his law natural good and evil as sanctions, which manifest a less degree of the feelings specified than the highest ? I answer ; that to suppose that he can, is to suppose what is absurd and impossi- ble. We have already seen that the moral governor, by annex- ing that degree of natural good and evil to his law as sanctions which would fully express the highest degree of the feelings specified, would thus manifest the true feelings of benevolence toward right and wrong moral action, and thus decisively establish his authority. But it is obvious, that natural good and evil in this case would become proof of his benevolence solely by expressing his highest approbation of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobedience. It is equally plain, that no less degree of natural good and evil would express these feelings. To suppose therefore, that any less degree of natural good and evil as legal sanctions than is necessary should manifest them, is absurd. To suppose that the mani- festation of any other feelings either in kind or degree, than the true and necessary feelings of benevolence, should prove benev- olence, is equally absurd. The benevolence then of the moral governor, and of course his authority, cannot be proved by any degree of legal sanctions less than that which shall manifest his benevolence in the form of its highest approbation of obedience, and his highest disapprobation of disobedience. Again ; the degree of natural good and evil annexed by the moral governor as sanctions to his law, is the measure and cri- terion of his approbation of obedience, and disapprobation of disobedience. It is undeniable, that by some given degree of natural good and evil as legal sanctions, he may express the highest degree of these feelings toward right and wrong moral action, and that by the lowest possible degree of natural good and evil as legal sanctions, he would express less approbation of right and disapprobation of wrong moral action, than the 142 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. highest, and of course less of these feelings toward these objects than the necessary feelings of benevolence. But we may as well suppose that the expression of the least possible degree of these feelings toward right and wrong moral action, is an ex- pression of the necessary feelings of benevolence, as to suppose that any expression of these feelings short of the highest, is an expression of such feelings. But I need not say how preposter- ous would be the attempt of a moral governor to prove his benevolence and so to establish his authority, by expressing the least possible degree of approbation of that kind of action, which is the necessary means of the highest happiness of all, and the least possible degree of disapprobation of that kind of action, which is the sure means of the highest misery of all. If then he annexes to his law a less degree of natural good and evil, than that which is requisite to express his highest appro- bation of obedience, and highest disapprobation of disobedi- ence, he furnishes no proof of the necessary feelings of benevo- lence, and of course no proof of his authority. On the contrary, he expresses a lower degree of approbation of obedience and of disapprobation of disobedience, than he as a benevolent being must feel, that is, he expresses that degree of approbation of right, and that degree of disapprobation of wrong moral action, which none but a selfish being can feel. The moral governor cannot establish or prove his authority, or rather he cannot avoid disproving it, without annexing as sanctions to his law, that degree of natural good and of natural evil which expresses his highest approbation of right, and his highest disapprobation of wrong moral action. I remark yet again, that natural good and evil, which ex- press a less degree of approbation of obedience, and a less de- gree of disapprobation of disobedience than the highest, can- not become legal sanctions by combining their influence with other influences, to establish the moral governor's authority. The contrary may be supposed. The supposition however is manifestly absurd, since there could be no legal sanctions in the case. Allowing what is indeed impossible, that benevo- lence of the moral governor may be proved, and that his authority may be fully or partially established by other evi- dence than that furnished by natural good and evil as legal sanctions, still neither this other evidence nor its sources can be legal sanctions ; for nothing can be legal sanctions except LESS GOOD AND EVIL INSUFFICIENT. 143 natural good and evil. Nor in the case supposed can they be such, since they do not by their own peculiar and exclusive in- fluence establish the moral governor's authority. Nor is this all. The natural good and evil in the case supposed, cannot have the least tendency or influence whatever to establish his authority. Not expressing his highest approbation of obedi- ence and disapprobation of disobedience, they furnish not the slightest evidence of these feelings, nor of course of the charac- ter, which is requisite to authority. They may be evidence of some kind or degree of approbation of right and of disapproba- tion of wrong moral action, but in no such degree as a per- fectly benevolent being must feel. Whatever evidence of authority therefore may be supposed to be furnished by other sources, none can be furnished by the natural good and evil now supposed. On the contrary, these being expressions , are also a proof 'of a less degree of approbation of 'right and of dis- approbation of wrong moral action than the highest, and are therefore evidence that the moral governor is not a benevo- lent but a selfish being, and can possess no authority. No other evidence then can establish the authority of the moral governor, except that which is furnished by natural good and evil as legal sanctions manifesting his feelings of benevolence toward right and wrong moral action. No matter what evi- dence or proof of benevolence he may be supposed to furnish in his other relations, it is altogether neutralized and set aside by his failure to annex as sanctions to his law, that degree of natural good and evil which fully expresses his highest aj3pro- bation of right and his highest disapprobation of wrong mora, action. If it should here be said — and I know of nothing more plaus- ible on the question at issue ( Vide Lectuke VI.) — that a greater amount of right moral action, and with it also of happiness, might be secured by a less degree of natural good and evil as legal sanctions than that now maintained, and that hence benev- olence would require that a less degree of such good and evil be annexed to the law as sanctions; I answer, in the first place, that while the natural possibility of the supposed consequence must be admitted in a system including moral beings, the moral governor when assuming this relation in the promulgation of his law, can furnish no proof to his subjects, that a greater amount of right action and of happiness would be secured by 144: MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. the supposed less degree of natural good and evil as legal sanc- tions. It may be otherwise, and to suppose that it would not be, is to make the supposition, when all the evidence in the case, and the best evidence the nature of the case admits of, is against its truth. It is supposing that a greater amount of right moral action would be secured by a less degree of influ- ence fitted to secure it, than by a greater degree of such influ- ence. The only rational conclusion in the case then is, that a greater amount of right moral action and of happiness would be secured by the degree of legal sanctions now maintained, than by any less degree. I answer, in the second place, that there could be no evidence or proof of the benevolence of the moral governor, but there would be decisive proof to the con- trary. Nothing can be supposed to exist in the case, of the na- ture of evidence to this main fact, except the mere declaration of a being whose benevolence and of course his veracity are to be decided by what he does as a moral governor, and this too when all the evidence in the case is against the truth of his declaration. His mere declaration therefore in respect to the greater amount of right moral action and of happiness, cannot be received as evidence of the fact nor of his benevolence. In the third place, in the act of assuming this relation of a moral governor, he comes under its high and peculiar responsibility. He must now in the very act of assuming this relation, and in claiming the homage of his subjects, either show himself re- creant to this high responsibility, and thus decisively disprove his right to rule, that is his authority ; or he must fulfill the grand function of his office by proving his right to rule, that is, establish his authority by the necessary means of doing so. He cannot establish or prove his authority without furnishing de- cisive proof of his benevolence ; and this he cannot do without annexing that degree of natural good and evil to his law as its sanction, which shall express the feelings of benevolence. On the contrary, without annexing such sanctions to his law, he shows himself selfish and recreant to his high and peculiar responsibilities as a moral governor, disproves his benevolence, and in consequence subverts his authority. Nor can this decisive proof against his authority be set aside or weakened by any supposable results in the conduct of his subjects. Let us suppose a law without such sanctions as I ad- vocate, and this law or rule of action to be followed with per- SANCTIONS NECESSARY. 145 feet conformity on the part of those to whom it is given, except in one single instance. In this case there could be no proof that a law with such sanctions as I advocate in its stead, would not be followed by perfect conformity without even one excep- tion. Of course, there could be no proof that the lawgiver, in giving the law without such sanctions, acts benevolently. On the contrary, the proof as above stated, that he does not act benevolently, remains unimpaired and decisive. lie makes no strong expression of the feelings of a benevolent being toward right and wrong moral action, which he must do, or disprove his benevolence and therefore his authority. Let us now sup- pose the same law to be given, and to be followed with perfect conformity on the part of subjects, without even a solitary ex- ception. This would furnish no proof that the supposed law would be followed by the supposed result, even for an hour or a moment beyond the time in which it actually exists, nor that a law with the sanctions which I advocate, would not be fol- lowed with the supposed perfect obedience forever. There can of course be no proof that the lawgiver, in the case supposed, has annexed those sanctions to his law which benevolence re- quires him to do. Nor is this all. There can be no proof that he would annex such sanctions to his law as I advocate, did he know that the greatest good required it, By annexing there- fore the supposed limited sanctions to his law, he not only does not prove his benevolence, but he never can prove it. He can furnish no evidence that he has any other feelings toward right and wron<>: moral action than those of a selfish beino-. The proof then of his benevolence, depends not on any present amount of right moral action on the part of subjects, under a law without the sanctions which I advocate ; nor on any con- jectures or supposed possibility respecting what would be the amount of such action under such a law. It depends not on what he declares respecting the result on right moral action, but on what he does in the time, and in the act of assuming the relation of one having a ri^ht to govern. The law must come forth from the throne, bearing the testimonial of such authority in its nature and form. It must be in itself, i. e. in its sanctions, a decisive testimonial of the feelings and the character of the law- giver. Instead of waiting for the conduct of subjects to create its authority by their conformity to its demands, or leaving them to conjecture its authority, which implies that it has no Vol. I.— 7 10 MO MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. authority, it must bear unqualified and decisive proof of this in its very promulgation. As an expression of the feelings of per- fect benevolence toward right and wrong moral action by the moral governor, that is, of his highest approbation of the one, and of his highest disapprobation of the other, its very an- nouncement must invest it with authority. It must thus show what the moral governor is in his character, by showing what his feelings are toward right and wrong moral action, and as depending on these, toward the weal and woe of his kingdom. Why ? Because, in this way, and in this way only, can the question of his authority be settled, when it should and must be, viz., when he gives the law. Because, as we have seen, in this way the best evidence which the nature of the case admits of would be furnished, because such evidence is imperiously demanded — because if he has the character which invests him with authority, it will be furnished, and because therefore if it is not furnished, it is decisive proof that he does not possess the character. Make what other supposition you will concerning his declarations or his doings, it is nothing better, and can be regarded by his subjects as nothing better than the barefaced hypocrisy of saying to a sufferer, ' Be warmed, be filled, and giving nothing.' He can easily settle the question of his char- acter and his authority — he can at once place it beyond all reasonable doubt; he can thus bring that highest, best influence on the minds of his subjects, an influence as desirable as the highest happiness, and the prevention of the highest misery of his kingdom. If he expects confidence in his character or homage to his authority, why does he not show that he has the feelings toward the conduct of his subjects and the welfare of his kingdom, which alone can entitle him to their confidence, and their homage, and enthrone him in rightful dominion. Plainly if he does not do it — if he does not annex those sanc- tions to his law which express the feelings of benevolence toward right and wrong moral action, feelings which as a benevolent being he must not only have but must express, then he authorizes the belief that he is selfish and not benevolent, and in consequence disproves his authority. And it will not be pretended, that presenting himself to his kingdom in char- acter nothing better than an infinite fiend, that he uses that degree of influence to secure right moral action, which will secure the greatest amount of such action which can be se- THE AUTHORITY OF THE CIVIL LAW. 147 cured, or that lie can secure the least degree of it, by that influ- ence which is essential to secure to the greatest amount of it, the influence of authority. Natural good and evil then, which as legal sanctions express the moral governor's highest appro- bation of right, and highest disapprobation of wrong moral action, are necessary to prove his benevolence, and so to estab- lish his authority. In the third place, I remark, that the view now given of the nature of legal sanctions, is substantially that which all men en- tertain of the supreme law of the state, so far as they regard its authority. I say, so far as they regard its authority, meaning so far as they regard the law of the state as established and administered by disinterested love of country. Such indeed is the evidence of selfishness, even on the part of civil rulers, as distinguished from true patriotism, that in our utmost respect for civil government, we regard it as having a quasi authority rather than a real authority, and find ourselves under the necessity of imagining the latter, and acting as if we be- lieved it, rather than actually believing it. Whether this be an imaginary or real regard for the authority of the law, I in- clude it under the language which I use, and contemplate it as real. By that law of the state, which I call supreme, I mean that which is essential to the government of the state as a moral government, and obedience to which is the test of loyalty. The ■reward of obedience to this law, in language which admits of some qualification in extreme cases,* but needs none for our present purpose, is the protection of life, liberty and property. The penalty of this law is death. If now we contemplate the nature of this reward, and the condition on which it is conferred, we cannot fail to see its peculiar characteristic as a legal sanction. In its nature, it is obviously the highest good which a civil government can con- fer as a common blessing on its obedient subjects. It is con- ferred solely on condition of the subject's obedience to the supreme law of the state. It is therefore a plain and unequiv- * I say admits of qualification, etc., because no man has, as some modern fanat- ical moralists and politicians maintain, an absolute right to either life, or liberty, or property, i. e., in all cases or circumstances. When the public good demands the sacrifice of either or of all these blessings, whether on account of crime or for the defense of the state, or for the greatest public good in any way, the surrender must be made. The state has a right to it, and the subject has no opposing right. 148 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. ocal expression — a direct and decisive proof of the moral gov- ernor's highest approbation of obedience to this law. No subject can fail to regard it in this light, who reflects at all on its design; nor can he regard it in this light, without regarding it as a decisive manifestation of that character of the lawgiver, which alone becomes him as the guardian of a nation's welfare, and which alone gives him a right to rule. The subject doubt- less will regard the reward as so much natural good, and as such, a motive to conform to the demand of the law. But as an obe- dient subject, as under and submitting to authority, he must re- gard the reward as something more than simply so much nat- ural good as a motive. He must regard it as that which by manifesting the lawgiver's design to secure the highest welfare of the state, gives majesty to his law, and inspires reverence for his authority. Otherwise all we call the majesty of law or the authority of civil government, is reduced to the contempt- ible conceit of a mere contract or stipulation of so much hire for a certain amount of service. To call such a contract gov- ernment or law, or to speak of its authority, is to talk of what has no existence. Yiewed as a legal sanction then, reward is something more than so much natural good as a motive to ful- fill the claim of law. It manifests the moral governor's highest approbation of that on the part of the subject which ought to be most highly approved, viz., his obedience, and carries to every mind the conviction of that character of the governor which gives him a right to rule, and thus establishes his authority. The same thing is true in respect to the penalty of the civil law, viz., it is designed to establish the authority of the gov- ernor. This, as I maintain, it does, and is designed to do, as a direct and decisive expression and proof of his highest disap- probation of disobedience to the supreme law of the state. The penalty of this law, as I have said, is death. Here it were highly desirable, did our limits allow, to distinguish this pen- alty of the supreme law of the state from those punishments or penalties as they are often called, which are annexed to various particular and subsidiary legislative enactments, as merely so much good or evil in the form of motive to prevent transgres- sion. This distinction I have attempted to trace in an appendix to this lecture.* I will only say here, that it is evident that * Appe^tdix I. THE AUTHORITY OF THE CIVIL LAW. 110 tills class of punishments are not legal sanctions ; inasmuch as the subject who incurs them, is virtually treated as an obedient subject, that is, he is virtually rewarded as such by being pro- tected, with some qualification greater or less, in his life, lib- erty and property. The offenses for which this class of punish- ments is inflicted, do not, in the eye of the law, involve a principle of hostility to the state. But the penalty of death — the penalty of the supreme law of the state, is inflicted only for such crimes as treason or murder — crimes, which in the eye of the law, do involve a spirit of war on the happiness and exist- ence of the state ; and which therefore require the expression of the highest disapprobation of him who is the guardian of the state. If now we consider this penalty in its adaptation and fitness to this end, w r e shall see that there can be no ground to doubt that it is designed to answer this end. And here it may be safely assumed that there can be no hesitation on this point, except this one, that death without torture is not, in the strictest accuracy of speech, the highest degree of natural evil winch the governor can inflict for disobedience. Hence it may perhaps be inferred by some, that it is not designed as a direct and deci- sive expression of his highest disapprobation of disobedience ; but only as so much natural evil to deter from disobedience in the form of motive. Admitting then, that in the strictest use of language (and who makes such a use of it in common life ?) death without tor- ture, is not the highest degree of natural evil which is possible in the case, there are three suppositions to be made and consid- ered. One is, that on this account death is not according to the true mode of judging, viewed either by the governor or his subjects as an expression and proof of his disapprobation, or that it is not designed to be such by the governor, nor to be so regarded by his subjects. From this supposition, it follows that there is nothing in civil government, either as viewed by the governor or his subjects,- which answers to the idea of authority. There is no evidence from the penalty, and there- fore none from any source, that he has the least degree of dis- approbation of obedience, and therefore no evidence that he has a right to rule. On the contrary, there is decisive proof that he has not this right. Civil government of course is not in the lowest sense a moral government. In its highest perfection, it involves not an iota of that influence which is called authority. 150 MOEAL GOVERNMENT IN" THE ABSTRACT. Another supposition is, that the governor and his subjects ac- cording to the true mode of judging — and it is difficult to see how it can be otherwise — regard the penalty of death as ex- pressing some degree of disapprobation of disobedience to the supreme law of the state, but not the highest degree. On this supposition there can be no ground of confidence in his charac- ter as a civil ruler ; and of course no recognition of his author- ity. As the head of an empire, that he may secure the confi- dence of his subjects, and command their submission to his authority as the rightful guardian of all, he is under a necessity of annexing a penal sanction of peculiar severity to the supreme law of the state. lie is obliged to show that he will sacrifice the life of any subject,who like the traitor or the murderer, shall war on the welfare and existence of the state, rather than sacri- fice the state itself. To test the truth of this remark, let it be supposed that he refuses to execute the traitor or the murderer, because he is his friend, or his favorite, or even his son ; and would not an enlightened and just public sentiment frown him into infamy and contempt, as unworthy of his place and as hav- ing no right to rule ? And why ? Is it that as the only guar- dian of the state, he does not express some degree of disappro- bation of a deed so hostile to the state which is less than the highest degree ? Or is it, that in their estimation he does not express the highest disapprobation of the crime by the inflic- tion of death as the requisite penalty ? Plainly the latter, for without this view of the penal sanction, there could be no proof that the moral governor regarded the welfare of the state as the supreme good ; that he would not sacrifice it to any inferior ob- ject or end. Whether the penalty of death can be justly re- garded as the expression and proof of his highest disapproba- tion or not, it is undeniable that it must be so regarded, or there can be no ground of confidence in his character as the ruler and protector of the state, and of course no recognition of his authority. A third supposition then is not merely that it is so regarded, but that it is justly so regarded ; in other words, that according to the true mode of judging in the case, both the governor and his subjects regard the penalty of death as a direct and decisive expression and proof of his highest disap- probation of disobedience to the supreme law of the state, and as such a legal sanction. But here the question arises, how can death without torture be justly regarded as such an ex- DEATH, THE SUPREME EYIL. 151 prcssion? I answer, that in the common conceptions of all men, death is the supreme evil to man. It is, as it were, con- stantly in common speech, and of course in the common con- ceptions of the human mind, distinguished as the greatest of evils to man, considered as a being of earth and time. As such it is signalized in all human thought, familiarized as the evil most to be dreaded, and even personified as the king of terrors. The idea of it, is of so great an evil — it so absorbs thought and feeling by its own magnitude, that the ordinary suffering which is an attendant circumstance, is unthought of as enhancing it. If we dread its approach, if we adopt means to escape it our- selves or to prevent it in others, it is death as death that we think of, and not the sufferings it may bring with it. Or if we suppose a degree of suffering to be connected with it, it would be apt to attract and engross thought and feeling, and so to divert the dread of the greater evil to the less ; and it is easier, as everyone knows, to harden the mind against bodily suffering than against death, when the mind conceives the latter as an evil in its true magnitude. Nor can it be reasonably doubted, that the threatening of death — of death simply — death as the supreme evil in the habitual thought and feeling of the human mind, is fitted to make a stronger impression than the threaten- ing of any other evil. Different effects might to some extent be produced on different minds by the supposed difference of penalty. But I now speak of the most general effect, and the thought and the fear of death are ever present to every mind in their practical and controlling power. Now it is of this universal habitual thought and fear of death, that the moral governor in presenting the penalty of his law avails himself. He conforms to this universal and familiar conception of the human mind ; and when he would impress most effectually every subject with his highest disapprobation of disobedience to his supreme law, he makes that which in their constant and familiar conceptions is signalized as the supreme evil —the great- est of all evils — the expression and the proof of his disapproba- tion. What so natural, what so fitted to his design? They know how the lan^ua^e ouo-ht to be understood. He knows how it will be understood. He knows their conceptions of the evil, and is sure of the judgment which they will form of the degree of his disapprobation of disobedience, when thus measured by death as the penalty of his law. He thus shows himself the 152 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. benevolent protector of the welfare of the state, by showing himself in their just estimation the mortal enemy of rebellion against it. In the most natural, obvious and impressive man- ner, even in the only possible way, he manifests the highest disapprobation of disobedience to his supreme law ; and so also the feelings and the character on which his authority de- pends. Thus I have attempted to show, that the view now main- tained of the nature of legal sanctions in a perfect moral govern- ment, is substantially that which mankind generally entertain of the sanctions of the supreme law of the state. If indeed we find, in the wisest and best administration of human govern- ment, some occasional departures from, or even violations of the principles contended for, still we also find the most distinct recognition of the principles themselves. Every such departure or violation is so obviously the result of the comparative in- feriority of the interests to be protected, and the necessary im- perfection of a human administration, not to say of its corrup- tion, as clearly to show,that they cannot mar the moral admin- istration of a Being infinitely perfect. Here no departure from the principles of eternal truth and righteousness can arise from weakness or error, from indifference or aversion to the end to be accomplished. The magnitude of the interests concerned, the value of the law as the indispensable means of securing these interests, the ill-desert of transgression as the destruction of this law, the relation and the authority of the lawgiver, are to be estimated, not by the standard of earth and time, but by that of eternity. And if what has now been said in respect to the sanctions of the law of the state be true, what can truth, and wisdom, and goodness demand in the government of a king- dom, where every act of every subject is virtually the perfect and endless happiness or misery of all, but a full and unquali- fied manifestation of the benevolence of Him that sitteth on the throne, in his highest approbation of right and disapprobation of wrong moral action ? What other influence can command respect and reverence, or be fitted to secure confidential and cheerful submission to his will, except that which emanates from the sanctions of his law, revealing that character which alone becomes the friend and guardian of universal happiness — an influence from the manifestation of himself, clothing him with majesty as with a garment? CHRISTIANITY NOT A SELFISH SYSTEM. 153 I shall conclude this lecture with three remarks : 1. Christianity is not a selfish system of religion. Infidels have often said, that Christianity, inasmuch as it aims to influ- ence men by rewards and punishments, is a selfish, mean, and mercenary system. And I am sorry to say, that many of the friends and advocates of Christianity have furnished too much occasion fur this reproach. It has often been said in the pulpit, that man cannot act under the influence of the divine threatenings without acting in a selfish maimer ; and yet of- tener, how this can be otherwise has been deemed an unsolvable problem. The question more fully stated, is this : how can the promised good and the threatened evil involved in these sanctions be presented to the mind of man, without directly ap- pealing to his selfishness ; or, how can man act in view of these motives without acting in a selfish manner ? I answer, that according to the view now given of legal sanc- tions as involving natural good and evil, they appeal not to human selfishness at all, but only to self-love, or to the consti- tutional susceptibility of the mind to happiness and misery. They do not appeal to selfishness, because that would be to offer a less good than the greatest. But these sanctions proffer the highest good of which man is capable — the happiness of being good and doing good. And to choose this is to be dis- interestedly benevolent. It is voluntarily renouncing every good which can come into competition with the public weal, and therefore truly virtuous. And further : the direct influ- ence of these sanctions on the mind, as natural good and evil, wholly terminates in awakening constitutional desires to se- cure the one and avoid the other. Such desires are not volun- tary states of the mind, not acts of the will, and therefore not selfishness, which is an act of will. They are simply constitu- tional feelings, inseparable from the nature of man as a sentient being, without which man could become neither benevolent nor selfish, but must be as insensible as a stone or a clod. By these susceptibilities, with their resulting states of desire, he is quali- fied, in one respect, to become either benevolent or selfish, and can therefore become selfish only by his own fault, only by the perversion of the influence, which is designed to secure the opposite result, benevolence. Nor is this all. For, while the reward and the penalty are designed and fitted to awaken strong constitutional emotion, the design by no means termi- 154 MOKAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. nates in this. They are designed to be subservient to an- other and a higher purpose — to show God to the mind, and to do it in the most impressive maimer conceivable ; to rouse thought and sensibility and emotion to behold God in his supreme approbation of obedience and supreme disapproba- tion of disobedience; to see and know this fact as one in which the mind has a direct personal concern. The design is to show, in such a manner that the mind shall not fail to see God in the glory of his holiness — with the full strength of his infinite will fixed on securing right and preventing wrong moral action. Such is the object presented through the medium of these sanctions. And is it selfislmess,for man thus seeing clearly and exactly what God is, to love him ? Is there any influence more directly sanctifying in its tendency, more fitted to make holy than that which is furnished by this vision of the perfect God ? And is it mean or mercenary for man to yield himself to do the will of infinite wisdom and goodness, and thus in heart, in will and character, to become like God himself? 2. In the view which has now been given of legal sanctions, we may see what it is to make light of the divine threaten- ings. I here speak hypothetically. If God is administering a perfect moral government over men, then in view of the sanctions of such a government, what is it to make light of them? "What are they? Manifestations of God, peculiarly bright, glorious, and awful. They are manifestations of God in that character, under that high relation to man, which is more desirable, more exalted, more worthy of Himself, and more useful to man, than any the human mind can conceive. If a perfect God is not also the perfect moral governor of his moral creation, what is he ? I am not now saying that he is. But if he is not, I ask you what he is ? Have you decided, can you decide surely and beyond all doubt, what that relation is which God sustains to moral beings if not that of their moral gover- nor ? Do not, then, make light of what are and what must be — if he is their moral governor — the sanctions of his law. Prove Christianity to be false if you can. But do you know, can you prove, that God is not administering a perfect moral govern- ment over his moral creation ? This is at least a possible truth. There may be such a God, such a government, such sanctions. And it is any thing but philosophy, reason, or magnanimity to trifle with such possible reality as this. Say if you must, that DEISTS CANNOT PROVE GOD'S BENEVOLENCE. 155 you do not believe that proof is wanting ; but do not ridicule, do not despise and make light of it, lest haply you make light of God in the brightest splendors of his glory. 3. Those who deny the view iioav given of the sanctions of a perfect moral government cannot prove the benevolence of God. Deists, universalists, all those who deny either the fact or the nature of God's perfect moral government, profess to be- lieve that God is perfectly benevolent. This belief, to man in his weakness and consequent dependence on his Maker, it would seem must be quite welcome, not to say natural. It is the only source of light in this dark world ; the only refuge from terror. What an amount of misery must result from the thought of a tyrant in the heavens, and of the cruelties to which his creation must be exposed. Ignorant as men may be of goodness, and little as they may esteem or desire it for themselves, all know how to appreciate it when compared with the opposite charac- ter, as that of the Being who holds in his hands their destiny. Hence, even with those who entertain inadequate and false views of its nature and its necessary doings, it is a fond and favorite belief that God is good. But it is a momentous question, can they, on their ^incijjle-s, show any ground for this belief; can they prove that God is good ? I answer, not unless they can show that he is adminis- tering a perfect moral government over men. If this can be proved, if it can be seen from the light of nature that he is administering a perfect moral government over men involv- ing on his part the highest approbation of right and the highest disapprobation of Avrong moral action ; if it can be shown that he has so hegun the administration of his moral government in this world, that he can, and that he furnishes sufficient evidence that he will finish it in another ; that he is carrying forward such a system in respect to each individual of our race as rapidly as its perfection demands, and this with a singleness of purpose to complete what he has begun, and with a benignity of execution which foretells results worthy of in- finite goodness, especially if it can be proved that he is admin- istering such a government under an economy of grace, then indeed it may not be difficult to prove his perfect benevolence. Then Ave may be able to show that he has adopted the best conceivable system, that moral evil is incidental in respect to divine prevention to this best system ; that natural evil is the 156 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. necessary means of the greatest good ; and that the system it- self, with its issues here and hereafter, is as decisive a proof of the goodness of its author, as had no evil but the perfect and universal happiness of his creation been the actual result. But if on the other hand, it cannot be shown that God is admin- istering a perfect moral government, involving the mani- festation of his highest approbation of right, and his highest disapprobation of wrong moral action, then his benevolence or moral perfection cannot be proved. Yet more is true. If the proof of benevolence is wanting in respect to a being who has been acting for thousands of years in the view of his intelligent and dependent creatures, the want of such evidence is itself proof of the opposite character. If you say,that aside from the fact that God is administering a perfect moral government over men, there is abundant proof of his benevolence, I ask, what is it and what are your premises ? You must know or prove something to be true of God, that you may frame an argument. If God then is not a perfect moral governor of men, what is he? What relation or relations does he sustain toward his dependent creatures, and what are his designs and purposes concerning them ? If you cannot decide these questions, then you know and can decide nothing to your purpose. On the question of his moral character you have no data, no premises ; and you must either believe nothing respect- ing it, or believe that he is a selfish or malignant being, or that he is good without evidence, and merely because you wish to believe it. What then is the proof that God is benevolent, on the sup- position that he is not a perfect moral governor ? Is it said, that as a being of infinite natural perfection, he must be also a being of infinite benevolence ? I answer, not so, not of neces- sity, for he is a free moral agent ; nor yet of certainty, for other moral beings are wholly selfish, and yet are not so through the imperfection of their natural powers. I admit indeed, that the natural perfections of God furnish a presumption of his moral perfection, even sufficient proof of it, if it can be shown to be uncounteracted by opposing evidence. But it is a kind of evi- dence which in its nature admits of opposing evidence, and may be wholly neutralized and set aside by his acts and his doings, by his treatment of his creatures. His natural perfections then, in view of the existing evil under his government, furnish no CAN GOD BE BENEVOLENT AND ALLOW EVIL? 157 proof, nothing like proof, of his benevolence, until the existence of evil be accounted for consistently with his benevolence. If a father, in all that he lias done for his dependent offspring from birth to manhood, has furnished no proof of affection and kindness toward them by his conduct, to what purpose should we appeal to his intellectual and physical superiority, or even to the fact that he is their father? The evidence from his do- ings, from the utter want of benevolent action, would be decisive against his benevolence. Do you then appeal to the doings of God, and claim that he proves himself to be good by imparting more happiness than misery to his creatures, and thus rendering their existence far preferable to non-existence ? This fact, though it may be necessary to the proof, is not itself proof of the goodness of the Creator. Beings who are not benev- olent but are wholly selfish, often produce more happiness than misery. Why then does not an omnipotent Creator impart per- fect and unmingled happiness to his sentient creation ; why, under his government, is there misery at all ? Do you say, that nothing is contrived to produce misery, that every design and adaptation is to produce good, that " teeth are made to eat and not to ache." This is not true in such a respect as your argument requires. Teeth are made to ache. lie who made them, knew that they would ache, and for some reason or other intended that they should ache. And the question is, why not make teeth which would not ache ? Is there any pretense that God has produced all the natural good he can, so far as mere power is concerned ? Do you then say, that the fact that crea- tures are not perfectly happy,is not owing to the want of power in God, but to some limitation in the nature of things ; that the 'system by which alone the greatest good possible to the Crea- tor can be produced involves, in respect to his prevention, evil in the nature of things? What evil? You cannot say all the natural evil which exists. Do you then say moral evil, and as a necessary and useful consequence, natural evil ? Be it so. But then, what is that system which thus.necessarily in the nature of things involves moral evil ? Plainly a moral system, a moral government ; and if it be proof of a perfect God, then it must be a perfect moral government. But now you arc on our ground. You are reasoning from the fact that God is admin- istering a perfect moral government over men. And thus you are compelled to reason, if you would find the shadow of proof 158 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. that God is benevolent, or rather if you would set aside the most decisive proof that he is not benevolent. And now if you mean to reason in proof of the divine benevolence on this ground, then do not forget it. God, you believe, is adminis- tering a perfect moral government over men. If you do not, and say that there is some other mode of proving his benev- olence than on the ground that he is administering a perfect moral government over men, then tell us what it is. This is one of the great points in the argument for God's benevolence. It is not to be passed over lightly, to be conceded for the mo- ment, to be used for the purpose of establishing a conclusion and then forgotten as the most momentous relation of God to his moral creation. If God is not the perfect moral governor of men, we want to know what he is, what are his relations, designs, and doings toward the children of men ; we want to know what his character is ; we want to know whether there is nothing on the throne of the universe but omnipotent selfish- ness or infinite malignity ; we want to know, in a word, what the God of the infidel is. He is not to have the benefit to his argument and his system of the belief in a benevolent God, unless he can prove that in truth there is such a God. This he cannot do without admitting: the fact — which, as I maintain, is fatal to his infidelity — the truth that God is administering a perfect moral government overmen. He is shut up to this alternative. He must admit either that God feels the highest approbation of right and the highest dis- approbation of wrong moral action, or that he does not ; that God reigns over us in the glory of a perfect moral dominion, or that the Being who holds all destiny in his hands is a being of unqualified selfishness, or even of infinite malignity. From this dilemma there is no escape. And now I request those infidels, universalists — all who deny that God feels the highest approbation of right and highest dis- approbation of wrong moral action, and as a perfect moral gov- ernor will express these feelings — to look carefully at this point. You believe in the perfect benevolence of God. But is your faith rational according to your own principles ; has it the least foundation or warrant unless God is the perfect moral governor ? You believe in God's perfect benevolence. Why ? Have you examined the foundations of your faith ? Have you seen, that if you believe in God's benevolence, you must THE DEIST'S IDEA OF GOB. 159 believe in God's perfect moral government over yourself and »all men? Have yon looked at the monstrons incongruity in a God perfectly benevolent, and yet not feeling the highest ap- probation of right, and the highest disapprobation of wrong moral action? Or rather, for you will allow me to ask the question, is not this aspect of God unwelcome and repulsive, and excluded from your faith for the sake of what seems to you the more attractive and lovely view of a being who is good without being just, and virtually indifferent to the best thing as the means of happiness, and to the worst thing as the means of misery, right and wrong moral action? If so, see where you stand. As a rational being you are bound to be- lieve in an infinite God who is virtually indifferent to that ac- tion in his creatures, which will secure their highest happiness or misery — indifferent to the weal and woe, the life and death of his own creation — a being who has no rectitude of principle, and who, for aught that appears, will sacrifice to self-will, to favoritism, to selfishness in some form, every interest of every creature whose character can excite no love, awaken no hope, inspire no confidence — whose heart is unmoved by pity, un- touched by woe — a being, the bare thought of whom is enough to fill the soul with consternation and dismay. If there is any thing in reason, such is — such must be the God of the in- fidel. And if the aspect of the God of Christianity is unwel- come and repulsive, what is that of the God of infidelity? The character of the former to a wise and good man (I know I speak with the approbation of every man's conscience) is ground only for hosannas of rapture — that of the latter would make all things tremble but the dark throne on which he him- self sitteth. LECTURE VIII. Y. A perfect Moral Government involves the exercise of authority through the medium of law. — The nature of the law further unfolded. — Seventhly. The Law of a perfect Moral Government involves the requisite sanctions of the Moral Governor's authority. — 6th. Legal sanctions in- clude the highest possible degree of natural good, &c, and the highest possible degree of evil. — Objections. — Punishment ought to terminate with sin; if all should disobey, all ought not to be punished; incredible and impossible that God should adopt a moral system with such liabilities. — Conclusion. I now proceed to show as I proposed — 6 tli. That the legal sanctions of a perfect moral government include the highest degree of nattered good possible in each case of obedience, and the highest degree of natural evil possible in each case of disobedience. The doctrine lias often been maintained) that natural good and evil in their highest degree, annexed to the best law as its reward and penalty, become legal sanctions by operating sim- ply as motives (or inducements) to secure the greatest amount of obedience. "We have seen however, that natural good and evil employed merely in the way of motives, cannot become legal sanctions. It is doubtless true that the natural good and evil employed as legal sanctions, have beside their sanctioning in- fluence and as necessary to it, another, even the influence of motives. This with the sanctioning influence, or with that which establishes the authority of the moral governor, may be necessary to secure the greatest amount of obedience. If we could suppose a system designed to secure the greatest amount of right moral action by the mere influence of natural good and evil as motives, and to the exclusion of the peculiar influ- ence of moral government — the influence of authority — then we could not say, that the highest possible degrees of natural good and evil would not be necessary to the end proposed. Be this however as it may, the present argument for the highest de- grees of natural good and evil is not placed on this basis. It rests solely on the ground that such degrees of natural good and evil are necessary for another purpose, that of sanctioning or establishing the authority of the moral governor. THE NATURE OF LEGAL REWARD. 