GIFT OF EVGENE .JKFFKKSON DAVIS The War Between the States or Was Secession a Constitutional Right Previous to the War of 1861-65? Arranged without verbal changes from "Is DAVIS A TRAITOR" / BY ALBERT T. BLEDSOE, A. M., LL. D. 1915 J. P. BELL COMPANY, INC. LYNCHBURG, VA. COPYRIGHT 1915 DANVILLE CHAPTER, U. D. C. DANVILLE, VA. ^ Introduction CONTENTS CHAPTER I PAGE CHAPTER II Is the Constitution a Compact? ......... . . ..................... 14 CHAPTER III Webster Scouts the" Idea that the States "Acceded" to the Constitution ................................................ ^ CHAPTER IV The First Resolution Passed by the Convention of 1787 ........ 24 CHAPTER V The Constitution of 1787 a Compact ........................... 20 CHAPTER VI The Constitution of 1787 a Compact between the States The Facts of the Case ................................................................. 40 CHAPTER VII The Constitution a Compact between the States The Lan guage of the Constitution ...................................................... 51 CHAPTER VIII The Constitution of 1787 a Compact between the States The Language of the Constitution Continued .......................... 58 CHAPTER IX The Constitution of 1787 a Compact between the States _ The Views of Certain of the Framers of the Constitution ...... 66 CHAPTER X The Constitution of 1787 a Compact between tne States Mr. Webster Again ................................................................. 79 CHAPTER XI The Absurdities Flowing From the Doctrine that the Con stitution is Not a Compact between the States, But Was Made by the People of America as One Nation.... 91 333710 $ , -CONTENTS CHAPTER XII PAGE The Hypothesis that the People of America Form One Nation 94 CHAPTER XIII Arguments in Favor of the Right of Secession.... - 111 CHAPTER XIV Arguments Against the Right of Secession.... - 148 CHAPTER XV Was Secession Treason? ............. - 1? () CHAPTER XVI The Causes of Secession ................ CHAPTER XVII The Legislators of 1787 as Political Prophets.... - 237 PREFACE It is not the design of this hook to open the subject of secession. The subjugation of the Southern States, and their acceptance of the terms dictated by the Xorth, may, if the reader please, be considered as having shifted the Federal Government from the basis of compact to that of conquest; and thereby extinguished every claim to the right of secession for the future. Not one word in the fol lowing pages will at least be found to clash with that sup position or opinion. The sole object of this work is to dis cuss the right of secession with reference to the past ; in order to vindicate the character of the South for loyalty, and to wipe off the charges of treason and rebellion "from the names and memories of Jefferson Davis, Stonewall Jackson, Albert Sidney Johnston, Eobert E. Lee, and of all who have fought or suffered in the great war of coercion. Admitting, then, that the right of secession no longer exists ; the present work aims to show, that, however those illustrious heroes may have been aspersed by the ignorance, the prejudices, and the passions of the hour, they were^ nevertheless, perfectly loyal to truth, justice, and the Constitution of 1787 as it came from the hands of the fathers. The calm and impartial reader will, it is believed, dis cover therein the grounds on which the South may he vindicated. ALBERT TAYLOR BLEDSOE. Baltimore, 1866. EXPLANATORY PREFACE Albert Taylor Bledsoe had been graduated at West Point in 1830. He was there with both Jefferson Davis and Robert E. Lee, though not a classmate of either. While professor of mathematics in the University of Mississippi his relations with Davis were maintained with great cordiality. He was not in favor of sesession, but with the call for her quota of 75,000 men from Virginia, to enter the Federal Army, like Lee and other Virginians he felt that he could not ally him self with the enemies of his State, so he entered the Confederate Army, receiving the title of Colonel; but he was preeminently a student and a scholar, not a soldier. Later President Davis gave him a position in the Confederate Cabinet : his title was Chief of the Bureau of War, his duties those of Assistant Secre tary of War. Later on in a consultation between Davis and Lee it was decided that the greatest service he could render to the seceded States was to write a constitutional history which should, if the facts were made clear, justify the South in the right to secede. In order to do this it was necessary for him to have access to the debates in the formation of the constitution, of the United States as well as of the individual States, then constituting the Union. The necessary documents were not to be found south of Mason and Dixon s Line. He was therefore obliged to go to England to study there in the British Museum. My mother, who was born in New Jersey, but for many years had lived in the South, was an ardent Southerner. She, out of a very limited inheritance, paid all of the expenses of the trip, of my father s stay of several years in England, and of the family while he was gone, as well as of the publication of the book after his return in 1866. He had intended to give it the title almost exactly like the sub title of the published volume; but on his return to America, Jefferson Davis was a prisoner in Fortress Monroe, and in peril of his life. He, therefore, gave the volume when it was issued the title, "IS DAVIS A TRAITOR?" Charles O Connor, Mr. Davis s advocate in the trial for treason, told my father that without the facts brought to light in his book, he could not have saved Mr. Davis s life. My mother never received any compensation for what she had expended, and she always rejoiced that she had been able to aid in justifying her beloved South. These few words of explanation seem necessary in issuing this volume again, as a book of reference for the schools of the South. SOPHIA BLEDSOE HERRICK. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION THE IMPORTANCE OF THE QUESTION THE final judgment of history in relation to the War of 1861 will, in no small degree, depend on its verdict with respect to the right of secession. If, when this right was practically asserted by the South, it had been conceded by the North, there would not have been even a pretext for the tremendous conflict which followed. Is it not wonder ful, then, that a question of such magnitude and impor tance should have been so little considered, or discussed? Perhaps no other question of Apolitical philosophy, or of international law, pregnant with such unutterable calami ties, has ever been so partially and so superficially examined as the right of secession from the Federal Union of the United States. From first to last it seems to have been decided by passion, and not by reason. The voice of reason, enlightened by the study of the facts of history and the principles of political philosophy, yet remains to be heard on the subject of secession. CONFEDERATION AND UNION Xo one, at present, denies that the States had a right to secede from the Union formed by the old Articles of Con federation. Indeed, this right was claimed and exercised by the States, when they withdrew from that Confederation in order to form "a more perfect Union. 7 Yet, while that Union was standing and in favor with the people, the right of secession therefrom was vehemently denied. Tke reason of this is well stated by Mr. Madison in The Federalist. Having explained and vindicated the right of the States, or any portion of them,- to secede from the existing Union, 10 THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES he adds: "The time has been when it was incumbent on all of us to veil the ideas which this paragraph exhibits. The scene has now changed, and with it the part which the same motives dictate." 1 That is to say, the time has been when it became all Americans, as patriots and worshipers of the existing Union,, to veil the right of secession ; but now it is the time to unveil this sacred right, and let the truth be seen!. Accordingly, the Convention of 1787 un veiled this right, and the States, one after another, seceded from the Union ; though the Articles by which it was formed expressly declared that it should be "perpetual," or last forever. MADISON S ARGUMENT The same thing happened, in a still greater degree, under the new and "more perfect Union." This, unlike the one for which it had been substituted, did not pro nounce itself immortal. Still it was deemed incumbent on all men by Mr. Madison, and especially upon himself, to veil the right of secession from the new Union; which he, more than any other man, had labored to establish and preserve. But having exercised the right of secession from one compact between the States, how could he veil that right under another compact between the same parties? Having, for the benefit of his age, revealed the truth, how could he hope to hide it from all future ages? Having laid down the right of secession from one Federal Union, as the great fundamental law to which the new Union owed its very existence, how could he hope to cover it up again, and make the new compact forever binding on posterity? There is not, it is believed, in the whole range of literature, a sophism more ineffably weak and flimsy than the one employed by Mr. Madison to veil the right of secession from the new Union. The first compact, says he, was made by the Legislatures of the States, and the second by the people themselves of the States. Hence, although the States had seceded from the first compact or Union, he supposed, or hoped, they would have no right to secede from the second. 2 The 1 The Ft-ilernlM, No. xliii. - "The Madison Papers," p. 1184. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 11 first compact was, it is true, originally adopted by the Legislatures of the States ; but then it was approved by the people themselves, who lived under it as the Constitu tion and government of their choice. Were not the States, then, just as much bound by this compact, as if it had been originally made by the people themselves ? What would be thought of an individual who should approve and adopt as his own a contract made by his agent, and, having derived all the advantages of it, should seek to repudiate it on the ground that it was not originally entered into by himself? He would be deemed infamous. Yet, precisely such is the distinction and the logic of Mr. Madison, in his attempt to justify the act of secession from the first Union, and to deny the right of secession from the second Union between the same parties ! The two compacts are construed differently ; because the one was originally made by agents and afterwards ratified by the principals, and the other was originally made by the principals themselves ! Could any sophism be more weak or flimsy ? Is it not, indeed, in the eye of reason, as thin as gossamer, as transparent as the air itself? Hopeless, indeed, must be the attempt to find a difference between the two cases, which shall establish the right of secession in the one and not in the other; since James Madison himself, with all his unsurpassed powers of logic and acute discrimination, was compelled to rely on so futile a distinction. PART PLAYED BY FEELING But the majority needed no veil, not even one as thin as that employed by Mr. Madison, to conceal the right of secession from their eyes. The mists raised by its own passions were amply sufficient for that purpose. The doc trine of secession was regarded by the reigning majority, as simply equivalent to -the destruction of "the best Gov ernment the world had ever seen," or was ever likely to see. Hence, before the dread tribunal of the sovereign majority, the touch of secession was political death. The public men of the country, and all aspirants after office, shrank from it as from plague, pestilence, and famine. 12 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES As to whether secession was a Constitutional right or otherwise, the multitude knew nothing, and cared less ; but still, in their passionate zeal, they denounced it as rebellion, treason, and every other crime in the dark catalogue of political offences. Their leaders, having studied the subject as little as themselves, were no less ignorant respecting the merits of the question, and even more fierce in denouncing secession as the sum of all villainies, treasons, and rebel lions. Thus, what the logic of Mr. Madison failed to ac complish was achieve! by the rhetoric of angry politicians and the passions of an unfuriated majority; that is, the right of secession was veiled. The object of this little book is simply to appeal from the mad forum of passion to the calm tribunal of reason. WHY EEVIVE THE DISCUSSION ? But why, it may be asked, appeal to reason ? Has not the war of secession been waged, and the South subjugated? Can reason, however victorious, bind up the broken heart, or call the dead to life? Can reason cause the desolate, dark, waste places of the South to sriiile again, or the hearts of her downcast and dejected people to rejoice? Can reason strike the fetters from the limbs of the down trodden white population of the South ? True, alas ! reason can do none of these things ; but still she has a high office and duty to perform. For, however sore her calamities, all is not yet lost to our bleeding and beloved South. She still retains that which, to every true man, is infinitely dearer than property or life. She still retains her moral wealth, the glory of her Jacksons, her Sidney Johnstons, her Lees, her Davises, and of all who have nobly died or suffered in her cause. These are her imperishable jewels; and, since little else is left to her, these shall be cherished with the greater love, with the more enthusiastic and undying devotion. Let no one ask, then, except a dead soul, why argue the question of secession? For it is precisely as this question is decided that the Jacksons, the Johnstons, the Lees, and the Davises of the South will be pronounced rebels and THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 13 traitors,, or heroes and martyrs; that the South itself will be disgraced, or honored, in the estimation of mankind. History is, at this moment, busy in making up her verdict on this momentous question, which is^ to determine so much that is most dear to every true son of the South. Shall we, then, remain idle spectators, mere passive lookers- on, while the North is flooding the world .with volumes against the justice of our cause? Shall we stand, like the dumb brutes around us, having no word to utter in the great cause of truth, justice, and humanity, which is now pending at the bar of history? Or shall we, on the con trary, contribute our mite toward the just decision of that glorious cause ? The radicals themselves might, perhaps, derive some little benefit from our humble labors. For, if duly weighed and considered by them, these labors might serve to miti gate their wrath, and turn their thoughts from schemes of vengeance to the administration of justice, from persecu tion and ruin to peace and prosperity. Be this as it may, however, I shall proceed to argue the right of secession ; because this is the great issue on which the whole Southern people, the dead -as well as the living, is about to be tried in the person of their illustrious chief, Jefferson Davis. CHAPTER II IS THE CONSTITUTION A COMPACT? THE QUESTION STATED IT is conceded, both by Webster 1 and Story, that if the Constitution is a compact to which the States are the parties, then the States have a right to secede from the Union at pleasure. Thus says Webster: "If a league between sovereign powers have no limitation as to the time of duration, and contain nothing making it perpetual, it subsists only during the good pleasure of the parties, although no violation be complained of. If, in the opinion of either party, it be violated, such party may say he will no longer fulfill its obligations on his part, but will con sider the whole league or compact at an end, although it might be one of its stipulations that it should be perpetual." In like manner Mr. Justice Story says : "The obvious deductions which may be, and, indeed, have been, drawn from considering the Constitution a compact between States, are that it operates as a mere treaty or convention between them, and has an obligatory force no longer than suits its pleasure or its consent continues/ 2 etc. Thus the great controversy is narrowed down to the single question- Is the Constitution a compact between the States? If so, then the right of secession is conceded, even by its most powerful and determined opponents; by the great jurist, as well as by "the great expounder" of the North. The denial that the Constitution was a compact is pre sented in every possible form, or variety of expression. We are told that it was not made by the States, nor by the people of the States, but "by the people of the whole United States in the aggregate. " ?> The States, we are assured, did not accede to the Constitution; it was ordained by the sovereign people of America as one nation. Echo ing the bold assertion of Webster, Mr. Motley says, that 1 Daniel Webster. - Commentaries on the Constitution." vol. iii. p. 287. first published in 188.,. :: Webster. Tin: WAK BETWEEN THE STATES 15 "the States never acceded to the Constitution, and have no power to secede from it. It was ordained and estab lished over the States by a power superior to the States, by the people of the whole land in their aggregate capacity/ 71 It was not made by the States, and it was not ratified by the States. It was, on the contrary, made and ordained by the people of America as one nation, and is, therefore, the constitution of a national government. Such is the doctrine which, in every mode of expression, is inculcated by the Storys, the Websters, and the Motleys of the North. When we consider, in the simple light of history, the manner in which the Constitution of the United States was made, or framed, and afterwards ratified, such asser tions seem exceedingly wonderful, not to say inexplicable, on the supposition that their authors were honest men. But who can measure the mysterious depths of party spirit, or the force of political passions in a democracy? I know something of that force; for, during the greater part of my life, I followed, with implicit confidence, those blind leaders of the blind, Mr. Justice Story and Daniel Webster. History will yet open the eyes of the world to the strange audacity of their assertions. Ever since the Declaration of Independence there have been two great political parties in the United States : the one, regarding the American people as one nation, has labored to consolidate the Federal Union; while the other, attaching itself to the reserved rights of the States, has zealously resisted this tendency to consolidation in the central power. Even under the old Articles of Confeder ation, or before the new Constitution was formed, these political opinions and parties existed. For, however strange it may seem, there were those who, even under those Articles, considered "the States as Districts of people composing one political society"; 2 or the "American people as forming one nation." 3 Nay, in the great Con vention of 1787, by which the Constitution was formed, it was boldly asserted by a leading member "that we never "Rebellion Records," vol. 1, p. 211. 2 "The Madison Papers," p. 087. 3 Marshall s "Life of Washington," vol. v, chap. i. 16 THE WAE BETWEEN THE STATES were independent States, were not such now, and never could be, even on the principles of the Confederation. The States, and the advocates of them, were intoxicated with the idea of their sovereignty/ 71 Now, if any aberra tion of the mind under the influence of political passions could seem strange to the student of history, it would be truly wonderful that such an assertion could have been put forth under the Articles of Confederation which expressly declared that "each State 7 of the Union formed by them "retains its sovereignty, freedom, and independence/ 2 The author of that assertion did not interpret, he flatly contradicted, the fundamental law of the government under which he lived and acted. The above opinion or view of the old Articles of Con federation passed away with the passions to which it owed its birth. No one, at the present day, supposes that the old Articles moulded the States into "one political society," or "nation/ 7 leaving them merely "districts of people." For since those Articles have passed away, and the struggle for power under them has ceased, all can clearly see what they so plainly announced, that "each State 77 of the con federation established by them retained "its sovereignty, freedom, and independence/ But the natures of men were not changed by changing the objects to which their political passions might attach themselves. Hence the same opposite tendencies arose under the new "Articles of Union, 77 as the Constitution of 1787 is habitually called by its authors, and produced the same conflicting parties. Each party had, of course, its extreme wing. There were those who, unduly depressing the States, identified their relations to the central power with that of so many counties to a state, or of individuals to an ordinary political community. On the other hand, there were those who, from an extreme jealousy of the central authority, resolved the States into their original independence, or into their condition under the Articles of Confederation. The watchword of one party was the sovereignty of the Federal Union ; and the watchword of the other was the sovereignty of the States. 1 "The Madison Papers." THE WAR BETWEEX THE STATES 17 THE QUESTION OF A COMPACT DEBATED It was in the Senate of the United States, in 1833, that these two theories of the Constitution stood face to face in the persons of those two intellectual giants Webster and Calhoun then engaged in the most memorable debate of the New World. It was then predicted, and events have since verified the prediction, that the destinies of America would hinge and turn on the principles of that great debate. The war of words then waged between the giants has since become a war of deeds and blood between the sections which they represented. Xow the question is, on which side was right, truth, justice? This is precisely the question which, in 1833, the great combatants submitted to the decision of after-ages. As he drew toward the close of his speech, Mr. Calhoun reminded his great antagonist "that the principles he might advani i- would be subjected to the revision of posterity. 77 "I do not decline its judgment/ 7 said Mr. Webster, in rising to reply, "nor withhold myself from its scrutiny. 77 Mr. Webster s speech on this occasion is pronounced by his learned biographer 1 the greatest intellectual effort of his life, and is represented as having annihilated every position assumed by Mr. Calhoun. But the combatants did not submit the controversy to the judgment of Mr. Everett; they sub mitted it to "the revision of posterity. 77 History is the great tribunal to which they appealed; and history will settle the great issue between them, and between the two sections of the Union. It was in 1833, for the first time in the history of the country, that it was solemnly asserted and argued that the Constitution of the United States was not a compact between the States. This new doctrine was simultaneously put forth by Mr. Justice Story in his "Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States, 77 and by Mr. Daniel Webster in "the greatest intellectual effort of his life, 77 that is, in his great speech in the Senate of the 16th of February, 1833. In order to show that the Constitution is not a compact between the States, the position is assumed 1 Edward Everett. 18 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES that it is not a compact at all. If it be a compact, say they, then the States had a right to secede. But it is not a compact, and hence secession is treason and rebellion. The great fundamental questions, then, on which the whole controversy hinges, are, first, Is the Constitution a compact? and, secondly, Is it a compact between the States? These are the questions which shall and ought to be subjected to "the revision of posterity." CHAPTER III WEBSTER SCOUTS THE IDEA THAT THE STATES "ACCEDED" TO THE CONSTITUTION "THE GREAT EXPOUNDER - ( ?) MR. WEBSTER was supposed to have studied the Consti tution, and its history, more carefully and more profoundly than any other man. He habitually "spoke, indeed, as if he had every particle of its meaning, and of its history, at his finger s end. Hence he acquired, at least among his political friends, the lofty title of "the great expounder." His utterances were listened to as oracles. If, indeed, his great mind had been guided by a knowledge of facts, or a supreme love of truth, the irresistible force of his logic, and the commanding powers of his eloquence, would have justified those who delighted to call him "the godlike Daniel." But, unfortunately, no part of his godlikeness consisted in a scrupulous regard for truth, or the accuracy of his assertions. He was, however, so great a master of words that he stood in little need of facts in order to pro duce a grand impression by the rolling thunders of his eloquence. I only wonder that he was not also called "the thunderer." N"o one better understood, either in theory or in practice, the wonderful magic of words than Daniel Webster. "Was it Mirabeau," says he, "or some other master of the human passions, who has told us that words are things? They are indeed things, and things of mighty influence, not only in addresses to the passions and high-wrought feelings of mankind, but in the discussion of legal and political questions also; because a just conclusion is often avoided, or a false one reached, by the adroit substitution of one phrase, or one word, for another." Xothing can be more just than this general reflection ; and nothing, as we shall presently see, can be more unjust than the application made of it bv Mr. Webster. 20 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES DID THE STATES "ACCEDE" TO THE CONSTITUTION? He finds an example of this adroit use of language in the first resolution of Mr. Calhoun. "The first resolution," says he, "declares that the people of the several States acceded to the Constitution." As "the natural converse of accession is secession^ so Mr. Webster supposes that Calhoun has adroitly, and "not without a well-considered purpose," shaped his premises to a foregone conclusion. "When it is stated," says he, "that the people of the States acceded to the Union, it may be more plausibly argued that they may secede from it. If, in adopting the Constitution, nothing was done but acceding to a compact, nothing would seem necessary, in order to break it up, but to secede from the same compact." But "this term accede asserts Mr. Webster, "is wholly out of place. . . . There is more importance than may, at first sight, appear in the introduction of this new word by the honorable mover of the resolutions. . The people of the United States," he continues, "used no such form of expression in establishing the present Gov ernment. ... It is "unconstitutional language." Such are a few of the bold, sweeping, and confident asser tions of "the great expounder of the Constitution." But how stands the fact? Is this really "a new word"; or is it as old as the Constitution itself, and rendered almost obsolete at the North by the progress of new ideas and new forms of speech? Was it not, in fact, as familiar to the very fathers and framers of the Constitution of the United States as it afterwards became foreign and strange to the ears of its Northern expounders? This is the question; and, fortunately, the answer is free from all metaphysical refinement, from all logical subtlety, from all curious speculation. For there lies the open record, with this very word accede, and this very application of the word, spread all over its ample pages in the most abundant profusion. Xo mode of expression is, indeed, more common with the fathers and the framers of the Constitution, while speak ing of the act of its adoption, than this very phrase, "the accession of the States." Xo household word ever fell more frequently or more familiarly from their lips. THE WAU BETWEEN THE STATES 21 Thus in the Convention of 1787, Mr. James Wilson, to whose great influence the historian of the Constitution ascribes its adoption by the State of Pennsylvania, 1 pre ferred "a partial union 7 of the States, "with a door open for the accession of the rest/ 7 rather than to see their dis position "to confederate anew on better principles 7 entirely defeated. 2 "But will the small States/ 7 asks another member of the same Convention, "in that case, accede to it [the Constitution] ? 77 Mr. Gerry, a delegate from Massachusetts, w r as opposed to "a partial confederacy, leaving other States to accede or not to accede, as had been intimated. 773 Even Mr. Madison, "the father of the Con stitution/ 7 as by way of eminence he has long been called, used the expression "to accede " in the Convention of 1787, in order to denote the act of adopting "the new form of government by the States. 7 4 In like manner Gouverneur Randolph, who was also a member of the Convention of 1787, and who had just reported the form of ratification to be used by the State of Virginia, said, "that the accession of eight States reduced our deliberations to the single question of Union or no Union.* 7 "If it [the Constitution], 77 says Patrick Henry, "be amended, every State will accede to it. 775 "Does she [Virginia] gain anything from her central posi tion/ 7 asks Mr. Grayson, "by acceding to that paper? 77 the Constitution. 6 "I came hither/ 7 says Mr. Innes, "under the persuasion that the felicity of our country required that we should accede to this system 777 (the new Constitu tion). "Our new Constitution/ 7 says Franklin, who next to Washington was the most illustrious member of the Convention of 1787, "is now established with eleven States, and the accession of a twelfth is soon expected. 778 And, finally, George Washington himself, who, watching the States as one after another adopted the new Constitu tion, says: "If these, with the States eastward and north ward of us, should accede to the Federal Government/ 7 1 Mr. Curtis, vol. i. p. 465. - "The Madison Papers." p. 797. -Ibid., p. 1101. * Una., p. 1103. 5 "Elliott s Debates." vol. iii, p. 652. "The Madison Papers." p. 1099. " "Elliott s Debates." Vol. iii. 8 "Franklin s Works," vol. v, p. 409. 22 THE WAR BETWEEX THE STATES etc. 1 Thus, while the transaction was passing before their eyes the fathers of the Constitution of the United States, with the great father of his country at their head, described the act by which the new Union was formed as "the accession of the States"; using the very expression which 7 in the resolution of Mr. Calhoun, is so vehemently condemned as "unconstitutional language," as "a new word/ 7 invented by the advocates of secession for the vile purpose of disunion. To these high authorities may be added that of Chief Justice Marshall ; who, in his "Life of Washington," notes the fact that "Xorth Carolina accedes to the Union." 2 This was many months after the new Government had gone into operation. Mr. Justice Story is, in spite of his artificial theory of the Constitution, a witness to the same fact. "The Constitution," says he, "has been ratified by all the States; . . . Ehode Island did not accede to it until more than a year after it had been in operation"; just as if he had completely forgotten his own theory of the Constitution. 3 If it were necessary this list of authorities, for the use of the word in question, and for the precise application made of it by Mr. Calhoun, might be greatly extended. There is, as Mr. Webster says, more importance to be attached to the word in question than may at first sight appear. For if "the States acceded" to the Constitution, each acting for itself alone, then it was a voluntary asso ciation of States, from which", according to his own admis sion, any member might secede at pleasure. Accordingly this position of the great oracle of the North is echoed and reechoed by all who, since the war began, have written against the right of secession. Thus says one of the most faithful of these echoes, Mr. Motley; "The States never acceded to the Constitution, and have no power to secede from it." It was "ordained and established" over the States by a power superior to the States, by the people of the whole land in their aggregate capacity. 4 1 "The Writings of Washington." vol. ix. p. L So. 2 Vol. v, chap. iii. 3 Book iii, chap, xliii. 4 "Rebellion Records." vol. 1. p. 211. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 23 If, with the fathers of the Constitution, in opposition to its modern expounder and perverter, he had seen that the new Union was formed by an accession of the States, then he would have been compelled, on his own principle, to recognize the right of secession. For he has truly said, what no one ever denied, that "the same power which estab lished the Constitution may justly destroy it." 1 Hence, if the Constitution was established by the accession or consent of the States, then may the Union be dissolved by a secession of the States. This conclusion is, as we have seen, expressly admitted by Mr. Webster and Mr. Justice Story. When, from his high position in the Senate, Mr. Webster assured the people of the United States that it is "uncon stitutional language" to say "the States acceded to the Constitution," he was no doubt religiously believed by the great majority of his readers and hearers. He was sup posed to know all about the subject; and was, therefore, followed as the great guide of the people. But, as we have seen, he was profoundly ignorant of the facts of the case about which he delivered himself with so much con fidence. The "new word," as he called it, was precisely the word of the fathers of the Constitution. Hence, if this word lays the foundation of secession, as Mr. Webster contended it does, that foundation was laid, not by Cal- houn, but by the fathers of the Constitution itself, with "the father of his country" at their head. So much for the first link in "the great expounder s" argument against the right of secession. His principles are right, but his facts are wrong. 1 "Rebellion Records," vol. 1, p. 214. C H A P T E R 1 V THE FIRST RESOLUTION PASSED BY THE CONVENTION OF 1787 A "XATIOXAL" GOVERNMENT (?) MR. WEBSTER lays great stress on the fact that the first resolution passed by the Convention of 1787 declared, "That a national government ought to be established, con sisting of a supreme legislative., judiciary, and executive." But the fact only shows that the Convention, when it first met, had the desire to establish "a national government," rather than a federal one. This resolution was passed before the Convention was fully assembled, and by the vote of only six States, a minority of the whole number. After the members had arrived, and the Convention was full, the resolution in question was reconsidered and rescinded. The Convention, when filled up, changed the name of their offspring, calling it "the government of the United States." 1 A fraction of the Convention named it, as Mr. Webster says, but the whole Convention refused to baptize it with that name, and gave it another. Why then resuscitate that discarded name, and place it before the reader, as Mr. Webster does, in capital letters? Is it because "words are things; and things of mighty influence?" or why persist, as Mr. Webster always does, in calling "the government of the United States" a national one? If the Convention had called it a national government, this name would have been so continually rung in our ears that we could neither have listened to the Constitution itself, or to its history, whenever these proclaimed its federal character. Xay, although the Convention positively refused to name it a national government, on the avowed ground that it did not express their views, yet has this name been eternally rung in our ears by the Northern School of politicians and declaimers; just as if it had been adopted, instead of having been repudiated and rejected, as it was, by the authors of the Constitution. 1 "The Madison Papers." p. 908. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 25 In like manner Mr. Justice Story, in his "Commentaries on the Constitution, 7 builds an argument on the name given to the new government. The Convention, by a vote of six States, decided that "a national government ought to be established." But, when this resolution was reconsidered, Mr. Ellsworth "objected to the term national government" 1 and it was rejected. The record says: "The first resolution that a national government ought to be established/ being taken up, . . . Mr. Ellsworth, seconded by Mr. Gorham, moves to alter it so as to run that the government of the United States ought to consist, etc." This alteration, he said, would drop the word national and retain the proper title, "the United States." 2 This motion was unanimously adopted by the Convention. 3 That is, they unanimously rejected "the term national government," and yet both Story and Webster build an argument on this term just as if it had been retained by them ! . "The name United States of America ," says the younger Story, "is an unfortunate one, and has, doubtless, led many minds into error. For it may be said, if the States do not form a confederacy, why are they called " United States ? " 4 This name is, indeed, a most unfor tunate one for the purpose of his argument, and for that of the whole school of politicians to which he belongs. But then, as we learn from the journal of the Convention of 1787, it was deliberately chosen by them as the most suit able name for the work of their own hands ; and that too in preference to the very name which the Avhole ^Northern school clings to with such astonishing pertinacity. From the same journal, as well as from the other records of the country, I shall hereafter produce many other things which are equally unfortunate for the grand argument of the Storys,-the Websters, and the Motleys of the Xorth. 1 "The Madison Papers." - Ibid., p. 90S. :! Ibid., p. 909. 4 "The American Question," by William IT. Story. CHAP T E E V THE CONSTITUTION OF 1787 A COMPACT THE QUESTIONS INVOLVED WAS the Constitution a compact? Was it a compact between the States, or to which the States were the parties ? Was it a compact from which any State might recede at pleasure? These three questions are perfectly distinct, and all the rules of clear thinking require that they should be so held in our minds, instead of being mixed up and confounded in our discussions. Yet Mr. Justice Story, in his long chapter on the "Nature of the Consti tution," discusses these questions, not separately and distinctly, but all in one confused mass, to the no little perplexity and distraction of his own mind. He carries them all along together, and, in the darkness and confusion occasioned by this mode of proceeding, he is frequently enabled to elude the force of his adversaries logic. Thus, for instance, he sets out with the flat denial of the doctrine that the Constitution is a compact ; and yet, when the evidences become too strong for resistance, or a cloud of witnesses rise up to confound him, he turns around, and instead of fairly admitting that the Constitution is a compact, asserts that if it is a compact it is not one between the States. AYhen too hardly pressed on this position, he replies that if it is a compact between the States it is not such a compact that it may be revoked at the pleasure of the parties. Thus, when he is driven from one position, he falls back upon another, and, finally rallies to a second, a third, and a fourth denial of the main proposition that the Constitution is a compact. ISTow, I intend to discus- each one of these questions distinctly and by itself; hold ing Mr. Justice Story to one and the same precise point, until it is either made good or else demolished. I hope, in this way, to dispel the mists and fogs he has thrown around the subject, and to bring out the truth into a clear and unmistakable light. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 27 WEBSTER S POSITION The same confusion of thought, and arising from the same source, pervades Mr. Webster s celebrated speech of February 16, 1833; though, it must be admitted, not to the same extent that it prevails in the "Commentaries" of Mr. Justice Story. Mr. Calhouii very justly complains of this want of clearness and precision in the positions of his great antagonist. "After a careful examination/ says he, "of the notes which I took of what the Senator said, I am now at a loss to know whether, in the opinion of the Senator, our Constitution is a compact or not, though the almost entire argument of the Senator was directed to that point. At one time he would seem to deny directly and positively that it was a compact, while at another he would appear, in language not less strong, to admit that it was." 1 Mr. Webster emphatically and repeatedly denies both that a Constitution is a compact and also that a compact is a Constitution ; or, in other words, he conceives that the natures of the two things are utterly incompatible with each other. He is very bold, and asserts that it is new language to call "the Constitution a compact." "This is the reason," says he, "which makes it necessary to abandon the use of Constitutional language for a new vocabulary, and to substitute, in place of plain historical facts, a series of assumptions. This is the reason why it is necessary to give new names to things, to speak of the Constitution, not as a Constitution, but as a compact, and of the ratification of the people not as ratifications, but as acts of accession." 2 Again, he complains of Mr. Calhoun, that "he introduces a new word of his own, viz., compact, as importing the principal idea, and designed to play the principal part, and degrades Constitution into an insignifi cant, idle epithet attached to compact. The whole then stands a Constitutional compact!" He is then particularly severe and eloquent upon the supposed outrage perpetrated on "our American political grammar," in thus degrading "CONSTITUTION" (the 1 "Mr. Calhoun s Speech," Feb. 26, 1833. 2 "Speech," Feb. 16, 1833. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATI :s capitals are his own) from its rightful rank "as a noun substantive." But, after all, the plain, simple fact is that this "new word," as Mr. Webster calls it, was as familiar to the ears of the authors of the Constitution as any other in the vocabulary of the great Convention of 1787. The terms Constitution and compact are, indeed, twin words, and convertible in the language of the fathers. Though "the term Constitutional affixes to the word compact no definite idee," says Mr. Webster, and in such connection "is void of all meaning," "yet it is easy, quite easy, to see why the gentleman uses it in these resolutions." Now, what is the reason, the deep design, that induces Mr. Calhoun to use an epithet "so void of all meaning?" "He can not open the book," says Mr. Webster, "and look upon our written frame of government without seeing that it is called a Constitution. This may well be appalling to him." We can not possibly imagine that Mr. Calhoun should, for one moment, have been disturbed or alarmed by such a discovery or revelation. It is certain that he nowhere betrays the least symptom of dismay at " the appalling" consideration that the Constitution is really a Constitution. That "noun substantive" seems to have inspired him with no sort of terror whatever. On the contrary, it appears to sit as easily on his political faith and to flow as familiarly from his lips as any other word in the language. We can imagine, however, why the Northern States should wish to get rid of both the idea of a compact and of the word; why the powerful should wish to ob literate and erase from the tablets of their memory every recollection and vestige of the solemn compact or bargain into which they had entered with the weak, but which they h#d never observed in good faith. OPPOSITE OPINIONS AND WEBSTER S OWN CONFLICTING STATEMENTS It is perfectly certain that Mr. Webster s horror of the term compact, as applied to the Constitution, is of com paratively recent origin. It was wholly unknown to the fathers of the Constitution themselves. Mr. Gouverneur THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 2i> Morris., it is well known, was one of the most celebrated advocates for a strong national government in the Con vention of 1787 ; and yet, in that assembly, he used the words : "He came here to form a compact for the good of America. He was ready to do so with all the States. He hoped and believed that all would enter into such a com pact. If they would not, he would be ready to join with any States that would. But as the compact was to be voluntary, it is in vain for the Eastern States to insist on what the Southern States will never agree to." 1 Thus, this celebrated representative of the State of Pennsylvania, and staunch advocate of a strong national government, did not hesitate to call the Constitution a compact into which the States were to enter. Indeed, no one, at that early day, either before the Constitution was adopted or afterwards, hesitated to call it a compact. Mr. Gerry, the representative of Massachusetts, says: "If nine out of thirteen [States] can dissolve the compact, six out of nine will be just as able to dissolve the new one hereafter." Here again the new Constitution is called a compact. "In the case of a union of people under one Constitu tion," says Mr. Madison, while contending for the ratifica tion of the new Constitution by the people, "the nature of the pact has always been understood to exclude such an interpretation." 2 Thus, in the Convention of 1787, Mr. Madison called the Constitution a compact; a word which he continued to apply to it during the whole course of his life. In the celebrated resolutions of Virginia, in 1798, Mr. Madison used these words, "That this assembly doth explicitly and peremptorily declare that it views the powers of the Federal Government as resulting from the compact to which the States are parties." Again, in his almost equally celebrated letter to Mr. Everett, in 1830, he calls "the Constitution" "a compact among the States in their highest sovereign capacity." In the same letter Mr. Madison speaks of the States as "the parties to the Con- 1 "Madison Papers." p. 1081-2. 2 Ibid., p. 1184. 30 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES stitutional compact"; using the very expression which is so offensive to Mr. Webster s new "political grammar." Nay, it was only three years before, in the great debate on Foot s resolutions, that Mr. Webster himself had, like evefy one else, spoken of the Constitution as a compact, as a bargain which was obligatory on the parties to it. "It is the original bargain/ 7 says he, in that debate ; "the com pact let it stand ; let the advantage of it be fully enjoyed. The Union itself is too full of benefits to be hazarded in propositions for changing its original basis. I go for the Constitution as it is, and for the Union as it is." Nor is this all. He there indignantly repels, both for "himself and for the North/ "accusations which impute to us a disposition to evade the Constitutional compact." Yet, in the course of three short years, he discovers that there is no compact to be evaded and no bargain to be violated ! All such trammels are given to the winds, and Behemoth is free! How sudden and how wonderful this revolution in the views and in the vocabulary of the great orator of New England I 1 This language, in which the Constitution is called a com pact, is not confined to Morris, and Gerry, and Madison, and the Webster of 1830. Mr. Chief Justice Jay, of the Supreme Court of the Union, in the case of Chisholm vs. the State of Georgia, expressly declares that "the Constitu tion of the United States is a compact." 2 "Our Constitu tion of the United States," says John Quincy Adams, the sixth President of the Republic, "and all our State Con- 1 The great mind of Mr. Webster was in general more like the ocean in repose than in action ; and. as is well known, his habitual indolence often induced him to rely on others for political information. No one who will attentively compare his speech of 1833 with book iii, chap, iii, of Story s "Commentaries on the Constitution," can be at any loss to account for the origin of his "new poltical grammar," his "new rules of syntax," and his "new vocabulary." If he applies these epithets to the doctrines of Morris, and Gerry, and Madison, it is because old things have become new with him, and new things old. The secret of this revolution will be found, as we shall soon prove, in the work of Mr. Justice Story, which work was not written in 1830. Indeed it was not published until 1833: but then the first volume, containing book iii, chap, iii, was prepared, if not printed, before the speech of Mr. Webster, with whom the author was on the most intimate terms. It would have been well for the fame of Webster, in the eve of posterity, if he had more carefully examined such a question for himself. 2 3 Ball. R., p. 410. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 31 stitutions, have been voluntary compacts, deriving all their authority from the free consent of the parties to them." The Virginia Resolutions of 1798, already referred to as expressing the opinion of Mr. Madison, assert that "Vir ginia views the powers of the Federal Government as resulting from the compact to which the States are parties." Again, in the Virginia Report of 1800, it is said, "The States being parties to the Constitutional compact," etc. Edmund Pendleton, President of the ratifying Convention of Virginia, in 1788, in the course of his argument in favor of the new Constitution, says, "This is the only Govern ment founded in real compact." 1 Judge Tucker, in his commentaries on Blackstone, repeatedly calls the Constitu tion in question "a compact between the States" of the Union. The third President of the United States, as well as the sixth, Thomas Jefferson as well as John Quincy Adams, considered the Constitution "a compact." "The States," says Jefferson, "entered into a compact, which is called the Constitution of the United States." 2 The Convention of Massachusetts, which was called to ratify the Constitution of the United States, was, if possible, still more emphatic and decided in the expression of the same opinion. "Having impartially discussed, and fully considered," say they, "the Constitution of the United States of America," we acknowledge, "with grateful hearts, the goodness of the Supreme Ruler of the Universe in affording the people of the United States an opportunity, deliberately and peaceably, without fraud and surprise, of entering into an explicit and solemn compact with each other, by assenting to and ratifying a new Constitution," etc. Yet, in the face of all these high authorities, and of a hundred more that might be easily adduced, running from James Madison in the Convention of 1787 to Daniel Webster in the great debate of 1830, and embracing the lights of all sections and of all parties, it is asserted by this celebrated statesman, though certainly not as a states man, that the term compact, as applied to the Constitution, is "a new word," is a part and parcel of "the unconstitu- 1 "Elliott s Debates." vol. iii, p. 57. - Correspondence." vol. iv. p. 415. 