161 This argument, in view of what has been already said, may be thus briefly presented. Natural good and evil are necessary as legal sanctions to the law of a perfect mural government ; they are necessary as legal sanctions, for in their relation they establish and sustain the authority of the moral governor; they are so as being the necessary manifestations of his benevolence in the particular forms of his highest approbation of obedience and disapprobation of disobedience. This degree of approval and disapproval can be manifested only by the highest possible degree of natural good as the reward of obedience and of nat- ural evil as the penalty of disobedience. It follows therefore, that the highest possible degree of natural good as a legal re- ward, and of natural evil as a legal penalty are necessary to establish the authority of the moral governor. This argument contains two premises in addition to others already considered, which, obvious as they are, may need a more particular consideration. I remark then — In the first place, that the legal reward must, for the purpose specified, consist of the highest possible degree of happiness to the obedient subject. + I now speak of that degree of reward which pertains to a perfect system of moral government — a system in which the highest happiness of each individual is consistent with that of the whole. Some indeed maintain the impossibility of such a system, affirming that the sin and misery of a part are the ne- cessary means of the greatest good of the whole. To this I here briefly reply, that the assumption of a system in which the highest good of each shall be consistent with that of the whole as an impossibility, is wholly gratuitous and unauthorized, since the supposition of such a system cannot be shown to involve any contradiction or absurdity. And further, if such a system of moral government is impossible, then a perfect system of moral government is impossible ; indeed, any thing which can be called a moral government is impossible ; for sin being ac- cording to the supposition, the necessary means of the greatest good, there can be no sincerity, truth, or benevolence, and of course no authority in a lawgiver who should forbid it. And lastly, the supposed perfect system is possible, nothing being more absolutely certain, than that every moral agent and there- fore every subject of a moral government can be morally per- il 162 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. feet, and that the moral perfection of each and of all in its true tendency, would secure the perfect happiness of each and of all. If then in such a system the moral governor does not secure the highest happiness of the obedient subject which he can se- cure, he does not choose to make the subject thus happy ; and as the highest happiness of each obedient subject is consistent with and necessary to the highest happiness of the whole, he neither chooses the highest happiness of the individual, nor of the whole. He is therefore not benevolent, and has no right to give law to a moral kingdom. The same thing on the present supposition may be shown in other forms. !Not choosing to make the obedient subject happy in the highest possible degree, the moral governor does not express the highest approbation of obedience, and therefore does not feel it. lie therefore proves that he is not benevolent, and of course subverts his authority or right to command. Or thus, according to what has been already shown, the decisive expression of the moral governor's highest approbation of obedience, is indispensable as a proof of such approbation, while not to make such an expression gives equal evidence of the want of such approbation — proof <*of the want of benevolence — of the opposite principle, and of course of the want of all authority or right to rule. But the only conceivable mode of proving his highest approbation of obedience, is by conferring on the obedient subject on account of his obedience the highest possible degree of happiness. Otherwise he can furnish no proof that he does not feel, and would not express higher approbation of disobedience than of obedience. If then he does not confer on the obedient subject the highest possible degree of happiness as a legal reward, he does not regard obedience as he ought, or as a perfect being must regard it. He shows himself to be destitute of benev- olence, and therefore without authority. Again ; if the moral governor does not confer the highest pos- sible happiness on the obedient as a reward, there can be no proof that he would do it, were it necessary to prevent the universal disobedience, and with it the universal and perfect misery of his kingdom. Xor is the supposition of such a ne- cessity unauthorized. There can be no proof that it does net exist. The declaration of the moral governor to the contrary cannot be received as evidence ; for there is no proof of his benevolence, and of course none of his veracity. Such a re- DEGREES AND CONTINUANCE OF REWARD. 163 ward may be necessary to prevent such a fearful issue. But since the moral governor refuses according to the present sup- position, to annex such a reward to his law, when as we have seen it is dictated by benevolence and demanded by the highest happiness of his kingdom, it follows, that there can be no proof that he would confer such a reward were it necessary to prevent the universal disobedience, and with it the universal and per- fect misery of his kingdom. As he does not confer the reward which is demanded by benevolence in the one case, there can be no reason to conclude that he would in the other. What confidence can be reposed in such a being — what authority can he possess? — He, a being of whose benevolence there is not the slightest evidence — of whose selfishness the proof is decisive, and who may, as all are bound to believe, consent to and actu- ally prefer the universal and perfect wretchedness of his king- dom, rather than confer the highest happiness which he can confer on perfectly obedient subjects. Should it here be said v that the highest possible degree of happiness as a legal reward, is inconsistent with different de- grees of reward according to the merit of different subjects, I answer, that the capacity of happiness in different subjects would differ according to their character. If we suppose va- rious degrees of merit in subjects who are perfectly obedient, we must suppose different degrees of capacity for happiness. Should each therefore receive as a reward the highest possible amount of happiness, that is, the highest of which he is cap- able, degrees of reward would exist, differing according to the degrees of merit. In respect to the duration of reward, I remark, that from the very nature of law, it follows, that reward must continue while obedience continues, and cease when obedience ceases. That it must do so, is obvious from what has been already shown. To suppose reward to be withheld from a subject who continues obe- dient, is to suppose no approbation, but disapprobation of obedi- ence on the part of the moral governor, and of course the want of authority. That the reward must cease when obedience ceases — every expression of approbation of the conduct of the subject on the part of the governor is equally obvious. The demand of the law is, that the subject render ceaseless obedi- ence, and the subject is bound to render it. When therefore he ceases to obey, he ceases to satisfy the claim of law — ceases 164 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. to fulfill his obligation — ceases to be an obedient subject. All ground of approbation by the moral governor ceases, and it is impossible that he should regard and treat the subject as obedient, without regarding and treating him as he is not; without regarding the non-fulfillment of the claim of law, as obedience to it. The governor can therefore never confer a re- ward on the disobedient subject, without approving of his fail- ure to satisfy the claim of law. If we suppose the disobedient subject to reform, this cannot so change his relation to law as to cause him to stand right in law, or to become the fit object of favor and reward from the moral governor. He has not satisfied the claim of law, but violated it. He never can satisfy it. The lawgiver therefore must cease to express all approba- tion of the subject by ceasing forever to reward, or he must reward in view of his unsatisfied claim for obedience; that is, he must pass by, overlook, and virtually approve and reward transgression, and thus subvert his authority. We may view this topic in another light. The disobedient subject destroys all law and all authority. His act in its true nature and tendency destroys all good and produces all evil. His ill-desert is not so diminished by subsequent reformation, as not to require that degree of penalty which is necessary to ex- press the moral governor's highest disapprobation of such an act. The deed has been done which creates the necessity for such an infliction of evil. Without it, no adequate expression can be made of the moral governor's feelings toward the act, nor of his benevolence. But the principle now stated will be still more obvious, when we consider the degree of penal evil which is necessary to establish and sustain the moral gov- ernor's authority. I remark, then— In the second place, that the legal penalty must consist of the highest possible degree of misery to the disobedient sub- ject. Were the moral governor to inflict a less degree of suffering as a legal penalty than the highest possible in the case, nothing would or could appear to show that he would not inflict greater suffering for something else, even for some act of obedience, than he inflicts for disobedience. Why else, when every object and end for expressing disapprobation at all, imperiously demands the expression of the highest disapprobation, when as we have THE LEGAL PENALTY. 165 seen, nothing can justify him in inflicting natural evil as a pen- alty, except the necessity of so doing to establish his authority by showing his highest disapprobation of disobedience, or that there is nothing which he so much abhors as this supreme evil, why does he not show it ? Were he to make the transgressor this enemy of all good, this author of universal and absolute misery, in the highest degree miserable, that would put at rest the question of his own supreme abhorrence of transgres- sion. None could doubt that he is a being of perfect benevo- lence, and has the necessary feelings of such a being toward wrong moral action. If this be not done, then he can furnish no proof that such is his character. He furnishes decisive proof to the contrary. The appropriate necessary expression of his highest abhorrence of rebellion is not made. Whatever may be the reason for refusing to do it, it is an insufficient reason. He furnishes not the shadow of evidence that lie acts upon the principle of immutable rectitude of benevolence. He does not show that he has that supreme abhorrence of rebel- lion which a benevolent being must have, and as a perfect governor must show himself to have. There is no evidence that he does not inflict suffering, regardless of every good and sufficient reason for inflicting it — regardless of every principle of rectitude, and therefore as a matter of caprice or despotic humor, at least as the dictate of the selfish principle. There is proof rather that he is actuated by the selfish principle. Xot acting in the relation of a moral governor, as a benevolent being must act, he proves himself to be a selfish being. Why then, if disposed, will he not inflict greater suffering on the obedient than he inflicts on the disobedient ! What confidence can be placed in the character of such a being ? What authority or right to reign can he possess ? Again; the moral governor, by not inflicting the highest possible suffering on the transgressor, shows that he esteems the transgression of Ids law a less evil than the infliction of such a penalty. Transgression, if unpunished in one instance, utterly destroys the authority of law — destroys the highest happiness of all of which the authority of the law is the neces- sary means, and produces all the misery, of the prevention of which the authority of law is the necessary means. When transgression occurs, the alternative on the part of the moral governor is, either to consent to the destruction of his authority 166 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. with these fearful results, or to sustain it, by expressing his highest disapprobation of transgression in the infliction on the transgressor of the highest degree of suffering. Such being the alternative, he shows, by refusing to inflict the supposed penalty, that he prefers a far greater evil to a less. JNo matter what the reason or motive may be, none can be supposed for not inflicting the requisite penalty, which will not bring upon him the imputation of preferring the destruction of his author- ity, and the production of all the misery, the prevention of which depends on its support, to the infliction of that penalty on the transgressor which is requisite to maintain his authority, and to prevent the evil resulting from it* subversion. By re- fusing to inflict this penalty, he shows that he esteems such a deed, with its ruin and its miseries, a less evil than the inflic- tion of the highest degree of suffering on the author of the deed. By the infliction of such a penalty, its evil tendency would be counteracted and its results prevented ; and yet the moral governor refuses to inflict it. He becomes there- fore the voluntary responsible author of all this evil. Who would or could confide in his character, or submit to his au- thority I Once more ; if the moral governor does not inflict the high- est possible suffering on the transgressor, there can be no evi- dence or proof that he would inflict such a penalty, if it were necessary to secure the obedience and perfect happiness of all, and to prevent the disobedience and perfect misery of all for- ever. I do not say, as some have said, that this penalty is necessary to the result now specified. But I affirm that there can be no proof that there is not. The moral governor's decla- ration would be no proof on this point, for as yet his character for benevolence and veracity is not established. There can therefore be no possible evidence or proof in the view of his subjects, that the supposed penalty is not necessary to secure the obedience and perfect happiness of all, and to prevent their disobedience and perfect misery forevermore; and therefore, none that the moral governor, with the knowledge of this necessity, would inflict the penalty — no proof that he would punish a single individual, were it necessary on the one hand to make his kingdom a paradise of holiness and joy, and on the other, to prevent it from becoming a pandemonium of sin and misery; no proof that he does not prefer the destruction TIIE LEGAL PENALTY ETERNAL. 167 of the perfect happiness and the production of the perfect mis- ery of all, rather than inflict the same evil on one who is the author of the direful result ; no proof that the least security — the least barrier against sin, exists in the character of the moral governor; that holiness and its joys will not utterly cease to exist, and sin and its woes reign without restraint and without mitigation ; the universe become an unqualified hell, and the moral governor stand revealed in his true character, a selfish, malignant being, the accessory of the transgressor, the patron of sin, the responsible author of the eternal misery of all. Such, according to the evidence in the case, and in the view of his subjects, would be the character of a moral governor who should refuse to inflict the highest degree of suffering, as the penalty of transgressing the best law. It can hardly be necessary to say, that according to the view now given of legal penalty, the suffering of the transgressor, if it be possible, must be unmingled and eternal. The only supposable case in which an Omnipotent moral governor can- not inflict unmingled suffering, is that of a penitent, reformed transgressor. The natural possibility that a transgressor, under a system of mere law, should reform or return to duty, and the impossibility of rendering such a one perfectly miserable, or as miserable as he might be rendered without reforming, may be admitted. On the supposition however of the refor- mation of a transgressor, he would still be capable of suffering in some degree; and the highest degree of suffering possible in his case, would fully evince the moral governor's highest dis- approbation of his transgression. It would, as such an expres- sion, fully establish his authority, and would be necessary for this purpose. In the case of the impenitent transgressor, unmingled suffering would be possible, and is therefore the degree of suffering which, in his case, is requisite to sustain the moral governor's authority. Its eternal duration is possible, and therefore in all cases it must be eternal, that it may answer the end of a legal penalty in a perfect moral government. Some objections to the view of legal sanctions, which has now been given, demand consideration. Objection 1. It is said, that on the principle, that reward is to be continued only while obedience continues, it follows, that punishment is to be continued only while disobedience con- tinues; in other words, that the repentance or reformation of 168 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. the transgressor is a just ground of forgiveness and favor from the moral governor.* This objection derives all its plausibility from a false view of the essential claim of law. It supposes that law does not in its very nature claim uninterrupted obedience, or that pres- ent conformity to law, however frequently it may have been interrupted by transgression, is still obedience, and as such justly entitled to the reward. If this be so, then all that the law claims is to transgress and reform. The claim of the law is satisfied by transgression and reformation. To transgress and reform, is obedience to law by satisfying the claim of the law. To transgress and reform is therefore all that the law does, or can justly demand of its subjects. Without affirming that the lawgiver in such a case would prove himself to be as well pleased with transgression as with reformation on the part of the subject, it is plain, that he shows himself to be as well pleased with transgression and reformation as with unin- terrupted obedience. This is too absurd to be maintained by any. But why is it, that when obedience ceases, reward must also cease, and punishment begin, never to cease ? It is be- cause the law of a perfect moral government requires, and to deserve the name of law must require, the uninterrupted obe- dience of the subject, and because the lawgiver can sustain his authority by the sanction of reward, only by rendering reward to that which satisfies the claim of law. In rewarding for uninterrupted obedience, he rewards on the only possible ground of a just legal reward — that the claim for uninterrupted obedi- ence is satisfied by the subject. In this way only can the reward become an expression of his highest approbation of that which satisfies his claim on the subject, and thus support his authority. If obedience be interrupted by an act of diso- bedience, the claim of the lawgiver is not satisfied by the subject, and never can be. Of course the only ground of con- ferring a reward, by which the lawgiver can accomplish the * Many advocates of the doctrine of endless punishment unwarily admit, that punishment is to be continued only while disobedience continues, by vindicating the justice of such punishment on the ground of continued sin. They thus concede, that without continued sin, eternal punishment would be unjust. I only say here, that this is not vindicating the doctrine of revelation, which declares, that " cursed is every one that continueth not in all things written in the book of the £tw, to do them." OBJECTIONS CONSIDERED. 1G9 end of a legal reward, does not exist, and never can exist. He can express no approbation of the subject by a reward confer- red on tlie ground of liis satisfied claim. If lie express appro- bation at all, it must be in view of liis claim, as unsatisfied and violated by the subject who is rewarded. By such an act, he relinquishes his claim for uninterrupted obedience, — allows transgression, which, in one instance, is the destruction of all good, lie shows himself satisfied with, and approving trans- gression, by becoming the friend and patron of the transgressor. The reason then is obvious, why uninterrupted reward, accord- ing to the very nature of law, is exclusively connected with Uninterrupted obedience, viz., the claim, and only claim of law on the subject, is satisfied by such obedience, and can be satis- fied by nothing else. The reason is equally obvious, why unin- terrupted punishment is connected with interrupted obedience, and not exclusively with uninterrupted transgression — viz., the claim, and only claim of law on the subject, is not satisfied by transgressing and repenting, but is as truly unsatisfied and violated as by continued transgression. Again; it is objected, obedience during a limited period, does not deserve a future endless reward, while disobedience in one instance does deserve an endless punishment. The good and ill-desert of conduct in a subject of moral government are to be determined by, or rather they are themselves the relations of his conduct to the support and the subversion of the moral governor's authority. The obedience of the subject supports the moral governor's authority so long, and only so long as it is rendered. It does not extend its influence in this respect through all futurity, and thus give eternal support to the law- giver's authority. The subject while obedient, fulfills only a present obligation, and satisfies a present claim. He therefore does nothing, and can do nothing which can have any influence to sustain the lawgiver's authority beyond the present effect of his present obedience. Whether he will support this authority in future, depends on his future obedience. Having then given no support by his obedience to the authority of the lawgiver for the future, he can deserve no reward for so doing. The sole reason for conferring upon him a reward for his obedience is, that his obedience supports the lawgiver's authority, while it is rendered. If then his obedience ceases, so does its influence in this respect and with it every reason for a reward, and of Vol. I.— 8 170 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN TIIE ABSTRACT. course all desert of reward. But this is not all. The subject, by ceasing to obey becomes disobedient ; and by this one act, if its influence be uncounteracted by the execution of penalty, he destroys the authority of the moral governor forever. He can in no way prevent the effect, either by doing or by suf- fering. He is as ill-deserving as were the effect to follow, as had he laid the authority of the moral governor in ruin forever- more, and must himself remain as ill-deserving forever. His ill-desert can neither be diminished, canceled, nor annihilated. The relation of transgression to law, its tendency to destroy its authority and to subvert moral government is eternal. It is true, the moral governor, by the execution of the legal penal ty, can counteract this tendency, can prevent the actual effect, can uphold his own authority. He can do this however, not by an- nihilating the transgression of his law, nor its tendency to de- stroy his authority, but only by punishment as his continued act, expressing his continued supreme disapprobation of the transgressor. The punishment cannot change at all the nature and tendency of the transgression. It simply in the manner already explained, counteracts this tendency of transgression, and thus holds back the effect which would follow the moment in which punishment should cease. The sole reason for inflict- ing the penalty of law is not diminished nor removed by its infliction for any limited period. Of course the ill-desert of transgression is not lessened nor removed by such an inflic- tion. The entire influence of the penalty is to uphold the moral governor's authority, as a continued expression and proof of his highest disapprobation of transgression. As the tendency of transgression to destroy his authority is eternal, the expression of his highest disapprobation of transgression in the form of legal penalty must be eternal. Let us look still further at the doctrine under consideration. The principle on which the doctrine rests is, that equity or jus- tice demands that the penitent reformed transgressor of law be forgiven and rewarded. It is to no purpose to say, that the act of forgiving the penitent transgressor is an act of sovereignty on the part of the lawgiver; for it cannot be vindicated as such under a merely legal dispensation, unless it be consistent with benevolence in the form of general justice ; and if it be consist- ent witl i general justice under such a dispensation, that the subject of law be exempted from the penalty of law, then it REPENTANCE NOT ENTITLED TO PARDON. 171 must be inconsistent with general justice either to threaten to punish, or actually to punish him for transgression. Of course justice forbids his punishment, that is, demands his exemption from the legal penalty. His exemption therefore is not by sovereignty. In respect to this principle, I remark, that it is a groundless and unauthorized assumption. Who will pretend that he either knows or can prove, that the great ends of a perfect moral gov- ernment and of infinite benevolence can be secured by such a principle? Who can know or prove, that were the moral gov- ernor to act on this principle in a single instance, it would not defeat every design of infinite goodness, and fill the universe with unniingled and unending woe? The principle derives no support from the practice of human governments. Whatever may be the ground of pardon in these cases, it is not the principle of equity or justice. When has the principle been recognized and proclaimed in the family, that murderers of fathers and murderers of mothers, or in the state, that traitors, conspirators, men reeking with crime and blood, are justly entitled to pardon and reward on condition of repent- ance? On this principle, the vilest malefactor cannot be justly jnmished, until it is first ascertained that he is not a penitent ; for being so, he has an equitable claim to pardon and reward. Why then in the name of all that is sacred in human rights, is not this principle of equity recognized and acted upon ? Why is not a court of equity established to vindicate these rights of injured innocence? On this principle a lawgiver has no right to punish transgres- sion of law at all, but only to punish impenitence after trans- gression. It is not rebellion, but solely the want of repentance. So also the transgressor of law cannot be justly punished for transgression which only deserves punishment. And if he can- not be justly punished for transgression, he cannot be justly punished for that which only deserves punishment ; cannot be justly punished for that for which alone he can be justly punished. On the same principle repentance itself is impossible. There can be no repentance where there is no guilt or ill-desert. But if there is no ill-desert except in the want of repentance, then there is nothing in transgression which can be repented of. The transgressor has no reason to repent of any thing whatever, or 172 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. at most of a transgression which furnishes no ground or reason for repentance. Is it said, that by repentance, the transgressor acknowledges that it would be just to punish him for his trans- gression? Then plainly justice does not require that he go un- punished, i. e., that he be pardoned for his repentance. Besides, if it is just to punish, benevolence or the general good requires punishment. How then can justice, benevolence, or the general good require his punishment, and also his exemption from pun- ishment ? On this principle, there is nothing in transgression or sin, neither guilt nor ill-desert to be forgiven ; nothing except im- penitence after transgression. But there can be no impeni- tence ; for impenitence implies previous sin, guilt or ill-desert. So that there can be nothing to be forgiven, neither sin nor im- penitence. Forgiveness therefore is impossible and inconceiv- able. There can be no grace in forgiveness ; for grace is favor or kindness to the guilty, and there is no guilt in transgression, nor yet in impenitence. There can be no influence to deter from transgression in law nor authority ; nor in anv thing else an in- nuence to prevent any thing but impenitence and this can have no existence. Repentance for sin cannot be a duty, for sin or transgression involves nothing to be repented of. There can be no reason on the part of the moral governor for prohibiting sin ; nor for displeasure, should every subject transgress his perfect law ; for the only evil in the case is impenitence after trans- gression, which impenitence itself is impossible. Nor can the moral governor with the least reason or propriety require obe- dience to his law ; for as there is nothing morally wrong in transgression, there can be nothing morally right in obedience. In short, the principle that justice requires the forgiveness of sin on condition of repentance, subverts all moral distinctions, and every relation between the moral governor and his sub- jects. This subject may be presented in other lights. Let it be supposed that a penitent transgressor is forgiven and restored to favor. The natural and authorized conclusion on the part of any and every other subject is, that if he transgresses and repents, he also shall be forgiven and restored to favor. What then is there in the legal penalty to prevent transgression ? Nothing. Its sole influence is, as so much natural evil, to deter from impenitence after transgression; for the moral governor has NO PUNISHMENT FOR IMPENITENCE. 173 authorized the conclusion, that, by repentance, the penalty shall he avoided. What the moral governor then aims at, by an abso- lute prohibition in the form of law with the absolute threatening of the penal evil, is not to invent sin, but only to prevent its continuance. For aught that appears, he is as well satisfied with transgression and repentance, as with uninterrupted and perfect obedience. Is such a ruler entitled to respect ; has he a right to reign ? Or thus : what is there in the law to prevent on the part of every subject, a continued series of alternate acts of transgression and repentance ? Nothing. As the law threatens to punish, not transgression, but only impenitence after transgression, and as transgression according to the sup- position is followed by repentance, there can be no place for punishment. Let it then be supposed, that acts of transgres- sion and of repentance occur in a series at such intervals as you please to imagine, and what shall be said of the government and the character of the lawgiver ? Can he be entitled to re- spect, or possess the least authority, or the lowest possible qualification to rule? In such a case, how could it appear that the governor would annex an endless penalty to transgression, if he knew that it would prevent all transgression? And if this could not be known, how could it appear that he would annex such a penalty, though he knew it to be necessary to prevent universal and endless transgression without repentance, and with the complete and endless misery of his kingdom ? Without however dwelling longer on the absurdities of this jxrinciple, there is one incontrovertible fact which must exempt this part of the subject from all difficulty and doubt, viz., that sin or transgression on its first existence, is the fit object of the highest disapprobation, and therefore requires the highest de- gree of penal evil. Sin, or the transgression of law, is a prin- ciple of action in a moral being, and in its essential nature, is at its first existence one and the same thing which it is in its continuance. It is true, that by continuance, in certain circum- stances, its strength as a principle of action may be increased, and also its ill-desert. In some circumstances, this is undeniably true. Under the reclaiming influences which they resist, evil men wax worse and worse. Placed under such influences, they are under the necessity of forming the selfish principle de novo with greater or less frequency, and thus greatly increase the strength of the selfish principle — their wickedness and guilt. 1 74 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. By continuance, it may also extend its actual desolations, and reveal to us more clearly its fell malignity ; and thus its intrin- sic turpitude and ill-desert may be iudged by us to be greater than in its beginning. But the question now is,not whether it becomes deserving of penalty by increasing in strength, or by developing its malignant tendency to our observation in actual results. But the question is, whether sin becomes ill-deserving or deserving of penalty by mere continuance; or whether it would cease to be ill-deserving by being repented of? I an- swer, that the mere continuance of the same principle both in kind and degree, neither gives it its ill-desert nor increases it one iota. Sin continued, differs not from sin begun, except in the mere circumstance of continuance, which can in no re- spect change the nature of sin or increase its ill-desert. Sin, when it first exists, is and must be, in its nature, tendency, and every essential relation of sin, all that it ever is or ever can be. In its true nature and tendency, and in the lowest degree of strength in which it can exist in the mind, and whether it produce its appropriate results or not, it prostrates law, author- ity, and moral government — it destroys all happiness and pro- duces all misery. It does not therefore become the fit object of the highest disapprobation by its continuance, nor by the impenitence of the transgressor, nor yet by any thing connected with or dependent on its continuance. It is so in its essential nature. As such an object, as demanding the expression of the moral governor's highest disapprobation in penal evil, it is, when it first exists, all that in its nature which it ever can be. The transgressor in his first act of transgression,strikes the death blow at all good, and puts his hand to the production of com- plete and universal misery. Then it is that the deed is com- mitted — done in heart — requiring no continuance, no repetition, no overt acts, no results in woe, to give it its full measure of ill-desert as the transgression of law. Were the full results of one sin instantly to follow its commission — the destruction of all good, and of all the means of good, with woe unmingled, complete, universal, and, without the execution of the supposed penalty, eternal, who would not see in these results the nature and ill-desert of sin, without supposing its continuance — would not see that its nature and ill-desert could not be changed by repentance, when its work was done \ Suppose now, that the execution of the supposed penalty in comparatively a few in- NO PUNISHMENT FOR IMPENITENCE. 175 stances would retrieve the evil, and cause a universe of joy, bespeaking the benevolence of its author, and lasting as eter- nity, to rise on these ruins, would not the execution of the penalty be demanded by benevolence; would not every voice of reason and of conscience respond, 'The judgment is righteous altogether V But if the supposed execution of the penalty would be demanded to retrieve the evil, why is it not required to prevent it ? We say that it is, as truly as a perfect moral government is demanded by the highest good which an infinite Being can produce. Sin then, as sin, does not derive its ill- desert in the lowest degree from impenitence, nor can its ill- desert be lessened by repentance. Being what it is in its essential nature, and viewed as a principle of action irrespect- ively of any increased strength of any actual results in evil, either natural or moral, and continuing but for a moment, it is the lit object of the highest disapprobation, and demands the highest degree of natural evil as its penalty. Objection 2. It may be said, that as punishment can be jus- tified only on the principle that the greatest good requires it, it would follow, that if all the subjects of a moral government should rebel, benevolence would forbid their endless punish- ment. If it be admitted, that in the case supposed, benevolence would forbid eternal punishment, it does not follow that it would forbid it in any actually existing case, nor in any case in which a benevolent being can be supposed to adopt a perfect moral government. ISor, to apply the objection to this world, and supposing all to be in a state of disobedience, does it follow, that benevolence might not inflict eternal punishment on all. It cannot be shown that the moral governor might not punish rebellion to whatever extent it may be supposed to exist in this world, and yet, by creating other worlds, produce on the whole an amount of creature happiness equal to that which would exist without the supposed punishment. The possibility of his so doing seems to be distinctly recognized in the Scriptures ; and the admission of it is also important, if we would duly appreciate the mercy of God in the work of redemption. "Think not," said John the Baptist, to the unbelieving Jews, " to say within yourselves, we have Abraham to our father ; for I say unto you, God is able of these stones to raise up chil- dren unto Abraham." As if he had said, God can destroy you forever, and yet glorify himself by creating and blessing other 176 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. beings. This is possible truth, and as such, it fully overthrows the present objection, as applied to the endless punishment of every human being. Such a punishment of the race may be consistent with God's benevolence. If it here be asked, why then did not God actually adopt this course? I answer, not because as a benevolent being he was under the necessity of adopting another — not because he could not secure as much (I do not say he could secure more) creature happiness, by the punishment of this world and the creation of another, as by the redemption of this ; but because, viewing this world as actually created — for it must be so, if we suppose it to de- serve punishment — it may be true that he could himself find more happiness in blessing with redemption creatures already existent, than by creating others to be the subjects of an equal degree of happiness. lie would thus derive the decisive mo- tive to redemption from himself, and not from a greater amount of creature happiness. In this view of the subject, with what emphasis does he say, "!Not for your sakes do I this, but for my own great name's sake." How rich is such mercy com- pared with that which benevolence, as is supposed, requires him to show to guilty beings ! The Christian must admit that it is, and the infidel that it may be, consistent with God's per- fect benevolence to punish a revolted world with everlasting destruction. More can be said on this point, Whether benevolence re- quires the eternal punishment of the transgressors of law in any actual case or not, it is undeniable, that there cannot be a perfect moral government without it as the penalty of trans- gression. According to the principles already presented, every subject in this case, would be authorized and required to be- lieve, by decisive evidence, that the moral governor does not regard the transgression of his law with the highest disappro- bation. He does not punish on this princij^le, but plainly shows that he esteems it of less consequence that his law is transgressed, than that that penalty be inflicted on the trans- gressor, which is requisite to sustain his own authority as a perfect moral governor. He would that the rebel should be made less than completely and eternally miserable, rather than secure and employ the necessary means of the highest happi- ness of all for eternity ; yea, rather than furnish so far as any evidence to the contrary is concerned, the necessary means of EXTREME PENALTY NOT IMPOSSIBLE. 1 V< preventing the absolute misery of all for eternity. lie shows that he does not regard obedience to his law as the supreme good, and disobedience to his law as the supreme evil. He shows himself too kind, too indulgent to the rebel, to make him as miserable as the support of his own authority and the highest happiness of his kingdom demand. In a word, he shows himself to be truly a selfish and malignant being. And what is law, authority, or moral government in such a case, but a pretense and a mockery ? To talk of a perfect moral govern- ment then, in a case in which benevolence will not allow the authority of the governor to be sustained by an endless penalty, is only to say, that a perfect moral government in such a case, is impossible; that benevolence itself forbids the necessary means of the highest happiness. Objection 3. It is said, that it is incredible and impossible that benevolence should adopt a moral government with a legal penalty consisting in the highest degree of natural evil. I answer, that to assume the impossiblity and incredibility that benevolence should adopt such a system, is wholly gratuitous and unauthorized. It cannot be shown, nor can it be rendered in the lowest degree probable, that such a system of moral govern- ment is not the necessary means of the best end which an in- finitely perfect Being can accomplish. The supposition that it is, involves no contradiction or absurdity. It may not only be true, that such a system is the necessary means of such an end, but that the end is so great that the supposed penalty in its actual execution, is in the comparison insignificant, an evil scarcely to be accounted of. Great as the evil may be to the individual sufferers, it is to be estimated not simply as related to them, but as related to the great end of the system — the end which an infinite being can accomplish only by means of it. This principle is familiar to every mind, and constantly re- cognized by right reason as indubitable. Why are the crimes of murder and treason punished with death, and this too con- sidered only as fatal to certain great interests of time ? Is not death a most fearful evil to man, viewed as a being of time only ? Why then is it made the penalty of some single acts of transgression? Because the interests which one such act de- stroys, the great ends of human society can be secured by no other means. Do you say, that the unminglecl and endless misery of a being is an evil so immeasurably great, that it is 8* 12 178 MORAL .GOVERNMENT IN TIIE ABSTRACT. incredible that there should he any necessity for it as the means of good ? But remember and admit, that the failure of the end which it may be necessary to secure, may be an immeas- urably greater evil. If you refuse to admit this, you are not a fair reasoner. If you do admit it, then why should it be thought incredible, that the penalty of the law should be the unmingled and endless suffering of the transgressor ? If the limited and comparatively inferior interests or end of an earthly kingdom, demand for their security the penalty of death, why may not the penalty under consideration be justly inflicted on him who would destroy the interests and defeat the end of an eternal kingdom. "Why may not an infinite Being propose an end, the accomplishment of which shall re- quire the infliction of the highest degree of natural evil on those who would otherwise defeat that end, who would even fill his creation with unmingled and endless woe ? The sum total of penal evil actually inflicted under this system may be ten thousand times less compared with the actual good of which it is the necessary means, than the penal evil in any kingdom, state, or even family on earth compared with the good which results from it. On this subject, if we would not be led by feeling instead of reason, we must think of the end — the happiness to be pro- duced — the misery to be prevented — the end worthy of an in- finitely perfect Being, and which shall be a full expression and manifestation of his infinite attributes — the end which such a Being will and must accomplish! And who shall prescribe limits to this, and undertake to tell how much evil may be jus- tifiably incurred in its accomplishment ? But it will probably be said, that infinite power can dispense with the supposed penalty, and that thus its necessity is wholly superseded. I answer, that a perfect moral government is the necessary means of the end proposed ; and that no degree of power can dispense with such a system, nor with any thing necessary to its perfec- tion. Perfect benevolence must adopt the system. Power can in no respect interfere with or change its nature. Omnipotence is here under a restriction from the nature of things, the gov- ernment of free moral agents. The power of an infinite Being is as truly restricted by the nature of the subject as the power of man ? What can power do ? It cannot secure as its proxi- mate effect right, nor can it prevent wrong moral action. It ETERNAL PUNISHMENT CREDIBLE. 