32 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES tional language," of the "new vocabulary, which lias been invented to obscure the fundamental principles of the Government of the United States, and to justify secession ! So far, indeed, is this from being a new mode of speech that it is one of the most familiar words known to the fathers of the Constitution itself, or to its more early expounders. Even Tlie Federalist, in submitting the Con stitution to the people, sets it before them as "the com pact." 1 "The man," says Mr. Webster, "is almost untrue to his country who calls the Constitution a compact." It were, indeed, much nearer the truth to say that the man is not only almost but altogether untrue to himself, as well as to the most solemn records of his country, who can assert that the term compact, as applied to the Constitu tion, is "a new word," or the exponent of a new idea. The arguments of Mr. Webster to prove that the Con stitution is not a compact, are, if possible, as unfortunate as his assertions. If words be not things in reality, as well as in effect, then it will be found that his arguments possess an exceedingly small value. There are two words, in particular, in the use of which he displays far more of rhetorical legerdemain than of rigid logic. These are the two words, "compact" and "Constitution." No one pretends for a moment that every compact is a Constitution. There are compacts about soap and candles, about pepper and calicoes, or some such trifling thing, which no one would call a Constitution. It is only when a compact has for its object the institution or organization of a political society, or a civil government, that it is properly denominated a Constitution. Hence, in the ordinary acceptation of the words, compact falls far below the high-sounding noun substantive Constitution ; a cir cumstance of which any rhetorician may, if he choose, very easily avail himself. Mr. Webster has done so, and that, too, with no little popular effect. "We know no more of a Constitutional compact between sovereign powers," says he, "than we do of a Constitutional indenture of partnership, a Constitutional deed of conveyance, or a Constitutional bill of exchange. But we know what the Constitution is," etc. 1 No. xxxix. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 33 Perhaps we do, and perhaps we do not ; that is the very point in dispute. But certain it is that if we do know what the Constitution is we need not seek to illustrate its nature or to exhibit its history by any such deceptive use of words. Akin to this sort of reasoning., or rhetoric., is all that is said by Mr. Webster and Mr. Justice Story about lowering the Constitution by considering it as a "mere compact/ 7 or as "nothing but a compact/ It is, indeed, something more than a compact, something more high, and holy, and honorable. Though in its nature it is a mere compact, yet in its object, which is no less than to institute or organize a political society, it is the most solemn and sacred of all earthly transactions. Such com pacts should not be despised, nor should they be explained away, or trampled under foot by the powerful ; they involve the destiny of millions. Mr. Webster admits that the Constitution is "founded on consent or agreement, or on compact"; meaning no more by that word than "voluntary consent or agreement/ But he denies that it is itself a compact. "The Constitu tion is not a contract," says he, "but the result of a con tract ; meaning no more by contract than assent. Founded on consent it is a government proper." Now, Mr. Webster himself being the judge, the Constitution is not a govern ment at all; for a government is, says he, "the political being created by the Constitution or fundamental law." But "founded on consent," not on implied or necessitated, but on "voluntary consent," it is a compact proper. Mr.. Webster is compelled to call the Constitution a govern ment in direct violation of his own definitions and princi ples, in order to keep from calling it a compact. In what manner the Constitution is founded on consent, on a deliberate and voluntary consent, Mr. Webster has himself told us only a few pages in advance of the above admission. "It is to be remarked," says he, "that the Constitution began to speak only after its adoption. Until it was ratified by nine States it was but a proposal, the mere draft of an instrument. It was like a deed drawn but not executed." This is most exactly and perfectly true. The Constitution was a dead letter, a powerless and in- 34 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES operative thing, until the ratification or solemn "voluntary assent" of nine States breathed into it the breath of life. It was from this consent, from this compact of nine States, that "the Constitution resulted" as a living or an authori tative document. But when the nine States assented to that "proposal or mere draft of an instrument/ and ratified the same by signing it, then each and every article therein specified and written became an article of agreement between the parties to it. "It was like a deed drawn but not executed." But when executed or ratified it was then like a deed signed by the parties; and all the written articles thereof became articles of agreement between the parties. Thus the Constitution not only resulted from the com pact of the nine States, but became itself the compact ; or, in other words, the written expression of the terms, the conditions, and the articles of the compact. This is what we mean by calling the Constitution a compact between the States. And is not this the language of truth ? THE NATURE OF A COMPACT Now, on what conditions, or in what cases, does such voluntary consent become a compact proper? Each of the nine States, as it assented to and ratified the Constitu tion, agreed to all its terms and articles. It agreed to forego the exercise of various powers, and to assume various important liabilities, in consideration that eight other States would do precisely the same thing. And it also agreed that the powers thus delegated by the nine States, or conferred on the general government to be erected for the common good, should be distributed, exercised, limited, and controlled, according to the terms and articles of the Constitution. Is not this a compact proper ? Have we not here mutual promises, each State parting with what it possessed, and, in consideration thereof, seeking to derive some benefit from the others? If so, then is not this a compact in the proper sense of the word ? The same idea is perfectly expressed by Mr. Webster in the speech before us. "On entering into the Union," THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES 35 says he, "the people of each State gave up a part of their own power to make laws for themselves, in consideration that, as to common objects, they should have a part in making laws for other States/ 7 Here is the voluntary relinquishment on the one part, and the valuable consider ation on the other. Is not this a contract proper ? If not, then have Blackstone, and Kent, and Pothier, and Domat, and Story written in vain on the nature and law of con tracts. If not, then indeed may we despair of ever arriving at the meaning of any one word in any one language under the sun. It possesses every conceivable attribute of a valid con tract. 1. There were "the parties capable of contract ing" the States. 2 It is admitted to have been "volun tary." 3. There was "the sufficient consideration"--the powers surrendered, and the liabilities incurred. Thus it fully answers to every condition laid down by Judge Story himself, 1 as the tests or criteria of a contract proper. It bears no resemblance to those imaginary transactions which certain European writers have invented to explain the origin of their governments, and to give stability to their political theories by fastening them, as with anchors, to past ages. On the contrary, it is historical and real. The time and the manner, the substance and the form, and all the stipulations, are written down and known. It was deliberately and solemnly entered into yesterday ; and it is as deliberately and solemnly denied to-day. Such is the incurable sophistry of power ! The constitution of England is not a compact. There is not, in all the history of England, the least intimation of the people s having assembled, either by themselves or by their representatives, to establish the institution of King, or Lords, or Commons. Yet these three powers constitute the main features in the government of Great Britain. Each power holding the balance between the other two, so as to prevent either from gaining the ascend ancy, is what forms the stable equilibrium of the constitu tion of England. But yet certain parts of the British con stitution are compacts, and are so called by writers who 1 "Conflict of Laws," p. 307. 36 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES reject the theory of a compact as to the whole. According to De Lolme, and other authors, Great Britain owes her admirable constitution to the Norman Conquest rather than to compact. "It is to the era of the conquest/ says he, "that we are to look for the real foundation of the English constitution." Yet changes and improvements in that constitution which, instead of growing, were made by competent parties, he calls compacts. Thus, says he, in reference to the accession of William III to the throne, "care was taken to repair the breaches which had been made in the constitution, as well as to prevent new ones, and advantage was taken of the rare opportunity of enter ing into an original and express compact between king and people." 1 Then, after having specified some of the improvements made in the constitution by this compact, he adds, "Lastly, the keystone was put to the arch by the final establishment of the liberty of the press. The Revolution of 1689 is, therefore, the third grand era in the history of the con stitution of England." Again, ^he says, "Without mention ing the compacts which were made with the first Kings of the Norman line, let us only cast our eyes on Magna Charta, which is still the foundation of English liberty, 2 being the great compact by which the Kings, the barons, and the people 3 entered into certain mutual stipulations respecting the prerogatives of the Crown and the rights of the subject." Thus the English revolution, like our own., was followed by a compact; and the only difference was that the com pact of 1688 was in addition to an old constitution, whereas the compact of 1788 was a constitution in toto ccelo. Locke, the great popular champion of the theory of the social compact, was then in the ascendant in the L T nited States, as he was with the Whigs in. England. That theory, though exploded now, was then almost universally received in America. That is to say, exploded by showing that there is no historical evidence of any such compact at 1 "De Lolme on the Constitution," p. 48. - Ibid., p. 287. 3 1 say the people, because those who followed the barons at Runny- mede demanded and obtained stipulations in favor of the people as well as in favor of their leaders. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 37 the origin of the governments of the Old World, and that v the alleged transaction was fictitious. 1 But the fiction, which had been only partially realized at the end of revo lutions, and not at the beginning of societies, became a fact in the hands of American legislators. In the language of Gouverneur Morris, they came to the Convention of 1787 "to make a compact/ 7 and they made one. But this draft of a compact, we are told, calls itself a Constitution, and not a compact at all. Very well. Sup pose it had called itself a compact, even an "original, explicit, and solemn compact/ 7 would it not have been just as easy for Mr. Justice Story to affirm that this only meant an "implied contract," as it was for him to do the same thing in regard to the Constitution of Massachusetts? But although the Convention of 1787 did not, on the very face of the Constitution, call itself a compact, yet in the letter which, by their "unanimous order/ 7 was dispatched with that instrument to the President of Congress, they use the same language in describing the nature of the transaction that is employed by Sidney, and Locke, and Eousseau to define "the social contract/ 7 as we shall here after see. Although Mr. Justice Story endeavors to bring discredit on the "explicit and solemn 77 compacts of the New World, by identifying them with the vague and visionary theories of the Old, yet he is perfectly aware of the difference between the fact in the one case and the hypothesis in the other, whenever it suits his purpose to use such knowledge. Thus, he says, in relation to his own Pilgrim Fathers: "Before their landing they drew up and signed a voluntary compact of government, forming, if not the first, at least 1 This is the ground taken, and unanswerably maintained by Hume, in his essay on the "Original Contract," "Essays," vol. i. Essay 12. The theory of Rousseau is rejected by M. Comte ("Theorie de Legis lation," liv. i, c. ii) on the same ground. Sir William Temple ("Works," vol. ii, pp. 37, 46) had previously rejected the doctrine of the "Social Contract." Kant, the philosopher of Kb nigsberg, treats it as a frivolous and impractical notion. Heeren ("On Political Theories," p. 239) says that a social contract neither was, nor could have been, actually concluded. Stahl ("Philosophy of Rights," vol. ii, part ii, p. 142) rejects the doctrine as visionary. Godwin, likewise .("Political Justice," book iii, c. ii and iii), rejects it. The doctrine of the social compact is subjected to an exhaustive analysis by Mr. Austin ("Prov. of Jurisprudence," 331-71), and triumphantly refuted. Jeremy Bentham, likewise, rejects the same hypothesis as visionary. 38 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES the best authenticated case of an original social contract for the establishment of a nation which is to be found in the annals of the world. Philosophers and jurists have perpetually resorted to the theory of such a compact by which to measure the rights and duties of governments and subjects; but for the most part it has been treated as an effort of imagination, unsustained by the history or practice of nations, and furnishing little of solid instruction for the actual concerns of life. It was little dreamed of that America should .furnish an example of it in primitive and almost patriarchal simplicity." 1 Thus Massachusetts has taken the lead of all the States in the world in the making of social compacts, and also in the breaking of them. This last point will, hereafter, be most fully illustrated and proved. , The original draft of the Constitution of Massachusetts was drawn up by John Adams, the second President of the United States, and he certainly entertained no doubt that he was drawing up an "explicit and solemn compact," or reducing the theory of European writers to practice, "It is," says he, "Locke, Sidney, Rousseau, and DeMably reduced to practice." 2 All these celebrated authors on the "social contract" reduced to practice ! But it is all in vain. For if the fiction is reduced to fact it is only that the fact may be again reduced to fiction. Massachusetts keep her bargains ! Even her most gifted sons, her Story s and her Websters, exert all their genius and exhaust the stores of their erudition to explain away and reduce to a mere nullity her most solemn social compacts, both State and Federal! The theory becomes a fact, and this fact calls itself "an original, explicit, and solemn compact." But then, as interest or power dictates, the fact is explained away, and there ends all the solemn farce. "Majorities, in a democracy, do not rely on Constitu tions, do not care for Constitutions. They rely on numbers and the strong arm." They spurn, with more than im perial scorn, the limitations and restraints which written Constitutions or judicial decisions would impose on their 1 "Story on the Constitution," book i, chap, iii, p. 37. 2 "John Adams Works," vol. iv, p. 216. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 39 sovereign will and pleasure. They respect such paper checks, such dictates of reason and justice, just about as much as the raging billows of the ocean respected the line which Canute drew upon its shores. In the strong lan guage of De Tocqueville, nothing can restrain them from crushing whatever lies in their path. CHAPTER VI THE CONSTITUTION OF 1787 A COMPACT BETWEEN THE STATES THE FACTS OF THE CASE IN discussing the question of the preceding chapters, whether the Constitution was a compact, I introduced much matter which incidentally showed that it was a compact between the States. In like manner, I shall, in proving that the States are the parties to the Constitution, produce much additional evidence that it is a compact. In order to show that the States are the parties to the Constitutional compact, let us consider : ( 1 ) The facts of the case; (2) The language of the Constitution itself; and (3) The views of Hamilton, Madison, Morris, and other framers of the Constitution; and (4) The absurdities flowing from the doctrine that the Constitution is not ^a compact between the States, but was ordained by the people of America as one nation. THE DEFECTS OF THE CONFEDERATION "It appears to me," says Mr. Webster, "that the plainest account of the establishment of this government presents the most just and philosophical view of its foundation." True, very true. There is, indeed, no proposition in the celebrated speech of Mr. Webster, nor in any other speech, more true than this; "and, besides, it goes directly to the point. For the great question which Mr. Webster has undertaken to discuss relates not so much to the super structure of the government, as to "its foundation." This is the question : How was the Constitution made or ordained, and on what does it rest? Bearing this in mind, let us proceed to consider, first, his plain account of the establishment of the government of the United States, and then the arguments in favor of his position. First, let us consider, item by item, his plain account. "The people of the several States," says he, "had their separate governments, and between the States there also THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES 41 existed a Confederation." True. "With this condition of things the people were not satisfied, as the Confederation had been found not to fulfill its intended objects. It was proposed, therefore, to erect a new common government, which should possess certain definite powers, such as regarded the property of the people of all the States, and to be formed upon the general model of American Consti- p tutions." . This is not so plain. It seems partly true and partly false. We are told that the people had discovered the defects of the Confederation, and were consequently not satisfied with it. Alexander Hamilton, a contemporary witness, tells a very different story. "Men of intelligence," says he, "dis covered the feebleness of the structure" of the Confedera tion ; "but the great body of the people, too much engrossed with their distresses to contemplate any but the immediate causes of them, were ignorant of the defects of their Constitution." 1 It was only "when the dangers of the war were removed," and the "men of intelligence" could be heard, that the people saw "what they had suffered, and what they had yet to suffer from a feeble form of government." 2 "There was no need of discerning men," as Hamilton truly said, "to convince the people of their unhappy con dition." But they did need to be instructed respecting the causes of their misery. So far was the great body of the people from having discerned for themselves the causes of their troubles that Mr. Madison ascribes his ability to make this discovery to his peculiar situation. "Having served as a member of Congress," says he, "through the period between March, 1780, and the arrival of peace, in 1783, I had become intimately acquainted with the public distresses, and the causes of them." Thus enlightened, and, under the dreadful aspect of affairs, "sympathizing in the alarm of the friends of free government at the threatened danger of an abortive result to the great, and perhaps last, experiment in its favor," Mr. Madison could not be "insensible to the obligation to aid as far as he could in averting the calamity." 3 Hence he acceded to 1 "Works," vol. ii, p. 445. - Ibid. 3 "Madison Papers," p. 693. 42 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES the desire of his fellow-citizens of the country, and became a member of the Legislature of Virginia, "hoping," as he declared, "that he might there best contribute to incul cate the critical posture to which the revolutionary cause was reduced, and the merit of a leading agency of the State in bringing about a rescue of the Union, and the blessings of liberty staked on it, from an impending catastrophe." THE NATURE or THE PROPOSED CHANGE It thus appears that the first step which, in the end, led to a change of the Federal Government, was not a popular movement ; it did not originate with the people ; it sprang from the brain of James Madison, and manifested itself in the action of the Legislature of Virginia. But what was this action ? Was it to change the form of the Federal Government ? Far from it. The resolution of the Virginia Legislature, drawn up by Mr. Madison, and introduced by Mr. Tyler, 1 merely appoints commissioners to meet such commissioners as may be appointed by the other States, "to take into consideration the trade of the United States," and "to consider how far a uniform system in their com mercial regulations may be necessary to their common interest and permanent harmony." It suggests no change whatever in the Federal Government, except in so far as this may be implied in a uniform system of commercial regulations. This resolution, as every one knows, led to the Annapolis Convention, which took the next great step towards the formation of the new Constitution. Nor was this a popular movement. It originated in the brain of Alexander Hamilton. In the address of that Convention, he says, "That the express terms of the power to your commis sioners supposing a deputation from all the States, and having for its object the trade and commerce of the United States, your commissioners did not conceive it advisable to 1 The resolution was introduced by Mr. Tyler, rather than its author, because, "having never served in Congress," he "had more the ear of the house than those whose services there exposed them to an imputable bias." "Madison Papers," p. 696. So great was the jealousy of the Federal Congress in those days. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 43 proceed on the business of their mission under the circum stances of so partial and defective a representation." The address then proceeds to recommend "a general meeting of the States in a future Convention/ with powers extending to "other objects than those of commerce." "They are the more naturally led to this conclusion/ says the Convention, "as in their reflections on the subject they have been in duced to think that the power of regulating trade is of such comprehensive extent, and will enter so far into the grand system of the Federal Government., that to give it efficacy, and to obviate questions and doubts concerning its precise nature and limits, may require a correspondent adjustment in other parts of the Federal system." "That there are important defects in the system of the Federal Government," continues the address, "is acknowl edged by the acts of those States which have concurred in the present meeting. That the defects, upon a closer examination, may be found greater and more numerous than even these acts imply, is at least so far probable, from the embarrassment which characterizes the present state of our national affairs, foreign and domestic, as may reasonably be supposed to merit a deliberate and candid discussion, in some mode which will unite the sentiments and counsels of all the States." HAMILTON AND MADISON ORIGINATE THE CHANGE IN FEDERAL GOVERNMENT In compliance with this recommendation of "a general meeting of the States in a future Convention," twelve States met at Philadelphia on the 14th of May, 1787, with instructions to join "in devising and discussing all such alterations and further provisions as may be necessary to render the Federal Constitution adequate to the exigencies of the Union." 1 "The recommendation was received by the Legislature of Virginia," says Mr. Madison, "which happened to be the first that acted on it, and the example of her compliance was made as conciliatory and impressive 1 "Madison Papers," p. 706. These are the words of the resolution of Virginia ; the instructions of the other States were equivalent to these. 44 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES as possible." 1 Thus it was Alexander Hamilton, as the master spirit of the Annapolis Convention., who first con ceived the idea of a general Convention to revise and amend the Federal Government, and it was James Madison, as the great ruling genius of the Legislature of Virginia, who gave the first and most powerful impulse to that conception. The great mass of the people had very little to do with the movement. "A resort to a general Convention," says Mr. Madison, "to remodel the Confederacy [i. e., the Confederation. Ed.] was not a new idea." 2 He then mentions five persons by whom this idea had been entertained ; namely, Pelatiah Webster, Colonel Hamilton, E. H. Lee, James Madison, and Noah Webster. None of these, however, go beyond the idea of Hamilton, "to strengthen the Federal Con stitution"; or of Madison, to supply its defects. 3 But if this had been a popular movement, Mr. Madison could easily have found, during the period of three years, more than five candidates for the once hotly-contested honor of having conceived the first idea of a Convention to remodel the Confederation or to amend the Federal Constitution. The plain truth is that it was Alexander Hamilton, and not the people, who, grappling with the vast and compli cated idea of a regular commercial system, saw the changes which such a system must introduce into the Federal Gov ernment. Hence it was Alexander Hamilton, and not the people, who became dissatisfied with the Confederation as it was, and sought to have its Constitution remodeled. "He was the first," as the historian of the Constitution has truly said, "to perceive and develop the idea of a real union of the people of the United States." 4 1 "Madison Papers," p. 70S. - Ibid., p. 706. 3 The two Websters, 1 elatiah and Noah, do show some originality. The one, in 1781, seeing that Congress had not sufficient authority "for the performance of their duties" (though he does not tell us what duties they had to perform, except to exercise the authority entrusted to them), suggests the plan of a Continental Convention, for the express purpose, "among other things, of enlarging the duties of their Constitution." The other, in 1784, wished for a government "which should act, not on States, but directly on individuals." If this idea really originated with Noah Webster, then there are many who will think that his political pamphlet cancelled the obligations which his spelling book conferred on the country. Mr. Webster was also original in his orthography. 4 "History of the Constitution of the United States," by Curtis, vol. i, p. 413. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 45 THE CONFEDERATION A GOVERNMENT It was not proposed then, as Mr. Webster alleges, and no one ever proposed, to set aside the Confederation in order to establish a government. The Confederation was itself a government. This contrast between the Confed eration and a government, as things essentially different in kind, which pervades the whole of Mr. Webster s speech, and which is even interwoven with his "plain account of the establishment of the government" of the United States, is purely a hypothesis of his own. Hamilton and the Convention of Annapolis repeatedly speak, as we have seen, of "the Federal Constitution" and "the Federal Government." Madison and the Legislature of Virginia use precisely the same language in reference to the same objects. Even Pelatiah Webster, in this respect, far less original than his great namesake, speaks of the "Constitution"^ of the Federal Government. The Con vention of 1787 also call the old Confederation "the Federal Government." 1 EACH STATE INDEPENDENT IN ADOPTING THE CONSTITUTION But we must proceed to the next item of Mr. Webster s plain account. "This proposal," says he, "was assented to", and an instrument was presented to the people of the several States for their consideration. They approved it, and agreed to adopt it, as a Constitution." True, as far as it goes. But when Mr. Webster asks, "Is not this the truth of the whole matter?" we are bound to answer that this is either not the truth of the whole matter, or it is not the whole truth of the matter. On the contrary, it omits precisely those great truths which shed the most light on the foundation of the government of the United States. One might well suppose, from the above statement, that the people of the several States had jointly approved the Constitution, and jointly ordained it as a Constitution. But however essential this view may be to the theory of 1 "Madison Papers," pp. 730-35, etc. 46 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES Mr. Webster and his theory is as baseless as the fabric of a vision without it it has not the shadow of a foundation in the facts of history. The plain and unquestionable fact is that each State adopted or rejected the Constitution for itself, and for itself alone. No twelve States could by their united action lay the bonds of a new Constitution on the thirteenth State. This was universally conceded. The little State of Ehode Island stood aloof ; and though her conduct was reprobated, no one denied her right. Neither all the other States com bined, nor all the people of America, had the shadow of an authority to constrain her action, or to control her own free choice. No power on earth could touch the priceless pearl of her sovereignty in the affair. No one presumed to question her right to decide for herself. This right was then as clear as the sun, and all eyes recognized it. And this was true, not only in relation to Rhode Island, but also to each State in the Confederation. For in the act of reunion each State was perfectly free and independent, uncontrolled and uncontrollable by any power upon earth. But this fact, which is far too recent and too well authenticated to be denied by any one, goes to the very foundation of the government of the United States, and shows that its Constitution rested on a federal, and not on a national act. It shows that it was a union of States, effected by the several acts of each State, and not the union of all the individuals in America, acting as one political community. EEPLY TO CONTRARY OPINION OF MOTLEY Mr. Webster s "plain account" is, in fact, a gross falsi fication of history. If possible, however, it is surpassed by Mr. Motley. This most unscrupulous writer asserts : "The Constitution was not drawn up by the States, it was not promulgated in the name of the States, it was not ratified by the States." 1 Now each and every one of these assertions is diametrically opposed to the truth. Strike out the little syllable "not" from every clause of the above 1 "Rebellion Records," vol. 1, p. 211. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 47 sentence, and it will then express the exact truth. For, in the first place, as the record shows, it is a plain and incontrovertible fact that the Constitution was drawn up or framed by the States. It was drawn up or framed, as every one knows, by the Convention of 1787; in which the States, and the States alone, were represented. Every iota of the Constitution was decided upon, and found a place in that written instru ment, by a vote of the States ; each State having one vote ; the little State of Delaware, for example, having an equal vote with New York, Pennsylvania, or Virginia. No fact should be more perfectly notorious, or well known, than this ; for it stands out everywhere on the very face of the proceedings of the Convention, which framed the Consti tution. Thus, for example, "On the question for a single Executive; it was agreed to Massachusetts, Connecticut, Pennsylvania, Virginia, North Carolina, South Carolina, Georgia, aye 7 ; New York, Delaware, Maryland, no 3." 1 In like manner, every other item of the Constitution was decided upon, and the whole instrument formed, by a vote of the States; acting as separate, independent, and equal bodies. How, in the face of such a fact, could Mr. Motley so boldly assert that the Constitution was not drawn up, or framed, by the States? By whom, then, was it framed? Was it framed by "the pe ople of the United States in the aggregate"; acting as one nation? Nothing is farther from the truth. There is not even the shadow of a foundation for any such assertion or insinua tion. Will it be said that the Constitution was drawn up, not by the States, but by those who proposed its various articles? If so, such a subterfuge would be nothing to the purpose, and very far from deserving a moment s notice. The second assertion of Mr. Motley, that the Constitu tion "was not promulgated in the name of the States," is equally unfortunate. For, as every one knows, it was promulgated by the Congress of the Confederation in which the States alone were represented, and in which all the States were perfectly equal. The "Articles of Confedera tion" says: "In determining questions in the United 1 "The Madison Papers," p. 783. 48 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES States, in Congress assembled, each State shall have one vote/ 1 It was thus as equals that the States voted in determining to promulgate the new Constitution ; and it was in consequence of that action of the States that the Constitution was promulgated and laid before the people of the several States for their adoption. Here, again, in direct opposition to the unblushing assertion of Mr. Motley, the Constitution was promulgated by the States in Congress assembled. If Mr. Motley had only deigned to glance at the history of the transaction about which he speaks so confidently, he could not have failed to perceive that the Constitution was first submitted, by the Convention of 1787, "to the United States in Congress assembled" ; 2 and that it was afterwards, in con formity with the opinion of the Convention, promulgated by the States "in Congress assembled." But Mr. Motley s theory of the Constitution takes leave of history; and has little to do with facts, except to contradict them. "The Constitution was not ratified by the States," says Motley. In the Resolutions just quoted, and which were unanimously adopted by the Convention of 1787, we find this clause: "Resolved, That in the opinion of this Con vention that as soon as the Convention of nine States shall have ratified this Constitution, the United States in Congress as*sembled should fix a day on which electors should be appointed by the States which slia/( hare ratified the same," etc. Not one of the fathers of the Constitution ever imagined that it was not ratified by the States. But in this instance, as well as in many others, their most familiar idea is repudiated, and their most explicit language is contradicted by Mr. Motley. In the sentence next to the one above quoted from Motley, he says : "The States never acceded to it \ the Constitution], and possess no power to secede from it." 3 This peremptory and flat contradiction of the language of the fathers of the Constitution deserves no further notice, since it has already -been sufficiently exposed. 1 Art. v. 2 Resolutions which, "by the unanimous order of the Convention" of 1787, was forwarded with the Constitution to Congress. 3 Chapter iii. A. T. BLEDSOE CHAP TEE VII THE CONSTITUTION A COMPACT BETWEEN THE STATES THE LANGUAGE OF THE CONSTITUTION The Preamble Quoted. "We the people of the United States, in order to form a more perfect union, . . . do ordain and establish this Constitution for the United States of America." The first clause of this preamble to the Constitution, wholly detached from its history and from every other portion of the same instrument, as well as from all the contemporary and subsequent expositions of its authors, is made the very corner-stone of the Northern theory of the general government of the United States. That tremendous theory, or scheme of power, has been erected on this naked, isolated, and, as we expect to show, grossly misinterpreted clause. From the bare words of this clause it is concluded, both by Story and Webster, that the Constitution was estab lished or ratified, not by a federal but by a national act; or, in other terms, that it was not ratified by the States, but by a power superior to the States, that is, by the sovereign will of "the whole people of the United States in the aggregate," acting as one nation or political com munity. With Puritanical zeal they stick to "the very words of the Constitution," while the meaning of the words is unheeded by them, either because it is unknown, or because it does not suit their purpose. But words are not the money, they are merely the counters, of wise men. The meaning of thje Constitution is the Constitution. In arriving at the meaning of these words, of the very clause in question, I shall not do the least violence to any law of language, or to any rule of interpretation. I shall, on the contrary, show that we are not "obliged to depart from the words of the instrument," 1 as Mr. Justice Story alleges, in order to sustain our interpretation of any por tion of it. I shall show that the Southern interpretation 1 "Commentaries on the Constitution," book iii, chap. ii. 52 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES of the clause in question is, in reality, the only fair, legiti mate, and reasonable sense of the preamble itself. Xor shall I, for this purpose, repeat the arguments which are usually employed by the friends of the South in this controversy. Those arguments are amply sufficient to refute the interpretation of Story and Webster. But they are so well put by others by John Taylor, of Caroline; by Judge Upshur, of A^irginia ; by John C. Calhoun, of South Carolina ; and especially by Mr. Spence, of Liverpool, that I need not repeat them here. Every one may find access to them in the admirable work of Mr. Spence. 1 Hence, passing by those arguments, I shall, by an appeal to the records of the Convention of 1787, make my position good, and annihilate the great corner-stone of the Northern theory of the Constitution of the United States. THE PREAMBLE DISCUSSED "We, the people of the United States/ The history of these words is curious and instructive. Only a portion of that history has, as yet, been laid before the public of England or of the United States. In the light of that history the great corner-stone in question will be found to crumble into dust and ashes ; and the only wonder will be, that considerations so clear and so conclusive should have been so long locked up, as a profound secret, in the records of the very Convention that formed the Constitution of the United States. It is well known that in the original draft of the Con stitution its preamble, instead of saying, "We, the people of the United States, 77 specified each State by name, as the previous Articles of Confederation had done. If it had remained thus, then the States would have appeared, on the very face of the preamble itself, as the parties to the Constitution. But the preamble, as is well known, was afterwards changed by omitting to mention the States by name. There are, however, some most important facts 1 We have only said admirable : but. all things considered. Mr. Spence s work is truly a wonderful production. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 53 connected with the change and the origin of the words in question, which seem to be wholly unknown on both sides of the Atlantic. They have, certainly, attracted no notice whatever from any of the writers on the great controversy between the North and the South. The first of these facts relates to the person by whom, and the manner in which, the change in question was effected; or, the words, "We, the people of the United States/ were substituted for an enumeration of the States by name. During all the great discussions of the Con vention, the preamble to the Constitution retained its original form; nor was there, from the beginning to the end of their deliberations, a single whisper of dissatis faction with it in that form. Every member of the Convention appeared perfectly satisfied that the States should stand, on the very front of the Constitution, as the parties to the compact into which they were about to enter. It was only after the provisions of the Constitution were agreed upon, and its language was referred to "a committee on style," that the names of the States were silently omitted," and the clause, "We, the people of the United States," substituted in their place. N~ow, it will not be denied that if this change had not been made by the "committee on style," then the States would have been the parties to the new Constitution just as they had been to the old Articles of Confederation. Hence, if the interpretation of Story and Webster be the true one, then it must be admitted that the "committee on style," appointed merely to express the views of the Con vention, really transformed the nature of the Constitution of the United States ! Then it must be admitted that the "committee on style," by a single turn of its pen, changed the course of history and the meaning of its facts ; causing the supreme power of the Federal Government to emanate, not from the States, but from the people of America as one political community! Did the "committee on style" do all this? And is it on legislation like this that a sovereign State is to be deemed guilty of treason and rebellion against the sublime authority of the people of America, and visited with the utmost vengeance? The 54 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES sublime authority of the people of America, the one grand nation, erected and established solely by the pen of the "committee on style!" This clause, "We, the people of the United States," introduced by the "committee on style," and passed over in perfect silence by the whole Convention, is the great stronghold, if it has one, of the Northern, theory of the Constitution. The argument from these words appears in every speech, book, pamphlet, and discussion by every advocate of the North. It was wielded by Mr. Webster in his great debate with Mr. Calhoun, in 1833, and still more fully in his still more eloquent speech on Foot s resolutions in 1830. "The Constitution itself," says he, "in its very front, declares that it was ordained and estab lished by the people of the United States in the aggregate." The fact is not so. The Constitution neither declares that it was established by the people of the United States in the aggregate, nor by the people of the United States in the segregate. But if we look into the history of the transaction we shall find that it was established by them in the latter character, and not in the former. We shall find that each State acted separately, and for itself alone; and that no one pretended, or imagined, that the whole aggregate vote of any twelve States could bind the thir teenth State, without its own individual consent and rati fication. In order to make out his interpretation, Mr. Webster interpolates the legislation of the "committee on style" with words of his own. How THE PREAMBLE WAS CHANGED The change in the preamble to the Constitution was effected by the pen of G-ouverneur Morris, one of the most zealous advocates in the Convention of 1787 for a strong national government. He certainly wished all power to emanate from the people of America, and to have them regarded as one great nation. But did he accomplish his wish? In the Convention, says the record, "Gkmverneur Morris moved that the reference of the plan [i. e., of the Convention] be made to one General Convention, chosen THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 55 and authorized by the people to consider, amend, and establish the same/ 31 This motion,, if adopted, would indeed have caused the Constitution to be ratified by "the people of the United States in the aggregate/ or as one nation. This would, in fact, have made it a. government emanat ing from the people of America in one General Convention assembled, and not from the States. But how was this motion received by the Convention ? Was it approved and passed in the affirmative by that body? It did not even find a second in the Convention of 1787. So says the record, 1 and this is a most significant fact. So completely was such a mode of ratification deemed out of the question that it found not the symptom or shadow of support from the authors of the Constitution of the United States. Now was the very object, which Gouverneur Morris so signally failed to accomplish directly and openly by his motion, indirectly and covertly effected by his style ? And if so, did he design to effect such a change in the funda mental law of the United States of America? It is cer tain that precisely the same effect is given to his words, to his style, as would have resulted from the passage of his motion by the Convention. Did Gouverneur Morris then intend that his words should have such force and effect? In supposing him capable of such a fraud on the Convention of 1787, I certainly do him no injustice, since we have his own confession that he actually perpetrated several such frauds on that assembly of Constitution- makers. "That instrument," says he, in reference to the Constitution, "was written by the fingers which write this letter. Having rejected redundant terms, I believed it to be as clear as language would permit ; excepting, nevertheless, a part of what relates to the judiciary. On that subject conflicting opinions had been maintained with so much professional astuteness that it became necessary to select phrases which, expressing my own notions, would not alarm others, nor shock their self-love; and to the best of my recollection this was the only part which passed without cavil/ 72 How adroitly, then, how cunningly, he 1 "The Madison Papers." p. 1184. 2 "Life and Writings of Gouverneur Morris," vol. iii, p. 323. 56 THE WAR BETWEEX THE STATES cheats the Convention into the unconscious sanction of his "own notions" ; and this great legislator of the jSTorth even in the purer days of the infant republic, was proud of the fraud ! Xor is this the only instance in which, according to his own confession and boast, Grouverneur Morris tricked the Convention into the adoption of his own private views. "I always thought," says he, in another letter, "that when we should acquire Canada and Louisiana, it would be proper to govern them as provinces, and allow them no voice in our councils. In wording the third section of the fourth article I went as far as circumstances would permit to establish the exclusion. Candor obliges me to add my belief that, had it been more pointedly expressed, a strong opposition would have been made." 1 Thus, as the penman of the "committee on style," he abused his high position, not only to mould the judiciary system of the United States to suit his "own notions," but also to determine the fate of two vast empires! Is not such legislation truly won derful? Instead of weighing every word with the utmost care, and then depositing it. in the Constitution as under the solemn sanction of an oath, the Convention trusts the style of the instrument to a fine writer, who cunningly gives expression to his own views in opposition to those of the assembly ! "In a play, or a moral," says Jeremy Bentham, "an improper word is but a word; and the impropriety, whether noted or not, is attended with no consequences. In a body of laws especially of laws given as Constitutional ones an improper word would be a national calamity and civil war may be the consequences of it. Out of one foolish word may start a thousand daggers." How true, and how fearfully has this truth been illustrated by the history of the United States ! But although Gouverneur Morris was capable of such a fraud on the Convention, we have no good reason to believe he intended one by the substitution of the words, "We, the people of the United States," for the enumeration of all the States by name. He has nowhere confessed to any such thing; and, besides, he did not understand his own words as they are so confidently understood by Story and 1 "Life and Writings of Gouverneur Morris." vol. iii. p. 193. THE AVAR BETWEEN THE STATES 57 Webster. Every rational inquirer after truth should, it seems to me, be curious to know what sense Gouverneur Morris attached to the words in question, since it was by his pen that they were introduced into the preamble of the Constitution. Xor will such curiosity be diminished, but rather increased, by the fact that he did, in some cases, aim to foist his own private views into the Consti : tution of his country. How, then, did Gouverneur Morris understand the words, "We, the people of the United States?" Did he infer from these words that the Consti tution was not a compact between States, or that it was established by the people of America, and not by the States ? I answer this question in the words of Gouvemeur Morris himself. "The Constitution," says he, "was a compact, not between individuals, but between political societies, the people, not of America, but of the United States, each enjoying sovereign power and of course equal rights." 1 Language could not possibly be more explicit. Xor could it be more evident than it is that Gouverneur Morris, the very author of the words in question, enter tained precisely the same view of their meaning as that maintained by Mr. Calhoun and his school. This point was, indeed, made far too clear by the pro ceedings of the Convention of 1787 for any member of that body to entertain the shadow of a doubt in relation to it. Xor can any one read these proceedings, as they deserve to be read, without agreeing with Gouverneur Morris that the authors of the Constitution designed it to be ratified, as in fact it was, by "the people of the United States," not as individuals, but as "political societies, each enjoying sovereign power, and of course equal rights." Or," in other words, without seeing that "the Constitution was a compact," not between individuals, "but between political societies," between sovereign States. This, in the next chapter, I hope and expect to make perfectly clear, by bringing to view the origin of the words, "We, the people," and by showing the sense in which they were universally understood and used by the member of the Convention of 1787 in the very act of framing the Con stitution of the United States. 1 "Life and Writings," vol. iii, p. 103. CHAPTER VIII THE CONSTITUTION OF 1787 A COMPACT BETWEEN THE STATES- THE LANGUAGE OF THE CONSTITUTION (Continued) FURTHER DISCUSSION OF THE CHANGE IN THE PREAMBLE THE Convention of 1787 did, as we have seen, refuse to call the government a national one, and gave it the name of "the government of the United States." Did they then make it a national one by enacting that it should be ordained by "the whole people of the United States in the aggregate" as one political society? Again, when it was proposed in the Convention to ordain the Constitution by "the people of the United States in the aggregate," in one General Convention assembled, the motion failed, as we have seen, to secure a second. Did Gouverneur Morris, then, the author of that proposal, achieve by his style what he failed to accomplish by his motion? If so, what should we think of the incompetency of the Convention ? Nor was this all. For Madison introduced a motion which required "a concurrence of a majority of both the States and the people" 1 at large to establish the Constitu tion; and this proposition was rejected by the Convention. All these motions, designed to connect the new government with a national origin, were lost, and the decree went forth that the Constitution should be established by the accession of nine States, each acting for itself alone, and to be bound only by its own voluntary act. Now,* the question is, was all this action of the Convention over ruled and defeated by the committee on style, or rather by its penman, Gouverneur Morris? If he formed such design, then it must be admitted that the Northern theory of the Constitution was conceived in fraud and brought forth in iniquity; and every honest man at the North ought to be ashamed both of its origin and its existence. 