179 cannot destroy the power of moral beings to act morally wrong without destroying their nature. In the language of Dr. Dwight, " Men are beings possessed of the full power to originate any and every moral action."* With this view of the nature of men as moral beings, it is absurd to talk of God's producing in them either rig] it or wrong moral action by dint of power; as really so as to talk of producing thought and volition by a machine, or breaking rocks with arguments, or governing the winds by motives. I am not saying that God cannot by influ- ences consistent with the nature of moral agency in men, in many instances, prevent wrong and secure right moral action. But I affirm, that in view of the nature of moral agency, it is impossible to prove that God could prevent sin in the best moral system. Moral agents can act morally wrong under every possible influence from God. To suppose him to pre- vent all wrong moral action on their part in all cases, may, for aught that can be shown to the contrary, be supposing him to do what in certain cases he cannot do, that is, that he can do in certain cases, what he cannot do. Vide Matt. xiii. 24. The system of a perfect moral government now maintained is possible, is credible, though moral evil and its eternal punish- ment in some cases be a foreseen and actual consequent. It may be true that it is the best — the necessary and only means of the best end which an infinite Being can accomplish. It may have in his estimation more value than all the worlds and beings which he has created; the end which he can accomplish only by a perfect moral government may be so great and good, that compared with it, the eternal destruction of such a world as this, nay, of thousands of such worlds, would be only as an infinitesimal compared with infinitude. It may at least be true that it were better, that heaven and earth, the created universe, should pass away, than that one jot or tittle should pass from the law. Do you say that this is telling what may be, that it is going off into the unknown regions of possibilities ? I know it. But that is where your objection goes, and we must follow. You * The same writer also says, "My actions are intuitively seen by me not to be the effects of an extraneous cause, or of something beside myself." "The changes passing in my own mind are produced bj^my own active powers." "We are agents possessing active powers by which we can originate changes." " Man chooses while possessed of a power to choose otherwise." — Theology. Sermons, 24, 21. 180 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. say it is impossible that God should adopt such a system as I have described. I show you that you cannot prove it, and have therefore no right to say it. Confess the possibility of such a system, and so take back your objection and I am satis- fied. My argument will then remain in unimpaired force. I have thus in several lectures attempted to show what a perfect moral government is, dwelling more particularly and fully on the nature of its legal sanctions. In conclusion, I pro- pose to make a few brief reflections on the subject and the manner in which it has been treated. You must have seen that the principles which I have at- tempted to sustain by reason are those which belong to the Christian system. If my endeavor has been successful, I have furnished on the authority of reason a full vindication of these great principles of Christianity, and have thus in effect re- futed every objection to Christianity which is derived from these principles. More particularly — If the view now given of the nature of moral government be correct, and if it be conceded that God is the perfect moral governor of his moral creation, then a strong not to say the strongest objection of the infidel against Christianity is re- moved, viz., that its law, or rather the law on which this sys- tem rests, involves such a fearful penalty. Most infidel writers, Paine not excepted, have conceded and applauded the excel- lence of the Christian morality — they have praised the law of Christianity, but have denounced its penalty. In view of what has been said in these lectures, I ask, what excellence would pertain to this law without its penalty? "Would it pro- pose or require the best kind of action, and so far as its excel- lence as a rule of action should be understood, furnish strong motives to obedience? Be it so. But it would not be a law — the law of a perfect moral government ; for it could possess no authority. It could not with propriety be called a rule of action. It would be advice merely ; leaving the question of conformity to the discretion of those to whom it is given, fully authorizing them to do their own will without the least respect to that of God. Yea, promulged in the form of law, it would subvert all authority in God, disprove his goodness, and justify abhorrence of his character and contempt for his government. It would reveal not even such a God as guilt makes welcome, but a being who would fill the moral creation with terror. And TIIE GOD OF INFIDELITY. 181 would such a law be excellent? What if it proposed right action, while it revealed such a being on the throne of the uni- verse, while itself was known to be — nut the law of truth, not the will of perfect benevolence, but a lie of infinite malignity ! Call this a rule of action, law, authority, moral government ! It were but the pretense, the mockery of it in the hands of an omnipotent fiend — the very patronage of iniquity, sanctioning its unrestrained perpetration, and exemplifying its horrors in the unmingled and unending miseries of the universe. Why is it that men cannot see here, what they see and know every- where else ? Who does not see and feel the power of law when administered by that supreme regard to the general good, which never wavers, never flinches, but carries it out in the full measure of its penal inflictions, whoever may be the transgressor? Were this the principle of our civil rulers, were it fully understood and known that law was in the hands of such a principle, what might and majesty it would possess ! What would become of the crimes that stalk so openly and shamelessly before our eyes? And if you want an illustration of the imbecility of law contemned and fit only to be con- temned, look at the too frequent use of the pardoning preroga- tive by the executive of our states, and at the riots, bloodshed, and murders perpetrated in anticipation of such clemency. If an armed mob in a great city, infuriate to desperation, can so impressively tell us what a law without a penalty is, why can we not learn, that a law from God without a penalty reveal- ing the feelings and the character of a perfect Being, would be no law, Worse than no law, a calamity and a curse to his moral creation ? Let us then judge of the law of God as it is ; judge of it with those sanctions which reveal a perfect God; judge of it in its true tendency, as the only law which is fitted to bring — as actually bringing the will of every moral creature of God into subjection to his will — then shall we see that the law of the Lord is perfect, that were God to give a law to moral beings without a penalty revealing his holiness, nay, his full abhorrence of sin, it would veil in darkness his brightest glories — would be the most fearful act of infinite malignity. And here, I venture to say, that the main principle in the reasonings of infidels is subverted, and their stronghold is broken down. Who does not know, that the most plausible and the most successful assaults on Christianity derive their force from 182 MORAL GOVERNMENT IN THE ABSTRACT. the fearful, and as it is represented, the incredible nature of its sanctions ? How much has been said and written on the sub- ject, to throw Christianity beyond the boundary of human cred- ibility ! as if the supreme Lawgiver of the universe had nothing to do in his administration, but to caress the foundlings of his love, and to scatter blessings among them whether obedient or disobedient ! How often are appeals made to all that is revolt- ing in the cruelty of a tyrant; how often is this contrasted with all that is touching in the tenderness of a mother; as if the governor of the moral universe must be either a Xero or a woman ! Surely a mother's tenderness, lovely as it is, does not exactly qualify her to rule a pandemonium ! To resort to such appeals in argument then,is not reasoning. To him who knows enough to reason at all on the subject, there is a majesty in law, there is certainly a majesty in God's dominion which looks down with contempt on such expedients to degrade it. But so it is. Thousands allow themselves to be misled by feeling, and to overlook without a thought, the magnitude of those interests, which for their protection employ, and will forever employ, the attributes of the Infinite Being. Indeed, if there be any case in which there can be no hope of a true verdict, it is when the question arises, what is the just penalty of transgressing the divine law, when the transgressor is the judge? We may safely say, that there is no subject within the limits of human inquiry , on which the human mind is more liable to be unduly swayed by interest and feeling, nor one on which such influence is less apt to be suspected. Argument in moral science depends much for its apparent force and conclu- siveness, on the impression which it makes on the mind. In- difference to truth and error here, is in fact out of the question. In the present instance, our reasoning, instead of meeting sen- sibilities to welcome and receive its influence, has first to en- counter the strongest tide of opposite emotion ; and so feeble is its power to impress, that its failure to convince is ascribed almost of course to its intrinsic weakness and insufficiency. Though the argument should be absolutely conclusive, and should utterly baffle every attempt to detect its weakness, it would not be strange should it leave the mind unconvinced, and be itself rejected as sophistry too ingenious to be detected. Kor would it be any more surprising, should harshness of tem- per, or at least the want of the more tender feelings of our TIIE FEELINGS SHOULD NOT DECIDE. 183 nature, be imputed to the author of an argument which sup- ports so revolting a conclusion. All this however is unphilosophical. Reproach not the ad- vocates of Christianity for severity of temper, in maintaining what may seem to you, gloomy or even terrific views of God's moral government. How easy is it to recriminate with at least equal plausibility! For what is more terrific than the God of Infidelity? On your scheme, all is uncertainty, darkness, terror. On ours only, is there light and hope even in well-doing. Hell itself giveth both, for it upholds the empire of righteousness. This is a subject then, which, above all others, calls on us to protect the understanding from all the vagaries of the imag- ination and all the feelings of the heart. Here if anywhere, should the mind be disciplined to the use of simple intellect, and be prepared to follow the light of evidence, to give up every thing to the supremacy of argument, to adopt conclu- sions however unwelcome, and to make sacrifices however painful, the moment truth demands them. For truth, be it said to her eternal honor, never can require a sacrifice which our highest good does not also demand. END OF SECTION I. THE MORAL GOVERNMENT OF GOD. SECTION II. THE MORAL GOVERNMENT OF GOD AS KNOWN BY THE LIGHT OF NATURE. LECTURE I. Thesis to be established in three leading propositions. — First, God administers a Moral Govern- ment in some sense ; for, 1, men are moral beings ; 2, God has given them a law. — Shown from the manifestation of the tendencies of action to good and evil. — No opposing evidence. — Perver- sion of a design does not disprove the reality of the design; nor the fact that such perversion was foreseen ; nor that the perversion is universal. — The perversion observed may be temporary. — Tendency to wrong, not greater than to right action. — Cause of the certainty but not of the necessity of such perversion.— The only proper method of reasoning.— Conclusion. My object in several lectures on the subject proposed, is to establish the proposition, that — God is administering a perfect moral government over MEN. For this purpose I propose : I. To show that God is administering a moral government over men in some proper import of the language. II. To prove the equity of his administration ; and — III. To prove his rightful authority. In proving the first of these propositions, we shall show that God is administering a moral in distinction from a providential government. In proving the second, i. petite. !Now true virtue leads its possessor to love and desire different objects according to their relative and real value. It gives to the greatest and to every inferior good its proper place, and thus removes all excessive desires and with them the cause of inward torment. Consider now the influence of virtue, as it regulates our pas- sions. No small portion of the unliappiness of man results from envy, anger, peevishness, impatience, revenge. Who can deny their power to annoy and torment the mind ? Who can say, as he wishes for enjoyment to-morrow, that he hopes to be angry, fretful,' envious, revengeful ? Is he who indulges these tempers happy in himself, or is he the man who contributes to the happiness of others, or is he a tormentor of himself and of others ? And yet these passions disquiet more or less every human bosom in which true virtue has not broken their do- minion. Look now at the man who governs himself. How gracefully he sways the scepter ! With what serenity and dig- nity he passes onward through life ! How equable his career ! In a world full of jarring elements and violent changes, no clouds of discontent, no whirlwinds of passion, obscure or dis- turb the steady sunshine of the soul. Like the sun in the heavens, he is far above the storms and tempests that infest and darken and agitate all beneath him. Similar remarks apply to all those peculiarities of temper 254: MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. and propensity, which are seriously calamitous to individuals. Is one the victim of that melancholy that throws its gloom over every bright prospect — is he hurried into calamities by indecision and levity of spirit — has he that selfish insensibility that shuts him out from all the sympathies and joys of earthly friendships — has he become the victim of dissipation and way- ward prodigality, what other remedy so effectual as to bring him under the influence of virtuous principle ? What like this can fix the inconstant, embolden the timid, strengthen the weak, reclaim the abandoned, and save the lost — what else can correct every infirmity, heal every mental disease, and give health and strength and perfection to the soul of man ? But the most terrible of all calamities which shake the soul, is the fear of an avenging Gocl. We know what thoughtless- ness and worldliness, absorption in business and pleasure, can do to blind us to this evil. But we know as well that it cannot be wholly avoided by wicked men. Even the hardiest in guilt cannot become wholly insensible to these forebodings. Cati- line and Nero felt remorse of conscience. The hardihood of a fiend cannot prevent it. There is the impression of a futurity on all human spirits. Every one has a conscience. All know that they have always and deliberately crossed and thwarted the will of another, and that he is no less than an infinite Being ; they know, that thus to cross the will of that Being is to offend him, and that they have always done it. They are afraid of death because they are afraid of God. They know that if there is a just retribution to sustain the prerogatives of heaven's Sovereign, and unfulfilled penalties to avenge their violation, they must fall on them. There is an emphatic voice of remonstrance and warning which they cannot quell, and a fearful looking for of judgment they cannot avoid. What is the remedy for these evils, and for those that spring from this alienation of the creature from his Creator — from this aversion of heart to the Almighty Sovereign of heaven and earth, but to return to affection and friendship — what but virtue, religion ? I say not here whether God be placable or not. But I ask, what other hope have we, or can we have, if not from conform- ity to his will ? Suppose him a selfish, even a malignant Being, what better can we do than to return to duty; what better, if we would secure the friendship of such a Being, than to do his will. If he is placable — aye, if too he is infinitely good, then ADVANTAGES OF VIRTUE. 255 what may wc not hope for ? The answer is in the feelings of an immortal, who lias seen and felt his desert of punishment — of the vengeance of the Almighty, bnt is now reposing in the bosom of infinite love. I might dwell here on the advantages of virtue in every con- dition of human life. In youth, what else can so protect from every danger and evil, and open such bright prospects for future life ? In old age, when decrepitude of body and the sinking faculties of the mind seem to open our graves, what else shall console us ? Under affliction, how disconsolate were human sorrow, with no appeal but to the unfeeling rock that crushes us. Friends forsake or betray us — all whom we love die — disease assails, which no remedies can reach, — poverty sinks us from affluence to want ; death comes — every arm is palsied, every countenance is pale in weakness and despair — what shall sustain us ? Nothing but virtue — nothing but re- ligion — nothing but doing the will of God. The love of God, the fixed purpose to do his will, gives hope of his favor. No- thing else can convert our very trials into blessings, and give the hope of a brighter world. This can change the gloom of the dark valley into the twilight of an eternal morning, and the dark grave into the gate of heaven. All else is darkness without light, guilt without hope, fear, remorse, terror, ruin and wretchedness. Why then are there, in the providence of God, such clear and abundant advantages in the practice of virtue, if it be not his design to allure men to the practice of it ? Why does he thus shut them up to virtue, to religion, as their only hope of his favor, if not to assure them that in this way they shall obtain it. (2.) The blessings of life, contemplated as the gifts of a divine Benefactor, tend by a strong influence, to reclaim men to the practice of virtue. It is philosophic truth, that "the goodness of God leadeth to repentance." Nor is there any kind of moral influence so powerfully adapted to this end as manifested kindness, which is sure to produce affection in re- turn. This influence reaches the last and lowest stages of human profligacy; for few are so obdurate as not to feel its thrilling efficacy. Nor can I conceive it possible, that an un- perverted mind should contemplate this sinful world, in its un- worthiness of the favors of its Maker, and also the ceaseless 256 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. and abundant communication of blessings to those who deserve only his displeasure ; the solicitude with which he watches, the care with which he protects, the compassion with which he relieves, the kindness with which he blesses, and not feel a mighty and an almost irresistible attraction to do the will of such a Benefactor. How is it possible that intelligent beings, qualified as we are, to read the clear intimations of our Maker's will in our constitution and circumstances as moral beings, and made as we are, the constant objects of his more than paternal care and kindness, can doubt or disregard his design to recover us to obedience and to the enjoyment of his favor? What child, in similar circumstances, could question the design of paternal love ? (3.) The natural evils of life justly and soberly estimated be- speak the same design. We no sooner inquire into the end which these evils are fitted to accomplish in respect to man, than we see that it is to restrain men from vice and restore them to virtue. The most striking fact in regard to these evils is, that to a vast extent they result from the wrong state of the heart and conduct of the life. It is suffering in connection with sin, telling us a truth we cannot fail to know, that if we would prevent the effect, we must remove the cause ; and far more distinctly and more impressively, that as God loves our happi- ness he loves also our virtue, and that he will secure the one only by means of the other. So plainly, so forcibly is this great truth taught in the providence of God, that every man knows and feels it in much the same manner as that, if he would avoid the sensation of being burned he must keep himself from the fire. By these evils too the insufficiency and vanity of earthly joys are made obvious in a manner the most impressive to the wayward mind of man. Let him take his lesson from these evils, let him take it from the sufferings, the agonies, the last breath of a dying man, and who would not realize what the world is? In the evils of life we are furnished with abundant opportunities for the exercise of all, and especially of the more difficult and nobler virtues. Even in those evils to which we are subject through what we call inadvertence or rashness, rather than by the execution of any criminal purpose, we find a powerful check to imprudence and temerity, and an impres- sive lesson of discretion and care, which may be indispensable to our moral well-being. Who can estimate the benefits of EYILS OF LIFE BENEFICENT. 257 watchfulness to moral beings? The necessity of continued oc- cupation and labor for our comfortable subsistence is also indi- rectly, and yet in the most important respects subservient to our moral interests. Its single influence to remove us from the temptations of sloth, and to deprive us of leisure to contrive and perpetrate iniquity, is sufficient to show its salutary effects on the conduct of men — to show us that what we are so apt to esteem one of the most intolerable calamities, is one of the greatest of heaven's blessings. It can scarcely be pretended, that the moral and of course all the real interests of a world in which calamities, disease, pain and death possess so benign a tendency and yet produce so little good effect, would be im- proved by any diminution of these evils ; nor can it well be doubted that they evince the design of their author to re- strain man from the perversion of his moral nature, and to re- store him to virtue and happiness. What would this world be without these ? "Were there no disappointments, no sufferings, no death, how ferocious, how desperate were human selfishness. It would be a pandemonium rather than a paradise, over whose crimes and woes even God's mercy would despair. In a word then, in all the evils of human life we discern only the disci- pline and the chastisements of a father's hand, and see only "the graver countenance of his love," intending our profit by making us partakers of his holiness and his favor. The present state of man is obviously one of trial and disci- pline, and as such is fitted and designed to form his character to permanent virtue. On this most important topic I have not time to dwell. The illustration of it by Bishop Butler in his Analogy, (P. I., Chaps. 4 and 5,) to those who will read his remarks, supersedes the necessity of any attempt on my part to exhibit the subject. Not merely the theological student and the Christian, but every man who would understand the true nature and design of his existence in this world, should read and read often, these chapters of Butler. The general doctrine which he establishes is, that the present world is a state of moral discipline adapted and designed to improve and ultimately to confirm man in virtue and hap- piness in a future world. This adaptation he has traced in a variety of particulars with such clearness of illustration and force of argument, that the reality of it cannot be doubted by any candid mind. He has not indeed applied this great fact to 17 258 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. this particular purpose, but the fact being admitted, who can doubt its application ? If it be obvious and undeniable, that the constitution of man and the entire course of God's providential dispensations toward him are fitted to reclaim him from sin and to improve and confirm him in virtue and happiness, I ask whence such adaptation, if God does not design to accomplish this end. It is to no purpose to say that in respect to the greater part of men this design is not accomplished. The light of nature leaves the future particular results of the present state in many respects unknown and indeterminate. Proba- tion, and with it this course of moral discipline, may also be con- tinued under even more favorable auspices, till the end shall be accomplished in manner and degree worthy of the attri- butes of its Author. Admit however the fact to be as sup- posed, it must be traced to the voluntary perversion of the design of God on the part of men, and the perversion of a design is decisive of its reality. (5.) The happiness of mankind, to a great extent — I may even say their perfect happiness — is placed in their own power. Immeasurably the greatest portion of the miseries of human life are the result of sin and moral imperfection. Suppose that all men were perfectly conformed to the rule of benevolent action, how would this dismal world, as we are often prone to esteem it, and darkened and afflicted as it is by sin and its woes, be cheered and brightened ! Let all unkindness between man and man cease ; let envy and malice, fraud, cruelty, contention, covetousness, pride, ambition and sensuality come to an end ; let these be followed by perfect benevolence, under all its forms of meekness, humility, contentment, self-denial, upright- ness, confidence, sympathy, a universal courteousness and cor- diality ; let benevolence go forth in an uninterrupted train of deeds of beneficence, and liberality pour abroad its gifts, and let gratitude and love reign pure and unruffled in every heart, and these be attended with submission, trust and joy, with the other delightful emotions of piety, and how trivial would be every possible evil — how would this world of sorrow cease to groan, and be transformed into a primeval Eden ! How would all nature smile in beauty and pour forth its bounties to bless, and the sunshine of every heart welcome a present God, and tell us of a paradise regained ! Does such a fact, in respect to this world of his creatures, bespeak no design of their Maker ? PERFECTION INSURES BLESSEDNESS. 259 Can an individual doubt, in respect to the part which God de- sires that he should act ? Can such a weight of motive as arises from this amount of good to each and to all, from the obvious practicability of its attainment as placed in their power, be furnished without being designed to move such beings to act accordingly % The question admits of but one answer, and this too plain to be stated. The whole world feels this influence. "With it there is a sense of duty and of obligation, which presses hard and almost irresistibly on the human conscience, to em- bark in this enterprise of blessing the world ; and there is a sense of guilt and self-condemnation which fastens on the soul, and compels those who live only to defeat this design of their Maker, to carry a wounded spirit with them through all their pilgrimage. Who can reflect on these things as the result of God's providential dispensations, without regarding them as the ceaseless efforts of his grace to recover man to virtue and to happiness? There is another fact, which has too important a relation to this part of the argument to be left unnoticed; one which gives a peculiar grandeur and glory to a moral agent — that such is the nature of a moral being, that perfection in character is per- fection in blessedness. Moral agency involves, in its very nature, the power so to occupy the mind and bless the moral being with the right object of affection, that any loss of good, and any pain or suffering which are possible in the case, shall be accounted almost as nothing. (I might say, and maintain the position, that it would be in the power of a moral being, if morally perfect, to avoid all suffering, even from omnipotence — at least from every created cause. I have no doubt of this fact, as one given in the true philosophy of the mind.) But I present the position with the slight qualification, almost entirely to avoid suffering. This may be illustrated in many forms, and in the commonest things. How frequently then, when thought and sensibility are wholly given to some object of absorbing interest, do we receive bodily injury without feeling or knowing the fact ? Every thing is relative, not only in thought but in feel ing. How unworthy in a Croesus to grieve for the loss of a farthing ! Archimedes was so absorbed in the solution of his problem, that he lost his life in the sacking of the city, without being aware of his danger. Soldiers, wounded and bleeding in battle, have 260 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. fought on, insensible of their wounds, till they were falling in death. Paul, in his own language, "suffered the loss of all things, and counted them but dung, that he might win Christ ;" and considered himself " as having nothing, and yet possessing all things." Martyrs, on the rack and in the fire, have triumphed, with hymns of praise on their lips and heaven in their hearts. The nature of mind explains all this. "When then the object that engrosses the mind of a moral being is God — as he is, his designs, the end, the results at which he aims and which he will accomplish — when the heart, the whole soul of a moral being, is fixed as it may be on such an object, and so becomes "filled with all the fullness of God," why should it be thought strange that the tortures of the rack and the fire should leave the perfect blessedness of the mind unimpaired ? Such is undeniably the nature of a moral being. By perfection in character he secures perfection in happiness, and becomes incapable of misery ! Evil, suffer- ing is possible to man only through his moral imperfection. I am not saying that perfect holiness will ever exist in this world ; experience and observation forbid us to expect it. But I have called your attention to the fact now stated, that I might ask, what is the design of God, in giving existence to moral beings ? Has he not placed their happiness in their power — happiness without alloy, absolute and perfect? And what is, what can be his design, but to induce man to attain it ; what but to persuade him to do the will and enjoy the friendship of his Creator ? (6.) I only add in support of this conclusion,that if there is no forgiveness with God, and if the proof is decisive that there is none, then all this course of effort to reclaim to obedience must of necessity be vain and worse than in vain. Under the conviction that there is no forgiveness with God, the world would become desperate in rebellion. That God then by the entire course of providence should thus aim to restore man to virtue, and yet authorize and even render unavoidable a con- viction which must render all his efforts to reclaim abortive, is incredible. The providential dispensations of God then author- ize and require the conclusion that there is forgiveness for the guilty. Indeed in view of what has been said, I ask is there in the entire providence of God any thing in the least degree in- consistent with this great design of his grace — is there any RECAPITULATION. 261 want of adaptation in the means adopted for its accomplish- ment; can any course of providential dispensation be conceived more decisively expressive of a design to restore a lost world to duty and to happiness. I now recur to what I claim to have proved, that God is ad- ministering his moral government on the principles of exact equity. In view of this fact we are brought to the unavoidable conclusion, that he will in a future world unfold these principles either in exact retribution or through an atonement. The former is indeed far more probable, than that he has abandoned the principles of eternal justice in his moral government. At the same time that man's present state is simply that of respite from deserved punishment under a merely legal dispensation, must be regarded as highly, even altogether incredible, when compared with the supposition of a gracious economy. In view then of the equity of God's administration, and all those influences to restore man to virtue, and those intimations of forgiveness so conspicuous in this course of his providence, the only conclusion is that God is administering his moral govern- ment through an atonement, or under a gracious economy. One remark in conclusion. You see that if you ever become the objects of God's favor, you must do so on the same ground and on the same conditions which Christianity reveals and pre- scribes. Without an atonement for your sins, like that which Christianity reveals, there is no hope that you can be forgiven; without repentance for sin, the renunciation of it by doing the will of God, and a cheerful unqualified trust in his pardoning mercy, there is no true happiness for you here or hereafter. Come then and act up to the dictates of right reason. If you have not proof that Christianity is from God, you have proof that with God there is forgiveness for the penitent sinner, and for none but him. There is, there can be no religion for you but one whose basis is an atonement for sin — a religion which involves a penitent and a contrite heart which hopes for mercy from God as the righteous avenger of sin. Act up then to the dictates of your sober judgment — conform the dictates of con- science to the will of the Being who made you, who in all his providence either smiles to invite you to his friendship, or frowns only to deter you from the guilt and the ruin of sin. Embrace that religion by which the infinite God, your Maker, your Redeemer would bless, and without which he will curse 262 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. you forever — that religion which is the perfection of your na- ture, the end of your existence. If truth is better than false- hood, if happiness is more desirable than misery, if God as your friend is better than God as your enemy, if to meet him as your Saviour is better than to meet him as the avenger of sin, if to go to his judgment-seat fearless and triumphant is better than to go there in despairing terror, if heaven is better than hell, choose this hour with a penitent, humble and steadfast heart, the service of a redeeming God. LECTURE VI. Second leading proposition continued, viz.— God administers an equitable moral government; also, God administers a moral government under a gracious economy. — Proof 3. We must * suppose God to administer his government in the way of exact retribution, or through an atonement. — One of these is true, or God is deficient in power, or malignant in intention. — Just conception of Benevolence in God. — What is Justice in God. — Infidels have false views of both. — Dispensations of God's Providence prove him not to be weak. — The equity of a mural government can be consistent with mercy only through an atonement. — Alternative for the unbeliever. In the preceding lecture, I entered on the proof of the prop- osition, that God is administering an equitable moral govern- ment over men under an atonement. I now resume the same subject, and, w T ith some recapitulation of principles and arguments adduced in former lectures, shall attempt to prove the same thing, by showing — In the third place, that the only admissible suppositions are, that God is administering his moral government over men either in the w r ay of exact retribution, or through an atone- ment ; and that as the former supposition is wholly inadmis- sible, it follows that he is administering it under an atonement, I propose to show — First, That God is administering his moral government over men either in the w r ay of exact retribution or under an atone- ment ; and Secondly, That he is administering it not in the former, but in the latter mode, or under an atonement. First. God is administering his moral government over men either in the one or the other of these modes of administration. If he is not, it must be that it is either through want of power, or through an unkind or malignant intention toward individual subjects, or through that excessive lenity which sacrifices the general good to individual happiness. It is not through want of power. On this point no argument, in view of the omnipotence of God, can be necessary. It is not through malignant intention • i. «?., not w 7 ith the de- sign of inflicting punishment hereafter with undue severitv, or of 264 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. treating his subjects worse than they deserve. This supposition would be wholly gratuitous, since there is not a pretense that in the whole course of his providence there is the least viola- tion of individual rights. J^or would it be merely gratuitous, but against strong evidence to the contrary. Every thing that can bear on the question, in the divine administration, is decis- ive of benevolence to man; all that can be alleged with the least plausibility, against the exact equity of his government, being the fact that he treats his subjects better than they deserve — a fact surely very remote from authorizing even a # conjecture that he will treat them hereafter more severely. Besides, malignity itself, though the manifestation of it might subvert rightful authority, cannot violate the principles of equity, in treating the rebellious subjects of God (and such are all men) worse than they deserve, for they all deserve evil. God then cannot be supposed to depart from the principles of exact equity in his moral administration, through malignant intention toward individual subjects. Again; nor can he be supposed to do this through excessive lenity. This, in the form in which it is often presented, is the most plausible of the suppositions which are now to be ex- ploded, and derives its plausibility wholly from the name given it. It is called benevolence, and thus held up to our admira- tion as the sum and perfection of moral excellence and beauty. And what is more calamitous to the cause of truth, the defend- ers of the equity of God's government have often conceded, that benevolence is the proper name of the thing intended ; denying that the divine moral perfection is comprised in this attribute, even when an apostle has said that " God is love," and maintaining, that justice in God, instead of being only a modification or specific form of benevolence, is another and distinct attribute, dictating and demanding what benevolence forbids.* Let us then form some definite conceptions on this most momentous of all questions — what is benevolence in God f At least let us distinguish it from what it is not, and from what often bears its desecrated name.-f What then is benevolence in God? * Dr. Chalmers' Bridgewater Treatise. f I am not here deciding that God is benevolent, but only reasoning ex concessis; i. e., on the assumption of the infidel, that God is benevolent. THE STRONGHOLD OF INFIDELITY. 265 Is any thing wliicli does not disapprove and abhor sin as the supreme evil, and which will not show even the highest disap- probation of it ? In opposition to this, we are told that such is not the benevolence of God, and that instead of viewing him in the character of a just and righteous Sovereign, we are to regard him in no other relation than that of a benignant, ten- der parent, who so delights in the happiness of his family, that to promote it he will sacrifice all that can be called law, jus- tice and equity. We here come to the stronghold of Infidelity. Let us then ascertain the precise question to be decided. It is not whether God, as a benevolent Being, delights in the happiness of his moral creation, and desires to promote it in the only way in which it can be secured. But can he accomplish that end without the influence of an equitable moral government; in other words, can God be benevolent without being just f What then is benevolence in God f And what is justice in God f Benevolence in God is a disposition to secure the high- est happiness, and to prevent all misery. Of course it must disapprove, hate, and abhor that which necessarily destroys the highest happiness and tends to produce all misery. But such is the nature and tendency of sin. What then is justice in God? It is simply one specific form or modification of benevolence; i. c, in respect to sin, it is benevolence, and no- thing but benevolence, disapproving, abhorring, and determin- ing to punish sin in the subjects of his government, as that which undermines his authority, and tends to destroy the high- est, happiness, and to produce all evil. God then, as a benevo- lent being, must feel the highest disapprobation and abhorrence of sin. In proportion as he loves happiness and hates misery, he must abhor sin, as that which destroys the one and produces the other. To suppose a benevolent God then, who is not also a just God, is to suppose a benevolent God who is not benevo- lent. Nor is this all. God as the governor of moral beings must show by his acts that he thus disapproves of and hates sin. He must come before his kingdom with the demonstration of his benevolence in the form of justice, either by a retribution or some equivalent manifestation of his supreme abhorrence of this evil. Words without actions in such a case are no proof in a question of character. In a moral kingdom all results in hap- Vol. I.-12. MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. piness and misery depend on the moral conduct of its subjects, and that depends on the influences nnder which they act. Of all these there is one which is absolutely essential ; viz., that of the moral governor's supreme approbation of right and supreme dis- approbation of every wrong moral action on their part. This is the only influence by which as a moral governor, he can move them. Motives as consisting simply in natural good and evil, whether furnished by the perceived nature and tendencies of action, or through the medium of promised good and threat- ened evil, are not the influence of moral government. This in- fluence arises only from the perfect character of the governor, as manifested in his supreme approbation of right and supreme disapprobation of wrong moral action. If he has these feelings then he will manifest them by his acts. To suppose otherwise, is to suppose him not to use the most perfect means for the most perfect end ; to give no evidence of his real character and of his right to govern — no proof that he is not the friend and patron of iniquity, none that he is entitled to the confidence or submission of his subjects. Nay more, it is to suppose him to give decisive proof to the contrary ; for in such a case, if he had the feelings of supreme approbation of right and supreme disapprobation of wrong action he would manifest them. The good of his kingdom demands it. Benevolence dictates and imperiously requires it, as the necessary means of the best end. If then he does not manifest these feelings, the proof is deci- sive against their existence, and of course that he is not worthy of the confidence and submission of his subjects, and not enti- tled to the throne. Were the whole moral universe a heaven of joy and rap- ture, what security for its continuance even for an hour ? And why under the government of a selfish deity, will not all good and all hope terminate at any moment in the agonies and woes of sin ? "What sort of obedience to God would that be, secured by such influences, when there is no ground of con- fidence, respect or love furnished in his character ? And what such ground could there be in the character of a God whose so- called benevolence dispenses with all justice and all equity, which does not supremely abhor, but actually patronizes and befriends, protects and rewards iniquity ? Than that sort of benevolence, there is nothing worse in point of principle in Satan himself. Adorn it with what tender names you will, THE PROVIDENCE OF GOD. 267 of parental love and kindness, yon wonld actually despise it in an earthly parent or a civil magistrate, and it ought to be and would be despised in God himself by all his intelligent creation. It sinks all that is venerable and awful in heaven's sovereign as a God of benevolence, guarding the general good of his kingdom at the sacrifice of individual good, not into that which is lovely,but into that which is contemptible. Such is the God whom Infidelity worships, cheating itself with names and words, while in the incense it offers to a fancied deity, it despises the object of its own adoration. Nay, rather it for- gets that the real object of its homage is and must be in prin- ciple, a being of absolute selfishness or infinite malignity. I only ask, is it possible, is it conceivable, that a benevolent is not also a just God ? Can there be a benevolent God who does not supremely abhor and who will not show that he abhors the worst thing in the universe ? Can a perfectly benevolent God be supposed to depart from the principles of eternal righteousness? Will he despoil his high and inviolable sanctuary of all its sacredness — his dominion of all its majesty? Will he yield to that excessive lenity or indulgent tenderness which will darken all his glories — will he by this most fearful act of infinite malignity fill his moral creation with terror and dismay ? Let us now briefly appeal to the providence of God. Here let it be remembered, that God must be supposed either to be strictly just as a moral governor, or to be so concerned for the happiness of individual subjects, that he consents for their sake to sacrifice the -equity of his moral government, and with it the highest happiness of his moral kingdom. Do then the dispen- sations of his providence authorize us to ascribe to him, even in conjecture, the latter character? Why — if he relincpiishes the character of a righteous moral governor for that of an in- dulgent parent — does he give such clear and decisive indica- tions of his supreme approbation of virtue and disapprobation of vice? Why does he render it the most manifest of all truths, that there is no way in which man can secure his own perfect happiness, or be safe against perfect misery, except by the prac- tice of virtue ? Why has he created beings whose very nature and condition on the least reflection, bring before the mind the everlasting distinction between right and wrong moral action, and constrain them to feel that by the latter they are defeating 268 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. the high end of their own creation, and doing the most palpa- ble violence to the will of an infinite Creator ? Why if reluct- ant to make man ultimately as miserable as strict equity de- mands — why if thus indifferent to the rights of the public, is there no instance of individual, or at least of public injustice? Why, if God is all tenderness, does he so distinctly express his displeasure toward iniquity in the various ways of his provi- dence, and actually produce such fearful forebodings of a com- ing retribution,that the heart of every man trembles while going on in iniquity — that every man is afraid of death because he is to meet God? Why is it that no error, artifice or system of opinions has ever been devised, adequate to quell the dread and the disturbance which the wicked feel when they think of the Sovereign of heaven ? Why is it that Universalism, Infidelity, Atheism have so often cried for his mercy when summoned by death into his presence ? Advert to another class of evils ; I mean those which God brings on men, not as the natural consequence of crime, but in the exercise of his high and irresponsible sovereignty, such as those which result from disease and pestilence. Is there not a cause? Who can suppose that they are brought on moral beings without reference to their character ? Who that knows that he is a sinner, a rebel against God, can feel these evils in his own person without the reflection, if not that he deserves them, at least that God is not too good to inflict the extremest evils on his creatures ? What is their design but to tell us of a degree of displeasure, which confines not its expressions in evil to the direct natural results of wrong doing, and that he has still other and more fearful treasures of wrath for the workers of iniquity? What if all the sufferings and death which have been endured on the face of this earth since its creation, could be arrayed before the eye in present and distinct vision ? What if all the sorrows and pains, and sighs and tears, and all the dis- tress by sickness, pestilence, famine, earthquakes, shipwrecks, wars, the rack, the gibbet, and the fire — what if all the weep- ing w r idows and orphans, all the lamentation and mourning of parents and children, of husbands, wives, brothers, sisters — what if all the massacres, the shrieks, agonies and groans of the dying — the seas of human blood and the mountains of human corpses — what if these scenes of woe and horror which have been witnessed on earth could be brought before us, and THE ALTERNATIVE. 