1 "The Madison Papers," p. 1470. THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES 59 But, as we have already seen, Gouverneur Morris did not understand his own words, "We, the people/ as they are understood by the more modern expounders of the Constitution at the North. Hence we have no reason to believe that he intended, in this case at least, a fraud on the design and will of the Convention. Was the whole thing done then, and the nature of the Constitution transformed, by a slip of the pen, or by accident ? After all their opposition both to the name and to the thing, did the Convention, by sheer oversight, blunder into the construction of a purely national government, by permitting it to be established by the people of America as one grand political community? If Mr. Justice Story s view of the words, "We, the people of the United States/ be correct, how did it happen that the opponents of such a mode of ratification said absolutely nothing ? The whole instrument, as amended by the committee on style, was read in the hearing of the Convention, beginning with the preamble, and yet the words, "We, the people of the United States," now deemed so formidable to the advocates of State sovereignty, did not raise a single whisper of opposition. How could this have happened if the words in question were supposed to mean the people of America, or the whole people of the United States as one political society? Were Mason, and Martin, and Paterson, and Ellsworth all too dull to perceive that meaning, which is so perfectly obvious to Mr. Justice Story, and which he imagines that nothing but the most purblind obstinacy can resist? Were all the friends of the States, as independent sovereignties, asleep on their posts while Gouverneur Morris thus transformed the nature of the Constitution, without knowing it himself, by causing it to emanate, not from the States, but from the people of America as one nation? No. Not one of these suppositions is the true one. The whole mystery is explained in the proceedings of the Convention of 1787, as exhibited in "The Madison Papers"; an explanation which, however, has hitherto been most unaccountably overlooked. We may there find the real meaning of the words in question, and see why they gave no alarm to the advocates of State sovereignty. 60 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES THE MODE OF KATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION If we cast our eyes all along the subject of "the mode of ratification/ 7 ranging from page 735 to page 1632 of "The Madison Papers/ we shall perceive that the question, whether the Constitution should be ratified by the people of "the United States in the aggregate," or by the several States, was not considered by the Convention at all. No such question was before the Convention. It was neither mooted nor considered by them. The error of Story and Webster is, that they construe the first clause of the Constitution as if it referred to one question; whereas, in fact, it referred to quite another and a far different question that is, they construed this clause in profound darkness as to the origin of its words, as well as to. their use and application in the Convention of 1787. If they had understood them as actually and uniformly used or applied by the framers of the Constitution, then they could neither have deceived themselves nor the people of the North. If, indeed, they had been members of that Convention, or had only examined its proceedings, they would have seen why the staunch advocates of State sovereignty raised not even the slightest whisper of opposition to the words, "We, the people. 7 Or, if Patrick Henry had been a member of that assembly/ then he could not have ex claimed, as he did, "Why say We, the people/ and not We, the States?" an exclamation so often quoted by Story, Webster, and the whole Northern school of poli ticians as a conclusive authority for then he would have seen that "We, the people/ 7 in the language of the framers of the Constitution., meant precisely the same thing as "We, the States/ 7 and neither more nor less. The question before the Convention was, whether the Constitution should be ratified by the legislatures or by the sovereign peoples of the several States. No one doubted that it was to be ratified by the States. This, as we shall see, was on all hands regarded as a settled point. The only question was, whether it should be ratified by the States, acting through their legislatures, or through THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 61 Conventions elected to represent the people for that special purpose. In the discussion of this question, most of -the members insisted that the Constitution should be ratified by the people, by the States in their sovereign capacity, or by their Conventions. These several modes of expression were, in the vocabulary of the Convention, used as convertible terms, as perfectly synonymous with each other. Hence the phrase, "the people of the United States," as used and understood by them, meant the people of the several States as contradistinguished from their legisla tures, and not the people of America as contradistinguished from the distinct and separate sovereign peoples of the different States. This application of the words is the invention of theorists merely. It was unknown to the Convention of 1787, and has had no existence except in the imaginations of those by whom their labors have been systematically misconstrued and perverted from their original design. Some few members of the Convention were in favor of leaving "the States to choose their own mode of ratifica tion" ; but the great majority of them insisted that the Constitution should be. referred to the States for ratifi cation, either through their legislatures or through their people in Conventions assembled. It was in regard to these two methods that the Convention was divided. All agreed that it should be done by "the States," and the only ques tion was as to how "the States" should do it. The idea that it was designed to be done, or that it was done, by the people of America as one nation, is the dream of a later day, and, as we shall see, is nothing but a dream. Some insisted that it should be ratified by the States in their corporate capacity this is, by their legislatures; and others that it should be ratified by the States in their sovereign political capacity that is, by their Conventions assembled for that express purpose. Or, in other words, some contended that it ought to be ratified by their general agents, the legislatures; and others that it ought to be ratified by their special agents, the Conventions elected and assembled to perform that high acl of sovereign 62 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES power. In both cases, it was to be ratified by the States, but. the opposite parties preferred different modes of ratification by them. THE DEBATE ox BATIFICATIOX In debating this question, as to the mode of ratification by the States (the only one before the Convention), some of the most inflexible advocates of State sovereignty insisted that it should be ratified by "the people of the United States." But then they understood this language, and every member of the Convention understood it to mean the peoples of the several States, as distinguished from their legislatures. If, for one moment, they had imagined that their language could have been construed to mean a ratification of the Constitution by the collective will of the whole people of America, they would have shrunk from its use with horror ! for they dreaded nothing more than the idea of such an immense consolidated democracy. On the contrary, they clung to the States, and to their rights, as the only sheet-anchor of safety against the overwhelming and all-devouring floods of such a national union of mere numbers or individuals. George Mason, no less than Patrick Henry, would have exclaimed against the words, "We, the people," if, as a member of the Convention of 1787, he had not learned that they only meant "We, the States." In discussing the question as to the mode of ratification by "the States," Mr. Mason said "he considered a reference of the plan to the authority of the people as one of the most important and essential of the resolutions. The legislatures have no power to ratify it. ... Another strong reason, said he, was that admitting the legisla tures to have a competent authority it would be wrong to refer the plan to them, because succeeding legislatures, having equal authority, could undo the acts of their prede cessors." 1 This argument was repeatedly urged by other members, and it was insisted that if the Constitution should be ratified by the legislatures of the States, instead 1 "Madison Papers," p. 1177. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 63 of by the people of the States, it would rest upon a weak and tottering foundation, since the legislatures which had established might claim the power to repeal. In like manner Mr. Madison said, "For these reasons, as well as for others, he thought it indispensable that the new Constitution should be ratified in the unexceptionable form, and by the supreme authority of the people them selves 1 that is, as the context shows, by the supreme authority of the people of the several States in opposition to their "legislative sanction only." Not one word was ever said during the whole of the debate about referring the Constitution to the people of the whole country in the aggregate for ratification. This idea had not then risen above the horizon of the political world, though it after wards became the great political sun of the Northern section of the Union. Those who advocated the mode of ratification by the people, or by the Conventions of the States elected for that purpose, prevailed over those who urged the ratification by the legislatures. The majority favored the mode of ratification by the people or the Conventions. Accord ingly, when the committee of detail reported a draft of the Constitution, we find these words : "Article XXI. The ratifications of the Conventions of - - States shall be sufficient for the organization of this Constitution/ 2 Thus it came to be perfectly understood that it should be ratified by the Conventions or the peoples of the several States, and not by their legislatures. But here the question arose, if the blank for the number of States should be filled with "seven," "eight," or "nine." The Constitution, as it stood, might, in the opinion of Mr. Madison, be put in force over "the whole body of the people, though less than a majority of them should ratify it." But, in the opinion of Mr. Wilson, "As the Constitu tion stands, the States only which ratify can be bound." 3 In order to remove this difficulty, and settle the question, Mr. King moved to add, at the end of Article XXI, the words "between the said States, so as to confine the opera- i "Madison Papers," p. 796. 2 Ibid., p. 1241. 3 Ibid., p. 1469. 64 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES tion of the government to the States ratifying the same/ 1 Thus it was Rufus King, at first one of the most strenuous advocates in the Convention of 178? for a strong national government, who introduced the words by which the Constitution was made binding "between the States so ratifying the same." These words proved acceptable to Madison and Wilson, though both were among the most zealous advocates of a strong general government in the Convention of 1787, and they became a part of the new Constitution. Tims it- was universally understood by the Convention, and so expressed, that the new Constitution was to be established "by the ratification of the Conventions of - States," and to be binding only "between the States so ratifying the same." During all this time the name of each State still retained its place in the preamble to the Constitution, in which the committee of detail made no change ; and if the party, with Gerry and Hamilton at their head, who wished to fill the blank with the whole thirteen States, had prevailed, we have no reason to believe that any alteration would in this respect have been made in the preamble to the Constitution. But when, after debate, the blank was filled k with "nine," it became impossible to specify the States between whom the new Constitution might be established or the new govern ment organized. Hence it became proper, if not necessary, to drop the specification of the States by name a change which, as we have seen, was first introduced by the committee on style, and read to the Convention without raising the slightest objection or murmur. We are now prepared to see, as in the clear light of noonday, why the words, "We, the people of the United States," which have since made so much noise in the political world, did not make any whatever in the Con vention of 1787. Why should George Mason, or any other adherent of State sovereignty, object to the words intro duced by the committee on style? They merely expressed the very thing for which he had contended, and which had been fully expressed in the seventh Article of the new 1 "Madison Papers." p. 147<>. THE AVAR BETWEEN THE STATES 65 Constitution. For when it was determined that the Con stitution should be ratified by "the Conventions of the States," and not by the legislatures, this was exactly equivalent, in the uniform language of the Convention of 1787, to saying that it shall be ratified by "the people of the States." Hence, the most ardent friend of State rights, or State sovereignty, saw no reason why he should object to the words, "We, the people of the United States/ because he knew they were only intended to express the mode of ratification by the States for which he had con tended that is, by the States in their sovereign capacity, as so many political societies or peoples, as distinguished from their legislatures. CHAPTER IX THE CONSTITUTION OF 1787 A COMPACT BETWEEN THE STATES THE VIEWS OF CERTAIN OF THE FRAMERS OF THE CONSTITUTION WEBSTER S STATEMENT THIS subject has already been anticipated, but by no means exhausted. Considering the unparalleled boldness of Northern assertion, it is necessary to lay bare a few more of its hidden mysteries. "Indeed/ says Mr. Webster, "if we look into all contemporary history ; to the numbers of The Federalist; to the debates in the Convention; to the publication of friends and foes, they all agree that a change had been made from a confederacy of States to a different system; they all agree that the Convention had formed a Constitution for a national government. With this result some were satisfied, and some were dissatisfied ; but all admitted that the thing had been done. In none of the various productions and publications did any one intimate that the new Constitution was but another compact between States in their sovereign capacity. I do not find such an opinion advanced in a single instance/ 71 Now this is certainly as bold and sweeping an assertion as could well be made in human language. It is certainly as full, round, and complete an untruth as was ever uttered. It will, upon examination, be found that, to use the mildest possible terms, it is fitly characterized by the two words high-sounding and hollow. It would, perhaps, be difficult for any man, except Mr. Webster and his successor in the Senate of the United States, to produce as bold and sweeping an assertion, which, like the above, is at every point diametrically opposed to the truth. I shall proceed to prove, and to establish beyond the shadow of a doubt, this heavy accusation against "the great expounder," by extracts from the records and publications to which he so solemnly appeals. 1 Speech in Senate, Feb. 16, 1833. THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES 67 I shall begin with the Convention that formed the Con stitution itself. It will not be necessary to reproduce the language of Gouverneur Morris. MADISON S OPINION James Madison himself, "the father of the Constitution," and the most laborious member of the Convention of 1787, called it, as we have seen, "a pact" between the States ii that Convention ; and from that day to the end of his life^ Mr. Madison continued to pronounce the new Constitutioi "a compact to which the States are the parties." In Virginia ratifying Convention of 1788, in "the numbei of The Federalist" in the Virginia Eesolutions of 98 am 99, in the Virginia Report of 1800, in his celebrated letter to Mr. Everett of 1830 ; in one and all of these well-known public documents, as well as in others from his pen, this illustrious architect of the Constitution most emphatically pronounced it "a compact to which the States are the parties." In the Virginia Resolutions, a political formula which the American people, of all parties and all sections, had sworn by for more than thirty years, Mr. Madison wrote for the legislature of his State: "This Assembly doth explicitly and peremptorily declare that it views the powers of the Federal Government, as resulting from the compact, to which the States are parties/ How com pletely, then, was the very existence of Mr. Madison, and of all the great transactions in which he had borne so conspicuous a part, ignored by Mr. Webster in the bold and astounding assertion that neither friend nor foe had ever considered the new Constitution as a . "compact between the States." The venerable old man must, indeed, have felt, as he read the speech of Mr. Webster, that he was fast sinking into oblivion, and that all the great transactions of his life were fast being forgotten amid the blaze of new ideas. Accordingly, in a letter to Mr. Webster, called forth by the very speech in question, Mr. Madison once more raised his voice in favor of the one invariable doctrine of his life. 68 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES "It is fortunate," says he in the letter referred to, "when disputed theories can be decided by undisputed facts ; and here the undisputed fact is that the Constitution was made by the people, but as embodied into the several States, who were parties to it." Again, in the same letter, he says: "The Constitution of the United States, being established by a competent authority, by that of the sovereign people of the several States, who were parties to it. " Most fortunate is it, indeed, when disputed theories may be tested by undisputed facts; but how infinitely unfortunate is it, when new and disputed theories begin to pass for everything, and indisputable facts for nothing! WILSON S POSITION All agree, says Mr. Webster, "The Federalist," "the debates in the Conventions," "the publications of friends and foes" all agree, "that a change had been made from a confederacy of States to a different system." ~Now, there is James Wilson, inferior only to Madison and Hamilton in the influence he exerted in favor of the new Constitution, who declares that the only object aimed at by the Con vention of 1787 was to enable the States "to confederate anew on better principles" ; and, if no more could be effected, he would agree to "a partial union of the States, with a door left open for the accession t>f the rest." Accordingly, it was finally agreed by the Convention that nine States might form the new Union, with a door left open for the accession of the other four. In fact, eleven States confederated on the new principles ; and it was more than a year before the remaining two States acceded to the compact of the Constitution, and became members of the Union. HAMILTON S VIEWS Even Alexander Hamilton in that great authority, The ^ederalist, to which Mr. Webster so confidently appeals, ift directly and flatly opposed to the bold assertion of "the great expounder." * If the new Constitution should be adopted, says he, the Union would "still be, in fact and in THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 69 theory, an association of States, or a confederacy. * 1 Again, in the eightieth number of the work, Hamilton calls the new Union "the CONFEDERACY"; putting the word in capital letters in order that it may not be over looked by the most superficial reader. If necessary, it might be shown by various other extracts, that Alexander Hamilton, while insisting on the adoption of the new Constitution in The Federalist, speaks ^of the new Union as a confederacy of States. How, then, could Mr. Webster avouch The Federalist to support the assertion that "a change had been made from a confederacy to a different system?" Was this in his character of "the great ex pounder," or of the great deceiver? This appeal to The Federalist appears, if possible, still more wonderful, when viewed in connection with other numbers of the same work. Indeed, it was objected to the new Constitution by its enemies, that "it would make a change from a confederacy to a different system" ; and this very objection is met and repelled in the pages of The Federalist. "Will it be said," demands The Federalist, "that the fundamental principles of the confederation were not within the purview of the Convention, and ought not to have been varied? I ask, what are these principles? Do they require that in the establishment of the Constitu tion the States should be regarded as distinct and inde pendent sovereigns? They are so regarded by the Con stitution proposed." 2 Nor is this all. In the preceding number of The Federalist, it is said : "Each State, in ratifying the Con-\ stitution, is considered as a sovereign body, independent of 1 V all others, and only to be bound by its own voluntary act."/ Thus, according to The Federalist, the Constitution was ratified by "each State, as a sovereign body, independent of all others."" No such thing, says Mr. Webster; it was not ratified by the States at all, it was ordained by a power superior to the States, by the sovereign will of the whole people of the United States; and yet he boldly and unblushingly appeals to The Federalist in support of his 1 The Federalist. No. ix. - No. xl. 70 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES assertion! Why did he not quote Tlie Federalist? Nay, why did he not read Tlie Federalist before he ventured on such a position? WEBSTER AND THE FEDERALIST Mr. Webster has, indeed, quoted one expression from Tlie Federalist. "The fabric of American empire/ says Hamilton, in the twenty-second number of Tlie Federalist, "ought to rest on the solid basis of THE CONSENT OF THE PEOPLE." After quoting these words, Mr. Webster adds, with his usual confidence, "Such is the language, sir, addressed to the people while they yet had the Constitution under consideration. The powers conferred on the new government were perfectly well understood to be conferred, not by any State, or the people of any State, but by the people of the United States." Eead the context, and this will be perfectly plain. "It has not a little contributed," says the context, "to the infirmities of the existing federal system, that it never had a ratification of the PEOPLE. Resting on no better foundation than the consent of the several Legislatures, it has been exposed to frequent and intricate questions concerning the validity of its powers; and has, in some instances, given rise to the enormous doctrine of legislative repeal." Such is the context of Mr. Webster s very partial and one-sided extract. It shows that Hamilton was arguing the advantage of the new system over the old, just as it had been argued in the Convention of 1787 ; because the old confederation rested on the consent of the Legislatures of the several States, whereas the new con federacy was to rest on the consent of the people of the several States. Hence it would be free from all doubts with respect to the power of "legislative repeal." If, instead of perverting the high authority of The Federalist by wresting one particular passage from its context, Mr. Webster had only read a little further, he would have discovered what was then "perfectly well understood" respecting the nature of the Constitution. He would have discovered that it was, according to The THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 71 Federalist, established, not by "the people of the United States in the aggregate," or as one nation, but by each of the States acting for itself alone. "The Constitution is to be founded," says The Federalist? "on the assent and rati fication of the people of America, given by deputies elected for the special purpose." This, too, is the language "addressed to the people, while they yet had the Consti tution under consideration." Why, then, is not this language seized upon, and held up as proof positive that the Constitution rested on the assent, "not of any State, or the people of any State," but on that of "the people of America ?" The reason is plain. Though these words, taken by themselves, would have answered Mr. Webster s purpose better than his extract from The Federalist; yet are they immediately followed, in the same sentence, by an explanation, which shows their meaning when used in The Federalist. "The Constitution is to be founded," says that highest of all authorities, "on the assent and ratification of the people of America, given by deputies elected for the special purpose; but," it is added, "this assent and ratification is to be given by the people, not as individuals comprising one entire nation, but as composing the distinct and independent States to which they respectively belong. It is to be the assent and ratification of the several States, derived from the supreme authority in each State the authority of the people them selves. The act, therefore, establishing the Constitution will not be a national, but a federal act." 2 Not so, says Mr. Webster, the Constitution was established not by a federal, but a national act: not by any State, or the people of any State, but by the whole people* of the United States as one sovereign body; and yet he appeals to The Federalist in support of his doctrine ! "That it will be a federal, and not a national act," con tinues The Federalist, "as these terms are understood by objectors, the act of the people, as forming so many inde pendent States, not as forming one aggregate nation, is obvious from this single consideration, that it is to result neither from the decision of a majority of the people of 1 No. xxxix. - Ibid. 72 THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES the Union, nor from that of a majority of the States. It must result from the unanimous assent of the several States that are parties to it, differing no otherwise from their ordinary assent than in its being expressed, not by the legislative authority, but by that of the people themselves. Were the people regarded in this transaction as forming one nation, the will of the majority of the whole people of the United States would bind the minority; in the same manner as the majority in each State must bind the minority; and the will of the majority must be determined either by a comparison of the individual .votes, or by con sidering the will of the majority of the States, as evidences of the will of the majority of the people of the United States. Neither of these had been adopted. Each State, in ratifying the Constitution, is considered as a sovereign body, independent of all others, and only to be bound by its own voluntary act." Could language be more perfectly explicit? Yet, directly in the face of all this, or else in profound ignorance of all this, Mr. Webster appeals to the authority of The Federalist in favor of the very position which, as we have seen, it so pointedly condemns. ISTay, in spite of the clear, explicit, and unanswerable words of The Federalist, Mr. Webster appeals to that work to show, as a fact then "perfectly well understood," that the powers of the new government were to be conferred, or its Constitution established, not by the States, nor by the people of the States, considered as sovereign bodies, and each acting for itself, but by the whole people of the United States as one sovereign body or nation ! To show, in one word, that the Union was formed, not by an accession of the States, but by the one people of the United States acting as a unit! "The great expounder" does not follow, he flatly contradicts, the very work he appeals to as the highest of authorities; and that, too, in regard to the greatest of all the political questions that have agitated the people of America ! OPPOSITION TO RATIFICATION There were those, it is true, who regarded the new Con stitution as the fundamental, or organic law, of one great THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 73 consolidated government. But these were its enemies. They represented it as such because they wished it to be rejected, and because they knew no other objection would render it so obnoxious to the people of the States. It is well known, indeed, that the greatest difficulty in the w^ay of the new Union was the jealousy of the central power, which the several States had long entertained. This jealousy was so great in the States of New York and of Virginia that when their Conventions met to ratify or to reject the Constitution it is well understood, and admitted, that they were both opposed to the new grant of powers. The State-Eights men in both Conventions, who, at first, were in favor of rejecting the Constitution, were in a majority, as is well known and fully conceded. It was only by the herculean labors of Alexander Hamilton that the Conventions of New York were, at last, induced to ratify it by a majority of three votes. In like manner, the labors, the management, and the eloquence of Mr. Madison succeeded, finally, after a long and desperate struggle, in carrying it in the Convention of Virginia by the small majority of ten votes. The result was long- doubtful in both Conventions. Patrick Henry, in the ratifying Convention of Virginia, put forth all his powers to cause the new Constitution to be rejected. His appeals to the jealousy of the States with respect to the power of the central government were tremendous. He dwelt, particularly, on the words of the preamble, "We, the people of the United States," to show that his most fatal objection to the new Constitution was well founded ; and he added, "States are the characteristic and soul of a confederacy. If the States be not the agents of this compact, it must be one great consolidated govern ment of the people of the United States/ He insisted that it would be so. But Patrick Henry, it should be remembered, was not a member of the Convention of 1787, and he was an enemy of the new Constitution. His mind was fertile and overflowing with objections. If he had known the history of the words, "We, the people of the United States/ 7 as it appears in the debates of the Con vention, which had not then been published, he would 74 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES have seen that "We, the people, 7 really meant "We, the States; or, We, the Convention/ acting in the name and by the authority of the sovereign people of the several States. 1 Or, if he had compared the words in question with the seventh Article of the Constitution he would have seen that the new Constitution was to be established by the States, and was to be binding only "between the States so ratifying the same." But as the enemy, and not the advocate, of the new Constitution, he labored to enforce his objection to it, rather than to consider and weigh its words, or explain its real meaning to the Convention. His objection would, no doubt, have proved fatal to the new Constitution, but for the presence and the power of James Madison, who met the great objection of Patrick Henry, and silenced much of the apprehension which his eloquence had created. He was known to have been the most diligent and active member of the Convention that formed the Constitution; and was supposed, therefore, to understand its real import better than any man in the ratifying Convention of Virginia. His position, and his means of information, certainly gave him a great advan tage over his eloquent rival, Patrick Henry. In his reply to Mr. Henry, he explained the words, "We, the people," precisely as he had before explained them in The Fed eralist. He said : "The parties to it were the people, but not the people as composing one great society, but the people as composing thirteen sovereignties." Again: "If it were a consolidated government," said he, "the assent of a majority of the people would be sufficient to establish it. But it was to be binding on the people of a State only 1 1/ their own separate consent/ This argument, founded on a well-known fact, was absolutely unanswerable. Yet Mr. Justice Story has, two or three times, quoted the words of Patrick Henry in the Virginia Convention, as if they were a most valuable authority, without a single, solitary word in relation to the unanswerable reply of Mr, Madison ! On this point he is profoundly silent ! That is to say, he construes the Constitution, not as it was under stood by its framers and friends, but as it was misrepre- : See chap. viii. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 75 sented by its enemies, in order to cause its rejection ! He holds up the words of the one as a great authority, and he does not let the reader of his most learned Com mentaries know the language of the other in reply! Was that honest? MISINTERPRETATIONS BY STORY AND OTHERS I object to the Massachusetts interpretation of the first clause of the preamble to the Constitution. 1. Because it falsifies the facts of history respecting the mode of its ratification, which was by the several States in Convention assembled, each acting for itself alone, "as a sovereign body, independent of all others, and to be bound only by its own voluntary act," and not by the people of America as one nation. 2. Because it makes these words, "We, the people," contradict the seventh Article of the Consti tution; an Article which, historically considered, has pre cisely the same origin and the same sense with those words themselves. 3. Because it attaches to these words a differ ent sense from that attached to them by the Convention of 1787, as seen in the debates which gave rise to them. 4. Because it contradicts the sense given to these words by Gouverneur Morris, by James Madison, and by other framers of the Constitution of the United States. 5. Be cause, not satisfied with making this clause contradict everything else, it makes it contradict itself, or at least the very next clause in the same sentence with itself. WEBSTER AND THE FEDERALIST AGAIN But there is another thing which Mr. Webster could not find in "all contemporary history," nor in "the numbers of The Federalist" nor in "the publications of friends or foes." In none of these various productions or publications, according to Webster, did any one intimate that the new Constitution was but another compact between the States in their sovereign capacity. Yet, with no very great research, I have found, and exhibited in the preceding pages, a multitude of instances in which "such an opinion 76 THE WAR BETWEEN- THE STATES is advanced." Nor was it at all necessary to ransack "all contemporary history" for this purpose. The Federalist itself, the great political classic of America, has already furnished several such instances. It teaches us, as we have seen, that "each State, in ratifying the Constitution, is considered as a sovereign body, independent of all others" ;* and also that, in the establishment of the Constitution, the States are "regarded as distinct and independent sover eigns." 2 But this, it may be said, does not use the term compact. Very well. The same number of The Federalist, which says that the Constitution was to be established by each State, as a sovereign body, independent of all others, calls that Constitution " THE COMPACT." Thus, according to The Federalist, the Constitution, THE COMPACT, was established by "distinct and independent sovereigns/" But numbers XXXIX and XL were written by Mr. Madison. Every one knows that he always regarded the Constitution as a compact between "distinct and inde pendent sovereigns." That is, every one at all acquainted with the political history of the United States, except Mr. Justice Story and Mr. Webster, during the great struggle of 1833. It must be conceded, then, in spite of the sweeping assertion of Mr. Webster, that Madison held the Constitution to be "a compact between the States in their sovereign capacity," and that, too, in the pages of The Federalist as well as elsewhere. A rather conspicuous instance to be overlooked by one whose search had been so very careful and so very conscientious ! Xor does this instance stand alone. Alexander Hamilton is the great writer of The Federalist. Out of its existing eighty-five numbers, no less than fifty proceeded from his pen ; five from the pen of Jay, and thirty from that of Madison; and, in the opinion of the Xorth, the numbers of Hamilton surpass those of- Madison far more in quality than in quantity. In the estimation of the Xorth, indeed, Hamilton is the one sublime architect of the Constitution to whom it owes "every element of its durability and beauty." What, then, 1 No. xxxix. - No. xl. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 77 does Hamilton say about the nature of the Constitution? Does he call it a compact between States, or does he allege that it was ordained by the people of the United States as one sovereign nation ? I do not wish to shock any one. I am aware it will be regarded, by many of the followers of Story, as akin to sacrilege to charge Alexander Hamilton with having entertained the treasonable opinion that the Constitution was a compact between the States. But as we have, at the South, no grand manufactory of opinions to supply "all contemporary history," so we must take the sentiments of Alexander Hamilton just as \ve find them, not in the traditions of the North, but in his own published productions. The simple truth is, then, that he calls the provisions of the Constitution of 1787, "The compacts which are to embrace thirteen distinct States, in a common bond of amity and Union" ; and adds, these compacts must "necessarily be compromises of as many dissimilar interests and inclinations." 1 Thus, according to Hamilton, the "thirteen distinct States" made compro mises with each other, and adopted them as "the compacts" of the new Union ! Xor is this all. On the following page, he says: "The moment an alteration is made in the present plan it becomes, to the purpose of adoption, a new one, and must undergo a new decision of each State." 2 Indeed, even Hamilton, the great consolidationist of his day, never dreamed of any other mode of adopting the new Constitu tion than by "a decision of each State." Hence, he con tinues, "To its complete establishment throughout the Union it will, therefore, require the concurrence of thirteen States." Again, he says, "Every Constitution for the United States must inevitably consist of a great variety of particulars, in which thirteen INDEPENDENT STATES are to be accommodated in their interests or opinions of interest. 3 Hence the necessity of moulding and arranging all the particulars, which are to compose the whole, in such a manner as to satisfy all the parties to THE COMPACT." That is, in such a manner as to satisfy the thirteen INDEPENDENT STATES, who are "THE PARTIES TO THE 1 The Federalist, No. Ixxxv. - Ibid. 3 Ibid. 78 THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES COMPACT." 1 The whole Federalist is in perfect harmony with this keynote of the system it recommended to the people. I might easily produce a hundred other proofs of the same fact from "The Federalist," from "publications of friends and foes," from the "debates of the Convention," without the aid of "all contemporary history." 1 The Federalist, No. Ixxxv. CHAPTER X THE CONSTITUTION OF 1787 A COMPACT BETWEEN THE STATES MR. WEBSTER AGAIN THE LETTER OF THE CONVENTION ON THE CONSTITUTION THE Convention of 1787, in their letter describing the formation of the new Constitution, use precisely the polit ical formula employed by Sidney, Locke, and other cele brated authors, to define a social compact. Hobbes was the first to reduce this theory to a scientific form ; and it is nowhere more accurately defined than by himself. "Each citizen," says he, "compacting with his fellow, says thus: I convey my right on this party, upon condition that you pass yours to the same; by which means that right, which every man had before to use his faculties to his own advantage, is now wholly translated on some certain man or council for the common benefit." 1 Precisely the same idea is conveyed by the formula of 1787 : "Indi viduals entering into society must give up a share of liberty to preserve the rest; and the great difficulty is, as to what right should be delegated to the governing agents for the common benefit, and what right should be retained by the individual." This is the social compact as defined by Hobbes himself; and, although it was an imaginary transaction in regard to the governments of the Old World, it became a reality in relation to the solemnly enacted Constitutions of America. But, in the letter of the Convention of 1787, it comes before us in a new relation. In Hobbes, "each citizen compacts with his fellow," as in the formation of our State Constitutions ; whereas, in the letter before us, each State compacts with her sister States. "It is obviously impracticable," says the Convention, 2 "in the Federal Government of these States to secure all rights of inde pendent sovereignty to each, and yet provide for the 1 "Hobbes Works," vol. ii, p. 91. - See their Letter. 80 THE WAK BETWEKX THE STATES honor and safety of all. Individuals entering into society must give up a share of liberty to preserve the rest. It is at all times difficult to draw with precision the line between those rights which must be surrendered, and those which may be reserved; and on the present occasion this difficulty was increased by a difference among the several States [the parties about to enter into a new Union] as to their situation., extent, habits, and particular interests." Yet, in the face of all this, the whole school of Massa chusetts politicians, with Story and Webster at their head, assert that the Federal Government is a union, not of States, but only of individual citizens ! Who, before or beside these perverters of the most palpable truth, ever applied the term "Union" to a government of individuals ? Who ever heard of the Union of Massachusetts, or of New York, or of Virginia? The truth is that this word is only applicable to a confederation of States ; and hence, even Alexander Hamilton, after he had failed to establish a consolidated national government, familiarly called the new Union "a CONFEDERACY." 1 It was reserved for a later day, and for a bolder period in the progress of triumphant error, to scout this as an Unconstitutional idea; and to declare, by way of proof, that "there is no language in the Constitution applicable to a confederation of States." 2 Is not the term "Union" applicable to a confederation of States, or is it only applicable to a social combination of individuals? Does not the Constitution speak of "the United States," or the States united? Nay, does it not expressly declare that it shall be binding "between the States so ratifying the same?" Or, if the Constitution itself has been silent, does not the letter of 1787, which was struck in the same mint with that solemn compact, declare that each State, on entering into the new Union, gives up a share of its "rights of independent sovereignty," in order to secure the rest? I shall now take leave of the proposition that the Consti tution was a compact between the States of the Union ; a 1 The FcilrraUKt. No. Ixxx. 2 "Webster s Works." vol. iii, p. 47<>. Great speech of 1833. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 81 proposition far too plain for argument, if the clearest facts of history .had only been permitted to speak for them selves. "I remember/ 7 says Mr. Webster, "to have heard Chief Justice Marshall ask counsel, who was insisting upon the authority of an act of legislation, if he thought an act of legislation could create or destroy a fact, or change the truth of history?" "Would it alter the fact," said he, "if a legislature should solemnly enact that Mr. Hume never wrote the History of England?" 1 "A legis lature may alter the law/ continues Mr. Webster, "but no power can reverse a fact." 2 Hence, if the Convention of 1787 had expressly declared that the Constitution was ordained by "the people of the United States in the aggre gate," or by the people of America as one nation, this would not have destroyed the fact that it was ratified by each State for itself, and that each State was bound only by "its own voluntary act." If the Convention had been lost to all decency it might indeed have stamped such a falsehood on the face of the Constitution ; but this would not have "changed the truth of history." Story and Webster lay great stress, as we have seen,- 011 the fact that the first resolution passed by the Con vention of 1787, declared that a National Government ought to be established. But, by a suppressio veri, they conceal the fact that this resolution was afterward taken up, and the term national deliberately dropped by the unanimous decision of the Convention. They also conceal the fact that, after the Constitution was actually formed, the Convention called the work of their hands, not "a National Government," but "THE FEDERAL GOVERNMENT OF THESE STATES." This name was given, not before, but after, the Convention was full : not before the first article of the Constitution was adopted, but after the whole instrument had been completely finished; and it was given, too, by "the unanimous order of the Convention. " :! Yet, in contempt of all this, Story and Webster say that the Convention made, not a "Federal Government of States," but a "National Government" for 1 "Works." vol. ii, p. 334. - Chap, iy. 3 See their Letter to Congress. 82 THE WAR BETWEEX THE STATES the one people of America, and they prove this by the exploded resolution passed by them ! That is, they still insist on the name expressly rejected by the Convention, as if it had received the sanction of their high authority; and that., too, in direct opposition to the name actually given by them ! Could any style of reasoning, if reasoning it may be called, be more utterly contemptible ? MR. WEBSTER VERSUS MR. WEBSTER In the preceding pages Mr. Webster has been con fronted with reason and authority ; showing . that "the greatest intellectual effort of his life" is merely a thing of words. In this, he shall be confronted with himself for, in truth, he is at war with himself, as well as with all the great founders of the Constitution of the United States. He is, in fact, too much for himself; and the great speech which, in 1833, he reared with so much pains and consummate skill as a rhetorician, he has literally torn to tatters. "If the States be parties [to the Constitution]," asks Mr. Webster in that speech, with an air of great confi dence, "where are their covenants and stipulations? And where are their rights, covenants, and stipulations ex pressed ? The States engage for nothing., they promise nothing." On reading this passage, one is naturally inclined to ask, did Mr. Webster never hear of "the grand compromises of the Constitution * about which so much has been written? But what is a compromise, if it is not a mutual agreement, founded on the mutual concessions of the parties to some conflict of opinions or interests? Does not the very term compromise mean mutual promises or pledges? Look at the large and small States in the Convention of 1787. We see, in that memorable struggle for power, the large States insisting on a large or pro portionate representation of themselves in both branches of the federal legislature ; and we see the small States, with equal pertinacity, clinging to the idea of an equal representation in both. The struggle is fierce and obsti nate. The Convention is on the point of dissolution, and THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 83 its hopes are almost extinguished. But a compromise is suggested, considered, argued, and finally adopted ; accord ing to which there is to be a proportionate representation of each State in one branch of the federal legislature, and an equal representation in the other. These are the terms, "the covenants," "the stipulations 77 on which the two classes of States agree to unite; these are their mutual promises. The same thing is true in regard to all the other "grand compromises of the Constitution. 7 It seems, indeed, that Mr. Webster could not well speak of these compromises without using some such word as terms, or covenants, or promises, or stipulations. Accordingly, if we turn to the general index to his work, in order to see how he would speak of the compromises of the Constitution, we shall be led to make a very curious discovery, and one which is intimately connected with an interesting passage of his political life. It will conduct us to a scene in which "the beautiful vase," then "well known throughout the country as the WEBSTER VASE," was presented to that celebrated statesman. Several thousand persons "had assembled at the Odeon, in Boston," in order to witness the presentation of that costly memorial, and to hear the reply of the great orator. "The Vase, 77 we are told, " was placed" on a pedestal covered with the American flag, and contained on its side the following inscription : "PRESENTED TO DANIEL WEBSTER, The Defender of the Constitution, BY THE CITIZENS OF BOSTON. October 12, 1835." Now this beautiful vase, so rich in its material and so exquisite in its workmanship, was presented to Mr. Webster in honor of his great speech of 1833 ; in which he demonstrated to the entire satisfaction of the New England universe that it is absurd to call the Constitution "a compact," or to speak of its "stipulations. 77 Now I shall produce one extract from this speech at the Odeon. not 84 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES only 011 account of the striking contrast it presents to the doctrine of the speech of 1833, whose glorious thousands were there assembled to celebrate, but also on account of the simple, solid, and important truth it contains. "The Constitution," says Mr. Webster, in that speech, "is founded on compromises, and the most perfect and absolute good faith ix REGARD TO EVERY STIPULATION OF THIS KIND CONTAINED IN IT IS INDISPENSABLE TO ITS PRESERVATION. Every attempt to accomplish even the best purpose, every attempt to grasp that which is regarded as an immediate good, in violation of these STIPULATIONS, is FULL OF DANGER TO THE WHOLE CONSTITUTION/ 1 Such glaring inconsistencies, and there are many of them in the writings of the great orator, will be flaws and cracks in the vase of his reputation as long as his name is known. Xor is this the only instance in which Mr. Webster has spoken of the stipulations of the Constitution. "All the stipulations," says he, "contained in the Constitution in favor of the slave States ought to be fulfilled." 