269 all be acted and felt over again as a present reality under our direct inspection. How should we be overwhelmed, and what should we think of that God who made and governs such a world as this? With such a spectacle of terror before us, should we reflect on nothing but his tenderness, and with our consciousness of guilt expect nothing but favors from his hands? What does the history of this world disclose, if not visible marks and traces of the vengeance of God upon it, in every age and every hour? And do these bespeak mere in- dulgence? Surely whatever other weakness or inconsistency may be ascribed to God, nothing is more inconsistent with the whole course of his providential dealings with men, than the weakness or inconsistency of excessive lenity. On whatever other basis man may rest his hopes of God's favor, that of mere tenderness, it w^ould seem, must be the last. The entire history of his providence furnishes not an instance of kindness at the expense of justice, but discloses to all who read the record, a severity of dispensation which proclaims that a sovereign law- giver and a righteous judge is on the throne of the universe. We do, we must see a God frowning at sin. And if amid these frowns we also witness the smiles of mercy, still they are too dark and awful to authorize the hope of his favor through the mere relentings of tenderness. We are then brought to the conclusion, that God is administer- ing an equitable moral government over men, either according to the principles of exact retribution or through an atonement. In other words, God will show his supreme disapprobation of sin, either by inflicting unmingled and endless misery on a world of transgressors, or by some other expedient which shall equally manifest such disapprobation. Solemn and tremendous as is this alternative, it is and must be real ; and from it there is no escape, according to any prin- ciples of correct reasoning. The benevolence of God, if we assume it as the infidel does — his providence, in all its facts and principles — every consideration that bears on the subject, conducts to our conclusion; while no fact, no principle, fur- nishes the least opposing evidence. Deny our conclusion, and you deny the perfect justice of God ; deny his justice, and you must deny his benevolence. Admit then, that he is a God of absolute selfishness, of infinite malignity, or admit his benevo- lence, and with it his supreme abhorrence of sin, and the mani- 270 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. festation of that abhorrence, either in an exact retribution here- after or through an atonement. This brings us to the question, in which of these only possible or conceivable modes, is God administering his moral govern- ment over this sinful world f This leads me to say, Secondly, That he is administering it, not in the former mode, but under an atonement. This position is fully sustained by two facts and a principle. The facts are these: the first, that God is administering an equitable moral government over men; the second, that the en- tire course of his providence bespeaks his design to restore man to duty and to favor. The principle is, that the perfect equity or justice of a moral governor, can be reconciled with mercy to transgressors only through an atonement. In respect to the first of these facts, we have seen that God administers a moral government over men; that he does it through the medium of the best law; and that this fact, un- counteracted by any opposing evidence, is decisive proof of the perfect equity of his administration ; that instead of furnishing any opposing evidence, the entire course of his providence shows him, as it were, most scrupulously avoiding every shadow of injustice — discloses the true tendency of obedience to his will, to bless, and of disobedience, to ruin the soul of man forever, and exhibits him in that severity of dispensation which com- ports only with the majesty of a sovereign lawgiver and right- eous judge. We have seen that he has destined the subjects of his government to a future state of being, thus furnishing an opportunity for the perfect display of the equity of his administration ; while the manner in which he removes them to that world tells of such a result, in the most fearful forebod- ings of every departing spirit ; and that whether we assume and reason from his benevolence or from the facts of his provi- dence, no other supposition can for a moment be admitted, than that of the perfect equity of his government. Shut up then to this conclusion on the one hand, we see at the same time on the other, the most satisfactory indications of his benignant design to restore man to duty and favor. The same course of providential dispensations, along with the lessons it gives of the equity of his administration, shows not less clearly the les- sons of his mercy to the penitent transgressor. Every thing, as we have seen, entirely harmonizes with such an economy, and AN ATONEMENT NECESSARY. 271 is fitted and adapted to the end of bringing man back to his duty and the friendship of his Maker ; every motive which can reach and move a rational, voluntary being, whether de- rived from his present or future well-being ; every thing in the form of manifested kindness and good-will on the part of a divine Benefactor; every thing in the form of paternal chas- tisement, in the nature and condition of man, adapted and designed to form his character to permanent virtue ; his happi- ness placed so completely in his own power as a moral being — every thing to invite to obedience, and to awe from transgres- sion, which is conceivable in such a system; while all these adaptations, influences, efforts to reclaim, must be worse than in vain — must evince even malignity of intention on the part of the Creator, if he has no design to forgive and to save. With these things in view, let us now advert to the principle, viz., that the perfect justice of God, as a moral governor, can he reconciled with mercy to transgressors only through an atone- ment. This is the impossibility, already sufficiently illustrated, that God should be either benevolent or just, without manifest- ing his supreme abhorrence of sin. I need not say, that it were easy for infinite wisdom to devise, and infinite power to exe- cute, a plan by which such a manifestation shall be made, in the pardon of transgressors. Here then let us judge, whether God has not adopted some plan by which the principles of eternal justice are consistent with favor to a revolted world. What else can be true, or even supposed possible, but that he is administering a perfectly equitable system of moral govern- ment over men under an economy of grace ? I say not here what will be the actual results of this economy in a future world. All that the light of nature can give on this point is at most, the general conclusion, that these results will be such as will accord with that benignity of design so conspicuous in his providential dealings. The great fact itself however, appears, to my own mind, to be shown by all the evidence of which the nature of the case admits. If it be pos- sible to manifest to rational beings the adoption of such a sys- tem without a revelation, i. <3., by merely providential dispen- sations, I see not why the evidence actually furnished of A just God and a Saviotjk, does not demand the most unhesitating belief. To conclude. If these things are so, we see on what ground 272 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. Infidelity must stand. The infidel must believe either in a malignant Deity, or in a future exact retribution of this sinful world, or in the great cardinal fact of Christianity, viz., that there is an atonement for sin. Let us look at this. If the infi- del denies a full, just and exact retribution of this sinful world, and also an atonement for sin, then he is shut up to the admis- sion of a selfish, malignant Deity. He may call him benevolent; but it is a name without the reality. Such a God is not be- nevolent, for he is not just. He is unjust. He is regardless, reckless of the greatest happiness of his moral creation — unjust to his kingdom — malignant. Again ; if now the infidel still denies an atonement for sin, and admits the benevolence of God, then he is shut up to the admission of a full and exact retribution of this sinful world in utter and endless misery. On his own premises there is no escape. If any thing is true in moral reasoning, it is this : that a benevolent God, as a moral governor, and thus the guardian of his kingdom, must feel and must express an abhorrence of the supreme evil of sin, and must make that expression either by a full and exact retribution or in some other way; i. e., through an atonement. The infidel denies an atonement. The consequence is inevitable. Every subject of God's moral gov- ernment is a transgressor, and doomed, without hope, to utter and endless misery. Does he say, this is in itself incredible, impossible ? I reply, it is neither. The destruction of such a world as this for its rebellion against God, may be less, in com- parison with his universal kingdom, than the penalties which every benevolent parent inflicts on his children compared with the end of their infliction ; it may be, as I have said, an infini- tesimal compared with unlimited vastness. The infidel then, on his present premises, is compelled to admit, that every human being is doomed to everlasting destruction. And if he will adopt such premises, let him abide the conclusion. He professes to reason. Let him see that he adopts premises that throw the midnight of despair over a guilty world ; premises, which give only " a certain fearful looking-for of judgment and fiery indignation." Again; if the infidel denies that such a retribution awaits this sinful world, and still maintains that God is benevolent, then, as a rational man, he must admit an atonement, even that of Christianity. If God is benevolent, he is also just ; and THE ATONEMENT OF CHRISTIANITY. 273 if liis justice is not manifested and vindicated by a future just retribution, then it must be by an atonement. But will any rational man admit an atonement and reject that which Chris- tianity reveals ? Let him ask, how — by what other means or expedient — can a sin-avenging God become merciful to trans- gressors of his law ? How can he make a manifestation of his abhorrence of sin equal to that of turning a rebellious world into hell ? How can the throne of eternal justice be upheld in all its strength and glory, and the defied penalties of sin be averted from the guilty ? Here, all is mystery and utter dark- ness. Before this problem, the intellect of man retires baffled, and confounded. ~No answer can be given; no conception can be formed. Christianity — Christianity alone, gives the solution. Christianity alone reveals a triune God, and shows us his throne upheld by the man that is also the eternal Logos, and a guilty world redeemed. Christianity thus solves the problem which God alone can solve. Christianity, on this most momentous of all subjects, and with this sufficient proof of its divine ori- gin, removes all rational doubt, satisfies all rational inquiry, and gives all rational assurance. If there is an atonement for sin, then we safely affirm, it is and must be that which Chris- tianity describes. It is the only adequate atonement conceiva- ble by the human mind. It is this alone which can still the agitations of conscious guilt, and bring relief to the laboring heart of sinful man. In its very nature and perfection, it bears the impress of God as its author. And can man, reasoning from his necessities as a sinner against a just and holy God, and admitting the fact of an atonement for sin, deny the atone- ment of Christianity ? No man has done — no man ever will do it. The only alternative here is, either no atonement, or the great atonement of the son of God. You see then what ground the infidel — every man that rea- sons from any possible premises in the case, must take. He must either deny the benevolence of God, — i. ) It is the best possible. — No proof that a better could be adopted. — The present, in its nature and tendencies, is the best conceivable, and therefore the best possible. — This argued under two heads; 1. From its general form as a moral system, in respect to the kind of beings and the kind of influence used. — 2. From its particular forms as a moral system, as involving influ- ences from the nature and tendencies of moral action, from moral government, from an equita- ble moral government, and the same with a gracious economy. — Remark. Ln t the two preceding lectures, I have attempted to show that there is no proof against the benevolence of God, by showing that the present system, with its results, may be not only better than none, but may be the best possible to the Creator. I now proceed, To offer direct proofs of his benevolence. Before I adduce the proposed proof, I will give an illustra- tion of the argument on which I rely. A system under which evil exists, may be shown by decisive evidence to be the best possible system. It is obvious however, that this must be shown in a somewhat different manner from what it would be were there no evil connected with the system. To illustrate then by an example : a physician may perform the best pos- sible operation of which the case admits, in amputating the limb of a patient, notwithstanding the pain which is insepa- rable from it. If all that can be shown in the case is, that the evils connected with the operation may be either inseparable from the necessary means of the greatest good, or may be them- selves the necessary means of the greatest good, then, although the operation would .not prove the physician to be benevolent, it would oblige us to admit that he may be benevolent, not- withstanding these evils. The question, when judged of merely by the facts now supposed, ought to remain undecided; or rather, cannot be decided in the negative. To this point, our preceding discussion respecting the question of the divine be- nevolence, so far as it depends on the existence of evil, has conducted us. INTRODUCTORY SUPPOSITIONS. 327 Let it now be supposed, that to amputate the diseased limb is better than to do nothing, and that there is no evidence that the physician has not done the best thing in his power, and there is good reason to believe the benevolence of the physi- cian in the act, This may be said to be the lowest ground on which we are authorized to believe that he is benevolent. It is however, sufficient for this belief. We will now suppose a stronger case — that the amputation of the limb is known to be the necessary means of the greatest good, and that all the evils connected with it either may le inseparable from it, so far as the power of the physician to prevent them is concerned, or may he themselves the necessary means of the greatest good. In such a case we have better grounds for awarding to the physician a benevolent design in the operation. We will now suppose a case still stronger. Suppose not only that the amputation of the limb is known to be the necessary means of the greatest good, and that all the evils connected with it, except those which are the necessary means of the greatest good, are inseparable from the operation beyond the power of the physician to prevent them ; that they result solely from the voluntary intemperance of the patient himself, and this when the physician does every thing in his power to prevent them, and the only legitimate conclusion is, that he is as benevolent as had this class of evils not existed. If we still further suppose, in respect to the other class of evils, viz., those which are the necessary means of the greatest good, that they become thus necessary only by the perverseness of the patient himself in his intemperance, then the conclusion is, that the physician is as benevolent as had these evils not existed, while these evils become themselves proof of his be- nevolence. On these suppositions, it is obvious that the benevolence of the physician is as fully proved by the supposed operation, as the using of the best means of the best end can prove him to be, or as had results in good, without the slightest degree of evil, followed in the case, If now we suppose once more, that he combines with this operation every other expression of real kindness, then more indisputable and decisive proofs of benev- olence could not be furnished. By all these forms of proof, it is now claimed that the benevolence of God is evinced to the 328 MORAL GOVERNMENT PROM NATURE. human mind by that system of things, with its results, which he has adopted. The argument as a whole, may be thus stated in a hypo- thetical form, with the conclusion : If there is no proof, so far as results are concerned, that God could have adopted a better system than he has adopted — if this system, in view of its results, is better than none — if this system be the best possible to God, and so the necessary means of the greatest good possible to him to secure — if all the evil connected with the system is either inseparable from the best system, in respect to divine prevention, or is the necessary means of the greatest good possible to God ; and if God, in addition to all this, actually shows kindness to his creatures, in every other conceivable form which is consistent with the great- est good possible to him — then it will follow, that God is benevolent — even as benevolent as had the best pos- sible, or best conceivable results, been actually secured. Having attempted to show that the present system may ~bc not only better than none, but the best possible, I now proceed to show as I proposed : 2. That it is not only better than none, but is the best pos- sible to the Creator. (1.) The present system is better than none. This I propose to show : First. From the comparative amount of happiness and misery in the present world. Secondly. From the results of the present system in a future world. I appeal — First ; to the comparative amount of happiness and misery in the present world. We claim then, that the amount of happiness so far tran- scends the amount of misery, as to put an end to all doubt on the question, whether the present system with its results is not far better than none. To contemplate the actual experience of men, and to institute such inquiries as the following, must de- cide this question. Where is the individual to be found who does not at every moment of life enjoy so much in present pos- session, or in hope of future good, as to render his existence de- sirable? How few— how very few are the instances of calamity and suffering with which manifold and rich blessings are not AMOUNT OF HAPPINESS. 329 combined — how few individuals within our own knowledge, who are not enjoying every useful and necessary gift of divine bounty, and prepared and qualified to enjoy any additional happiness that might be furnished ! Who is not ready to wel- come the knowledge or information that gratifies curiosity — to be entertained with the humor of the wit, or the ingenuity of the artist? What an amount of all that can be called hu- man misery, is chiefly imaginary; and how may that which is real be diminished by contentment, by submission, or by resort- ing to available sources of happiness. Even when war, famine and pestilence pour in their floods of suffering and distress, how large a portion of the wide earth, untouched by their desola- tions, exhibits scenes of joy and gladness, while the sufferers themselves cling to life through the remembrance of joys that are past, or the hope of those that may come ! In short, when we look over the world and see all its millions with exceptions which scarcely are to be thought of, retiring to rest every night, with the quiet and assured anticipation of the supply of the essential wants of to-morrow, and reflect that this is founded only on the uniform experience of the past, how can we fail to pronounce this a happy world — one at least in which existence is far better than non-existence ? If we turn our thoughts to the innumerable sources of enjoyment in the animal, rational and moral departments of creation — if we contemplate the in- visible existence that peoples every leaf, the sportive mazes of the insect tribes that abound in the atmosphere and the waters — the notes of joy which are heard from every grove, the de- lighted activity of the larger animals, the wonderful provision made for their supply of food, the obvious and nice adapta- tions in their nature and condition for their comfortable or joyous existence; if we consider man's capacity for enjoyment from the wide creation around him, through the organs of sense, and the amount of good which would in this way be fur- nished, were the means of it never perverted ; if we think of the numerous channels of higher pleasures which are opened to man in his intellectual and social nature, and reflect how these are supplied by the everflowing streams of divine bounty in all the tender relations of life ; and then reflect on the anni- hilation of all these earthly joys in the utter darkness and deso- lation of non-existence, how can we either wish not to have been or to cease to be ? 330 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. If we contemplate men as moral beings, how are the vicious and guilty even exempted by divine compassion from the overwhelming agonies of remorse ! — how are the virtuous solaced and gladdened as with the peace of heaven! !Nor ought we to overlook the capacity of happiness involved in the very nature of moral beings ; what a condition of per- fection and of bliss it places within their power, and one not to be despaired of, but rather to be hoped for and ex- pected by the well-founded belief of the enrapturing truth, that God is, " and is the rewarder of them that diligently seek him." If now we take the most gloomy view of human existence, so far as it can bear on the present inquiry, we can at most find but here and there an individual bosom so desolate of all good, so oppressed with present griefs and gloomy forebodings, as to consent to plunge into the dark gulf of non-existence, w T hile myriads are exulting in life and its joys. How would these myriads, instead of counting their existence undesirable, prefer its endless duration as it is, rather than hazard a dimi- nution of their happiness by any essential and yet uncertain change in their condition? Supposing the prospect of im- provement to be fair and promising, very few with the uncer- tainty remaining whether the change would not be for the worse instead of for the better, would rationally in their own view incur its risk. This shows how we value life, being so well satisfied with its blessings, that to hazard the uncertain- ties of a change in our condition of existence, would be deemed the height of folly. It shows how readily, were the alternative a great diminution of happiness or non-existence, we should prefer the former, and how appalling would be the prospect of ceasing to be, compared with our present existence and the abundance of its joys. Every thing in human society, in the de- vices of man, the laws made to protect human life, the remedies used to heal diseases, the safeguards from accident and danger, the provision of food and raiment, in short, every preservative of life, shows that its loss is esteemed the greatest to which man in this world is liable. To preserve life is the great end to which human solicitude has ever been directed, and for which human ingenuity and skill have been exhausted. Nor can there be a doubt that it would still be so, were death known to be an eternal sleep — at least to such an extent, as to show how AMOUNT OF HAPPINESS. 331 • highly man values tlie existence wliicli his Creator gives him in the present world. Should it here be said, that I have now taken but a partial view of the results of the present system — that, although it be true that our earthly existence merely, is greatly to be preferred to non-existence, yet there is a future state, and a majority of men actually leave this world with that character, which in- sures their future unmingled and endless misery — I answer as before, that if we suppose a majority of men to die in sin, the light of nature does not decide that the present life is the whole of man's probation; and that therefore it may he true, that the design of God to recover men to virtue and to happiness, so conspicuously manifested here, will secure the perfect happi- ness of far the greater part of mankind hereafter. Indeed, this cannot, from the light of nature, be shown to be in the lowest degree improbable. Here then I might form a conclusive argument for the divine benevolence, thus : as there is no evi- dence that God is not doing all the good in his power, or that he could adopt a better system than the present ; and as the present system, in view of its results in the present world, is better than none, it follows that God is benevolent. But not to rest the argument on this ground merely, I re- mark secondly, that the present system, in view of its results in a future world, is better than none. Here it may be asked, with some degree of incredulity, what can we know, or ration- ally believe, under the mere light of nature, respecting the allot- ments of men in a future state ? I answer, we can know all that which legitimate evidence warrants us to believe ; and the decla- rations of God on this subject are not the only kind of evidence of which the case admits. His doings may as truly indicate his designs, and tell us what will be their results, as his decla- rations. Here then I appeal to what has already been shown respect- ing the present system. I shall however but briefly appeal to these facts, intending more particularly to consider them in a subsequent argument, to show that the present system is the best possible to the Creator. The same facts show that the present system is better than none, as they evince the designs of God toward men in a future state. The facts to which I refer are briefly these : the creation of the most perfect beings in kind ; the end of their creation, as 332 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. « indicated by their nature, which is the best conceivable ; the actual giving of the best law, or rule of action ; the adminis- tration of a moral government involving this perfect law, and a strict adherence to the principles of perfect equity, and not only this, but connected with it, an economy of grace; every thing in the condition and circumstances of man fitted to re- store him to virtue and haj)piness, and to secure him in this state of perfection; while no change is conceivable, which would add perfection to the system as the means of this high end. What then can we — ought we to believe, will be the results of such a system in a future world % Will this high design of a Being of infinite wisdom and power be wholly de- feated % Will our present state, so bright with the smiles of his mercy, be followed by one only dark and dreadful, under the frowns of his anger ? When God is so clearly aiming to restore man to holiness and happiness, is there nothing to hope for but universal sin and exact retribution ? True it is, that from the light of nature alone, we cannot in all respects give a definite answer to the present inquiry. But we are constrained to give one that is general, and altogether decisive on the point before us. The nature of the present system, so clearly and extensively benignant in its design, proves that this design will not be wholly abortive, but in some good degree accomplished. This system, begun by infinite wisdom and power, and carried onward through all the generations of men, clearly indicates results in a future state corresponding with its own benignity and grace. To hesitate or doubt on this point, especially in view of the infinite natural perfection of the Being whose de- sign it is, is to do violence to the laws of belief, as well as to disregard and distrust the only possible proofs of the divine placability. In view then of what we must suppose will be the actual results of the present system in a future world, we must also believe that the present system, viewed in relation to these results, is better — far better than none, and the best possible to the Creator. The way is now prepared to offer direct proofs of the benev- olence of God from his works. Argument I. The first argument is, that there is no proof, so far as results are concerned, that God could have adopted a better system than the present, and there is proof that the present THE TWO ARGUMENTS. 333 system is better than none. That there is no proof so far as re- sults are concerned, that GqcI could have adopted a better system than the present, I have already attempted to prove, by showing that it may be such a system notwithstanding the existence of natural and moral evil. If what has been said on this sub- ject be true, then their existence is to be wholly laid aside as entitled to no consideration in the argument. We have shown that all existing evils may be either the necessary means of the greatest good possible to the Creator, or in re- spect to divine prevention may be incidental to the best sys- tem possible to the Creator. Of course if there be other facts, which, were there no existing evil, would be sufficient to prove his benevolence, then as the existing evil furnishes no proof that he is not benevolent, or that the present system is not the best possible to the Creator, this evil must, in a fair argument, be laid out of consideration. The present system may be, not- withstanding the existence of the evil, the best possible to the Creator. Again; it has been shown that the present system is bet- ter than none. And if this is true, and there is no evidence that God could have adopted a better system than the present, then it follows that the present system is the best possible to the Creator, and that he is therefore benevolent. It may be well to remark here, that the argument, according to the illustration of it before given, is cumulative. "When we have established the two premises of the foregoing argument, we have furnished a valid proof of the divine benevolence, and therefore in each of our remaining positions we shall increase the proof. I now offer a second general argument : Argument II. The present system in its nature and tenden- cies is the best conceivable, and therefore the best possible to the Creator. I have said that the proof of the divine benevolence is cumu- lative. What I claim for it in this respect is, that when as in our first argument, it is shown that in view of the results of the present system, it is the best possible to the Creator, then if in view of the nature and tendencies of the system, it be shown that it is the best conceivable, we have still further proof that it is the best possible to the Creator, and so much addi- tional proof of his benevolence. The nature and tendencies of 334: MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. the system, if they can be shown to be the best conceivable, now become in view of the perfection of the system as judged by its results, so much uncounteracted and independent proof of the highest possible perfection of the system ; proof as de- cisive and complete as were the system actually followed by the highest conceivable good which it is fitted to produce. Nor is this all. But when, as we have shown, not only there is not the least counteracting evidence from any other source, but the present system, judged of by its results, is the best possible to the Creator ; then each and every adapta- tion, fitness, tendency of the system to the production of the highest conceivable good, is so much additional proof that the Author of the system designed the highest conceivable good ; and is therefore so much additional proof of his benevolence in adopting the system. In this mode of reasoning then,I now proceed to show that the present system is the best possible to the Creator, by proving that in its nature and tendencies it is the best conceivable system. This I shall attempt to show : 1. From its general form as a moral system ; and 2. From its more particular forms as such a system. That the present system then is the best conceivable, and therefore the best possible to the Creator, I argue — 1. From its general form as a moral system. As a moral system in distinction from any system not moral, it is in hind the best conceivable. It is so, if we consider the kind of beings and the kind of influence which it involves. And first in respect to the kind of beings. These are of course moral beings ; and as such are formed in the image of God himself. No other work of the Creator could so employ his wis- dom and his power — no other creatures could be so exalted in the scale of existence — no other product could so manifest the infinitude of his natural attributes. On no other could he look with so much self-complacency. "There is," said Augustine, "but one object greater than the soul, and that object is its Creator." Had God then not adopted a system of creation including moral beings, the highest place in the scale of created being had been vacant, and without them the inter- val between mere animal existence and God himself, had been unoccupied. What then had been a system of creatures, endowed only THE HIGHEST KIND OF BEINGS. 635 with animal sensation, compared with a system of beings capable of holy affections and holy activity, and each and all capable of possessing perfect, even the highest degree of happiness conceivable? If God were good, what else could he do but create mind — beings in his own image, with intelligence to know himself, his character, his will, his designs, his works ; with hearts to burn with love, with wills to obey his perfect will — with conscience to feel the high deservings of right and wrong moral action, and to sway all the powers of the soul in the harmony of perfect virtue; beings with sympathies and social tendencies, capable of living in the past, the present, and the future — capable of entering into fellowship with God, and of awakening his confidence and his complacency as the executors of his high counsels ; beings so powerful in intellect, as to be able to look with open face on the full effulgence of his Godhead, so capacious of heart as to receive the fullness of joy at his right hand, and who thus filled with all the fullness of God, might stand around his throne as mirrors of his own creation, to reflect the light of his glory forever ? For such a creation what shall be substituted ? The present system then, in respect to the kind of beings which it includes, is the best conceivable, and in this respect, there being no counteracting evidence, fur- nishes another independent and decisive proof of the Creator's goodness. The same thing is true of the present system, as it employs a moral influence. After what has been already said, I may as- sume the position as incontrovertible, that the universal and perfect holiness of a moral creation is necessary to the highest conceivable happiness of such a creation. It is equally unde- niable, that the kind of influence which is peculiar to a moral system, is indispensable to the production of holiness in the least degree in moral beings. It is of course necessary to the highest degree of holiness, and therefore to the highest degree of happiness. In this view of this kind of influence, and of the system which includes it, the system has all the value which would pertain to a moral creation made perfectly blessed by perfect moral excellence. And who can estimate the worth of an in- fluence which is indispensable to such a result ? Who will attempt to conceive of any other as its substitute? ISor is this its only feature. There is a high and ennobling pleasure in 336 MORAL GOVERNMENT PROM NATURE. using this influence, nor scarcely less in feeling it. To uphold and move the material universe in all its regularity and beauty, to give form, and life, and activity to the whole intelligent crea- tion — to pervade, sustain, and animate all as the handywork of Omnipotence, is a source of high delight to the infinite Author of all. But to influence mind — to be the author of that system of truth, of evidence, of motive, which is adapted to control and direct intelligent, free, moral beings, and to secure the high end of their existence — fitted to accomplish such a result in beings with powers adequate to defeat it — to bring forth an influence which shall give absolute perfection to a moral uni- verse for eternity, without in the least infringing on the noble prerogative of their freedom, imposes a new demand on omnip- otence, and imparts a grandeur and glory to God's dominion, which excludes from thought every other. At the same time, to be the subject of such influence — to live under that system, and those manifestations of truth, which are thus adapted to move moral beings, and to secure such re- sults — a system which has tasked the wisdom and the power of the infinite Being, and whose results can fail only through the perverseness of creatures, when in respect to the kind of influence God could do no more; to have such interests placed within one's own power — committed to choice, enlightened and guided by intelligence to comprehend them — to be able to se- cure the result designed by an act of will, and if secured, to say, " I have done it, when I could have done the opposite" — to live under a system, where the alternative is the self-perfec- tion or self-destruction of an immortal being — this is to occupy a place of exaltation and dignity, which none can transcend or equal. If such a being rises, what a height of glory ! If he falls, what ruin! The alternative is indeed tremendous, but is demanded by the essential perfection of the system, and its foreseen and glorious results. Every tendency justly estimated is adapted to a successful and triumphant issue. The influence from the doom foreseen is only salutary. It can be incurred only by voluntary perversion and fault ; it can come only by the great law of choice between life and death, without which a more dreadful ruin must come to all — without which the in- finite Being himself must sacrifice his perfect character, and with this his perfect blessedness. Such then is the influence which is involved in the present, THE HIGHEST KIND OF INFLUENCE. 337 as a moral system. How degrading to creatures, liow unwor- thy of a perfect God, were any other in its stead ! How re- pulsive, how revolting a system of coercion — or rather, what degrading absurdity in the thought of controlling moral beings by physical agency, or by the mechanism of cause and effect ! The mind, created in God's image, must be governed, if at all, by the influence which moves him in all his doings — even by that truth which fixes and reveals the eternal relations of things, and gives the soul its life in perfect holiness and perfect bliss. Without this influence of the system, what will become of its issues, in all the self-complacency, free, voluntary, joy- ous activity, and eternal triumphs, of which perfected moral beings are capable? On this influence in distinction from every other, these results all depend. Its tendency is to pro- duce such, and only such — even the highest conceivable good of the best conceivable system of creatures. This tendency of this influence in a system which is better than none, and which, for aught that can be shown to the contrary, is the best possi- ble to the Creator, is as conspicuous, and as obviously designed by its Author to secure its benign and blessed results, as were they actually secured. The present system then, as it involves a moral influence in distinction from any other, is the best conceivable, and in this respect furnishes another independent and decisive proof of God's benevolence. That the present system is the best conceivable, and there- fore the best possible to the Creator, I argue — 2. From its more particular forms as a moral system. Here I appeal to it as comprising four particular forms of a moral system : that influence to secure perfection in character and in happiness, which results from the perceived nature and tenden- cies of moral action ; the influence of a moral government ; that of an equitable moral government ; and that of an equitable moral government under a gracious economy. In the first place, the present system comprises that influence to secure perfection in character and in happiness, which results from the perceived nature and tendencies of moral action. These are plainly and impressively manifested in the constitu- tion and condition of the human mind. I need not here repeat the facts on this part of the subject, which have been so re- cently presented. In view of them, I may ask, what more in this respect could God have done? The answer is, nothing — Vol. I.— 15. 22 " 338 MORAL GOYERNMEXT FROM NATURE. which for aught that appears to the contrary, would not have been for the worse. If we contemplate the knowledge of truth which is thus given to every mind, in its source, its nature, its power, can any thing be conceived in this respect to heighten the excellence of the system? It is knowledge of the fixed and immutable relations of right and wrong, given in the very nature and elements of our being; knowledge of good and evil in their highest conceivable degrees, and of the only means of obtaining the one and avoiding the other ; knowledge of all that man need to know as a being made for immortality, that he may secure his perfection in character and in happiness ; knowledge, which is pressed upon thought and susceptibility in experience, and as it were every moment ; knowledge, which can be practically resisted and counteracted only by the most desperate violence and infatuation of which moral beings are capable ; knowledge which even when thus resisted puts its firm grasp on the conscience and holds it there: still opens the bright visions of hope in the self-complacency of virtue, and re- veals the terrors of self-condemnation in the remorse of guilt, and thus distinctly and at every step of life is telling man of a retribution in that heaven or hell which he carries in his own bosom ; knowledge therefore which is fitted so far as knowl- edge from these sources can be, to secure in the best manner and in the highest degree, man's perfection in character and in happiness. This tendency of this knowledge is as manifest as were the result actually secured. It is furnished in a system which is not only better than none, but which for aught that can be shown to the contrary, is the best possible to the Creator. It is there- fore as obviously designed by the author of the system to se- cure the result which it is fitted to produce, as were that result actually secured. The present system then, as it comprises that influence from the perceived nature and tendencies of moral action, which is fitted to promote the highest blessed- ness of God's moral creation, furnishes another proof of the highest conceivable perfection of the system and of the benev- olence of its author. In the second place, the present system comprises a moral government. Moral government in the lowest import of the terms, includes a moral governor, a rule of action as the ex- pression of his will — good promised to obedience and evil PARTICULAR FORMS OF INFLUENCE. 330 threatened to disobedience. These things, though they do not necessarily include the equitable administration of a moral government, are essential to what can be properly called a moral government. Without now insisting on the equity of God's moral administration over men, still he is administering a moral government over them, and such a moral government as is consistent with the system's being the best possible, and also better than none. In this view of a moral government, I claim that it is an excellence which is essential to the perfec- tion of the system. Let then the present system without, be compared with one which includes a moral government, and be contemplated in relation to the great end of a moral system. What would it be, when compared with one which exhibits the infinite Creator of men, as also their sovereign Lawgiver and Judge? In this relation that great Being is presented to the mind as taking a deeper, stronger interest in the moral conduct of his moral creatures as the means of their perfection and happiness, than in any and every thing besides. In this relation he makes a clear expression of his preference of right to wrong moral action on the part of every subject, and shows them that their highest interests can be secured only by obedience to his will. With their happiness and mis- ery at his disposal, he authorizes only the expectation on their part that all depends on their conduct. Whatever conviction of duty then we may suppose men to derive from any other source — what additional strength and power must be given to that conviction by the clear and decisive promulgation of the will of God in exact accordance with it! How feeble and fluctuating — how evanescent, easily forgotten and disre- garded the conviction derived from one source only, com- pared with the same derived from both ; how must the con- viction of duty first obtained from our nature and condition and the tendencies of moral action, be impressed by its known coincidence with the will, the law of Him who holds all destiny in his hands ! While our very being reveals the ab- solute and unalterable law, that if we would be happy and not miserable we must be good, the execution of this law is made known in the immutable will and resistless power of an infinite being. But if we suppose no moral government over this world, then no evidence can be found of a retribution for the right and wrong doing of men. The distribution of good and 340 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. evil in this world is not in the lowest sense retributive. Aside from God's relation as a moral governor of men, legal sanc- tions — good and evil awarded to sustain authority — a Judge to approve and condemn, to reward and to punish are not to be thought of. But with a moral governor in view, and he no other than the infinite Creator of all, holding the allotment in the happiness and misery of every creature in his power, and giving a full indication of his purpose to make them in a high degree happy or miserable as they obey or disobey his will, what other influence can be substituted for this, in a system which is better than none, and which for aught that can be shown to the contrary, is the best possible? It is an influence which can be viewed in such a case as tending only to good, and to good in the highest conceivable degree. The present system therefore, as it comprises a moral government on the part of God, has another excellence which is essential to its highest conceivable perfection, and in this respect furnishes another independent and decisive proof of the benevolence of its author. In the third place, the present system includes cm equitable moral government. There is a sense in which the equity of a moral administration or of a moral government may imply the benevolence of the moral governor. I use this language how- ever as I have before said, merely to characterize what may be called his providential dispensations as being in accordance with the principles of equity, whether we suppose him to be a benevolent or a selfish being. In other words, by the equity of God's moral administration over this world — I mean that his providential dispensations are what they would be on the sup- position of his perfect benevolence, without assuming that such is his character. In this sense the equity of his administration whether he be a benevolent or a selfish being, consists in his giving the best law or rule of action, and in annexing to this law those sanctions in good and evil which express his highest approbation of right and highest disapprobation of wrong moral action, and which are requisite as such expressions to sustain his authority. I claim to have shown already, that God is administering in the sense now stated, an equitable moral government over men,*and that without so doing it would be impossible that he should show himself to be entitled to the least respect as a GOD'S EQUITY PROVES BENEVOLENCE. 341 moral governor. The impossibility of this on the supposition of his not giving the best law, will not be denied. So if we suppose him to annex to the best law, less degrees of natural good and evil than the highest as the sanctions of his law, it would show that he approves of right moral action less than supremely, and disapproves of wrong moral action less than supremely. Such a manifestation of feeling toward these ob- jects would be decisive; that he does not regard things as they are ; that he does not act on the principle of eternal rectitude — that of regarding the best kind of action as the best, and the worst kind of action as the worst ; that instead of showing him- self disposed to sustain his authority, and to employ this influ- ence for the welfare of his kingdom, he acts on principles of partiality, favoritism, injustice, tyranny; that he is therefore a selfish and malignant being, and in no respect entitled to the homage of his subjects, or to the throne he occupies. But in the present system, instead of thus subverting his authority as a moral governor by disproving his benevolence, God, as we have seen, adheres to strict equity in his moral administration. lie gives the best law or rule of action, and by the requisite legal sanctions, expresses the highest approba- tion of right, and the highest disapprobation of wrong moral action. lie does the very things in these essential respects which he would do were he a being of perfect benevolence ; the very things, without which he cannot prove his benevolence and sustain his authority as a moral governor. For what other higher or better influence can be substituted for this, for the purpose of securing the greatest amount of right moral action, and thus the greatest amount of happiness, in a moral creation ? Could any higher or better influence for the purpose be derived from natural good and evil, considered as merely so much mo- tive employed to secure right and prevent wrong moral action ? Could it result from giving any other law than the best — from expressing in the form of law any other preference than of the best kind of action ? Could any higher or better influence for the same purpose result from legal sanctions, considered as the expressions of any other particular feelings or emotions toward right and wrong moral action, than those of the highest appro- bation of the one and the highest disapprobation of the other ? In these respects plainly, no other influence conceivable can possess the same salutary tendency. In this way only can he 34:2 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. manifest those attributes of a perfect moral governor, which, we call his holiness^ justice ; — holiness in all its love and compla- cency toward moral excellence, and in that inaccessible purity which recoils from, and in that withering abhorrence which forbids the approach of the least moral defilement ; — -justice in that serene and awful majesty of its inflexible purpose to sweep a rebellious world into the abyss of ruin, rather than suifer the least obscurity or infringement of his right to reign. Under no other manifestation of God, could obedience to his will be rendered as the will of a perfect being. There might indeed, be a moral system, and moral influences, and if you please, a moral government ; but there could be no moral government in the hands of a perfect being ; none in that distinctive char- acter which results from the absolute prerogative of rightful dominion. Unless Ave see God through the medium of an equitable administration, we cannot see him as immutably holy and just, and can therefore never confide, love, and obey. In a word, it is only through an equitable moral administration, that God as a moral governor, can manifest his perfect char- acter. Now I do not say, that such an administration necessarily excludes all opposing evidence on the question of his moral character; but that when it exists, as it does in the present case without the least opposing evidence — when it exists as an element of a system, which, in view of its results, is, so far as we have seen, the best possible to the Creator, it can be viewed only as an essential element of the perfection of the system, and as such, another and decisive proof of its perfection and of the benevolence of its Author. In such a case, what other view can be taken of his giving his perfect law — perfect in its precept, and perfect in its sanctions — except that of the most unequivocal and decisive expression of his supreme and benev- olent preference of right moral action, and as its consequence, the highest possible happiness of his moral creation ? "What can be the design of making such an expression of these feel- ings, in this most impressive form conceivable, except that by so doing he may secure this result ? Were this actually accom- plished by this means, who then could doubt its adaptation to the end, and the benevolent design of its Author ? But its tendency to this result is a matter of absolute knowledge, and would be no more obvious than it now is were the result actu- AN ECONOMY OF GRACE. 343 ally produced. And now, when the design of its Author to secure this result, instead of being obscured by the slightest shade of evidence to the contrary, is confirmed by the manifes- tation of his benevolence in every other form, this design is as conspicuous and undeniable as is the tendency to this result of the same element of the system. Neither can be denied or doubted. The design of God in administering an equitable moral government over men, in order that the end should be produced, for which it is perfectly adapted, stands forth as con- spicuous as were that end actually accomplished in the highest conceivable happiness of his moral creation. In view then of the equity of God's moral administration, we say that it is one element of the best possible system, which is not only an indis- pensable, but an independent and decisive proof of equity in principle ; thus revealing on the throne of moral dominion, a God of perfect holiness and perfect justice, and of course, a God of perfect benevolence. In the fourth place, the present system is the best conceiva- ble, as it includes an equitable moral government under an economy of grace. That God is administering such a govern- ment over men, I persuade myself has been shown in former lectures. We have seen that the manner in which he distrib- utes good and evil in this world entirely harmonizes with an economy of grace ; that while there is nothing in the whole history of his providence inconsistent with the strict principles of equity in his administration, there are still decisive intima- tions that he has not abandoned these principles — that every thing in the manner in which he treats this world of transgres- sors, clearly and impressively bespeaks his will that they should return to duty and to happiness, rather than continue in sin, and die forever. "We see him furnishing to all the most deci- sive proofs that their highest happiness can be found only in obedience to his Will — drawing them to repentance by the most powerful influence, that of manifested kindness; by those "cords of love and bands of a man," which it would seem no perver- sity of heart could resist ; dispensing natural evil, under the kindest forms of necessary moral discipline or paternal chastise- ment, with the obvious design to reclaim and bless his disobe- dient children — making the present state of man most obviously one of trial and of discipline, and as such, designed and fitted to form his character to permanent virtue and happiness — 344 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. placing man's present enjoyment so far and so clearly in Ms own power, as to show beyond the possibility of doubt, that a universal and perfect moral reformation would transform the world, darkened and afflicted as it is by sin and its woes, into a primeval paradise ; thus in every conceivable form and mode of dispensation, clearly evincing his power to sustain such a system of justice and of grace — forbidding a surmise either of malignant intention, or of weak and indulgent connivance at iniquity, and so rendering every other supposition inadmissible, except, that while he sustains the principles of eternal righteous- ness inviolate, he is, in the fullness of love and mercy, aiming to restore a lost world to duty, to favor, and to happiness. Thus does the great Creator present himself to his guilty moral creation, a just god, and yet a saviour. Here then we see the crowning excellence of the present system. I shall not attempt to specify in detail those parts of God's providence which are eminently fitted to extend and heighten our admiration of this system of justice and of grace. To sustain the principles of eternal righteousness unsullied and unobscured, and show himself placable to the guilty, and even solicitous to reclaim and bless — to uphold in all their stability the pillars of his throne, and yet give it the attractions of a throne of grace — this is a system which combines with every other conceivable excellence, the highest, brightest of them all, that of an economy of grace. The present system then, in an- other respect, i. e., as including an economy of grace, is the best conceivable. The argument for God's benevolence, as thus furnished by the light of nature, may be thus presented. The present sys- tem with its results, is better than none; notwithstanding the evil which exists, the system may be the best possible to the Creator ; while in its adaptations and tendencies to good, it is in every respect the best conceivable. God therefore is benev- olent, Were a physician to perform an operation on a patient, which were better than to do nothing, and though connected with some pain, might still be the best possible, and in respect to all its tendencies, were it ascertained to be the best conceiva- ble operation, who would doubt his benevolence. Were it however my principal object here to prove the be- nevolence of God, I might proceed greatly to increase the force of the present argument. For having once shown, on the OTHER PROOFS OF BENEVOLENCE. 345 premises now presented, that God is benevolent, it were per- fectly legitimate to infer not merely that all existent evil may he consistent, but that it is consistent with his benevolence, either as the necessary means of the greatest good, or as in- cidental in respect to his prevention, to that system which is the necessary means of the greatest good. In respect to natural evil, viewed as it must be, as the nec- essary means of the greatest good, instead of furnishing an objection to his benevolence, it becomes an additional proof of it. As to moral evil, viewed as it must now be : viz., as inci- dental in respect to divine prevention to a system in which God has done all that was possible to prevent it, and to secure universal holiness in its stead, it leaves the benignity of his design unobscured ; and we are obliged to say, there is all the proof of God's benevolence, which there would have been, had the universal and perfect holiness and happiness of his moral creation been the actual result. Having arrived at this point, I might bring forward, as still further proofs, furnished in the fact that he shows kindness to his creatures in every conceivable form which is consistent with their greatest good ; and this, not in respect to its salutary tendencies and relations, in view of which it has given so much force to our preceding arguments, but under two very different relations: viz., as so much good or enjoyment merely, and as such, all that in degree, which is consistent with the highest good of the recipients ; and also, as so much good conferred on sinful, ill-deserving creatures, whom, as a benevolent and just God, he might have utterly destroyed. To all this good, we must add the grand and glorious results of that system of grace and mercy in future and eternal happiness, as conferred on guilty beings whose endless destruction had been alike con- sistent with justice and benevolence. Here let us then advert, first, to what had been the proofs of God's benevolence, had perfect holiness and happiness actu- ally resulted to his moral creation. Wc have this proof at hand, for we have proved that he most truly and sincerely designed this result. Let us now advert again to what would have been the condition of this world of transgressors, had God, as he might, displayed his benevolence and been just, instead of displaying his benevolence in pardoning grace. Let the fear- ful results of exact retribution in the woes of the second death, 15* 346 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. be compared with the riches of his long-suffering, and the ever- flowing streams of his providential bounty in this world, and with (as our previous argument authorizes us to expect in the world to come) the eternal blessedness of a multitude which no man can number, of pure, holy, and happy spirits, so vast, so glorious, that the few incorrigibly wicked whom necessity con- fines in the prison of state, shall be only as an unnoticed speck amid the overwhelming glory of the whole. I have thus attempted to exhibit the proofs of God's benevo- lence, as shown by the light of nature. And what other or higher proofs could be furnished by his works or his doings, I am compelled to say, is beyond my power to conceive. Con- templated as a state of trial and preparation for results in eternity, the nature, the condition, and the prospects of man, manifest infinite wisdom and power, directed by infinite good- ness, aiming at results which shall forever tell the Creator's capacity to bless. To specify an imperfection, or suggest an improvement, defies the power of the human intellect. This world then, must be esteemed not as furnishing merely some faint intimations, some slight grounds of conjecture that God is good, but as presenting to every eye that witnesses the oper- ations of his hands, one of the brightest theaters of his infinite benevolence — a scene in God's creation, in which,, counter- acted indeed in its fullest results by human wickedness, it only awakes to new and unheard of desires and efforts to bless : benevolence which shines forth like a sun, when all that might seem to obscure its light, only serves to give new warmth and splendor to its beams. For in what brighter forms of love and goodness could God appear, than as the God of redemption to this guilty, lost world ? If now I have proved that God is a being of perfect benevo- lence, it follows that he administers his moral government over this world in the exercise of rightful authority. Having before proved that God administers a moral government over men in some proper import of the phrase ; having shown that he ad- ministers his moral government in equity and in the exercise of rightful authority ; I have established my leading proposi- tion, that God administers a perfect moral government over men. I conclude with one reflection on the views which have been given of the moral government of God over this world, viz. : TRUTH OF CHRISTIANITY DESIRABLE. 347 Hoio undesirable that Christianity were not a revelation from God. If Christianity is not a revelation from God, still every thing of vital importance to man which Christianity says, is true, except its grand peculiarity, the manner in which this world's redemption from sin is achieved — every thing is true, except its discovery of a triune God, the Father, the Son, and the Holy Ghost, in their respective relations to the work of man's redemption from sin. If Christianity is not a revela- tion, still there is an infinite being who has given existence to creatures, formed in his own image, and destined to live and to act, for weal or for woe, through a coming eternity. For the accomplishment of his eternal counsels, God has as- sumed the high relation of a perfect moral governor of these creatures of his power. Perfectly benevolent, he is also in- flexibly just. He will never sacrifice the majesty of law, the glory of his moral dominion, and the happiness of his moral creation, in tenderness to rebels. His throne stands in all its grandeur on the pillars of eternal justice, and, though changed into a throne of grace, still in all its darkness and tempest, it speaks undiminished terror to the determined transgressor. It is changed into a throne of grace, but only to the rebel who is penitent and contrite in heart. It is a throne of grace, that, with its attractions and its charms, it may win rebellion to loyalty. If then, Christianity is not a divine revelation, every thing (I mean every thing substantial, for I certainly admit that Chris- tianity sheds a new and brighter light on all moral truths), with the exceptions made, which Christianity teaches, is true. Every thing respecting God, man, time, and eternity — every relation of God to man, and of man to God — every relation, tendency, and consequence of right and wrong moral action — every foundation of hope, ground of fear, retrospect of the past, reality of the present, prospect of the future — the same proba- tion, the same law, the same economy of mercy, the same judgment and retribution, the same heaven and hell — all, all in every great and substantial respect, is the same. Christian- ity, with the exception made, is only a republication in brighter characters, of the truths of God and of nature — of God and nature immutable as its author. If Christianity then is not a divine revelation, where are we ? Just where we are if it is a revelation, with this difference, the light it sheds on the scheme 348 MORAL GOVERNMENT FROM NATURE. of redemption is extinguished! How the perverseness of rebels is to be subdued to love, and if subdued, how can a just God re- ceive them to favor ; here all is mystery unsolvable — darkness impenetrable, even appalling! Man, a sinner, and guilty as he is, I admit might repent, and might hope for mercy from his Maker. But would he? Man, in the bondage of sin, what chains so strong? — man, dead in sin, what death so hopeless? who shall deliver? what power shall raise to life, give health, and strength, and beauty immortal to this victim of sin and death but the power of him who made him ? Man, I said, might hope for mercy. But with a clear perception of his fearful guilt and God's fearful justice ; when looking at a sin-avenging God as he must, and asking, how can such a God show the same abhorrence of sin and yet forgive, which he would show by the endless destruction of a rebellious world, then it is that the fears and dismay of guilt take hold on the spirit, and hope trembles, faulters, expires. I say not that it must be so, but that it always has been, and always will be, at least with exceptions not to be named. For remember, it is not the hope of the infidel that we need — the hope that God is unjust — the hope like his, that reposes in a selfish, malignant deity ; it is not the hope which fancy and the love of sin beget, and which rushes fearless on the thick bosses of Jehovah's buckler, without knowing who or what he is ; it is the hope which looks upon a just God, and with a sense of his righteous indignation, reposes sweetly in his mercy. And yet there is so much terror here, there is so much midnight darkness and thunder, that the feeble rays of mercy do not suffice. Guilt will look up with confidence only when it sees the throne of God upheld by the man that is his fellow. Take away " the incarnate mystery," extinguish the light which reveals the great atonement of Christianity, (ignorance and presumption might indeed hope in a selfish deity, in an unjust God, and realize a just perdition), but extinguish this light, the light which reveals God's mercy through his Son, and let in the terrors of guilt and of God on this sinful world, and how would they weep and howl in the frenzies of despair ! Thanks — may I not say it — thanks to the impostor, if such he was, who de- vised the great atonement of the gospel. Falsehood — can we say less ? — falsehood is better than truth ! Imposture ? False- hood? No. Here is the seal of God. It is just the atone- TRUTH OF CHRISTIANITY DESIRABLE. 349 ment which man needs, the atonement which he must have, to embolden conscious guilt to approach a spotless God ; the only atonement which will in fact, give hope and peace and heaven to a guilty world. God devised it. God revealed it, that all other manifestations of his mercy might not be in vain. With no known instance of actual forgiveness, with no formal decla- ration of God that he will forgive, with the burden of conscious guilt upon us, and with no possible conception of any expedi- ent by which God could show mercy, we should in fact, be conducted to the most fearful forebodings of wrath. In this midnight of gloom and terror all our research and all our rea- sonings would actually terminate. And back again to this midnight, from the light which beams upon us from the gospel of God would the infidel conduct us. Let him go, if he will, into all this darkness and dwell amid its terrors. Let him go, if he will, to the bar of a just God on the footing of his own righteousness, and be tried by his innocence or his merit ; let him trust an unjust, selfish, malignant deity, for he has no other God. But give me hope in a God of mercy. I speak what you feel, and what I feel, when I say, I am a sinner — a sinner against a holy, just, and perfect Gocl. I need his mercy. I am a guilty, lost immortal. I need deliverance from de- served and endless misery. Oh ! hide not from me the mercy, the abundant mercy of God in Christ Jesus. LECTURE XI. APPLICATION OF THE ARGUMENT FROM NATURE, TO PROVE THAT CHRISTIANITY IS FROM GOD. Nature of Divine Bevelation. — Argument for its necessity. — Different views of the grounds of this. — I. Not necessary, because man cannot discover moral and religious truth: but II. Neces- sary, 1. To make known the truth in the most perfect method, especially by language. — Absur- dity of objecting to this medium. — 2. To receive the practical influence of such truth. — The experiment by the light of nature decisive, shown by the ancient philosophers. — Their views scanty, vacillating, erroneous. — Practical influence feeble on themselves and others. — Preva- lence of immorality. — Their teachings and example limited. By a divine revelation, we may understand some mode adopted by our Creator of imparting the knowledge of reli- gious and moral truth to the human mind, more direct than any such knowledge obtained by the light of nature; or em- ploying human reason on the character, the works and provi- dence of God. On the question whether a divine revelation is necessary to man, the parties have, in my view, often adopted unqualified assertions, which are erroneous and even fatal to a satisfactory conclusion. On the one hand, it has been affirmed that all the knowledge which is necessary or useful to man as a moral being may be obtained from the works of God, and that every other mode of discovering truth to the human mind on the part of God, is impossible, incredible, and useless. On the other, the utter in- sufficiency of human reason to make the least useful discovery of moral and religious truth from the mere light of nature, and the consequent absolute necessity of a direct revelation from God, have been strenuously maintained. It is true, that some of the advocates for the necessity of a revelation, concede that the light of nature furnishes the means of much important knowledge, and often seem to contend only for the necessity of further discoveries by the light of revelation. And yet the same writers assert with frequency, " that human reason can- WHY REVELATION IS NECESSARY. 351 not attain any certain knowledge of the will or law of God, or of the true happiness of man."* This incongruity, which ap- pears to characterize the discussions on this subject by leaving the real question vague and indeterminate, has contributed in no small degree to unsettle opinions and to perpetuate discus- sion. To what extent the necessity of a divine revelation exists, and what are the precise grounds or reasons of it, are points of the first importance to all satisfactory views on the subject, as well as to the termination of the controversy with the opposers of revelation. It may be admitted generally and indefinitely, that a reve- lation is necessary to man, and yet its ends or purposes, and the extent, grounds, or reasons of the necessity, may be left undecided. In a state of utter darkness, light is necessary as the only medium of vision. But we may suppose a degree of light adequate for a distinct sight of surrounding objects, and yet that a man should refuse to see them, and this in a case in which Greater light would result in actual vision. In the one case, light is necessary, because man cannot see without it ; in the other, to secure his actual vision, because he loill not. Again, there may be a degree of light adequate to the dis- tinct vision of some objects and not of others ; and the consequence may be, either that neither class of objects will be seen, or that the former only will be. In these cases, the particular purposes or ends, on account of which greater light is necessary, are different, as are the objects to be seen. The grounds or reasons of the necessity differ — greater light in the one case, being necessary to actual vision of any of the objects; in the other, necessary to the actual vision of all the objects. Further ; a greater degree of light may be necessary, not be- cause man cannot, nor because he will not see every object, but to enable him to see every object with greater distinctness and effect than would otherwise be possible. So in respect to a divine revelation. It may be necessary for a great variety of particular purposes or ends, and the grounds or reasons of the necessity in respect to these ends may be very different. To maintain the general proposition that a divine revelation is necessary, is not fitted to convey precise and definite views on this important subject, nor to * Horxe. 352 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. terminate this part of the controversy with the opposers of rev- elation. While therefore, I maintain the general doctrine, that a divine revelation is necessary to man, to prevent misapprehen- sion, I remark — I. That a divine revelation is not necessary to this world, because man cannot discover much moral and religious truth without it. The advocates of the utter incompetence of human reason to make any such discoveries, seem to have fallen into the error, by mistaking the lamentable ignorance of the world, for proof of an entire incapacity for knowledge, and from a mis- guided zeal to magnify the gift of a revelation, and the grace that conferred it. That this mode of reasoning is unauthorized, may be confidently decided, in view of its intrinsic deficiency, and on the authority of revelation itself. It is intrinsically de- ficient, since the mere fact of ignorance is no proof of incapacity for knowledge. In revelation itself the ignorance and crimes of the heathen world are never traced to incapacity for knowl- edge, but the clear manifestation of God, and the consequent inexcusableness of man both for his ignorance and his crimes, are constantly asserted, and these are traced to the humiliating fact " that men did not like to retain God in their knowledge." The attempt to exalt the grace of God in the gift of a rev- elation by depreciating man's capacity for knowledge, is still more to be regretted. Admit, as the reasoning assumes, the entire incompetence of the human mind to obtain any knowl- edge of religious truth, and the grace of God in conferring a revelation on the world is wholly subverted. On the part of men there could be neither obligation nor crime. The neces- sity of a revelation is created by their Maker and not by them- selves. Revelation could not be a gift to a sinful world, criminally resisting the light of truth and perverting the means of knowledge, and thus deserving to be given up to a repro- bate mind. But it is a provision absolutely necessary to con- stitute men moral and accountable beings, and therefore de- manded, if they are held responsible for their conduct by every principle of equity. It is a matter of debt, of justice; and grace is no more grace. This attempt therefore, to magnify the grace of God in the gift of a revelation wholly defeats its object. WHY REVELATION IS NECESSARY. 353 In proof of the position that the human mind is competent to discover much important truth without a revelation, I might appeal to what I have already shown to be true concerning God and concerning man, from the mere light of nature. I might appeal also to the actual discoveries of such truth, especi- ally to the writings of many of the ancient philosophers. The appeal to revelation itself on this point would he still more decisive. On this authority it might be shown that man can know the very truths to a considerable extent, without a revelation, which the advocates for its necessity affirm that he cannot know without it. For example, the being and perfec- tions of God, his moral government, his moral character ; the law of his moral government, and of course the sum of human duty — to a great extent the specific duties toward God, toward man, and toward himself; the doctrines of human sinfulness, of the necessity of a change of moral character ; the placability of God ; the immortality of the soul, future rewards and pun- ishments. Here it would be a very useful inquiry, how far the Scrip- tures will bear us out in the assertion of this matter of fact — not only by appealing to their explicit declarations, and their clear implications, but especially to the variety of forms, and to the great extent in which the sacred writers make the previous knowledge of mankind the basis of their reasonings, instead of resting on their authority as inspired teachers, although this is never abandoned. But whatever ground the advocate of Christianity may take, the infidel will admit that the human mind is competent to discover much religious and moral truth without a revelation. I proceed to show — II. That a divine revelation is necessary to the world — (1.) To give the highest conceivable perfection to the mode of making known the truth to the human mind. (2.) To any extensive and useful discovery of truth to the human mind. (3.) To the discovery of some important truths, which man could not discover without it. (1.) A divine revelation is necessary to the highest conceivable perfection of the mode of making 'known the truth to the human mind. There are only two conceivable modes of discovering truth to the human mind by our Creator: viz., through the 23 354 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. medium of his works of creation and providence and by a rev- elation. My object is not to compare the excellence or desir- ableness of these two modes, bnt simply to show that the mode which combines both, is better than that which should include but one ; or rather is the best conceivable. Xor does my ob- ject require me to examine the different specific modes of making a revelation which are possible, although it were easy to show the superiority of that mode to every other in which it is claimed that God has made a revelation. I speak only of some mode of revelation, as additional to the mere light of nature, and maintain that it is indispensable to the highest con- ceivable perfection in the mode of discovering religious and moved truth to the human mind. This position is, to my own mind, so palpably obvious, that had it not been denied, it could scarcely require or justify an attempt to prove its truth. Who does not know the power of speech and written language to convey truth with peculiar precision, clearness, and effect? Why is it that the very men who deny all revelation, and pro- fess, while so doing, to impart to the world the light of truth, resort to oral and written language as the medium of convey- ance ? Why not leave the world to spell out truth on this great question from the nature of things, as affording ample light without the addition of speech and writing to instruct them? Plainly because they believe that by this addition they adopt the most effective mode of imparting knowledge and of giving it permanence, impression, and prevalence in the minds of other men. And will they pronounce their own con- demnation, by pronouncing that mode of conveying truth use- less, on which themselves rely as the best ? And if not useless on the part of men, why useless on the part of God ? God has confessedly formed the human mind to be taught and instructed by himself, through the medium of his works. And is it not equally manifest that he has formed the human mind to be taught and instructed through the medium of language? Is not this mode of conveying knowledge one which involves every facility and every advantage? If God has qualified men to learn truth from what he does, has he not also qualified them to learn truth from what he says? Why then should it be thought a thing incredible, that God should adopt one method as well as the other, or rather, that he should adopt both ? If his children are to read and learn his character, will, REVELATION BY LANGUAGE. 355 and designs, their duty and destiny from his teachings, why not avail himself of their capacity to be taught through the medium of language ? Why may he not instruct them by his words as well as by his works; why not give them two books as well as one — the book of revelation as well as the book of nature? Would not the latter mode be as natural, as effectual — as truly in accordance with their accustomed manner of learn- ing truth as the former ? Are not the advantages of the latter so great, so obvious, as to render it exceedingly desirable to all who would wish to learn ? Why is it that we wish every thing in art, science, literature, history, morals, and religion, that is true and of importance to be known, reduced to writing ? Why is it that laws must be written and published, that contracts, bonds, deeds, mortgages, every title to an estate, must be put upon record? Because this is confessedly the most perfect method of securing the knowledge of facts. No man is igno- rant of the importance and necessity of written records and books on every subject of moment pertaining to this world. And yet if we speak of a book from God, teaching man how to secure the great end for which God made him, we talk of a useless book — aye, of one worse than useless. Books from men, even on religion, if it be of the right sort, are of inesti- mable value ; but a book from God, teaching such a religion as God might be supposed to teach, would be a thing of naught. You cannot feel too much contempt for it ! And this is a con- sistency of which to boast ! But not to dwell on absurdity so glaring, let us for a moment reflect on the end to be secured and the mode of accomplishing it. The end is, so to instruct this sinful world in religious and moral truth, that it shall become effectual to its moral reforma- tion. Now, without disparaging at all the light of nature, without supposing God to reveal one other truth to man than what may be learned from it, I ask what mode of bring- ing this very system of truth before the human mind would be best fitted to the end to be accomplished ? Simply that which we call the light of nature, or that which should combine with it — the light of a revelation through the medium of human lan- guage. Such a revelation, such books from deists, from infi- dels, are at least regarded by themselves as an improvement in the method of imparting instruction to men. Why then may we not suppose that such a book as God could make, would 356 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. also be an improvement on their productions ? Suppose then God to qualify certain men, to declare the same system of truth to the world through the medium of written language ; sup- pose him to give the most indubitable proofs that they are thus qualified and commissioned by God himself for this work ; let us suppose the book actually written, containing simply that system of truth which the light of nature discloses, presenting these sublime doctrines concerning God — his nature, his charac- ter ; the great facts respecting man — his nature, his character, his destiny ; his relations to him, promulgating the great law of God's moral government in its perfect requirement ; its diverse specific precepts, its high and awful sanctions ; making known an economy of mercy, unfolding with new clearness a future state with its regions of immortality in bliss and woe — let us suppose this system of truth set forth to the human mind in all the simplicity, perspicuity, force, and conclusiveness of which human language admits ; by argument, illustration, exemplification ; shown to us in real life, embodied in rites of worship, and carried out in all the forms of human action ; presented in history, poetry, parables, allegory, epistles — in every conceivable form fitted to render it intelligible, impres- sive ; easy to be fixed in the memory, and ready for use at all times ; accessible to all minds, fitted to all classes of men in all circumstances and relations ; capable of being brought in all its clearness and power on the human mind, from the beginning of moral and accountable agency, and ever and always from its own pages, as well as through its ordinances and appointed ministry, pouring its light over a world like the sun in mid- heaven. Suppose God to give such a book to this world, hav- ing that perfection which his own inspiration could give it, would it be no valuable addition to the mere light of nature ? Would such instruction from God possess no value ? "Would this light from heaven, truth enforced by the authority of God, the very testimony of the living God, be nothing ? Would it be nothing to man that his God should speak to him? Or, is such a revelation from God absolutely necessary to give the highest conceivable perfection to the mode of discovering re- ligious and moved truth to the hitman mind f Let any honest man who understands the use and power of language answer this question. (2.) A divine revelation is necessary to secure to any extent, WHAT HAS PHILOSOPHY DONE? 357 the practical influence of religions and moral truth on the human mind. In support of this position I shall attempt to show, that such an experiment has been made, as to prove, that the great end of man's creation woui be entirely defeated without a revelation from God. In other words, facts enable us to decide what the human intellect would accomplish in the discovery of religious and moral truth, and what would be the practical results un- der the mere light of nature ; and that these discoveries and results show that the moral reformation of men would never be accomplished to any considerable extent, without a divine revelation. The question is not as to the sufficiency of this light, but as to its actual efficacy in leading men to duty and to happiness. Has it in fact ever done it ? I appeal then in the first place, to the ancient heathen philos- ophers. And here I might say, there is great reason to be- lieve that nothing in the writings of these philosophers, of the least value either in theology or morals, was strictly the result of their own mental efforts. Many of them confess that they derived their knowledge from very ancient traditions, to which they assigned a divine origin. " What Socrates said of the deity," observes Dryden, " what Plato writ, and the rest of the heathen philosophers of several nations, is all no more than the twilight of revelation, after the sun of it was set in the race of Noah ;" while the Christian fathers furnish abundant proof that Plato especially learned much from the Hebrews while he was in Egypt. Of Zoroaster, of whom deists have had much to say, it has been shown by Dr. Hyde in his treatise " De Re- ligione Yeterum Persarum," that Zoroaster had been a disciple of one of the Jewish prophets, and that all the writings ascribed to this philosopher are unquestionably spurious. I cannot but add here the apparent prediction, but yet real conjecture of Plato, founded probably on the traditions and truths he de- rived from the Jews in Egypt. He says, " We cannot know of ourselves what petition will be pleasing to God, or what worship to pay him, but that it is necessary that a lawgiver should be sent from heaven to instruct us ;" and such a one did he expect ; and " oh," says he, " how greatly I do desire to see that man and who he is !" He goes further, and declares this lawgiver must be more them a man, "for since every nature is 358 ARGUMENT PROM NATURE APPLIED. governed by another nature that is superior to it, as birds and beasts by man, he infers that this lawgiver who was to teach man what he could not know by his own nature, must be of a nature superior to man — that is, of a divine nature." He gives indeed, as lively a picture of the person, qualifications, life, and death of this divine man, as had he been acquainted with the fifty-third chapter of Isaiah. He says " that this just person must be poor, and void of all recommendations but that of virtue alone; that a wicked world would not bear his instruc- tions and reproof; and that therefore within three or four years after he began to preach he should be persecuted, im- prisoned, scourged, and at last be put to death." "Would it then be strange if all in the writings of Plato and other ancient philosophers, which has been held up to our admiration, should have been directly or indirectly derived from divine revela- tion ? Laying aside however, this consideration, and conceding all that can be claimed in respect to the unaided powers of the ancient philosophers, let us inquire what they actually accom- plished in morals and religion. The answer must be admitted to be decisive upon the point before us. The fact appealed to, is that of the employment of the most powerful human intellects on this subject, with unparalleled devotion, and under the high- est advantages. Who will pretend that more would ever be accomplished in this department of human knowledge, under the mere light of nature, than was done by Socrates, Plato, Seneca, Cicero, and other eminent philosophers of antiquity ? When has the world seen, when could it expect to