2 Here, then, are stipulations in favor of States, and made by States. "Slavery," says he, "as it exists in the States, is beyond the reach of Congress. It is a concern of the States themselves; they have never submitted it to Congress, and Congress has no rightful power over it" 3 Xor has the Federal Government the rightful power over anything in relation to the States; unless this pow r er was granted by the States, and so became one of tlie stipulations in the new "Articles of Union," as the Constitution is called throughout the debates in the Convention of 1787. 4 The power of the Federal Government over commerce has been very justly called "the corner-stone of the whole system." The Constitution originated, as we have seen, in the desire to establish a uniform and permanent system of commercial regulations, by which the hostile legislation of Europe might be resisted, and the havoc of the inter national legislation of the States repaired. Whence did this great power, or rather this great system of powers, emanate? "The State*" says Mr. Webster, "delegated Uidr 1 "Works." vol. 1, D. 381. -"Works," vol. v, p. 847. 3 Ibid. 4 "Madison Tapers," pp. 782, 784, 761, 861, 1118, 1221. 122."). THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 85 whole authority over imports to the genera] government" 1 In like manner, every other power of the vast super structure reared upon that corner-stone was delegated or conferred on the Federal Government by the States in the "Articles of Union." Mr. Webster and Mr. Justice Story say the Constitution speaks the language of authority to the States, saying you shall do this, or you shall not do that, and eschews the verbal forms of a compact. Very great stress is laid on this point. The Constitution, say they, is not "a compact between States," it is "the supreme law," as if the two things were utterly incompatible. But it is a rather un fortunate circumstance for this argument that precisely the same language of authority is used in the old Articles of Confederation, which is universally admitted to have been a compact. "Xo State shall/ is the style of the old "Articles of Union," 2 as well as of the new ; in this respect they are perfectly parallel. But here, again, we may appeal from Philip drunk to Philip sober, from Webster intoxicated with the fumes of a false theory of power to Webster under the influence of a simple view of truth. After having read the terms on which Texas was admitted into the Union, Mr. Webster asks, "Xow what is here stipulated, enacted, secured?" thus admitting that the stipulations were enactments, or that the contract was a law. Xor is this all. For, having speci fied the stipulations in this case, he proceeds to say, "I know no form of legislation which can strengthen this. I know no mode of recognition that can add a tittle to the weight of it. I listened respectfully to the resolutions of my friend from Tennessee. He proposed to recognize that stipulation with Texas. But any additional .recognition would weaken the force of it ; because it stands here on the ground of a contract, a tiling clone for a consideration. IT IS A LAW FOUNDED OX A CONTRACT WITH TEXAS." There is, then, after all, no incompatibility between a contract and a law ! On the contrary, the very highest form of 1 "Works," vol. ii, p. 318. These words are quoted by Mr. Webster, with his expressed approbation. 2 See Articles v and vi. 86 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES legislation may be that of a compact between sovereign States. It was thus that Texas came into the Union; and, in consideration of certain things promised to her, agreed to accept the Constitution of the United States as the supreme law of the land. It was thus also that the original thirteen States, in view of certain advantages expected by them, and held out to them, conferred various powers on the Federal Govern ment to be exercised for the common good. Each State, as it adopted the Constitution, virtually said to every other, I will abstain from the exercise of certain powers, and grant or delegate certain powers, according to all the stipulations of this instrument, provided you will do the same thing. I will neither coin money, nor emit bills of credit, nor enact laws impairing the obligations of con tracts, nor do any other thing which, in the view of the authors of the Constitution, has proved so injurious to the best interests of the country, provided you will abstain from the exercise of the same powers. And I will, on the other hand, consent that the general government may regulate commerce, levy taxes, borrow money on the common credit, wage war, conclude peace, and do all acts and things as stipulated in the new "Articles of Union," provided you will delegate the same powers. Such was "the contract, the thing done for a consideration." The great stipulation of all was that the Constitution should be the supreme law of the land, for that became the supreme law only by the mutual agreement of the States. But why argue a point so plain? How any man can look the Constitution in the face, or read its history, and then ask, where are its stipulations? is more than I can conceive. It does seem to me that he might almost as well look into the broad blaze of noon, and then ask, If the sun really shines, where are its rays? But if the Constitution is not a compact for the North, it is at least held to be binding, as such, on the South. The free States, said Mr. Webster in 1850, "complain that, instead of slavery being regarded as an evil, as it was then, it is now regarded by the South as an insti tution to be cherished, and preserved, and extended." 1 1 "Works," vol. v. p. 359. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 87 "The North finds itself," he continues, "in regard to the relative influence of the South and the North, of the free States and the slave States, where it did not expect to find itself when they agreed to the compact of the Con stitution/ 71 THUS, AFTER ALL, THE STATES AGREED TO THE COMPACT OF THE CONSTITUTION, MR. WEBSTER HIM SELF BEING THE JUDGE. Again, in 1851, Mr. Webster says: "When the Consti tution was framed, its f ramers, and the people who adopted it, came to a clear, express, unquestionable stipulation and compact." 2 In the same speech, he says: "These States passed acts defeating the law of Congress, as far as it was in their power to defeat it. Those of them to whom I refer, not all, but several, nullified the law of 1793. They said, in effect, we will not execute it. No runaway slave shall be restored. Thus the law became a dead letter. But here was the Constitution and compact still binding ; here was the stipulation, as solemn as words could form it, and which every member of Congress, every officer of the general government, every officer of the State government, from governors down to constables, is sworn "to support." 3 Thus, in 1850 and 1851, it appears that Mr. Webster had as completely forgotten "the greatest intellectual effort of his life," as in 1833 he had forgotten all the great intellectual efforts of Mr. Madison s life. The truth is, that Mr. Webster had become alarmed at the condition of the country; because the North, which he had taught to deny that the Constitution is a compact, seemed resolved to reduce his theory to practice and give all its stipulations to the winds, provided they only stood in the way of their passions. Many of his former friends had, indeed, deserted and denounced him, because he would not go all lengths w r ith them in disregarding the most solemn compact of the Constitution, which all had sworn to support. Hence, he wished to retrace his steps ; but he could not lay the mighty spirit of insubordination and rebellion which he had helped to arouse in the North. He could only plead, expostulate, and denounce in return. 1 "Webster s Works," vol. v, p. 359. 2 Ibid., vol. ii, p. 574. 3 Ibid., p. 575. "THE WAH BETWEKN THE STATES Accordingly, in the speech just quoted, he says: "It has been said in the States of New York, Massachusetts, and Ohio, over and over again, that the law shall not be executed. That was the language of the Conventions in Worcester, Massachusetts; in Syracuse, New York; and elsewhere. And for this they pledged their lives, their fortunes, and their sacred honors. Now, gentlemen, these proceedings, I say it upon my professional reputation, are distinctly treasonable. Resolutions passed in Ohio, certain resolutions in New York, and in Conventions held in Boston are distinctly treasonable. And the act of taking away Shadrick from the public authorities in Boston, and sending him off, was an act of clear treason. 71 The spirit of the resolutions which are here so emphatic ally denounced by Mr. Webster, afterward seized whole States, and controlled their legislation. In fourteen of the Northern States, indeed, laws were enacted to prevent the execution of the law of Congress. These laws, as Mr. Webster himself, if living, would have said, were "distinctly treasonable." They came directly into conflict with the law of Congress, and nullified the compact of the Constitution relative to fugitive slaves. What shall we say then? Was secession, under such circumstances, treason? Was it rebellion? Mr. Webster has, in one of his speeches, laid down a principle which never has been, and never can be, controverted. He says : "I do not hesitate to say and repeat, that if the Northern States refuse wilfully arid deliberately to carry into effect that part of the Constitution which respects th e restoration of fugitive slaves, the South would be no longer bound to keep the compact. A bargain broken on one side is broken on all sides." I have said that this is a principle of truth and justice which never has been, and never can be, denied. It was, indeed, precisely the prin ciple which governed the Convention of 178? in with drawing from the first compact between the States. I do not mean to say, however, that this great principle of truth and justice may not be practically denied. In fact, the Northern power has not only claimed, but exercised, 1 "Webster s Works." vol. ii. p. 577. THE WAI? BETWEEN THE STATES 89 the right to trample the compact of the Constitution under foot; and, at the same time, to visit with fire, sword, desolation, and ruin those who merely wished to withdraw from the broken thing, and let it alone. According to the doctrine laid down by Story and Webster, if a compact between States assign no term for its continuance, then the States have a right to secede from if at pleasure. 1 This doctrine is, no doubt, perfectly true. But precisely such was the compact from which the Southern States wished to withdraw ; no period was prescribed for its continuance. Yet the Xorth, who had trampled it under foot, punished the South with the most terrible of all wars, because she was pleased to regard secession as a violation of that "most sacred compact." Xo man, as we have seen, could well be more inconsistent on any subject than "the great expounder was in relation to the most important of all questions respecting the Constitution. It was, with him, either a compact between the States, or not a compact between the States, according to the exigencies of the occasion. He could be equally eloquent on both sides of the question. He complained, in 1850, that the South had changed her opinions on the subject of slavery. Might not the South complain that .he had no opinions, or at least no convictions, to change? The man who really seeks the truth, and, when found, clings to it as the choicest treasure of his soul, may well leave his consistency to take care of itself. But the man who seeks place, or power, or popularity more than the truth, should indeed have a good memory. The one may, and indeed will, sometimes change his opinions, but then, in the midst of all his changes, he will be ever true, like the needle, which only turns until it finds the pole. Whereas the other, in his variations, is like the weather cock, which shifts with the breeze of the passing hour, and never finds a point of permanent rest. Even the intellect of a Webster, where the moral man is deficient, can fur nish no exemption from this law of retributive justice. Mr. Webster s real opinion, however, seems to have been that the Constitution was a compact between the 1 See chap. ii. 90 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES States. His great speech of 1833 may have convinced others; it certainly did not convince himself, for, during the remainder of his life, he habitually and constantly spoke of the Constitution as the compact formed by the States. Especially after his race was nearly run, and, instead of the dazzling prize of the Presidency, he saw before him the darkness of the grave, and the still greater darkness that threatened his native land with ruin, he raised the last solemn utterances of his mighty voice in behalf of "the compact of the Constitution" ; declaring that as it had been "deliberately entered into by the States/ 7 so the States should religiously observe "all its stipulations. 77 CHAPTER XI THE ABSURDITIES FLOWING FROM THE DOCTRINE THAT THE CONSTITUTION IS NOT A COMPACT BETWEEN THE STATES, BUT WAS MADE BY THE PEOPLE OF AMERICA AS ONE NATION THE "SOVEREIGNTY" OF THE PEOPLE WHEN I come to consider "the sovereignty of the people," about which so much has been said, we shall see the fallacy of the position, which is everywhere assumed by Mr. Webster and his school, that "the aggregate com munity, the collected will of the people, is sovereign." 1 We shall then see that this doctrine is utterly without foundation in history, and without support from reason. On the contrary, it will then be rendered manifest that the\ people of America have never existed as one nation,! clothed with sovereign authority; an idea which has nqj foundation in fact, and which has grown out of the popular use of language and the passing of politicians. But, at present, I merely wish to point out a few of the absurdities flowing from this doctrine, that the Constitution was ordained by "the aggregate community, the collected will of the people" of America, acting as one sovereign political society. This argument alone, this reductio ad absurdum, is amply sufficient, unless I am greatly mistaken, to shatter that already shattered hypothesis. Mr. Justice Story, quoting the Declaration of Inde pendence, says: ."It is the right of the people [plainly intending the majority of the people], to alter, or to abolish! it, and to institute a new government, laying its foundation* on such principles, and organizing its powers in such forms? as to them shall seem most likely to effect their safety andj happiness." 2 Now this is what is meant by the sovereignty of the people of America. But will any one contend that the people of the United States, that is, a majority of 1 "Works," vol. vi, p. 222. 2 Vol. i, hook iii, chap. iii. 92 THE WAI: BKTWKKN THK STATES them, may alter, or amend, the government of the Union? If they are, indeed, one people in the political sense of the word, then are they sovereign ; and if as such they made the Constitution of the United States, then, according to all our American ideas and doctrines, they have the right to alter or amend that Constitution at their pleasure. Xay, more; they have the right to pull down the existing government, and to set up a new one in its place. But who will accept such a consequence ? This right of sovereignty, if it exist, or if the one people exist to whom it naturally belongs, is, according to the universally received doctrine of this continent, inherent and inalienable. Xo laws or Constitutions can take it away, or abridge and limit its exercise. Who will say, then, that the people of the United States, "plainly meaning the majority of them," have such a right or authority? Xo one. Plainly and inevitably as this consequence flows from the fundamental position of Story and Webster, that the sovereign people of America or dained the Constitution, it will be avowed by no one, who has any reputation to lose, and who has the least respect for the reputation he possesses. Mr. Lincoln has avowed this consequence. But in this instance, as in many others, his logic has taken advantage of his want of information. This consequence flows, so naturally and so necessarily from the premises that Mr. Justice Story has, in one place, inadvertently drawn it, or rather it has incidentally drawn itself. "The people of the United States," says he, "have a right to abolish, or alter, the Constitution of the United States." 1 True, if they made it ; but they did not make it, and therefore they have the right neither to alter nor to abolish it. The power that made is the power to unmake. Mr. Justice Story did not mean, that is, he did not deliberately mean, that the people of the United States, or the majority of them, could alter or abolish the Constitution ; for he was too well informed to be capable of such a blunder. But in this instance, as in many others, his logic, speaking the language of nature and of truth, got the better of his artificial and false hypothesis. 1 "Works," vol. i. book iii. chap. iii. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES !W If the people of the United States are, in reality, one sovereign political community, and, as such, ordained the Constitution, then they have the most absolute control over all the parts: and the States bear the same relation to this one grand and overshadowing sovereignty that counties sustain to a State. They may be divided, or moulded, or abolished, at the pleasure of the whole people. But everybody knows better than this. Mr. Lincoln did, it is true, endorse this conclusion, in the first speech he ever made to the American public. When the long silence was broken, and, as President-elect, he addressed his first word to an anxious country, he likened the relation between the States and the Union to that of counties to a State. Until then, there were many intelligent and well- informed persons who did not believe that there was one individual in the United States capable of taking such a view of the Constitution, except among political preachers or parsons. 1 But however absurd, it is only the necessary consequence of the premises laid down by Mr. Justice Story and Mr. Webster. It will, however, be regarded by every student of the Constitution in the light of a reductio ad absurdum, which, instead of establishing the conclusion to which it leads, only shatters and demolishes the position from which it flows. 1 Indeed, this doctrine, and the very illustration of it, was borrowed by Mr. Lincoln from the celebrated Preacher of Princeton. N. T. Compare Mr. Lincoln s speech with Dr. Hodge on "The State of the Country." C H A P T E E XII THE HYPOTHESIS THAT THE PEOPLE *OF AMERICA FORM ONE NATION INTRODUCTORY WE have seen, in the preceding chapter, some of the absurdities flowing from the assumption that the people of America form one nation, or constitute one political community. But as this is the first and all-comprehending falsehood of the Northern theory of the Constitution, by which its history has been so sadly blurred, if not obliter ated, and by which its most solemn provisions have been repealed, so we shall go beyond the foregoing reductio ad dbsurdum, and show that it has no foundation whatever in the facts of history. I was about to say that it has not the shadow of such a foundation; but, in reality, it has precisely such a shadow in the vague, popular use of language, to which the passions of interested partisans have given the appearance of substance. And it is out of this substance, thus created from a shadow, that have been manufactured those tremendous rights of national power, by which the clearly reserved rights of the States have been crushed, and the most unjust war of the modern world justified. I purpose, therefore, to pursue this monstrous abortion of night and darkness into the secret recesses of its history, and leave neither its substance nor its shadow in existence. Fortunately, in the prosecution of this design, it is only necessary to cross-examine those willing witnesses by whom this fiction has been created, and compare their testimony with itself, in order to show that they are utterly unworthy of credit as historians of the American Union. I shall begin with Mr. Justice Story. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 95 THE ATTEMPT OF MR. JUSTICE STORY TO SHOW THAT THE PEOPLE OF AMERICA FORMED OXE XATIOX OR STATE This celebrated commentator strains all the powers of language, and avails himself of every possible appearance, to make the colonies of America "one people," even before they severed their dependence on the British crown. Thus, he says : "The colonies were fellow-subjects, and for many purposes one people. Every colonist had a right to inhabit, if he pleased, in any other colony; and, as a British sub ject, he was capable of inheriting lands by descent in every other colony. The commercial intercourse of the colonies, too, was regulated by the laws of the British empire, and could not be restrained, or obstructed, by colonial legis lation. The remarks of Mr. Chief Justice Jay on this subject are equally just and striking: All the people of this country were then subjects of the king of Great Britain, and owed allegiance to him; and all the civil authority then existing, or exercised here, flowed from the head of the British empire. They were, in a strict sense, /W/ow-subjects, and, in a variety of respects, one people 7 ." 1 Now all this signifies just exactly nothing as to the purpose which the author has in view. For, no matter in what respects the colonies were "one people," if they were not one in the political sense of the words : or if they had no political power as one people, then the germ of the national oneness did not exist among them. But this is conceded by Mr. Justice Story himself. "The colonies," says he, "were independent of each other in respect to their domestic concerns." 2 Each was independent of the legislation of another, and of all the others combined, if they had pleased to combine. In many respects, indeed, the whole human race may be said to be one. They had a common origin, a common psychology, a common physiology, and they are all subjects of the same great Euler of the world. But this does not make all men "one people" in the political sense of the words. In like manner, those things which the colonists had in common, and which are so carefully enumerated 1 "Story on the Constitution." vol. i. p. 164. - Ibid. 06 THE WAR BETWEEN THE SPATES by Mr. Justice Story, do not make them one political community; the only sense in which their oneness could have any logical connection with his design. Xay, so palpably is this the case that he fails to make the impression on his own mind which he seems so desirous to make on that of his readers; and the hypothesis that the colonies were "one people," is utterly dispelled by his own explicit admission. For, says he, "Though the colonies had a common origin, and owed a common allegiance, and the inhabitants of each were British sub jects, they had no direct political connexion with each other. Each was independent of all the others; each, in a limited sense, was sovereign within its own territory. There was neither allegiance nor confederacy between them. The Assembly of one province could not make laws for another, nor confer privileges which were to be enjoyed or exercised in another, farther than they could be in any independent foreign state. As colonies, they were also excluded from all connexion with foreign states. They were known only as dependencies, and they followed the fate of the parent country, both in peace and war, without having assigned to them, in the intercourse of diplomacy of nations, any distinct or independent existence. They did not possess the power of forming any league or treaty among themselves, which would acquire an obligatory force, without the assent of the parent State. And though their mutual wants and necessities often induced them to associate for common purposes of defence, these confed eracies were of a casual and temporary nature, and were allowed as an indulgence, rather than as a right. They made several efforts to procure the establishment of some general superintending government over them all; but their own differences of opinion, as well as the jealousy of the crown, made these efforts abortive." 1 It is impossible for language to be more precise and explicit. Hence, in whatever other respects the colonies may have formed " one people," we are here authorized, by the undisputed and the indisputable facts of history, to 1 "Story on the Constitution," vol. i, pp. 163-H54. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 97 consider them as separate and independent of each other, in the political sense of the terms. And this is all our argument needs. Mr. Justice Story, not satisfied with the oneness of the people of the colonies before their separation from Great Britain, which he has been at so much pains to establish, next endeavors to show that they were certainly moulded into one nation by the Declaration of Independence. If they were "one people" before, it is difficult to conceive how they were made so by that Declaration. To that act, says he, "union was as vital as freedom or independence." 1 But what sort of union? Did the people unite and become one nation, in the sense that it was a sovereign political community, so that the whole could make a Con stitution and laws for the parts ? If not, then the assertion misses the mark aimed at, and must go for nothing. But no one pretends, for a single moment, that they became one people in any such sense of the words. Mr. Justice Story himself admits that such union was temporary, and designed to perish with the common danger which had called it into existence. "The union thus formed," says he, "grew out of the exigencies of the times ; and from its nature and objects might be deemed temporary, extending only to the maintenance of the common liberties and independence of the States, and to terminate with the return of peace with Great Britain, and the accomplishment of the ends of the revolutionary contest." 