see, men of brighter genius, of higher intellectual power, of superior liter- ary accomplishment, of such unrivaled industry, toil, and self-consecration too, in philosophic research ? Whatever may be thought of the intellectual stature of Bolingbroke, Gibbon, Hume, and Yoltaire, they appear diminutive compared with these giants of the Academy and the Lyceum. What then did these philosophers accomplish? What for themselves, and what for the world ? And here we have no occasion to deny any excellence or impute any imperfection or defect which is not real, in their systems of philosophy. It is conceded then that passages may be found which seem to express exalted conceptions of God and of some of his attributes. In some of their moral codes, par- WHAT IIA.S PHILOSOPHY DONE? 359 ticularly in the Etliics of Aristotle and the Offices of Cicero, some beautiful theories of morals and precepts fitted for the regulation of external conduct are to be found. Some of them admit that virtue is the chief good and its own reward ; and some of them, at times at least, indulged in sublime specula- tions respecting the nature and immortality of the soul. But after all, what was the amount of their knowledge or belief on these great subjects, and what were the actual results to them and to the world ? While some of these philosophers asserted the being of God, others openly denied it ; few, probably none of them believed God, in the proper sense, to be the Creator of the world ; most of them were polytheists, and all of them either sincerely or hypocritically sanctioned, defended, and practiced idolatrous worship, and enjoined it as the duty of every citizen. In respect to a future state, whatever may be said of their arguments, the best of the philosophers spoke doubtfully ; none of them applied the fact to its proper use and end ; most of them entertained of it the most puerile and contemptible con- ceits. They did believe in future punishment, and their ideas of future rewards were so indefinite, low^, and sensual, as to give no importance to their faith. In short, as to the merit and demerit of right and wrong moral action, the happiness and misery in kind and degree of which the soul is capable, a just judgment of a righteous God, and the grand and awful idea of accountability — they believed nothing — or at least en- tertained conceptions so inadequate and so false as to amount to nothing. - In respect to morals, nothing like a true system was to be found in the writings of any one of them, nor of all of them together. On the great, the vital question — in fact the only question — viz., in what does the supreme happiness of man consist, Varro tells us that there were three hundred different opinions among the philosophers. Cicero says, that these opin- ions were so numerous and discordant that it is impossible to enumerate them ; while it may be added, that in respect to the true nature of moral excellence — viz., disinterested love — true benevolence either in God or man — no one of them seems to have formed a conception. Where this is not understood, it is in vain to talk of morals, of piety, or religion. Every thing is wrong in principle. Call it by what names you will, ascribe 360 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. to it what restraining and regulating power you will on tlio conduct of the life, it is nothing but the selfish principle, the sum and essence of all moral evil. Did these philosophers then ever teach intelligibly and truly, that love to God and love to man is the sum and substance of all moral excellence ? — that love is the fulfilling of the law — and that all else with- out it is in a moral respect nothing but sin ? So far as I can find, never in any decisive instance, while, with the exception of a few, instead of inculcating the expression of this principle in loving enemies and forgiving injuries, they accounted re- venge lawful and commendable. Pride and ambition (prin- ciples which have caused more wretchedness on earth than any other), were esteemed the best incentives to virtuous and noble deeds. Suicide was deemed lawful, and a proof of true heroism. Lying lawful, when profitable ; theft, adultery, for- nication, infanticide, cruelty to children, inhumanity to slaves, degradation of the female sex, gratification of sensual appetite and unnatural lusts ; in a word, the most flagitious practices were countenanced on the part of the philosophers, both by argument and example. Even the doctrines of the wisest and best, notwithstanding the slight hints or the faint and transient glimpses of truth they include, were as a whole, uncertainty, darkness, jargon, pueril- ity. What truth concerning God, his character, law, govern- ment ; or concerning man, his character, his relations, his pros- pects, at all fitted in its combination with error, to give any just or adequate conception of either God or man, or to reform a lost world ? The answer is given in matter of fact. Philoso- phers, statesmen, poets, priests, and people, were avowedly addicted to the most abominable uncleannesses and crimes ; the gods they worshiped were guilty of the same enormities; their sacrifices were deformed with cruelty and the most horrid rites ; their sacred groves were consecrated to prostitution, their temples were brothels. Think of such worship rendered to the three hundred Jupiters mentioned by Yarro, or to the three hundred and sixty-five gods mentioned by Orpheus, or to thirty thousand by Ilesiod— gods celestial, aerial, terrestrial, and infernal ; gods worshiped by rites profane, cruel, debauch- ed ; gods worshiped by shameless prostitution and the immo- lation of human victims ! "With this entire corruption of all religion was of course connected an ecpial corruption of morals WHAT HAS PHILOSOPHY DONE? 361 both in public and private life. Fraud, theft, injustice, suicide, adultery, fornication, systematic abortions, murder of infants, and the most unnatural crimes, ambition, hatred, and fell re- venge ; gladiatorial shows, and all the atrocious cruelties of war and rapine not only abounded but were patronized, counte- nanced, authorized by law, connived at and practiced by statesmen and philosophers, and publicly reprobated by none. From this source, the corruption of all religion and morals, aided by the depravity of the human heart, flowed forth a torrent of crimes and abominations desolating a world of all that is good and happy in virtue and religion, and leaving all, all in moral darkness and moral death. Its state became more and more hopeless as time rolled on. Even in the land of Judea the last feeble rays of divine truth were almost extinct, while this vast portentous cloud hung over the nations, thick- ening, darkening, and foreboding only the blackness of dark- ness forever. I now ask, whether God has not made a sufficient experi- ment on the question, what human reason would accomplish in the discovery of religious and moral truth, and what would be the practical results under the mere light of nature ? What reason or shadow of reason is there to believe that modern deists, or any other men, or any individual man, under the mere light of nature, and to the end of time, w T ould have be- come wiser or better than Socrates, Plato, Seneca, or Cicero ? When or where has human genius shone more brightly, or the power and majesty of the human intellect more excited our admiration and wonder than in the poets, the orators, the legis- lators, the philosophers of antiquity? And when, to the end of the world, could we hope for better results in the discovery of moral truth in the formation of moral character? "What then could be hoped for from philosophy, from human reason, under the mere light of nature ? Is not the experiment abso- lutely decisive ? Is not the necessity of a divine revelation to secure to any extent the salutary practical influence' of religious and moral truth on the human mind, placed beyond all denial ? In confirmation of this argument, if it can need any, we might appeal to many other considerations. So far as there was any thing really commendable in the instructions of the philosophers, they were delivered to their immediate pupils, and in no respect to the great mass of the community. Indeed, 362 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. their ethical systems were far too refined for the common peo- ple ; their discourses being rather subtle disputations, where truth was left obscure, doubtful, and subject to controversy. Nothing was settled. What one affirmed, another denied. "What could be expected of the common people, when the penetration and the labors of the philosophers resulted in dis- agreement, contradiction, and uncertainty? Allow that they discovered and proved some truths in speculation, what author- ity could they give them in practice ? What philosopher could secure submission to his rules of life ; or what can human law effect in the renovation of the heart ? " Your systems of vir- tue," says Tertullian, "are but the conjectures of human phi- losophy, and the power which commands is merely human ; so that neither the rule nor the power is indisputable ; and hence the one is too imperfect to instruct us fully, the other too weak to command us effectually ; but both these are effectually pro- vided for by a revelation from God. Where is the philoso- pher that can so clearly demonstrate the true good as to fix the notion beyond dispute ? And what human power is able to reach the conscience and bring down that notion into prac- tice ? Human wisdom is as liable to error as human power is to contempt." What would be the influence of a system of truth coming from man, compared with that of the same sys- tem clothed with God's authority ? In addition to all this, let the idolizers of human reason remember that the wisest of the ancient philosophers and legislators were fully convinced, by their own experience, on this great question. Socrates and Plato both confessed that they needed a divine revelation to instruct them in matters of the greatest consequence. Cicero and others, instead of the vain conceits of some modern deists respecting the powers of man employed in religious and moral inquiries, often acknowledged their imbecility and darkness. These great men were so impressed with the actual state of the world, and the waywardness and corruption of the human heart, that they not only often acknowledged that there were no human means of reformation, but expressed a strong hope and expectation, that God would one day give to man a revela- tion that should dispel the dark cloud in which the human mind was involved. In short, it is notorious that nearly the whole system of religion and of worship, with its sanctions of future rewards and punishments, with its oracles, divina- VALUE OF CHRISTIANITY. 363 tions, mysteries, were in fact political expedients, useful fic- tions, originated and perpetuated by legislators, from the ne- cessity of keeping the people in awe, and under greater venera- tion for human laws. If the world could stand without a real revelation, experience had proved at least one thing, that it could not stand without a pretended revelation from God. After such an experiment then, an experiment which left the world in a most deplorable condition of darkness, crime, and wretchedness; an experiment which convinced the very men that made it of its utter inefficacy; which actually led them to abandon all hope of the world's reformation without a revela- tion from God, and which actually compelled them to resort to the pretense of such a revelation, to give even any salutary re- straining influence to human law ; I say, who after such an ex- periment can doubt the absolute necessity of a revelation from God, to secure to any extent the reforming influence of moral truth on the human mind ? One brief reflection ! What a value does the view we have taken of this world, of the ignorance, the depravity, the crimes, the miseries of mankind in every age and in almost every country for six thousand years, give to Christianity, and this, whether it be a revelation from God or not. "Who will not read and study the Bible, whether he be an infidel or a Chris- tian? Christianity, as a system of morals, whether it be of God or not, is true. Here, here, it gives light where all was uncertainty, confusion, darkness, without it. Here, where the thickest gloom of moral midnight overspread a lost world, it comes as the morning sun to remove the darkness and reveal the day. In or is this all. In its proposed way of our accept- ance with an offended God, if there is any way — I mean in the general form of an atonement for sin — it is also true. The great question then, in every substantial respect, is not between Christianity and Infidelity, but between Christianity and noth- ing. If Christianity is false, Infidelity is false. Reject the morals of Christianity as false, and all here is midnight. We can know nothing to be true. Reject also the great fact of some atonement for sin, under the government of a just and perfect God, and there is no mercy, no hope. Oh, how would Socrates, how would Plato, have hailed such light as this ! Who that has it shall despise it ? Who will not study, under- stand, apply, such truth as the Bible contains? Whose eye 36tL ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. will not weep, and whose heart not break, that a fellow-crea- ture, a friend, a companion, is not willing to read this book and weigh with candor the evidence of its origin from God ? Oh ! what maniac madness to sport on the verge of eternity, with the dream that Christianity is false — an immortal mind, deny- ing such truth, and attempting to sustain and cheer itself, as it were, at the foot of God's judgment-seat, with the empty, vapid declamation about the sufficiency of human reason — and this with the knowledge of the fact, that for six thousand years this boasted human reason has only plunged a lost world into error, sin, and death, without hope! And if all these were without excuse, what will, what must become of the man who will not love the truth, and embrace the truth, and obey the truth, which he knows Christianity reveals ? LECTURE XII. Argument for necessity of revelation continued: Prop. 2 continued — Revelation necessary to secure the practical influence of the truth.— Argued from the state of Pagan nations at pres- ent. — From the influence of Deism. — Deists greatly indebted to Christianity. — The influence of their systems is feeble, scanty and uncertain, denies the holiness and justice of God. — Theii views of sin and repentance defective. — Their morality superficial. — Men are not made better by them. — Little zeal for reforming men by them. — Give no comfort in death. — Prop. 3. Revelation necessary to make known truth undiscovcrable without it. — Conclusion. In continuing the argument for the necessity of a divine revelation to any useful discovery of truth, I appeal — In the second place, to the state of pagan nations at the pres- ent time. This point needs no illustration. The facts on this subject are familiar to all, and they carry with them their own infer- ences. In the third place, I appeal to the influence, of Deism. It is claimed by that class of philosophers called deists, that the book of nature is the only book to be studied, or that deism as a system derived from human reason under the light of nature, is all that is requisite actually to instruct and guide the world in respect to religion and morals. My first remark on this part of the subject is, that this class of philosophers, have derived the best parts of their system from the very revelation which they reject and affect to de- spise. Let it then be conceded, that in their system of faith there is much truth concerning God and concerning man — truth, which human reason rigidly employ v^, might and would discover under the mere light of nature. But it is one thing to grant that these doctrines of deism are discoverable, and quite another to affirm, that they have been actually discov- ered by the light of nature. What then is the fact ? It is here to be remarked, that the name of deist was unknown till about the year 1565, when Christianity had been in the world more than fifteen centuries. How then did it happen, that Socrates, and Plato, and Aristotle, and all the wisest philosophers groped 360 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. in such darkness during so many ages, and that this purified and perfect system of truth called deism, should be first discov- ered and taught by men who lived and were educated under the meridian sun of Christianity ? Had these men at this period of the world, made such advances in knowledge as to leave the philosophers of Greece and Rome and all other na- tions out of sight, and to be able effectually to guide them- selves and the rest of the world by their own reason ? Can they lay claim to superior genius or mental culture ; or did the light of nature shine brighter on them than on all who lived before? This cannot be pretended. No; what they knew, and all they knew, more than was known and taught by the sages of antiquity, they learned from God's revelation. Chris- tianity had shamed away the grosser errors and vices of the pagan philosophy, and shed its blazing light so intensely on the mind, as to compel men as it were to see its perfect system of moral and religious truth, and to adopt so much of it as to shield them from contempt. They stole a torch from the temple of God and called it the light of their own reason. The fact cannot be mistaken — the pretension to discovery is ridicu- lous. As well might a New Zealander residing among the discoveries in the arts and sciences made in Christendom for the last hundred years, pretend to be their sole author. Are not such pretensions to discovery from the light of nature ridic- ulous, contemptible, beyond all possible respect ? But I will waive this point, and ask, what is this system of truth which is to accomplish so much for the moral reforma- tion of the world? No one can tell what it is! To whom shall we apply — where shall we find it ? Shall we resort to the deistical writers en masse and listen to their instructions ? But the ear is stunned with contradiction, inconsistency, disagree- ment, controversy, mutual censure and recrimination without end. When it must be optional in the highest sense with all to adopt one or another or none of these systems, what is to be expected but the same jargon among the disciples, as prevails among the masters ; or rather, what but the rejection of every system ? Or if every one is to read and judge for himself, what will be the consequence but confusion, compared with which that of Babel were harmony of sweetest music ? Who that knows any thing of man, or of the experience of past ages, will not regard as perfectly ridiculous the scheme of bringing this THE DEIST'S PREMISES DEFECTIVE. 367 world to receive any system even of truth, which lias no higher authority than that of human reason. But further, without insisting on this fatal obstacle, there is yet another. Their system can possess no authority, not even that of reason itself. The most perfect system of deism con- sists in these particulars, that there is one God possessing in- finite natural and moral perfection; that God is to be wor- shiped and served in the forms of piety and of virtue; that God will forgive our sins against him on condition of repent- ance ; and that he will reward the good and punish the bad in a future state. Now I readily admit that these propositions are all true, in their proper import, and that they can all be proved to be true, by human reason. But what I now main- tain is, that the infidel cannot, by reason, prove any one of them to be true. He cannot, because he denies the premises by which alone these propositions can be thus proved to be true. lie denies the justice of God, the equity of his moral administration over this world ; and, denying this, he can prove nothing concerning God or man of the nature of relig- ious or moral truth arising out of the character of God, or the relations between God and man. Denying that God is just as a moral governor, he cannot prove that God is benevo- lent. Denying that perfect benevolence in God involves in its very nature exact and perfect justice, he denies the very nature of benevolence ; he denies an essential element of all moral rec- titude, and utterly subverts the distinction between right and wrong. The God of Infidelity then is not, and cannot be, a be- nevolent God-; but is and must be a selfish and malignant deity. This spoils alike its entire system of theology and of morals. A God of such a character cannot have the least claim to any worship or service from man, either in the form of piety or vir- tue. With such a view of God, there can be no love, no confi- dence, no gratitude, no piety, no virtue toward him, for there is no fit object of these affections. All moral relations between him and his moral creation are subverted. Moral obligation, obedience, disobedience, sin, duty, can have no place. Where is moral obligation ? Such a God has no right to command. Where is obedience or disobedience ? He has no authority. Where is the standard of duty ? The will of God is the will of a selfish or malignant being. Where is the object of one right affection? God is exhibited only as an object of abhorrence '368 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. and of dread. Where is sin against God ? It were sinful to love, and right to hate such a being. Where is repentance ? There is no cause for contrition in the past, and no return to duty for the future. Where is forgiveness ? There is nothing to be forgiven. Where is the ground of trust or hope? The vain illusion that a selfish being, who is more likely to destroy than to promote the interests of his creatures, may prove in- dulgent through partiality or favoritism. Where the prospect of immortality ? No purpose or plan of God, no designs either of justice or mercy, require a future state for their accomplish- ment, Where are rewards and punishments ? All are a mock- ery — at best the expressions of unjust lenity or unjust severity. Where is religion ; where is virtue ; where is the principle of recovery from the gulf of moral ruin ; where is relief for the alarmed conscience ; where is mercy, peace, hope, heaven ; where is a perfect God ? All is a blank. Indeed, a system of religion which denies the gkeat relation of god as the righteous moral governor of men, is all error, all delusion. It is worse than not true. It is most fearfully false. It is worse than nothing, worse than any thing. The God of such a system can be viewed in the light of truth only under two aspects — as the patron of iniquity, or an omnipotent tyrant, Ko God at all were better than the God of Infidelity. What man not already the hopeless victim of his wrath, would not wish that God were benevolent, though benevolence involves perfect justice. Under any other idea of him, there is nothing but that which in wanton malice patronizes iniquity with all its woes or tortures, nothing but that which is fitted to overwhelm with terror. Such then are the unavoidable results which rea- son gives from the premises of the infidel. If we can suppose him inconsistent enough to believe any thing better himself, he cannot prove it to be true, he cannot enforce it on the minds of other men by the authority of reason. He must give up his premises, and admit the great fact of a just God, or aban- don all pretense to reasoning. His premises do not give his conclusions, but others which are opposite and appalling. What then can be hoped for, from a system of reason in which there is no reason ? Will the world be reformed by a system of faith professedly founded in reason, and yet so obviously built on falsehood ? Yain is the dream. Deism, with all the seem- ing comeliness of its most unexceptionable form, has, according WHAT IS THE INFIDEL'S FAITH? 369 to its own principles, no warrant, no authority, from human reason. It is an utterly baseless system. But I have another inquiry to make concerning this system : viz., what is it? The deist — at least a few deists — professes to believe that there is a perfect God ; that he is to be worshiped and served by piety and virtue ; that he will forgive our sins on condition of repentance; and that good men will be re- warded and bad men punished in a future state. This, so far as it goes, sounds well in words, but what does he believe concerning God? He tells us he is good. But what is goodness in God ? We have seen that it is that senti- mental tenderness, that indulgent lenity that sacrifices the gen- eral good to individual happiness ; goodness that does not abhor the supreme evil, goodness that refuses to adopt the best means of the best end. Does the infidel then believe in God as he is ? Does he conceive of him in the glory of that holiness which recoils from sin with supreme and eternal indig- nation, in the glory of that justice which will maintain his law, uphold his throne, sustain the interests of holiness, and express his supreme and immutable abhorrence of sin, though it in- volves the eternal destruction of a rebel universe ? "Who does not know, that all such exhibitions of God, are, in the view of infidels, repulsive, odious, intolerable falsehood? Who does not know, that they can tolerate no idea of God but that which exhibits him as more concerned for the happiness of his crea- tures than for their virtue; that view of God, which represents him as entirely dispensing with the eternal nature, relations, and dependences of things ; and therefore as sacrificing the in- terests and the principles of righteousness to make his creation happy, by which he must inevitably make that creation wretch- ed; that view of God which exhibits him in the glory of his mercy, sacrificing his justice, in the plenitude of his goodness as a tender, indulgent friend and patron of iniquity — a selfish ma- lignant deity? Such is the good, the benevolent, the perfect God of Infidelity ! I ask here, are these words merely, and not things? The same hollow emptiness, the same meaningless nothing, or rather the same fearful falsehood characterizes every part of the infidel's creed. What is sin ? A venial evil — the merest trifle — nay, rather, so far as it exists, the best means of the best end ! What greater practical error than to believe the worst kind of moral action to be the best kind of moral action ? 16* 24 370 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. Where is the true exhibition of the nature and tendency of sin against God, as hostility to him and all good and the source of absolute and universal woe ; as the subversion of God's law, his government, his throne, his kingdom, as the destruction of all good — yea, of God himself, as the infallible source of misery, unmingled, complete, eternal. Are such the views of the true nature and tendency of sin which Infidelity gives us ? Nothing like it. They are, of all things, the views which infidels most abhor. That sin is such an evil, involving such fell destruction, such guilt or ill-desert, and that a perfect God must feel and act toward it accordingly, is, in their estimation, the most in- credible of all nonsense. These views of sin are the false, absurd, austere, gloomy, self-torturing views of hair-brained fanatics. With such conceptions of God as the infidel entertains, what must that be which he calls piety? Can love, reverence, confi- dence, submission, gratitude, joy, be exercised toward the God of Infidelity? How preposterous. Can every thing be taken away from the character of God which awakens dread and disturb- ance when sinful beings think of heaven's Sovereign ; can every moral attribute of the Godhead be amalgamated into one — that of unqualified tenderness; can all that is venerable and awful in God be sunk into that which is so grateful to the rebel ; with such a view of God can the heart of his worshiper feel the holy reverence and awful love which are due to a perfect God? True piety, in all the sacredness and solemnity of devout emo- tion, adoring the tender, sentimental, weak-hearted God of In- fidelity ! When does the infidel contemplate God in his true character, that awful goodness which connects misery with sin, and welcome the aspect of such a God ? When does he look upon that august and inviolable sanctuary, where the fires of his indignation forever burn to guard the approach of the least moral pollution, and adore, and love, and praise, with grateful and exulting joy? We all know that such a God is the object of aversion and ridicule, and even of blasphemy, with infidels. All their piety, all their joy in God, is, and can be, nothing but those selfish, sordid emotions which are founded in the be- lief that an unprincipled deity will be indulgent to them in their rebellion. And further ; what is that which the infidel calls repentance f xsot sorrow for sin as it is — not as hostility to God, and the INFIDEL VIEWS OF RELIGION. 371 frustration of his designs ; not sorrow for sin, as that which in the estimation of God and of truth, deserves his wrath in the endless misery of the sinner. But rather, it is regret for a tri- vial evil, for that toward which God feels no supreme abhor- rence, hut which he on the whole prefers to its opposite — sor- row in a word, for that which in their estimation and in that of God, is the best means of the best end, with a determination to forsake it! And as to future rewards, what are these — what is the heaven of Infidelity ? Nothing positive, nothing definite — a general undefined state of happiness irrespective of moral character. It may be the heaven of Mohammed, or it may be the blissful elysium of heathen poetry, or a paradise of earthly sweets in some other form. But it is not a world of happiness, because sin is not there, and because holiness is there reigning in all its purity and its joys. The happiness of the infidel's heaven is not that which is peculiar to holy spirits in communion with a holy God. It is any thing but a perfect God in fellowship with creatures bearing his perfect image. And what is future punishment? Not a supreme and endless misery inflicted as the expression of the wrath of God against sin ; but at most paternal chastisement, disciplinary evil, kind inflictions to reform and to save ; evil inflicted according to the exigency, so that they who are not reformed by less shall be reformed by more, so that rebellion itself, much as it may abhor the service of God, shall be compelled by dint of suffering to surrender to God's authority, and thus to serve him at best with a rebel heart. No other motive, nothing but the compulsory influence of natural evil is thought of or presented. Thus it is that Infi- delity in its fairest form is plausible in ivords only. In 'respect to truth, it means nothing which it seems to mean. It knows nothing of God as he is — nothing of holiness or of sin, of piety, virtue, repentance, or of the nature of those influences by which alone moral beings can be governed and blessed. All it means under its fair show of words, is error the most destructive. And in further confirmation on this point, I appeal to any man ac- quainted with the writings or the character of infidels, and ask, is there a more palpable solecism than a pious infidel — a de- vout, spiritual, heavenly-minded infidel ? If now we appeal to Infidelity's code of morals, what is it? True morality is in the heart. Men talk of good morals. What are they? Benevolence in the heart; love to God and love to dl2 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. man. Holiness, a spiritual principle, which as much surpasses all that infidels call morality as a living man does a dead man. In all the writings then of infidels, I fearlessly affirm, that the inculcation of the great, the true, the only principle of morality cannot be found. It follows of course, that whatever else may be true of their system, it includes not the slightest tendency to reform men in respect to morality. In most if not in all cases, there is an open and avowed contempt for many of the particular virtues which adorn the character of man as a social being, and which are essential to the happiness of an earthly community. At the same time the most heartless, sordid self- ishness is inculcated in many forms, and many of the most degrading and destructive vices, with an almost unlimited in- dulgence of the sensual appetites, are countenanced and even formally vindicated. A few testimonies from the least excep- tionable of deistical writers must suffice on this topic. Lord Herbert asserts that lust and anger are no more to be blamed than the thirst occasioned by the dropsy, or the drowsiness produced by lethargy. Mr. Hobbes, that the civil law is the only foundation of right and wrong — that every man has a right to all things, and may lawfully get them if he can. Lord Bolingbroke resolves all morality into self-love, meaning selfish- ness, and teaches that ambition, the lust of power, sensuality and avarice may be lawfully gratified if they can be safely, that man lives only in the present world, that the chief end of man is to gratify the appetites and inclinations of the flesh, that adultery is no violation of the law of nature, that polyg- amy is a part of this law, and modesty is inspired by prejudice or vanity. Mr. Hume maintained that self-denial and humility are not virtues, but are useless and mischievous, and that pride, self-valuation, &c, are objects of moral approbation, that adul- tery must be practiced if men would obtain all the advantages of life, and if practiced secretly and frequently would be no crime at all ! But I need not go into further details. Substantially the same things or worse, are to be found in all this class of writers of most distinction. If now we refer to their characters, we shall see that in their practice they gave proof of their faith. Lord Herbert, Hobbes, Lord Shaftsbury, Woolston, Tindal, Chubb, Lord Bol- ingbroke, Collins, were all guilty of the vilest hypocrisy and lying on the face of their publications; professing in words CHARACTER OF INFIDELS. 373 high respect for Christianity, while they felt toward it the most deadly hate, wearing a mask of friendship that they miorht stab it to the heart. The morals of Rochester and Wharton were notoriously degraded. Woolston was a blas- phemer ; Blount was a suicide ; Tindal and Morgan were shameless hypocrites. Yoltaire was an adulterer, and as famous for falsehood, treachery, envy, profligacy, low sensuality and cruelty, as for his exalted talents. Rousseau, by his own pub- lished confession, was a thief, a liar, and a debauchee. Thomas Paine, than whom perhaps no one has done more by his writ- ings to extend Infidelity in this country and in Europe, was in- famous for his hostility to all morals and all religion, for his impiety, blasphemy, licentiousness and adultery, and sunk at last into all the filth and wretchedness of a sot; an object of pity and contempt to his own deluded disciples. In presenting these examples, I do not pretend that every deist has been thus degraded by open vice and immorality. Doubtless there are cases in which pride, respect for character, literary ambition, and other causes have predominated over the grosser appetites ; but in many of these an avowed hos- tility to the true principle of morals, a ridicule of the milder virtues, an extreme indifference and selfishness in respect to the best interests of man, have varied the aspect without less- ening the guilt of their principles or their conduct. Nor let it here be said that some of the professed disciples of Chris- tianity have also been depraved and wicked men. We admit it. But this we reply is notwithstanding Christianity — it is in spite of it, riot its effect ; while the wickedness and the profli- gacy of professed infidels are the genuine fruits and effects of their religion itself. The proof from facts is decisive. Such has been the character of the teachers of the one system almost without an exception, while the contrary character has been that of the teachers of the other, with almost no exception. In respect to the disciples of the two systems, in the one case a hundred to one have been openly wicked and profligate, in the other not one in a hundred has been. Again ; infidels themselves do not believe in the salutary, reforming tendency of their own system. What have they done, I do not say to propagate their faith, but to propagate it for practical, reforming purposes ? what, to secure any useful practical influence on the human mind ? Is it not notorious o(4: ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. that the grand, the supreme object, end, and aim of this class of men, has been to pull down and destroy Christianity, and to set up Infidelity in its stead? Is it not a fact that Infidelity, so far as it comprises truth in words, is a mere show, an empty pretense of truth, brought forward only as matter of display in argument; never as having any practical bearing on the conscience ; never exhibited as a system embodying obliga- tions, persuasives, motives — the least tendency or power to re- claim from sin and death — but used as an imposing semblance of truth — a foil to set off and commend the most destructive error. Does the infidel care what men believe, provided only that they do not believe Christianity ? Or rather, so far as he teaches any thing positive, does he not inculcate false views of God, of his character, of his relations ; and false views of man, his duty, his character, his prospects? Is it not a system to console rather than disturb human wickedness ? Where are the truths brought forth for practical purposes which are taught by the light of nature itself? Where, in the writings or addresses of this class of men, is God presented to the human mind as he is — God in his holiness, his justice, or even in his mercy, for practical purposes ; where do you find any exhibi- tion of sin as it is, in its true moral deformity, turpitude, and odiousness ; repentance in its ingenuous relentings, its godly contrition, brokenness of heart, and abhorrence of all sin ; of the graces of humility, meekness, forgiveness, active benefi- cence, with the self-denial and self-government which they in- volve ; where any exhibition of the rewards of the righteous and the punishments of the wicked pressed on the hopes and the fears of men as incentives to piety and virtue? Where is there any assault on corrupting error save that of Christian- ity, or any defence of truth, except that Christianity is false. Where is truth (I speak of truth taught by the light of nature), developed by illustration, defended and confirmed by argu- ment, and pressed home on the bosoms and business of men in its practically reforming power ; where are the sinful practices of men exposed and condemned ; where are the corrupt princi- ples of the human heart, its selfishness, deceitfulness,its lusts and inordinate passions, its worldliness, pride, and rebellion against God laid open ; where is the law of God in its broad and spiritual demands unfolded ; where is the full-length portrait of man drawn as a sinner against God without excuse, and without WHY INFIDELS DO NOT PREACH. o<0 hope save in the mercy of a just God — mercy without merit — - mercy that can save while justice can destroy; where is the entreaty and the expostulation, the earnest solicitude, the be- seeching tenderness, the faithful reproof, that true-hearted kind- ness that consults not the passions but the welfare of men, not their inclinations but their duties, that offends rather than de- ceives, that utters painful truth rather than flatters to destruc- tion, that humbles, and rebukes, and wounds, rather than not save ; where is the study, and the toil, and the prayers, the compassion, the tears, that become a reformer of fellow-beings ruined for eternity ? Where are their Baxters, and Leigh tons, and Doddridges, their Edwardses, and Davieses ? A death-like silence answers. There is not one Christian book that does not contain the essential elements of moral truth, illustrated, ap- plied, enforced ; you cannot find one infidel book that does. What signifies then all this pretense of infidels about reform- ing the world by the light of reason? If there is truth in their system, fitted and sufficient to reform and save their fellow- creatures from the doom of sin, and if they sincerely believe it, why not bring it forth for this high purpose, and go abroad on this errand of salvation with that apostolic zeal, self-denial, and devotedness, which become such a cause. Sin still maintains its dark and gloomy dominion, with scarcely an exception, throughout this wicked world, frowning resistance and defiance a gainst God and goodness. Why, as true men and good men, do they not open their powerful battery of truth, and make their artillery thunder on the strongholds of sin and death ? Honest men, believing that they have the means of such a triumph, and yet doing nothing ! Friends of God and of man, true-hearted philanthropists, do you believe that Infidelity will reform and save a lost world ; then apply it to that purpose, show your faith by your works. In the name of truth and reason let us have the experiment. Oh, but Christianity is in the way. Then go where there is no Chris- tianity. Christianity in the way ? But Christianity, by their own confession, is the best, even a perfect system of morals. Why not then take truth — truth where they can find it — truth, if the devil be the author of it ; and carry it forth in its enlightening, transforming, and saving power, upon this dark and wicked and dying world ? The infidel sincere ! An apostle of Infidelity loving the souls of men ; truly believing that a 376 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. lost world is to be reclaimed to God by deism ; aiming to ac- complish this end by this means ! No. Every thing shows that his grand, his only object is, to destroy Christianity. He lives to annihilate its truths and to throw the reins loose on the neck of rebellion against God. He hates Christianity. He hates its author; he lives with the watchword on his lips, " Crush the wretch ;" and to any labors, undertaken and pur- sued from jDrinciple, for the glory of God and the salvation of men, he will not make the least pretension. Labors for the conversion and salvation of men ! There is not an infidel who would not be ashamed of, and even resent, the imputation. Once more, what have been the actual effects of Infidelity, the practical results on the human mind. I speak of its effects where it has been most successful in respect to its real object of displacing the influence of Christianity and securing the prevalence and legitimate results of its own principles. Here I might appeal to the testimony of that multitude who have been converted from Infidelity to Christianity p what is their conversion in every instance by their own frank confes- sion but a conversion from sin to holiness — what is it in most cases but a conversion from vice, profligacy, hostility to all that is good — what but a resurrection from moral degradation and death ? Facts innumerable of this kind betray the camp of the enemy — they show us the interior of this sepulcher. But has Infidelity any such facts to show — facts of men made better by renouncing Christianity for Infidelity ? Converts to Infidelity from among devout and enlightened disciples of Christianity, confessing their guilt for having embraced it, confessing vice and crime, profligacy and debauchery as the results of receiving and obeying Christianity ! Baxters, Leigh- tons, Doddridges, Brainerds, Edwardses, such men in the in- tegrity of their hearts renouncing the corrupting influence of Christianity for the sanctifying power of Infidelity ! All the world knows the absurdity, the self-contradiction, the utter im- possibility of such a thing ; and know as well that the differ- ence between Christianity and Infidelity is the difference be- tween truth and error — truth that blesses and saves, and error that curses and destroys the souls of men — the difference be- tween life and death. What has been the reforming influence of Infidelity, of human reason rejecting Christianity, or perverting it, or obscuring its DOES INFIDELITY REFORM? 377 light ? What was the cause of the decay and of an almost utter extinction of religion and virtue among men, from the seventh to the sixteenth century? The corruption of Christi- anity left the human mind to be governed by human reason and depraved morals, superstitions multiplied, heathenism re- vived under the garb of Christianity, spiritual tyranny was established, moral duties exchanged for vows, pilgrimages, aus- terities ; God, his worship, his service forgotten ; selfishness, vice, crime, a long, fearful night of woe. And what brought back the day ? TV" as it Infidelity ; was it human reason, unaided by revelation, or was it the book of God, reopened and republished by the reformers? Take any period in this world's history and show when or where, in a solitary instance, Infidelity has ever raised the human mind from the gulf of ignorance and moral degrada- tion ; show where Infidelity first planted religion, or preserved it when planted, or revived it when it had declined, or purified it when it had been corrupted.* Show the spot made bright and fruitful by its boasted irradiations of light. "Where has it prevailed without producing darkness, sterility, and death? Need we speak of the actual experiment made in France not half a century ago ? Need we refer to the corruption of all ranks of her people ? Have we forgotten the goddess of rea- son, the temples of reason, the religion of reason, the abolition of the Sabbath, the proclamation of death as an eternal sleep, and God voted out of existence ? Have we forgotten that the reign of reason was the reign of terror ? I only ask, on this part of our subject, what are the effects of Infidelity in the hour of death? This is the hour of truth and honesty. Now comes a grand catastrophe, and what is that religion worth which condemns, and deserts, and betrays the soul at last. And what is the testimony then of dying in- fidels ? In whatever manner infidels die, the testimony fur- nished by their deaths, though circumstantially different, is, on the main fact, substantially the same. How many are their confessions, that Infidelity has been only the cause of profligacy, crime, and ruin ? How many criminals have avowed that In- fidelity is the cause of the crimes expiated by their ignomini- ous deaths ! How many have imprecated curses on the hour * Wilson. 378 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. in which they first saw an infidel book, or on the murderer of souls, who put it into their hands ! But who has heard a dying Christian,lament or curse the day in which he believed in his Saviour? How then does the infidel die? Does he die in obdurate insensibility ? Often. But what a state of mind to meet death with ! What is the question now in a moment to be decided? Whether Ins soul, with its stupendous powers is to be blasted into annihilation, expanded to the fruition of its God, or filled with endless despair and woe. And this soul, callous to its every interest, indifferent to its God, without a prayer for mercy, repelling every thought, suppressing every emotion that becomes a dying immortal — yes, a cherished, hardened insensibility, on the brink of eternity, and so soon to meet the God of eternity — asleep, for aught he knows or cares, on the brink of everlasting damnation! Does the infidel die in the pride and presumption which ventures on the footing of his merits to challenge the justice of his God? Thus died Rousseau claiming the favor of his Maker, and affirming that he returned him his soul pure and immaculate as he had received it ! What a lie — what daring of God to his face ! Does the infidel die in the careless levity of cold-hearted skepticism? Mr. Hume is our example. He amuses himself. He reads perhaps Don Quixotte, or the Tales of Genii. He laughs at death, joking about Charon and his boat, and the fabled Styx, and playing at his favorite game of whist. And on his death-bed finishes, what ? — his Essay on Suicide, vindi- cating self-murder. Thus dies the applauded hero of Infidelity ! Thus David Hume fell into the hands of the living God ! What an unnatural contempt of death and of the tribunal of the final Judge! Was it all pretense, or was it the brand of God's reprobation ? \ Or does the infidel die in the anguish of despair ? How nu- merous the examples — how agonizing their cries! How did Paine die? Under the compulsive power of conscience he declared, " That if the devil ever had had an agent on earth, he had been one." When his infidel friends said to him, "You have lived like a man," (lived like a man!) "and we hope you will die like one!" he said to one near him, " You see what miserable comforters I have." To the woman whom he had seduced from her husband, her friends, her religion, he THE INFIDEL AT DEATH. 379 said, "The principles I have taught you will not bear yon out." As death approached, he began to betray those terrors which before he laughed a't. lie would not be left alone night nor day, nor suffer his attendant to be out of his sight, and often for a long time together would exclaim in anguish, " O Lord, help me ! O Christ, help me!" Look now at the death of Voltaire. This prince of infidels is overwhelmed with terror! What does he think now of his infidel friends? "It is you," said he, " who have brought me to my present state — begone ! I could have done without you all." What now does he think of that Saviour he had pronounced " a wretch ?" Alternately he blasphemes God, and supplicates his mercy exclaiming, " O Christ, O Jesus Christ !" till his friends flew from his bedside horror-struck, declaring the sight too terrible to be borne."* I have no time, nor is there need for comment. I have only to ask, does philosophy, does human reason in that form of it called Infidelity, supersede the necessity of a revelation from God? What is Infidelity? In its fairest form, it is a theft on revelation, and yet refusing to wear the garb it has stolen, except to cover its own nakedness and shame ! It has no support in its real form, not the shadow of warrant from reason, but is a manifest defiance and contempt of all reason. It has no truth, no principles. It obliterates all distinction between right and wrong, and subverts the moral dominion of God. It denies his true character ; it proposes to give him neither honor, love nor service ; it despises holy affections, spiritual enjoyments, heavenly anticipations, and gives up the whole man to the dominion of the lower appetites, and the sensuality of earth and time. It forgets all connection with eternity and the God of eternity. Of heaven as a home, of eternal happiness in fellowship with God, it has no hope. Of hell as the place of his retributive wrath it has no fears. In a word, Infidelity is a total disruption of the human mind from the only living and true God — a wretched device for the in- dulgence of the worst propensities of a fallen spirit. Will such a system reform the world, or must we look to one which has upon it the stamp, the seal of truth, of God, of heaven? I need only state the third proposition, viz. : * Wilson, Lect. XXII. 380 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. 3. That a divine revelation is necessary to the discovery of some important truths which man could not discover with- out it. The important truths here referred to, are the doctrine of the Trinity, and those doctrines which depend on it, as the doc- trine of atonement made by the Son of God, and the renewing influence of the Spirit of God. In conclusion, allow me, my young friends, affectionately to entreat you to avoid Infidelity. I have briefly shown you what it is. Can it be true ? Can it be true that man, a crea- ture of God, and formed in his image, is left to live, and act, and die, under a system of faith, so fatal to the high end of his creation, so dishonorable to his Father in heaven, so full of dark despair to the soul? Let the infidel in his scorn for truth, and in the miserable pride of exalting beyond measure the light of reason, shut his eyes on the glories of Christianity. Let him hold up his feeble, fading taper kindled by the light of the sun of revelation ; let him pretend that it is his own, and try to extinguish the very luminary at which he lighted it. But be not deceived. Be not so lost to reason, to conscience, to the known end of your being, so lost to all experience, to truth, to God and all real good, as to listen to this empty declamation about human reason. Follow him not in his infatuated wan- derings. What does reason teach ? Reason employed on the nature of things, of God, of man, of all moral truth. Reason em- ployed on facts given in all experience. What does reason thus employed teach ? That Infidelity as it is, is false — that Chris- tianity, whether a revelation or not, as a moral system is true. Who does not feel his blood chill at that vain pride, that love of error and of sin, that can reject the moral system of Chris- tianity, and treat with scorn and sarcasm and objection, a sys- tem so full of hope and peace and joy to his own guilty spirit? Who does not know that if he embraces Infidelity as a prac- tical system, that his soul is lost, ruined, without help even from its God ? Who does not know that eternal truth binds such a soul in chains of everlasting darkness, guilt and woe ! Who does not know that in so doing he is playing at the despe- rate game of daring not only Almighty God, but everlasting truth ? That he forms a hell in his own bosom, that God can- not bless and save such a self-ruined immortal? Yield then to reason. Obey the truth. Put on this pan- CONCLUSION. 381 opoly,even the whole armor of God. Now in the beginning of life, in this season of temptation — in this condition of danger from the frivolity, the thoughtlessness, the vanity of youthful companions, remember God your Creator in the days of your youth. Religion is always an ornament. In youth it is a finish and a crown — it gives a charm to every accomplish- ment, a luster to every excellence ; and " rich are the tints of that beauty, and sweet the fragrance of those blossoms on which in the morning of life the Lord God sheds down the dews of his blessing." LECTURE XIII. Direct Argument. — Question proposed. — Preliminary remarks. — 1. Question to be decided by human reason. — Limits of reason. — Perversion of reason. — 2. Rational to bftlieve in divine origin of Christianity on low evidence. — Eolation of Christianity to our character and life. — Conclusions from this principle.— a. Unjust to demand high degree of evidence.— b. Shows the true cause of Infidelity. — c. The most promising method of convincing men of the truth. — rf. The reasonableness of faith in unlearned men.— 3. Common facts and principles must be assumed by all parties as premises of argument. — Illustrations. — How common premises may be fixed and agreed on. — Argument stated in four propositions. — First two have been previously proved. The inquiry now proposed is — Whether the system of religion contacted ln the Bible is from God ? Before however we enter into the investigation of this in- quiry, there are some preliminary topics which deserve a brief consideration. I remark then, 1. That the question proposed must be decided on the author- ity of human reason. Deistical writers have maintained that the belief of a divine revelation involves the renunciation of reason. This is a favorite topic with Bolingbroke, Yoltaire, Hume, and many others. " Our most holy religion," says Mr. Hume, " is founded on faith not on reason ; and it is a sure method of exposing it, to put it to such a trial as it is by no means fitted to endure." Well had it been for the cause of truth, had the professed friends of Christianity given no coun- tenance to this sentiment. Every enlightened friend of revela- tion will and must disclaim it. Christianity on its own author- ity is a reasonable service, and its demand on all its disciples is, " Be ready always to give an answer to every one that asketh you a reason of the hope that is in you." Reason is our only guide in religion, in examining the evidences of a revelation, in ascertaining its import, in believing its doctrines, and in obey- ing its precepts. If there ever was a religion addressed to human reason, and insisting that its every claim be adjudged at this tribunal, that religion is Christianity. Reason and TRUE USE OF REASON. 383 truth can never war with each other. Reason is that high and noble power, whose sole prerogative it is to discover truth, to weigh the evidence of truth and to receive it, and it is not in the nature of the human mind, to believe either what it does not understand, or what when understood, it regards as irra- tional or absurd. We may indeed very rationally believe that there is more in a thing than we understand. We may believe a fact, the mode, the how of which we do not comprehend, but then the mode, the how is not the object of our faith. Con- cerning this, having no understanding, we have and can have no faith. The true use of reason in matters of religion can easily be apprehended, if we would remember two things — one is, that man is not omniscient, and the other that he knows some- thing. Xot being omniscient, there are things which lie be- yond the grasp of his intellect, wdiich for aught he knows may be true or may be false, and in respect to such, while we have no evidence either of their truth or falsehood, reason forbids all faith. But if in respect to these things, evidence come to us, whether it be by extending our vision by a telescope, or whether it be by sufficient testimony of men who have seen what we have not seen, or by visitors to our planet from some other parts of the universe — or whether it be by God himself, or by messengers from God. I say, if we have legitimate evi- dence respecting things, which from the limitation of our knowl- edge we must admit may be true, then on the basis of such evidence, reason requires faith. To a well authenticated mes- sage from God on such matters, reason in the act of uncon- ditional surrender, appears in its true dignity, its highest glory. Who that knows what God is, can refuse to listen to a message which he believes comes from him ? True, if we could suppose a well authenticated message from God delivering known false- hood, then the case would be altered. We should have oppos- ing decisive evidence, truth opposing truth, reason in her own absolute infallibility giving opposite results — reason reduced to a quandary from which with all its boasted prowess there would be no deliverance — reason that is no longer reason, but a name of worthlessness and contempt. But reason is now supposed to be in a condition in which it cannot be reason. The case sup- posed can never be, if there is such a thing as reason. The exercise of reason giving results, implies truth and the evidence 384 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. of truth. There cannot be the former without the latter. A well authenticated message from God can no more deliver known falsehood, than two and two can be five. If it does, it is not from God; if it is from God it gives infallible truth. Eeason then having ascertained that God speaketh, must deem it its highest honor to bow to his declaration with implicit con- fidence. To oppose such a message with fancies and theories of our own devising, is an infamous violation of reason's pre- rogative, by exalting shameless ignorance to her throne — and as to being rational or philosophical, is as ridiculous as was ever schoolman with his quiddities, or a Cartesian with his whirl- pools. Further ; while there are some things which fall without, there are others that fall within the limits of human knowledge and human judgment. The human mind can and must judge of the truth and falsehood of many things for itself, in entire in- dependence of a revelation. And not only so, it can judge of truth and falsehood within given limits, and every item of its actual faith within these limits, shall be as truly rational as were man omniscient, The mind is made to know some things, and to believe some things. To refuse to confide in faith, or those judgments which are given by evidence, is to throw away and in effect to annihilate one part of the mind itself, that on which man is doomed to place reliance more exten- sively than on any other ; and he who does it, if he does not thereby in fact become, must expect in all equity to be esteemed, an idiot. This part of the mind is made to be used, and its results are as truly and properly to be confided in, as those of intuition or demonstration. Man then to a great extent can judge of truth and falsehood, of possible and impos- sible things, of evidence, its kinds, its weight absolute and comparative — particularly, he can judge of the merit and de- merit of testimony, as these depend on the character and cir- cumstances of the witness, and on the subject matter of what he testifies. He can judge of and perceive the truth and false- hood of such credentials as the performance of a miracle or the fulfilment of a prophesy, he can judge of the signs of honesty and veracity, of dishonesty and imposture, of mental imbe- cility and strength, of credulity and incredulity, of soundness of mind, and fanatical or enthusiastic illusion and extravagance, as these are indicated in the manner, the style, the tone, the WHAT CAN REASON DECIDE? 385 countenance, the intellectual operations, the benevolent design, the uncompromising principle, the undaunted constancy of the witness. lie can judge to a great extent of fitnesses and adap- tations, of the tendencies of the great principles of action in men and in God ; of what is right, what is wrong, of what man is made for, of what he is, and what he ought to be. lie can see what God is, what he has done and has not done, what he is doing, what he will do and what he will not do. All this to a great extent reason can do, has a right and is bound to do. Otherwise it matters not as to the rationality of our faith, whether we are Mahomedans, Boodhists, Infidels, or Christians. If reason can make no distinctions, discover no differences, con- fide in no judgments, it were as rational to be one thing as another, to confide in malignity as in benevolence, to receive the illusions of Satan as the inspirations of the Holy Ghost. Human reason too can judge of the subject matter of testi- mony, and this in every respect in which it is important to a sound and rational conclusion. It can decide in some cases what can be true, and what cannot be true ; and it can decide when it cannot decide either, and can thus assign a limit to its own decisions. It can settle the important previous question, wli ether the subject matter of the testimony lies within its antecedent knowledge, or whether it does not. If it does not, but comes to us as information from a region which reason has not explored, and from its own limitations cannot explore, then reason can judge whether in its own nature it be credible or in- credible. If incredible, it can and ought to reject it. If credi- ble, it can then judge whether the allegation be sustained by evidence or not. If not thus sustained, then again it can and ought to reject it ; if thus sustained, then why refuse to learn from one competent to instruct and entitled to confidence? Again, the subject matter may lie within our antecedent knowl- edge, and cases of this kind may be supposed to be very diverse. It may be one in which the knowledge communicated is in- significant and worthless in itself, or in which its communica- tion from heaven would be unnecessary and useless because already fully possessed and acted upon, or one in which the knowledge though highly useful is not possessed at all, or only partially and imperfectly, or in which the knowledge is possess- ed but perverted, and needs to be presented in some new and more impressive form, or it may be one in which the knowl- Vol. I.— 17. 25 386 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. edge is attainable only, but not attained, and never will be, ■without such a mode of communication, or it may be one which shall be characterized by several of these facts. Of the sub- ject matter, in all these respects human reason is competent to form the requisite judgment. On the contrary, the fact to be believed may be supposed to be utterly incredible in itself. For example, should the witness tell us that the planets do not revolve around the sun, that the sun itself does not shine, that the rivers do not run into the ocean, that the three angles of a triangle are not equal to two right angles, that a part is equal to the whole, or that man is a perfect being, loving God with all his heart, and his neighbor as himself, we should and we ought at once to confront him with our philosophical de- monstrations, our daily experience and observation, our own intuition and consciousness. Thus human reason can judge, has a right, and is bound to judge of each and every thing re- specting a revelation which has, or can have, any bearing on faith or no faith. Here is the prerogative, to sit in judgment on the credentials of heaven's ambassador, and on the message which he brings. When there is no evidence, let it have no faith. When there is evidence, let it judge according to evi- dence, and every item of its faith, whether in the form of assent or dissent, is as truly rational and trust-worthy as were its knowledge infinite. But reason may be perverted. Yes, and that is our concern, and its consequences will be ours. Reason may be perverted ; is reason then all our strength and all our reliance? Yes. But when I say this I mean reason ; not reason perverted. When I speak of and commend Christianity, I mean not a corrupted, false Christianity. When I speak of man, of his exaltation and dignity, of his noble powers, and the achievements of which he is capable, I mean not a corpse corrupted in its grave. Reason perverted is not reason, it is folly, madness. And be- cause reason may be perverted, is it therefore not all our re- liance and all our strength in the discovery of truth ? Reason may be perverted, and therefore is not to be used! What then, in the name of reason, shall we use ? Answer, in the name of reason, and not use your reason, if you can. Or an- swer with self-consistency, and say our folly, and you are welcome to the results. What nonsense to pretend to prove by reason that there is no reliance on reason ! LOW DEGREE OF EVIDENCE. 387 2. It may be rational to believe in the divine origin of Chris- tianity, on the supposition of a comparatively low degree of evidence of the fact. Those who reject Christianity have often insisted that a peculiarly high degree of evidence is requisite, to warrant faith in the divine origin of this system of religion. This claim is based on the principle, that a benevolent God in giving a religion to men, on the reception or rejection of which such tremendous consequences depend, would not fail to furn- ish such a degree of evidence as would infallibly secure human belief. To this I reply, that it either proceeds on the principle that faith can be compelled by evidence, to the entire exclusion of disbelief, or it does not. If it does, it rests on a false princi- ple. The human mind can disbelieve, and has disbelieved, against the highest probable, and even against demonstrative evidence. Besides a compelled faith would be utterly incon- sistent with moral responsibility on the part of man. "What moral worth, what respect for God or confidence in his charac- ter would be involved in a faith which a man could not shun nor avoid. Nor is this all, it is in fact claiming that the whole system of Christianity shall be changed from a moral system to one of physical influence, and of course that it shall neither be right to receive nor wrong to reject it. The act of reception would be of physical necessity, not moral obedience. Is it then said, that the evidence might be so increased as to secure faith without compulsion ? I answer, that any supposable increase of evidence, instead of securing faith, might prove the greatest calamity, since for aught that appears, men might still reject that evidence and thus greatly augment the guilt of unbelief. Suppose then, that when Christianity was introduced into the world, it had been written in the heavens above us in letters of light and fire so that all the dwellers on earth would read it, " Christianity is a revelation from God," this would have compelled the faith of men to the exclusion of disbelief, or it would not. If it would, then it would have been inconsistent with a moral system, and faith itself had been no virtue. If it would not, then like any other miracle, as that of the rend- ing rocks, the opening graves, the rising dead, the quaking earth and darkened sun, it might have only aggravated the guilt of every unbeliever. We are therefore utterly incompe- tent to decide what would be the dictate of benevolence in the case. The rn'oper question for us then, is not what a benevo- 388 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. lent God would do, but what it is rational for ns to do, in view of what he has actually done. Or, to present the question which I now wish to examine, more precisely — is it rational on our part to believe in the divine origin of Christianity, on the supposition of a comparatively low degree of evidence of the fact? The infidel then will not complain, if we impute to him the opinion, that the religion which he takes so much pains to de- stroy, is unfriendly, or at least unnecessary to human happiness. Nor, if he can make good this opinion, shall we have any con- troversy with him in respect to the reasonableness of his demand for a higher degree of evidence that this religion is from God. Such a religion would, in its very nature, furnish a strong pre- sumption against its divine origin, and a very high degree of evidence be fairly required to counteract, if indeed any degree could counteract, such a presumption. But if a religion demands our faith in its divine origin, and if to believe it divine, is obviously, and in every respect essen- tial to our true and best interests, then the case is materially changed. It is a common mistake, that a man's interest ought to have no influence on his faith. There are cases in which it removes presumptive evidence to the contrary, and even be- comes evidence of truth. Were one of you to be told that your father had disinherited you in his will, it would require more evidence to make you believe it, than if you were told that he had bequeathed to you your portion of his estate. True it undoubtedly is, that his interest should never leact him to believe without, or against evidence. But sound reason often dictates faith, and faith that shall be practical, in view of what may be termed comparatively very slight evidence. If in a particular case my interest will not be injured by believing — if it may he greatly injured by not believing, and if it may he essentially promoted by believing, then to believe on the ground of slight evidence, so far as to control action, is the dictate of sound reason. That this principle of faith is the dictate of sound reason and common sense, may be shown by its universal application in all the affairs of human life. A scheme for the accumulation of wealth occurs to the merchant, which can result in no possible loss, which may produce large acquisition, and which, neglected, may involve him in ruin. A sick man may soon die, unless SUPPOSE OUR "WELL-BEING IS CONCERNED. 389 some proposed remedy be used ; the use of it can do no pos- sible injury, but may restore him to health. Now what is the dictate of reason in respect to faith — that degree of faith which is necessary to action — however slight the evidence or proba- bility, if it be real evidence, that a good result will be secured ? Ought such evidence to be rejected or disregarded ? Would that be sound reason ? But in the case before us, we have in- terests at stake immeasurably more momentous. We are con- fessedly in the hands of an Almighty Being, and at his disposal forever. A system of religion, claiming to be from Him, is in our possession, and demands our faith in its divine origin, on the alternative of endless happiness or endless misery. To be- lieve it to be divine, we will now suppose, can result in no real evil, but may result in immeasurable good ; not to believe it to be divine may result in immeasurable evil. Who can ration- ally hesitate what to believe, be the balance of probability from other sources in support of the divine origin of this religion ever so small ? The case would be still stronger, if we were here to assume (what would be perfectly legitimate, in view of our former conclusions,) viz., that to yield to the practical influence of Christianity is indispensable to man's highest happiness in this world. Nor would it be too much to assume, as a point con- ceded by the most respectable infidel authors, that the practical tendency of Christianity is to perfect man in character and in happiness. If then we suppose that a man may conform his character substantially to this system of religion, without be- lieving it to be divine, still it is undeniable that such a faith would secure to it a far higher and more perfect influence. I may go farther still. If we suppose there is no evidence to the fact of the divine origin of this religion, except that which arises from its perfect adaptation to man's moral perfection and consequent happiness, it were the highest, noblest act of reason to believe. And further still, on the supposition of this per- fect adaptation to this high end, I say, if Christianity be a de- lusion, disturb not my faith in its divine origin. If falsehood is better than truth, then let us have falsehood. As a moral being, who has much to enjoy and to hope for in time, and who may live onward in the ages of eternity, I cannot dispense with the influence of such a faith, nor abandon its consolations and its prospects. 390 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. I might add did our limits allow, that on the supposition of a low degree of evidence for Christianity, while more proof might be useless and worse than useless, there may be great advantages in exactly that degree of evidence which God has furnished. Particularly, it may be one benignant part of that system of moral discipline by which our honesty and integrity of principle are to be tried and confirmed, by which men are to be made considerate, impartial, and attentive to every degree of evidence ; to be kept from levity, and contempt, and ridicule, on a subject on which their eternal well-being, and that of a world, may depend. If the principle of faith which I have now presented be rational, it shows the following things, viz. : (1.) The injustice of the demand for any peculiarly high de- gree of evidence in favor of Christianity as the only legitimate ground of faith. (2.) It shows the true cause of Infidelity in those who make this demand for higher evidence, viz., that they do not regard Christianity as adapted to promote their true and best inter- ests, and that they do not like it as a system of religion. It involves, in their view, a derangement of their plans, and a thwarting of their inclinations. I am not now saying whether they are right or wrong in this opinion, but simply that such must be their opinion. For when was it known that a man dis- believed against even the slightest balance of probability, while he fully regarded it for his interest, in every respect, to believe? (3.) It shows what, in many cases, is the most promising method of convincing men of the divine origin of Christianity, viz., to show them its adaptation to man's present and future well-being. If such be the real nature of this religion, its re- ception or rejection must depend greatly on its being seen and understood to be what it really is. As long as the thing itself is not understood, its rejection, if not rational, is not strange, but easily accounted for. Why should a man receive a system of religion of which he knows nothing, merely because some one tells him it is from heaven? Kay more; why should he even examine the question of its divine origin ? He sees no- thing in its nature or its adaptations that give any importance to the question, whether it come from heaven or not ; nothing of course, to render it worth a demonstration. And if with this ignorance of the thing itself, we suppose the conviction to REAL IMPORT OF THE SCRIPTURES. 391 be associated of its utter uselessness, and even of hostile tend- ency to good results, why should such a mind, with these views of the matter, care to know what the evidence of its divine origin is ? By what asseverations of the divine origin of Ma- homedanism could you induce the population of New Eng- land seriously to examine the question ? But now suppose a man to become well acquainted with the Bible, and to find that the book actually develops the most perfect system of means for the accomplishment of the most perfect conceivable end — a mighty scheme for a mighty pur- pose — a scheme and a purpose worthy of an infinite being, nothing less than a scheme or system of means to secure to a world of his intelligent and immortal creatures, perfection in character and perfection in happiness. Suppose him to see that the scheme is as simple as it is grand, as perfect in its adaptation as it is glorious in its end, as indispensable as it is useful — that it is so in the very nature of things, that it is and must be so from the very constitution of the human mind, and that the belief of it as divine has as direct a tendency to secure the result in the absolute perfection of every human being, as the belief of danger to produce alarm, or the prospect of good, the desire and pursuit of it. I ask, would not such a man be very apt to say, " I shall examine the evidence of the divine origin of this book, here is something worthy of such an origin, every presumption that it is the imposture of empirics, villains and enthusiasts is removed — it may be from God, it comports with his character, it is the very thing and the only thing fitted to accomplish the design of Him who made man, it is that, and exactly that which a benignant Creator would do for his own creatures — my highest, best immortal interest may depend on the question — I must see and know whether God has done this thing or not." I am not now saying what the result of such an examination would be, but that without some just knowl- edge of what Christianity is, no man will examine the question of its divine origin, and with such knowledge, no man who has not become reckless of God, and of his own immortal nature and immortal interests will refuse to examine it. It may be from God, all it says of God may he true, all it says of the Sav- iour, of the miracles of his power and grace, of the scenes of immortality and retribution — all it says of those who believe not may he true. He who refuses with this tremendous perad- 392 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. venture in view, despises God, despises a soul, the next greatest thing to God, and that soul is his own. (4.) It shows the reasonableness of faith in that great num- ber of believers in Christianity, who do not and who cannot consistently with the other duties of life, become acquainted with but a small part of the evidence on the question. Of this class of men not one in a thousand has the leisure, or the talents, or the learning requisite to examine and weigh one-half of the evidence, especially what is called the external evidence. What qualification have the greater part of believers in Chris- tianity to enter into the controversy with Hume or Yoltaire ? And have they therefore no reasonable faith? Have the common people no reason to believe the almanac because they are not astronomers — to believe that an eclipse will happen as foretold because they are incompetent to calculate an eclipse themselves ? Have the same class of men no reason to believe that boats and locomotives are propelled by steam, because the jmilosopher has evidence that it must be so, which they have not ? Plainly we may have sufficient evidence of truth with- out having all that which others possess. And in the present case, the author of the gospel may have intended that its great object and end and its perfect adaptation to that end, should be its chief evidence, especially to the great mass of mankind. Of this they may be perfectly competent judges. This, according to the laws of evidence, may be altogether sufficient to an honest, while more would be utterly insufficient to a dishonest mind, and while to neglect this, may be to neglect the very ground on which God has rested the proof, and required belief of by far the greater part of mankind. Accordingly, I hope to show that from the Bible alone, in the adaptation of its con- tents to man's perfection in character and happiness, a most conclusive argument may be derived that it is from God, one on the strength of which the unlettered peasant, ignorant as lie is of all history, and destitute as he is of all learning, shall be more rational in his belief than Hume, Yoltaire and Gib- bon in their unbelief with all their scholarship. (5.) If the principle of faith before stated be rational, it will enable us to form a juster estimate of the amount of the actual evidence, and to see how abundant and overwhelming it must be to a well balanced mind. Nothing is more remote from the truth than the supposed confession by the advocates of Chris- VARIETY OF ARGUMENTS. 393 tianity, that it rests its claim on a low degree of evidence. So far from it, there is scarcely any single question on which in their view evidence may be so accumulated. Witness " the piles of authorship," not merely as made up of repetitions, hut of divers arguments resting on independent grounds, and drawn from distinct sources. Let the works of Butler, of Lardner, of Paley, of Wilson, of Erskine, of Gregory, and many other modern authors, tell how in the estimation of the friends of Christianity, its proofs have been augmented in later times and down to the present hour. It is not then to he as- sumed,thsit the claim for the divine origin of Christianity rests on any thing like a low degree of evidence. It is a question to be tried, a question not to be disposed of in favor of such a claim, till some hundredth or thousandth part of the evidence shall be examined and overthrown by those who make it. If any considerable part of the evidence offered and relied on is substantial, then indeed it is abundant and overwhelming. iSTay more; there is evidence in every form, of every kind and degree which can be well imagined on the subject ; evi- dence, in the language of another, fitted alike for " the high achievement of silencing Infidelity in the lofty and academic walks of life, as well as to carry Christianity into workshops and cottages." Christianity in the fullness of her strength, if one-half of what is claimed for her be true, has arguments for Jew and Gentile, for bond and free, for men of a false religion and men of no religion — arguments " by which she may con- front the powers of literature, and compel the most arrogant of her disciples to do her homage, and those also by which her ministers from the pulpit may spread a well grounded faith amidst the multitude of the people." I am not now saying that such evidence does in fact, but only that it is claimed to exist ; and that on the true principle of rational faith, if only a considerable part of what is claimed, does exist and is substantial evidence, then it is abundant and even overwhelming, to an enlightened and well-balanced mind. 3. While it is essential to a fair argument on the question of a revelation from God, that the facts and principles which constitute the premises should be mutually understood and admitted by the parties, it is true that to a considerable ex- tent they are not thus understood and admitted. These facts 17* 394 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. are very numerous, and while some of them are understood and admitted by the parties, others are not, and others only in some general respects, but not in those on which the con- clusion depends. I need not say, that it is to no purpose that the parties reason in such a case for the conviction of one another. In my own view, the fact that there has been so much of this mode of argumentation, is a principal reason that this controversy has not long since been terminated, so far as its continuance has depended on any show of argument. I say not whose fault it is. But so much is undeniable, that the premises of the argument, if any thing is accomplished by reasoning, must be understood and admitted by the parties. What is not understood must be explained, and if denied must be proved or abandoned. To see the bearing of these remarks let us take a case. Suppose you have received a letter from another, having the signature of your father, and the question should arise, whether it is actually written by him. Now to take the question ah in- itio', if you have no father, the debate is ended before it can be really begun. If you have a father, then there is room for the question whether the letter be from him. Again, if you have a father, and yet there is some absolute impossibility that he should be the author of the letter, or of any letter whatever, this precludes all further debate ; while if the possibility of his writing a letter be admitted, then the question in this respect is open for discussion. Again, let it be supposed that he is one of the wisest and most affectionate of parents, and that the letter, in respect to its contents, is wholly and even contempti- bly useless and unnecessary, as advising you to eat and drink and breathe, if you would live; or suppose that without any sufficient cause or reason, and under pretexts known to be en- tirely groundless, it consists of threatenings to injure you — even to withdraw all support and kindness, and to cast you out as a disinherited exile; suppose that in one of these respects the contents of the letter are absolutely irreconcilable with the known character of the father, here again there is a strong presumption against the supposed authorship. Again, let it be supposed that the father is not only most judicious and affec- tionate, but a man of high literary and scientific acquisitions ; that he is, above all things, intent to secure the scholarship of LETTER FROM A FATHER TO HIS SON". 395 his son, and peculiarly competent to aid him in attaining the highest literary eminence, and that the letter is written in sub- servience to this object ; that it contains counsels, directions, inducements, and information, which are peculiarly fitted, and even necessary, to secure the end on which his heart is set ; in a word, it is just such a letter as such a father in such circum- stances would write to such a son, and you perceive some of the strongest reasons for believing that he actually wrote it. Again, as we suppose certain other things to be true or not to be true — the handwriting, the style, the manner, &c, &c, to be or not to be those of the father ; or the letter to contain or not to contain allusions, implications, coincidences, statements of facts, of a certain character — these things, as they may be supposed to be or not to be, would have an important bearing on the question. Again ; let it be supposed that the letter de- clares, that for the purpose of placing the authenticity of the letter itself beyond all reasonable doubt, that the father has done what in the case would be deemed a very singular and extraordinary thing — something which neither he nor any other man ever did before — something indeed, which if done would settle the question, but which, in your view of the case, it is absolutely incredible that he should do — so incredible, that no evidence, especially no testimony, can, in your view, when simply placed and balanced against its inherent incredibility, be esteemed sufficient proof that he has done it, and yet that the authenticity of the letter is made to depend on the fact that he has done this very thing. Here again is something which bears against the alleged source of the letter. But now again, in view of the high importance and even necessity of your believ- ing it to be from your father, in order to accomplish its object, let us imagine what was not before supposed, that your father is fully apprised of some cause, some peculiar structure of your mind, some propensity or mode of thinking, that will prevent you from believing the letter to come from him without the supposed extraordinary marks of its authenticity ; and that he knows, and that you and others know, if the object of the let- ter is to be attained, this is altogether the best way to attain it. Now, in view of the father's ardent and supreme desire to accomplish the object, there arises a strong presumption that he will adopt the very method, which, under another view of 396 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. the case, appeared so entirely incredible ; for yon now see a reason why he should do it, even one which renders it almost incredible that he should not. Thus you see how, on the supposition of one kind of prem- ises, the mind is led to one conclusion, and on the supposition of another kind, to the opposite conclusion, respecting the sup- posed origin of the letter. Just so it is in respect to the great question, whether God has given a revelation to man. The cases are entirely analogous. And the force of an argument for a divine revelation on each individual mind will depend on the views which that mind has of what God is, what his char- acter is, what his relations to man are, what he has done, and what he has not done, what is and what is not his great end in man's creation, and what are his particular designs toward him ; what he will do to accomplish his designs; what man is, what his character is, what his relations and his destiny are; and what the Bible is, what it is in its design, adaptation and tend- ency, and how it agrees or disagrees with the character of God and with his relations and designs toward man. It is only as we understand these things, that we^are competent to make an argument on this subject, or to judge of one when it is made. It is only as the parties in this controversy understand and are agreed in these great facts and principles respecting God, and man, and the Bible, that they are prepared to enter on the dis- cussion with any prospect or hope of advantage. How could any man be a competent judge of the question concerning the supposed letter, who knew nothing of the character, the designs, the relations of the father, nothing of the son, and nothing of the contents of the letter ? You see then, that unless the par- ties in the present discussion are agreed in the premises, the discussion must be fruitless. Now I readily admit, that in many of the facts which con- stitute the premises they are agreed, but I maintain that in many others they are not ; and that so long as they are not, the argument for the divine origin of Christianity must prove in- effectual. I said they are agreed in some of the premises. They agree that there is a God of infinite natural perfection ; that he is a being of a perfect moral character, or infinitely benevolent, disposed to secure the greatest amount of happi- ness which in the nature of things he can secure; they agree that he is the providential governor of the world, and, as the PARTIES NOT ENTIRELY AGREED. 397 omniscient author of all tilings, his providential will must ex- tend to all actual beings and events ; they may also agree that he is the moral governor of men, in some very general and indefinite sense. But in respect to the particular nature of the government which God exercises over this world, and therefore in respect to the precise method, way, or means by which God aims to secure the happiness of his creatures, whether it in- volves necessarily in the nature of things, a perfect moral gov- ernment of free moral agents by law, with a strict adherence to all the peculiar principles and influences of such a system as the best means of the best end ; and if it does, whether such a system does or does not in its own nature involve the existence of evil, natural and moral, and whether it does or does not in its own nature preclude the final termination of all evil — whether there is a future state, and whether we have any means of deciding what will be man's condition hereafter— what hopes and what fears he would be authorized to entertain from the light of nature, — whether man, without a revelation, would or could, on the basis of evidence, look forward with cheering anticipations to the future, or whether he would be compelled by the most decisive evidence only to forebode a fearful hour of retribution — on these, and many other main questions, the parties are not agreed. Ko one can have at- tentively read the controversy on both sides of this great question, without seeing that one of the parties reasons on one set of premises and principles, and the other party on another. Were we to see an artificer employed in constructing a ma- chine, though we were ignorant of its nature and its design, still, if we knew that he was neither deficient in power, skill, materials, or disposition to finish it, but was fixed and immuta- ble in his resolution to give it ultimately, and as rapidly as the case allows, its highest perfection, we should have no doubt that the machine, whatever it might be, would be finished, and the end proposed accomplished. Again ; if now we suppose the purpose or end aimed at to be ascertained, this at least, in many cases, would give us the means which he would adopt, or was adopting, to accomplish his end. If his object was to propel a boat through the water, we should expect him, in these days, to make a steam-engine. If his object was to see what is to be seen in the moon, we 398 ARGUMENT PROM NATURE APPLIED. should expect liim to make a telescope; or if it was to mark the divisions of time, we should expect him to make a watch or a clock. Again, let ns now suppose that the machine is so far ad- vanced, that any competent judge can decide beyond all mis- take, both what the machine is, and what is its object or end. Then also such a jndge can decide with entire confidence in respect to many particular things ivhich will be done and vihich will not be done by the artificer, in order to complete the machine and accomplish his end. Let it now be supposed that you and I are spectators of the progress of the work, and this particular question to arise between us and to engage us in fierce debate, viz., whether the machine when finished will contain a main-spring or not f And let us further suppose, that although there is in fact no reason to doubt on the point, that by some strange obliquity or imbecility of mind on the part of one of us, we are not agreed as to what the machine is, and you insist that the man is making a telescope, and I insist that he is making a watch. Xow to what purpose shall we discuss the question concerning the main-spring, unless we can settle the preliminary question, whether the artificer is in fact making a watch or a telescope ? And how can the debate be prolonged a moment with the least show of reason until this previous question is correctly decided ? Substantially like this, in my view, is the state of the con- troversy between the opposers and the advocates of a divine revelation. The former have such views of the character of God, of his object and end in the creation and govern- ment of this world, and especially of the means he has actu- ally adopted to accomplish this end, that they can no more see a reason why God should give a revelation to men, and such a revelation as the Bible is supposed to contain, than why a skillful artificer should insert a main-spring or a pend- ulum in a telescope. Hence their constant asseveration — it is utterly impossible, or if obliged to qualify a little by being reminded of God's omnipotence, and of the manifestation of his direct agency in creation, still they affirm that consider- ing the character and designs of God, and the object and na- ture of Christianity, it is irrational, even utterly incredible, that it should be the subject of a direct interposition from heaven. The advocates of Christianity however from their premises WHAT MAN CAN KNOW. 399 come to the directly opposite conclusion. With their views of the character of God, of his great object and end in the crea- tion and government of this world of intelligent beings, and especially of the means or system which he has adopted for the accomplishment of this end, there is the same reason to conclude that God would give a revelation to the world, and the very revelation claimed, which there is for concluding that the supposed artificer in making a watch, would insert a main- spring to complete the instrument. Why should not God as well as man give completeness to the means of an end ? But here we come to another vital question, viz., is man comjM- tent to say what God will do and what he will not do f Is not the subj ect altogether too high for us ? When we think what God is, of the eternity of his government, and of our distance from all direct and personal observation of him and the depth of his counsels, are not the form and mode of the management of his empire, wholly inaccessible to all our faculties ? I answer, if this indeed be so, then let us cease all inquiry, for to what purpose is it to in- quire or reason or form opinions where nothing can be known ? If it is all darkness here, then it is as dark to the infidel as to the Christian, and if the Christian cannot say what God will do, the infidel cannot say what he will not do. We may be right or we may be wrong in our conclusions, and that is all that can be said of the matter. But is it credible that a benevolent God has doomed his dependent creatures — creatures who know that their all depends on what God will or will not clo, to the darkness and agony of utter uncertainty. Can it be that the almighty and supreme disposer of all destiny has given us no intimation of his designs ? True indeed it is, that man is in- competent to say in many respects what God will or will not do ; but in other resj)ects, and we may safely say in all which are important to man's well-being, man is competent to say what God will and what God will not do. The great point here undoubtedly is to distinguish what we can know or prove, from that which we cannot know or prove. And what I maintain is, that we can do this to such an extent as to furnish the sure premises of irrefragable argumentation on the most momentous of all questions to man, viz., what must be his destiny and on what it depends ? Kor should it be forgotten, that the argument must of course be confined ex- clusively to what we do know or can prove ; and that we are 400 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. to place no reliance on what we do not know, ignorance being alike incompetent to make either an objection or an argument. The premises being conceded, all they involve and give, must be conceded also. If there is a benevolent God, then man can say, if such a God does any thing, what he does will be better than to do nothing. If he proposes an end, it will be the best end which he can accomplish. If he adopts the means of ac- complishing an end, the means will be the best which he can adopt. If man can know what the best end is, as he most assuredly can, viz., the highest well-being of all, and if man can also ascertain what are the necessary and best means of accomplishing this end, then he can say that God will pro- pose this end and adopt these means. If man can ascertain that a perfect God has actually adopted a given system of means for a given end, then can he say that system is the best. If man can know that any practicable thing is either essentially or circumstantially necessary to the perfection of this system of means, then also he can say God will do that. Thus knowledge gives knowledge, if w T e know one thing we know another — if we know what a triangle is, we may know its angles to be equal to two right angles — if we know that whiteness exists, we know also that there is something white. On the contrary, if that knowledge is wanting which is necessary to further knowledge, then of course such further knowledge will not ex- ist. If I know that one has made a watch, then I know what a watch is ; and knowing what a watch is, I know it has a main-spring — if it answers the purpose for which it is made, I know it must be wound up, and if I also know either that no one could, or that no one would do this but the maker, and know that it has been done, then I know that he has done it. But if I do not know any one of these things on which my knowledge of another thing depends, then I do not know the latter. In the same manner is our knowledge of God and of his doings more or less extended or limited. If we know or can prove certain things concerning God, then we can know and prove certain other things, and are as truly competent to say in such cases what God will do and what he will not do, as we are in like cases to say what a man will do, and w T hat he will not do. Xor can I dismiss the topic here. To maintain the doctrine of this necessary ignorance of God on the part of man, is not WHAT MAN CAN KNOW. 401 only to provide a refuge from the power of truth, it is to sub- vert all reasoning respecting God and the relations subsisting between God and his creatures. Whether there be a God or not, whether he be omnipotent, wise and good or not, are things of no importance for man to know, and for this decisive reason, such knowledge gives no results. On this principle God might as well be without power, without intellect, without goodness — the idolater's god — a thing "which the smith fash- ioneth with tongs and with hammers," or such as the prophet supposed who " perad venture sleepeth or is on a journey," as a being of infinite perfection. If we cannot say what God will and will not do, then there would be as much ground for love, for confidence, for hope, for joy in one sort of deity as an- other, and to see omnipotent malignity or even blind chance on the throne of the universe, would be as sufficient a basis for exultation and joy, as to behold a perfect God reigning there ; for whatever perfection be ascribed to him, there is no telling what he will do and what he will not do. On the other hand, if we know that it were better or more desirable that there should be one sort of deity than another, and better simply and solely because by knowing what he is, we can know to some extent what he will do and what he will not do, then we also know that the doing of some things is bet- ter than the doing of some other things. And knowing these things we know yet more. We know that a perfect God see- ing the end from the beginning, and being immutable in his purposes, will accomplish his plans, and carry them on and out with all possible perfection to their results. And when the plan or system of things is actually adopted and developed to our inspection in its essential characteristics, we can tell what it is and what it is not. We can decide whether it is a system of mere physical agents, whether God reigns merely over mate- rial forms and animal life and sensation, and is the spectator only of the laws of matter and the acts of instinct, or whether he has adopted a moral system, and reigns over it according to the principles and laws of such a jurisdiction. The argument for a divine revelation materially depends on the fact that God is administering a perfect moral government over man. The proposition to be proved from this source is, that the SYSTEM OE RELIGION CONTAINED IN THE BlJJLE IS FROM GoD. 26 402 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. The argument divides itself into the following propositions : I. God administers a perfeet moral government over men. II. By the administration of this government, God proposes or decrees to reform and bless a great multitude of our race. III. The importance and necessity of a revelation to the ac- complishment of this end, create a strong probability or a moral certainty that God would give a revelation to men. IY. That which is claimed to be a revelation from God, and which is contained in the Bible, is what it claims to be. The first two of these propositions have been sufficiently dis- cussed in preceding lectures. We need only consider the two which remain. LECTURE XIV. Direct Argument continued. — Two remaining propositions considered. — Prop. 3. The importance of revelation renders it probable, if not certain, that God would give a revelation. — Opposed by some. — Their views discussed. — Man not competent to decide on the manner, &c, of revelation. Recapitulation of argument on necessity of revelation. — Prop. 4. That which claims to be a revelation, is what it claims to be. — Conclusion. Our third leading position is the following, viz. : The impor- tance and necessity of a revelation to the accomplishment of the great end of God in the creation and government of this world, furnish a strong probability, not to say a moral certainty, that God would give a revelation to men. In the present lecture I propose to establish this position, and also briefly the fourth, viz. : IV. That which is claimed to be a revelation from God, and which is contained in the Bible, is what it claims to be. I proceed then to establish the third leading position, viz. : III. The importance and necessity of a revelation to the accomplishment of the end of God in the creation and govern- ment of this world, furnish a strong probability, not to say a morcd certainty, that God would give a revelation to men. This position has to encounter a strong prejudice, which I have already had occasion to notice in another connection. Among the advocates of revelation, there are those who would rely wholly on what is called the external evidence of Christian- ity. They tell us " that we are utterly unable to say what God w T ill do, and what he will not do; that the subject is altogether too high for us; that we have had experience of what man will do in given circumstances, but we have had no experience of what God will do in given circumstances ; and that to pretend to determine what God will do, or what he will not do, in any given circumstances, is an act of glaring rebellion against the authority of the Baconian philosophy." That none of those 4CM: ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. defenders of Christianity, who have relied on the internal evi- dence, have violated the true principles of reasoning, I am not concerned to show. Be this as it may, the above opinion, in the broad and unqualified form of statement in which it is pre- sented, is utterly incredible, as well as destitute of the least claim to the true mode of philosophizing. For to what pur- pose is it to inquire, or reason, or form opinions at all concern- ing the acts and the doings of God, if nothing can be known or concluded on the subject? What matter is it who or what God is, if from our knowledge of what He is, we can in no re- spect infer what he will do and what he will not do ? Why is it that these men, who so zealously contend for an exclusive reliance on the external evidence of Christianity, are so suspi- cious of all attempts to decide what God will do and will not do ? Do they themselves not believe that a perfect God, if he professes to give a revelation to man, will speak truth in that revelation? Do they not believe that a perfect God will not work miracles in attestation of falsehood ? And is not this inferring and believing what God will do and will not do, in given circumstances ? At least in two respects then, let them qualify their broad and sweeping position. Besides, are these two the only respects in which we are competent to say what God will do and what he will not do ? If there are no other acts or doings which we can surely and safely affirm that a perfect God will perform, how can we ever prove that there is a perfect God ? And if we cannot prove this by his acts and his doings, and this on the principle that a perfect God will do some things and will not do other things, then how can we know that he is a perfect God, or, if he gives a professed revelation, that he will speak truth ; or if he works miracles, that he does not work them in attestation of false- hood ? The plain matter of fact is, that there are two modes of reasoning in respect to intelligent voluntary beings, which are alike founded in experience, and accord with the Baconian philosophy. Thus, in certain cases, experience fully authorizes us to reason from the acts of voluntary beings to their charac- ter, their principles, their designs, and to determine what these are. In other cases, having ascertained the latter from their acts and doings in some respects, experience fully authorizes us to reason from these to their acts and their doings in other re- spects, and to determine what these will be and will not be. OBJECTION TO INTEIINAL EVIDENCE. 405 If I know that an artificer lias begun to make a watch, with adequate power and skill to finish and give it the highest per- fection, and if I know him to possess an unfaltering firmness of purpose, I may infer that he will perfect what he has begun, as particularly, that he will insert a main-spring in the watch. And further, if I know that he is fully resolved to secure in the most perfect degree possible to him the true use of the watch ; and if I know that he is making, or has actually made it for the use of another, who will never understand its true use un- less the maker instructs him, then I may infer that he will give this instruction; and if the requisite instruction respecting the true use of the watch should be liable to, or should be foreseen to be actually connected with some incidental evil, still it is quite supposable, that the maker should evince, in the most decisive manner, an inflexible purpose to give not only the highest per- fection to the watch, but' to every thing which can be regarded as the means of its perfection; so that if the end fails in any degree to be accomplished, it shall be seen that the failure is in no respect truly and properly attributable to any thing which he has done or failed to do. That such premises give such conclusions respecting man is obvious ; they can do no less in respect to God, when it is remembered that he is a Being absolutely and immutably perfect. If then we can know or prove certain things concerning God, then we can know and prove certain other things con- cerning him, and are, in view of the immutability of his pur- poses, more competent to say what God will do and what he will not do in given circumstances, than we are to decide the same things in respect to man. If we can know or prove what the best end of creation is, as we most assuredly can — viz., the highest well-being of all — and if avc can also ascertain what are the necessary and best means of accomplishing this end, then we can say that a perfect God will propose this end and adopt these means of accomplishing it. And further, if we can know or prove that any practicable thing is either essentially or circumstantially necessary to the perfection of this system of means, or to secure the end in the most perfect degree possible to him, then we can infer, that notwithstanding any incidental evils, he will give perfection to this system of means. It is not true, then — it is indeed utterly incredible, that a benevolent God has doomed his moral creation, even 406 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. under the light of nature, to the darkness and agony of utter uncertainty in respect to what he will do and what he will not do. The supposition, as it would be easy to show, subverts all natural and all revealed theology. But here let me not be misunderstood. I am not saying, if we were to assume simply that God is benevolent, that we could, with no knowledge of his doings, make the same sure inferences which we can now make. I readily concede also, that man in his actual condition is wholly incompetent to say, in many respects, or in respect to many things, what God will do and what he will not do. The great point is to distinguish what man, in his actual condition, can know or prove, from what he cannot know or prove, respecting the doings of God. The presumption that fearlessly ventures to dogmatize its de- cisions in the dark, and the timidity that rejects truth in the broad daylight of evidence, are alike reprehensible. To come then to the particular inquiry before us, can we dis- tinguish what cannot be known or proved from what can be known or proved in respect to God's giving a revelation to this world? What I maintain is, that we can do this to such an extent as to decide with entire confidence that God would give a revelation to man; and from this fact, and in view of the nature, the adaptations and actual results of that system of religion which is contained in the Scriptures, we must con- clude that Christianity is a revelation from God. To prevent misapprehension then, and the confounding of one thing with another, I would here explicitly concede that we may be wholly incompetent to say in what manner God would give a revelation to man, or at what time, or to what ex- tent. In these respects we may be unable through the want of all requisite premises to form any conclusion. More particu- larly in regard to the time when God would do this, I would say, that under the mere light of nature, we might be ignorant whether the revelation would be made in this or a future state. Human reason might be utterly incompetent to judge whether man's probation would not continue after death, and whether further discoveries of religious and moral truth would not be deferred to some indefinite period of man's future existence. In regard to the manner, we may be incompetent to deter- mine whether it will be orally or by writing, by the ministry of men or of some superior agents, or even by a direct com- THINGS WHICH WE CANNOT KNOW. 407 munication from himself. Li regard to the extent, we may be unable to say, whether he will give it to all men of all ages and nations, or only to a part of the race. Still we can say that he will give it to such an extent, as shall be sufficient to prevent the utter defeat and frustration of his design in adopting the system. If he does not give a revelation to some extent, this design will wholly fail. We must conclude there- fore that he will give a revelation to some extent, and to that degree which will best subserve his benevolent end, though we cannot determine what that extent is. In maintaining there- fore that there is proof from the light of nature, that God would give to men a revelation, I affirm nothing in respect to the time, the manner, or the extent of such a revelation beyond what has now been stated. On these topics I do not pretend that we have the requisite premises for any conclusion. It is obvious however, that we may still have abundant proof of the fact, that God would give a revelation. We may have sufficient premises for one conclusion, though we have none for another. To recur to the example, we may have decisive proof that a watch-maker will complete the watch he has begun, and that he will give the requisite instructions concerning its true object, to him for whose use he makes it, and yet we may pos- sess no means of deciding tvhen, in what manner, and to what extent he will do the latter. While in respect to these particu- lar points of inquiry, all may be left indeterminate and uncer- tain ; still the fact that he has begun to make the watch, that he has proceeded so far in the work, surmounting all obstacles, and showing in every conceivable way that he is fully intent on the accomplishment of his design, that nothing can come into competition with it, nor hinder him from doing all that is necessary to give entire perfection to every thing fitted to secure the end aimed at ; the fact ascertained by the most abundant and decisive experience, that he for whose use he makes the watch, will never so understand it as to secure the end without instructions from the maker — these things being known, render the conclusion unavoidable, that the requisite instructions concerning the use of the watch will be given. We have all the reasons for this conclusion which are or can be well conceived of, in respect to the acts and doings of volun- tary beings in any case whatever. There is according to the supposition, no possible ground of doubt in respect to the ulti- 408 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. mate end of the watch-maker, nor in respect to his purpose to give the highest possible perfection to the means of accom- plishing it, nor the necessity of instructions in the use of the watch to the perfection of these means. Who then can doubt in regard to the fact that such information will be given ? Such is the argument by which we prove from the light of nature that God would give a revelation to men. To present the argument, we now recur to what we have attempted to prove in the preceding course of lectures. We have seen that man from the nature of his constitution and the condition in which he is placed, is a moral being — that conformity to the law of benevolent action is the true and only means of his perfection in character and in happiness. We have seen that God, his Maker, administers a perfect moral government over this world, through an economy of grace ; that in this system he aims at the great, the best con- ceivable end by the best conceivable means, or that this sys- tem of means is in every conceivable respect perfectly adapted to the best conceivable end — that God has proposed the high- est happiness of his moral creation which he can secure as the end of his government; that he gives to the system of government which is the means of this end every conceivable perfection — that to this end and the perfection of this system of means every thing else in his whole course of providence — all that can be called good, is subservient, and every thing that is evil, if it can be made to contribute to this end, is used for this purpose — that every evil which to him is incidental to the system and unavoidable in the nature of things, if the system be adopted, is incurred, or to speak in the language of theology, is purposed or decreed rather than not adopt and carry out the system. We have seen, that in administering his moral govern- ment under a gracious economy, God manifests himself as a just God and yet a Saviour — that in this way he evinces the fact of an atonement, though not the matter and method of it, thus manifesting the immutability of his purpose, not only to ac- complish the end of the system adopted, but to give the sys- tem itself the highest perfection in respect to fitness and adap- tation to its end, so that instead of spreading the gloom of despair over this world of sin and guilt, he authorizes the belief of a future state,in which the order, beauty and splendor of his moral administration will be completed in the blessed- WILL THE DESIGN BE ABANDONED? 409 ness of the righteous, and in the merited punishment of the in- corrigibly wicked — results, which in the comparative amount of happiness and misery, will fully accord with the benignity and grace manifest in the system of means adopted for their accomplishment. Such then is the great, the comprehensive design of God in the creation and government of this world, as presented to us by the light of nature. Reason duly employed on the subject gives us the whole and every part of it. It gives us not only the end, viz., the highest perfection of his moral creation, in character and in happiness, possible to the Creator, but also the perfection of the system of means, both in every essential respect as a system of moral government under grace, and in every circumstantial respect as involving all that can be con- ceived to be necessary to prevent the failure of the end, and to secure its most perfect accomplishment. I now ask, what will become of this great plan of God the Creator ? "Will his design in creating men moral beings — be- ings the most exalted in kind which he can create, be aban- doned through indifference or fickleness ? Will the great object of all his works — that to which every thing beside is subordi- nate and subservient — be relinquished as impracticable by an Omniscient and Almighty Creator ? Will it prove in the issue to be a design, for entering upon which, he who sees the end from the beginning, will see that there were no reasons, or for abandoning which he will discover new reasons 1 Will that design of God, in forming beings in his own image, which stands forth first, brightest, greatest of them all, terminate in utter failure and defeat? Will the progress of this plan of God come to a sudden end — the moral constitution of his creatures, this whole moral system, be divested of all significance, and its author of all his wisdom and honor, and all that can deter from iniquity and secure the moral perfection of moral beings ; all that can bless man, exalt God ; all that can make heaven rejoice and hell tremble, be frittered away into an insignificant and degrading mockery ? If the immutability of God, the in- finite perfections of his Godhead — if the clear manifestation of designs worthy of himself — if their superior excellence as stamping all others with insignificance, and if their ceaseless development and unfaltering progress for six thousand years, give any security in respect to what God will do, then must Vol. I.— 18 410 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. we look for a full and perfect consummation of God's great design as the moral governor of men. I now advert to another position, which I persuade myself has been fully established in preceding lectures, viz., the neces- sity of a revelation from God. I attempted to show that there is a necessity of such revela- tion, in three respects : First. To give the highest conceivable perfection to the mode of discovering truth to the human mind. Secondly. To any extensive and useful discovery of truth to the mind. Thirdly. To the discovery of some important truths, which the human mind could not discover without a revelation. The question now is, whether, in view of this necessity of a revelation as existing in these respects, we have reason to con- clude that God would give a revelation to mam I proceed then to show — First, that the necessity of a revelation to give the highest conceivable perfection to the mode of discovering truth to the human mind, supposing it to be necessary for no other purpose, furnishes decisive proof that God would give a revelation to men. The argument here rests on two facts which have already been established, viz., that a revelation is necessary to the high- est conceivable perfection in t/ie mode of discovering truth to the human mind ; and that God has actually evinced his design to give perfection to that system which he has adopted to re- claim and save this lost world. That a revelation is necessary to the highest perfection of a reclaiming system, so far as per- fection in adaptation, fitness, and tendency to secure the end of such a system is concerned, no one will deny. Nor can I imagine any possible ground for doubt on the question, whether God, for this reason, would give a revelation to men, except one, viz. : the possibility that through perversion on their part, it might prove for the worse instead of for the better — become a curse instead of a blessing. To this I answer, that admitting this possibility, it furnishes no proof that it would in fact prove to be for the worse, nor that God would not give a reve- lation. I answer again, that the whole history of his provi- dence, as I have abundantly shown, evinces a fixed purpose to give perfection to his system of moral government under a gracious economy, or to his system of reclaiming influence THE SYSTEM PERFECT. 411 irrespectively of its foreseen perversion on the part of his sub- jects. This foreseen fact of perversion in its (almost) absolute universality, has not prevented him from giving to the system every essential perfection, nor from giving it every circumstan- tial perfection, to such an extent as to remove all presumption against the fact ; while what he has done furnishes the highest probability of the fact that he will, sooner or later, add that of a revelation. Without supposing that God designs actu- ally to reclaim and save one of the human race, I maintain that one design of God is too conspicuous in his providence to- ward this world to be denied or doubted, viz., his design to give absolute perfection to his system of reclaiming influences. The fact that he has done so much for this purpose already, in an economy of grace, bringing every conceivable influence in the universe to bear on this great object, and doing every con- ceivable thing to accomplish it except that of giving a revela- tion, is as truly decisive of his design to give perfection to this system as had he done more. Whatever may be supposed to be the reason for giving such perfection to this system as he has actually given — whether he proposes to reclaim some of our guilty race or not, or whether we can or cannot assign any reason for this perfection of the reclaiming system, or whether we can or cannot say why he has not already added a revela- tion, supposing that he has not, one thing is decisively proved, viz., that he chooses to give it the highest conceivable perfec- tion. Take the case of the watch-maker. Suppose the work has progressed to a certain point — that he has done every thing but one which is necessary for accomplishing the end proposed ; he has finished a perfect watch, he has put the parts together, has inserted the main-spring, oiled the machinery, wound it up, placed it in the hands of a son for whose use he made it ; he has done all this at no ordinary expense of time and labor, and with no ordinary degree of self-sacrifice; in a word, he has thus done all that can be conceived to be adapted and fitted to secure the end, except he has not told the possessor of the watch how to wind it up. And now, with all these proofs of his real design, do you, can you believe that he will never ex- plain that to him ? Suppose you cannot tell the results of giv- ing this instruction — whether it will prove for better or for worse ; suppose you can give no reason for delaying to give it for a few minutes or a few hours, can you therefore believe that 412 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. the requisite instruction by the watch-maker on this material point will never be given ? This, with any fair-minded man, could not be a matter of hesitation or doubt. So in respect to the reclaiming system of God. In view of what he has actually done toward giving it perfection as a system of adaptations and fitnesses, there is decisive reason for believing that he will give it absolute perfection ; and in view of the necessity of a reve- lation to this, there is all the reason for believing that he would give a revelation, which there is for belies- ing that he would perfect the system. And there is all the reason to believe that he will perfect the system, which the actual perfection of it in all respects but one can furnish. Having done all things neces- sary to its perfection but one, is there not a moral certainty that he will do that also ? Having done so much, he has fur- nished, so far as this kind of evidence is concerned, all that is possible in the case, more being impossible without giving a revelation. If too we reflect on what God actually does to give perfection to this system, how the object stands forth the first and the highest, and as it were the whole and sole object of nature, of providence, and of grace ; how all things are sub- ordinated to this ; how all influences from himself, his charac- ter, his relations, his friendship and favor, his displeasure and his wrath — every influence from man himself, every influence from earth and heaven, from time and eternity, is brought to subserve this design, who can doubt that, sooner or later, the Being with whom one day is as a thousand years, and a thou- sand years as one day, will give to such a system perfection absolute ? The probability is the highest of which the nature of the case admits. If the acts and doings of God can prove any thing, they show that he would give a revelation to men. It is easy to account for what he has done, on the supposition that he intends to do more ; but it is not possible to account for what he has done, unless you suppose that he intends to do more. God, by perfecting the system, would give higher proof that he preferred holiness to sin, than he would or could give. There is no reason for concluding that he will not perfect the system ; there is therefore all the reason for concluding that he will per- fect it, that the above consideration affords. I proceed to show — Secondly. That the necessity of a divine revelation to secure REVELATION HIGHLY PROBABLE. 413 to any extent any useful practical knowledge of religions and moral truth to man, in connection with other facts, furnishes further proof that God would give a revelation to man. Let us look at the facts as already established. God, as we have seen, has, as the Creator and Governor of this world, proposed the best conceivable end, and has also adopted the best system of means for its accomplishment, with the single exception that it does not include a revelation. This great end is the highest happiness of his creation; the system of means is a perfect moral government under an economy of grace. This end will fail, and this system of means will be in vain, and worse than in vain, without a revelation. If facts — if the experience of a world for thousands of years can prove any thing, it has proved, that without a revelation from God, all the generations of men will live and die in sin. At the same time, the nature, the immutable principles of God's perfect moral government, give another and still more appalling result — the complete and eternal misery of all these creatures of God. The great, the awful experiment has been made in respect to what man as a subject of God's moral dominion, will do without a revelation. It has proved that he will sin, and only sin. The throne of God, though a throne of grace, stands on the pillars of eternal justice, proffering no pardon, giving no hope to impenitent transgressors, but frowning in terrific majesty, and dooming a world of such transgressors to just and fearful retribution. The alternative is, either the failure of God's great end in creation, even the moral perfection and consecpient perfect happiness, of every moral being, involving, as it must, the utter and endless misery of all, or the gift of a revelation from God to this lost world. I maintain the high probability of the latter. To estimate this aright, we must recur to all those providential dealings of God to restore man to virtue and to happiness, which so clearly and so impressively disclose his design as a moral governor. If it be said, all this may be without a providential purpose actually to restore any ; I admit the bare possibility of it, but this is not evidence, it is only probability. How then is this probability to be estimated ? Is there even the slightest pre- sumption that God would give existence to such a world, to such myriads of immortal beings, with the foresight, and there- fore with the providential purpose that each and all should be 414 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. miserable forever? Every presumption is against it. The merest surmise of such, a fact without evidence, is unauthorized and injurious, and proscribed by every principle of just reason- ing. The entire want of evidence of such a fact, in view of his perfect benevolence, is proof against it. Indeed as we have already shown, there is the most satisfactory proof, that the Creator will secure such results in the holiness and happiness of this part of his moral creation, as will furnish bright displays of his infinite goodness. Nay more. We have seen in that economy of grace and mercy which he has clearly disclosed in all the ways of his providence, the sure pledge of results, in the holiness and happiness of men corresponding with its benignity and grace. Who are the objects of all this grace? The crea- tures of his power, the children of his love ! Will God then adopt such a system of means to reclaim and save, giving it every conceivable adaptation and tendency to such an end — will he bring all creation and providence to attest his sincerity, and his overflowing kindness toward his disobedient children, with- out a design actually to reclaim and save, and with the knowl- edge and the purpose that the only result shall be the aggrava- tion of the guilt and the ruin of all ? Reflect and see what benignity and grace assail a thoughtless, wicked world at every step of life! What solicitude and earnestness to reclaim his wayward children, which none but a perfect God could feel or manifest ! What riches of long-suffering and forbearance — (what evil that is not the infliction of paternal love) — what goodness leading to repentance and drawing with the cords of love and with the bands of a man — what yearnings of compas- sion, what bowels of mercy — what a length, breadth, height, depth in God's restoring love ! And do such love and mercy thus seek their objects with the foresight that it will, and the purpose that it shall augment the guilt and ruin of them all ? Is such the errand on which this mercy of God comes to this ruined world ? Oh no. It is the breaking, the bursting forth of the heart of infinite love in acts of sincerest mercy actually to reclaim and save all that can be saved ! It is the mercy of God, doing for each, and for all, and at every moment, all that can be wisely done. It is the decree of God unchangeable, actu- ally to reclaim and save a multitude which no man can num- ber, out from all nations, and kindreds, and people and tongues — a decree of God unchangeable, to bring home to himself bright STILL ANOTHER NECESSITY. 415 hosts of holy, happy immortals, to satisfy, and bless, and rejoice that heart which sought their salvation ! But without a revela- tion all will be lost — this design of mercy will fail ! Surely that mercy will not withhold from the guilty beings it decrees to save, the revelation they need. No act of paternal kindness — no gift of a father's love is so sure, as that of revelation from its God to this lost world. Once more — Thirdly: The necessity of a revelation to the discovery of some important truths which man could not discover without it, proves that God would give a revelation. I have already taken occasion to show how utterly hopeless would have been the condition of this sinful world, without the discovery which the Scriptures make to us concerning the manner in which its redemption is achieved — in other words the revelation of the triune God, the Father, the Son, and the Holy Ghost, in their respective relations to the work of man's redemption from sin. The two great problems are, how shall the perverseness of rebels be subdued to love ; and if subdued, hoiv can a just God receive them to favor f Here all is mystery unsolvable, darkness impenetrable and appalling ! How could human reason alone and unaided have discovered the mystery of redemption ? Even when God has revealed it, reason is lost in this abyss of love and mercy, and needs all its submission to believe! Man, sin- ful as he is, I admit, might repent and might hope for mercy from his Maker. But would he? What bondage so strong as bondage to sin — what death so hopeless as death in sin ? Who shall deliver? What power shall give life, and health, and beauty immortal to these victims of sin and death? I said man might hope for mercy. But with a just apprehension of God's fearful justice and his own desert of its fearful doom — looking upon a sin-avenging God as he must, and asking how can such a God show the same abhorrence of sin and yet for- give, as he would by turning a rebellious world into hell, then it is that the terrors of God come over us ; hope trembles and expires. ISTot that it must be so, but it always has been and always will be, with exceptions that need not be mentioned. It is not hope in a God all tenderness which we need. It is that which looks upon a just God, and with a sense of his righteous indignation toward sin, reposes calmly and sweetly in his mercy. But there is so much terror here, so much darkness and tern- 416 ARGUMENT FROM NATURE APPLIED. pest around the throne of God, that in the eye of guilt, the rajs of mercy fade and will not suffice. Guilt will look up with confidence, only when it sees the throne of God upheld by "the man that is his fellow." Take away " the incarnate mystery," extinguish the light that reveals the great atonement of Chris- tianity, and where is hope for human guilt ? Zeno, Socrates, Plato, Pythagoras, Epicurus, Porch, Academy, Lyceum, Infi- delity, Deism, Philosophy, Human Peason, all, what can ye do, what can ye substitute for the blood of the Son of God? Ex- tinguish that light which reveals the mercy of God through his Son, and let in the terrors of guilt and of God on this sinful world, and how would each and all, in the gloom or frenzy of despair, take their way down to everlasting burnings? Will a redeeming God then withhold that light from the world he would redeem ? Will he abandon every purpose of mercy — render every other manifestation of it vain, and worse than in vain; will he give up his lost creature to the perdition of hell, when he has, for the light of nature teaches it, actually made an atonement ? Will he do this by concealing from their view what that atonement is ? Has he made, and given abundant proof that he has made the only atonement, by the knowledge of which conscious guilt will ever be emboldened to approach a spotless God — the only atonement, the knowledge of which will ever give hope and peace and heaven to a guilty world ; and will he refuse to give the knowledge of this atonement ? Has he done all this in fact for us, and will he, by refusing to tell what it is, leave us only to a certain, fearful looking for of judgment and fiery indignation ! It is incredible. I say not at what time in this world's history, nor whether in this or a future state ; but that, sooner or later, the God of grace — that God who tells us in all his works and ways that he has in pur- pose or in fact, made an adequate atonement for human guilt, will also reveal its nature and its power. Having done the greater, he will also do the less. Xo act of an immutable God, no gift of his mercy, can be more certain than that of a revela- tion, declaring to the faith, the wonder, the gratitude, the joy of redeemed men, " God so loved the world that he gave his only begotten Son, that whosoever believeth in him should not per- ish, but have everlasting life." I have thus attempted to establish my third leading position : III. That the importance and necessity of a revelation to the THE BIBLE, WHAT IT CLAIMS TO BE. 417 great end of God in the creation and government of the world, give a strong probability, not to say a moral certainty, that he would give a revelation to men. The next and last position now claims consideration, viz. : IV. That which is claimed to be a revelation from God, and which is contained in the Bible, is what it claims to be. The argument is this : God will give a revelation to this world. We take the Bible, and if we had heard nothing of it before, we read, examine, understand it ; we see that it is ex- actly such a book as we have decisive reasons to believe God would give to man, harmonizing with all our just views of the character, the relations, the government of God ; adapted won- derfully and perfectly to the wants, the character, the condition and prospects of man ; fitted to secure the high end of his crea- tion, even his perfection in character and in blessedness. Its actual effects confirm and illustrate its j)erfection as the means of this great end. The writers of the book assert its divine origin. It had not a human origin, for we have proved the necessity of just such a book from God, and that man would never make such a book. Now I ask, whence came this book ? What is its origin ? Is it from God, or is it not ? 14 DAY USE kb™nto DESKfromwhichborrowed loan dept. * **• *»*• «» . tmm "*;■ LD 21A-50w-8 '57 (C8481sl0)476B .General Library University of California Berkeley