2 Thus it is conceded that they became "one people," not to ordain a Constitution or to enact laws, but only to resist a common enemy, and to continue united only during the presence of the common danger. Hence, this union was, according to Judge Story s own admission, more imperfect and fragile than that which, from the operation of a similar cause, had sprung up among the States of Greece, the Swiss Cantons, the United Netherlands, or the members of the German Diet. Yet no one has ever considered any one of these unions as form ing one nation, or people, as contradistinguished from a 1 Vol. i. book xi, chap. 1, p. 200. Note. - Vol. i, book ii. chap, ii, p. 209. 98 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES federation of sovereign and independent States. Such attempts, indeed, to prove that the colonies, or the States of America, were one nation, or political community, are simply desperate. They are scarcely made before they are overthrown by the hand that reared them. But let us admit, for the sake of argument, that the colonies formed one people before their separation from Great Britain, and that they were again made one people by the Declaration of Independence. Then no one colony could lawfully act without the concurrence of the others, as the parts would not be independent of the whole*. Ac cordingly, Mr. Justice Story declares that "the colonies did not severally act for themselves, and proclaim their own independence." 1 But it is well known that Virginia did so. "Virginia," says Judge Story, "on the 29th of June, 1776 (five days before the Declaration of Independence), declared the government of the country as formerly exer cised under the crown of Great Britain, totally dissolved, and proceeded to form a new Constitution." 2 Nay, she had already formed a new Constitution, in pursuance of her resolution of the 15th of the preceding month, and she adopted it on the 29th of June, 1776. Yet Virginia has never been regarded as tainted with treason, or rebellion, against the people of America, because she thus proclaimed her own separate independence, and established her own Constitution. On the contrary, she has ever been honored by her sister colonies and States for this bold and inde pendent act. This is not the only insuperable difficulty in the way of the hypothesis that the colonies were made one people by the Declaration of Independence. For, if this hypothe sis be adopted, we must believe that this one people were afterwards broken up into separate and independent States by an act of Confederation ! In the case of Gibbons and Ogden, 3 the Supreme Court of the United States, says (and the words are quoted with approbation by Mr. Justice Story), 4 "As preliminary to the very able discussion of the Constitution which we have heard from the bar. and 1 Vol. i, hook ii, chap, i, p. 197. - Ibid. 36. Wheaton, p. 187. 4 Vol. i, p. 323. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 99 as having some influence on its construction, reference has been made to the situation of these States, anterior to its formation. It has been said that they were sovereign, were completely independent, and were connected with each other only by a league. THIS is TRUE." 1 Now, if this be true, as the Supreme Court of the United States affirms, and as Mr. Justice Story admits, how were this one people broken up into so many separate, "sovereign" and " completely independent" States? This must have been done by the Articles of Confederation, since it is only in the presence of these Articles that this fine theory about the oneness of the American people dis appears, and the States once more shine out as free and independent sovereignties. No other cause can be assigned, for the change. It is perfectly certain, indeed, that if the people of America were one nation, or political community, prior to the adoption of those Articles, they then became divided into separate, distinct, and independent States. For, according to those Articles, "Each State retains its sover eignty, freedom, and independence." Each State retains ! This language implies, indeed, that each State was free, sovereign and independent before those Articles were adopted. But then this is only one of the difficulties in the way of the theory of Judge Story. If they were not free and sovereign States before ; if, on the contrary, they were one people, or nation, or political community, then it were absurd to speak of their union as an act of confederation. For it would, indeed, have been an act of separation, and not of confederation. It would have been the dividing of one nation into separate and sovereign States, and not the uniting of such States into one Confederacy. This is another of the difficulties which stand in the way of the theory of Judge Story, and of the Northern school of politicians. Again, if one people were thus divided into free, sover eign and independent States, by the Articles of Confedera tion; then it is very inaccurate in Judge Story to say, as he always does, that the States granted the powers by l Vol. i, book ii, chap, iii, p. 323. 100 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES which the Confederacy was formed. He should, on the contrary, have spoken only of powers resumed by the States, or restored to them by the American people. But we may now take leave of his theory and all its insuperable difficulties. It is sufficient for my purpose that, after the Articles of Confederation were agreed upon as the supreme law, the States were then free, sovereign, and independent. It is asserted by the Supreme Court of the United States, as well as by Judge Story himself, that anterior to the adoption of the Constitution the States "were sovereign, were completely independent, and were connected only by a league/ It was in this capacity, it was as free, sovereign, and completely independent States, that they laid aside the old, and entered into the new, "Articles of Union," as the Constitution is everywhere called in the proceedings of the Convention of 1787. This is conceded. Hence, the situation of the colonies before their separation from the mother country, or of the States before the adoption of the Articles of Confederation, has nothing to do with our present inquiry; which relates to the character in which the people, or the peoples of America, ordained the Constitution of the United States. If any one has a mind to amuse himself by binding up or pulling down speculations or hypothesis on this subject he may do so to his heart s content. It is sufficient for every practical purpose that, when they came to adopt the new form of government, each State was a completely free, sovereign, and independent political community, and in that capacity acceded to the compact of the Constitution. THE ATTEMPT OF MR. CURTIS TO SHOW THAT THE PEOPLE OF AMERICA FORMED ONE NATION, OR POLITICAL COMMUNITY Mr. Curtis, in his extended and elaborate History of the Constitution of the United States, seems to view with the introductory sketch of Judge Story, in the establishment of the foregone conclusion, that it was created by and rests on "the political union of the people of the United States, as distinguished from the States of which they are THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 101 the citizens." 1 For this purpose, it is necessary to show, in the first place, that such a political union of the whole people of the country had an existence. Accordingly, the facts of history are recast and moulded in order to suit this hypothesis. If possible, the conflict between fact and theory is, in his work, even more glaring than it is in that of Mr. Justice Story. "The people of the different colonies were," says he, "in several important senses, one people" 2 This is true. But it is not even pretended, by Mr. Curtis, that this was a political union; he only says that it enabled them to effect such a union. He admits, on the contrary, in the most explicit terms, "that the colonies had no direct political connexion with each other before the Eevolution commenced, but that each was a distinct community, with its own separate political organization, and without any power of legislation for any but its own inhabitants ; that, as political communities, and upon the principles of their organizations, they possessed no power of forming any union among themselves, for any purposes whatever, with out the sanction of the Crown or Parliament of England." 3 "It is apparent," says he, "that previous to the Decla ration of Independence the people of the several colonies had established a national government of a revolutionary character, which undertook to act, and did act, in the name and with the general consent of the inhabitants of the country." 4 Thus, even previous to the Declaration of Independence, the people of the colonies formed one nation, and established "a national government." A nation, with a national government, and yet dependent colonies ! "This government," says he, "was established by the Union in one body of delegates representing the people of each colony." That is, each colony, acknowledged to be perfectly and wholly independent of every other, sends delegates to one body; and this body, whose duty it is to advise and recommend measures to the several colonies, is "a national government!" Surely, if such an advisory council may be called a government at all, it is anything 1 Vol. i, p. 122. 2 Vol. i, p. 9. 3 Ibid. * Vol. i, p. 39. 102 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES rather than national in its character. It is, in fact, merely the shadow of a Federal Government. Mr. Curtis himself is evidently not satisfied with the "one nation" in this stage of its development, or purely verbal existence. Hence, he insists, with Mr. Justice Story, that the colonies were really made one nation by the Declaration of Independence. "The body by which this step was taken," says he, "constituted the actual gov ernment of the nation, at the time" , 1 that is, while they were yet dependent colonies! "It severed the political connexion between the people of this country and the people of England, and at once erected the different colonies into free and independent States." 2 Thus, the colonies formed "one nation" before their separation from Great Britain, and afterwards became "free and inde pendent States." Or, in other words, the nation preceded the States; an opinion for which Mr. Lincoln has been most unconsciously laughed at. This opinion is still more explicitly advanced by Mr. Curtis in another portion of his history. "The fact," says he, "that these local or State governments were not formed until a Union of the people of the different colonies for national purposes had already taken place, and until the national power had authorized and recommended their establishment, is of great importance in the Constitutional history of our country ; for it shows that no colony, acting separately for itself, dissolved its own allegiance to the British crown, but that this allegiance was dissolved by the supreme authority of the people of all the colonies," etc. 3 This fact, which is deemed of so much importance in the Constitutional history of this country, happens, as we have seen, to be fiction; and a fiction, too, in direct conflict with the well-known fact that Virginia declared her own separate independence. But if, by the Declaration of Independence, the colonies became "free and independent States," how could that act have moulded them into one sovereign political community or nation? This is one of the mysteries which I am glad it is not incumbent on me to solve. Was the Declaration iVol. i, p. 51.- 2 Ibid. 3 Vol. i, pp. 39, 40. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 103 of Independence itself necessarily, or ex vi termini,, a decla ration of independence, and, at the same time, one of subjection to a higher authority? If we may adopt Mr. Curtis as a guide, we must answer this question in the affirmative. For, says he, although the colonies were thereby "erected into free and independent States," "the people of the country became henceforth the rightful sovereign of the country ; they became united in a national corporate capacity as one people; they could thereafter enter into treaties and contract alliances with foreign nations; could levy war and conclude peace, and do all other acts pertaining to the exercise of a national sover eignty. "* If so, then, of course, they could ordain Consti tutions and enact laws; they could set up, or pull down, or modify the parts called States, as if they were counties, or mere districts of people. For such is the power of one sovereign State, or nation, over its various members. But, unfortunately, for this bold assertion, Mr. Curtis himself tells us, on the very next page of his work, that "on the same day on which the committee for preparing the Declaration of Independence was appointed, another committee, consisting of a member from each colony, was directed to prepare and digest the form of a confederation to be entered into between these colonies," that is, after they should become free and independent States. "This committee," he continues, "reported a draft of Articles of Confederation on the 12th of July, etc." These Articles were discussed, postponed, resumed, amended, and, finally, adopted. Now whence resulted the powers conferred by these Articles of Confederation? "Were they not granted by the "free and independent States?" Most assuredly they were ; no one has ever had the hardihood to deny so plain a fact, except by implication. But if all the powers of the new "national government," as it is called by Mr. Curtis, were granted by "free and independent States," each acting for itself, as every one acknowledges it to have done; then for what conceivable purpose has he conjured 1 Vol. i, p. 52. 104 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES up the phantom of a preexisting national sovereignty of the whole people of the country? It is certain that this phantom has been completely laid by Mr. Curtis himself. The whole elaborate illusion, w^hich it has cost him so much pains to get up, is thus dispelled by a plain, simple, and unpremeditated state ment of unquestionable facts by the author himself. "The parties to this instrument," says he, referring to the Articles of Confederation, "were free, sovereign, and inde pendent political communities, each possessing within it self all the powers of legislation and government over its own citizens, which any political society can possess. But, by this instrument, these several States became united for certain purposes." 1 Surely, all this must have been absent from the mind of Mr. Curtis, when he spoke of the people of the several States as having been previously merged into one absolutely sovereign political community. But it seems- to be requiring too much to expect a Massa chusetts politician to remember anything he may have said on any preceding page of his work. Nor is this all. For it is also conceded that the States, which were "free, sovereign, and independent political communities" before they adopted the Articles of Confed eration, retained the same prerogatives, or attributes, after that event. "The Article," says he, "declared, as would indeed be implied, in such circumstances, without any express declaration, that each State retained its sovereignty, freedom, and independence." 2 It was, then, in this condition of "free, sovereign, and independent political communities," that the States passed from the old to the new Articles of union, or severally agreed to the compact of the Constitution. Why, then, conjure up shadows and phantoms of a national unity only to dispel them ? The cause of secession only demands the fact that the States, as "free, sovereign, and independent political communities," formed and entered into the new "Articles of Union"; and this fact is conceded both by Story and Curtis. 1 Vol. i, p. 143. - Ibid. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 105 THE USE OF THE TERM PEOPLE Much of the inconsistency and contradiction in the views above examined is due to the ambiguities of the word people, and the utter confusion of its loose, floating significations,, with its technical or scientific sense. We sometimes pronounce a people one, because they have a common origin, or a common language, or a common religion, or even because they inhabit the same portion of the globe. Thus, we speak of "the people of Europe/ or "the people of America/ without intending to convey the idea that they are a people in the political sense of the term. When we say, however, that "the people are sover eign/ we use the word in a more restricted sense. We then speak of the people in the political or technical sense of the term. This includes only the qualified voters of the community, or those by whom the Constitutions may be ordained and remodeled. For no other persons participate in the exercise of the sovereign power. Women and minors are excluded, as well as some other classes, even in our American States. It is in this limited sense of the word that the people are said to make compacts, or Constitutions and laws, either by themselves or by their agents. If Mr. Justice Story had borne this in mind he might have saved himself from all his criticisms on the doctrine of a social contract based on the ground that "infants, minors, married women, persons insane, and many others," 1 take no part in the formation of civil societies, or in the creation of constitutions and governments. No one in cludes such persons in the idea of a people, when these are said to be sovereign. Hence, his "limitations and qualifications" of the doctrine in question have exclusively arisen from his own misapprehension. Something more than a mere natural person is necessary to constitute one of "the people," one of the multitudinous sovereignty of an American State. "The idea of a people," says Burke, evidently using the term in its restricted or political sense, "is the idea of a corporation; it is wholly artificial, and made, like all other legal fictions, by common agreement." 2 1 Vol. i, book iii, chap, iii, p. 296. - "Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs." 106 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES That is, says he, "in a rude state of nature there is no such thing as one people. A number of men in themselves can have no collective capacity." Or, in other words, something more than a number of men is necessary to make a people, or State. It must be agreed and settled as to who shall take part in the exercise of political power, ere Constitutions and laws may be ordained or remodeled by them. But in vain did Burke, and Hobbes, and other writers on the philosophy of politics, endeavor to "fix, with some degree of distinctness, an idea of what we mean when we say, the PEOPLE." 1 Their labors seem to have been lost upon the politicians of the Massachusetts school; and, in some instances, at least, they appear to have only cast their pearls before swine. For one of the great lights of that school kindles into a blaze of fiery indignation against Mr. Burke, for simply advancing the incontestable truth that what we call a PEOPLE is, in the political sense of the word, the result of an agreement or mutual understanding of a community of persons. " 0, that mine enemy had said it! the admirers of Mr. Burke may well exclaim," cries this great light of Massachusetts. "0, that some scoffing Voltaire, some impious Eousseau had uttered it ! Had uttered it? Eousseau did utter the same thing, etc." 2 This is true. For, widely as Edmund Burke and Eousseau differed on most points, they agreed in this, that it is not nature, but art, which determines the question as to who shall participate in the exercise of political power, or con stitute a PEOPLE, in the political sense of the word. Even "the impious Eousseau" is sometimes right, and nearly, if not quite, always so when he agrees with Edmund Burke. In his attempt to show that the Constitution was adopted by the people, and not by the States, Mr. Justice Story deceives himself by means of the ambiguities of the term people, and repeatedly contradicts his own positions. "The States never, in fact," says he, "did, in their political capacity, as contradistinguished from the people thereof, ratify the Constitution." 3 1 "Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs." 2 Everett s "Orations and Speeches," vol. i, p. 122. 3 Vol. i, p. 330. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 107 This is very true, if by States in their political capacity he means, as he seems to do, the State governments. But this is not to the purpose. Every one admits that the Constitution was ratified, not by the governments, but by the people of the States. NOT does any one deny that the term State is sometimes used to signify the government of a State. Thus we often say that the States does so and so, when the thing is done by its government. But the ques tion is, may we not say that the Constitution was ratified by the States, as well as by the people of the States? Or, in other words, are not the terms State and People properly used as equivalent expressions? These words were, as we have already most abundantly seen, habitually used as convertible terms by the Convention of 1787. We may truly say, indeed, with Judge Story, that the Constitution was not ratified by the States, as contradis tinguished from the people, because it is not very easy to distinguish a thing from itself. In assuming this position, Mr. Justice Story forgets what he had said in the preced ing Book of his Commentaries, namely, "the State and the people of the State are equivalent expressions." 1 "Nay, the State," he again says, "by which we mean the- people composing the State, may divide its sovereign powers among various functionaries, etc." 2 Here the term people is clearly used to include only the qualified voters, or those who share the sovereign power; and, in this sense, they are called "the State." It is precisely in this sense that the Constitution was ratified by the people, or the States. We may, and indeed should, distinguish between the meanings of the term State, when it is figura tively used to signify the government of a State, and when it is used to signify the State itself. But we shall never distinguish the people of a State from the State itself, until we can find a State which is not composed of people. But the attempt is made to show that, in adopting the Constitution, the States acted as mere districts of people, and not in their sovereign political capacity. 3 But if this 1 Everett s "Orations and Speeches," vol. i. book ii, p. 198. 2 Ibid., p. 194. 3 Story s "Commentaries on the Constitution," vol. 1, p. 330. 108 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES were so, then the different districts would have been con sidered together in making up the final result, and the majority of the one grand, national whole would have ordained the Constitution. The fact, however, the un- denied and the undeniable fact, is quite otherwise. Each State, with all its own laws, and institutions, and govern ment, either went in, or remained out, at its own sovereign will and pleasure. In the words of The Federalist, it was "only to be bound by its own voluntary act." No other State, nor all other States combined, nor the whole people of America, had the least authority to control its decision. This was an absolutely free, sovereign, and independent act of each State. It may be doubted, indeed, if there was ever a more superficial gloss, or a more pitiful subterfuge, than the assertion of Judge Story, that the States adopted the Constitution, not as States, but only "as districts of people" composing one great State or nation. It is at war with facts ; it is at war with his own repeated admis sions ; and it is at war with the plainest dictates of truth, as well as with the unanswerable arguments of Tlie Federalist. Sad, indeed, must have been the condition to which the great sophist was reduced, when he could stoop to so palpable a gloss on one of the plainest facts in the history of the Constitution ! THE USE OF "SHALL" IN COMPACTS Mr. Justice Story has, I am aware, as well as Mr. Web ster, laid great stress on the fact that the Constitution ad dresses the language of authority to the States. "The lan guage of a compact is," says he, "I will, or will not do this ; that of a law is, thou shalt, or shalt not do it." 1 This is what the act of entering into a compact signifies, but it is not usually the language of the instrument itself. On the contrary, the Articles of Confederation, which are universally admitted to form a compact, use precisely the same style as the Constitution. Both say what shall, and what shall not, be done by the States. Precisely the same 1 Story s "Commentaries on the Constitution," vol. i, p. 308. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 109 style is also employed in the formation of compacts or treaties between wholly separate and independent powers. Nay, in the most ordinary articles of co-partnership, it is usual to say, in the same manner, what shall, and what shall not, be done by the parties thereto. Yet all such instruments rest upon the agreement of the parties, and derive their binding force from their voluntary act. There is a very simple law of language, which seems to have escaped the attention of these great expounders of the Constitution. The language of written contracts usually speaks of the parties in the third person, and not for them in the first person. Hence, they necessarily assume the imperative style; laying down w T hat shall, and not saying what will, be done by them. It would have been ridiculous, indeed, if the Constitution had said, No State will emit bills of credit, or coin money, and so forth, instead of saying, as it does, that no State shall do such acts. Like other written contracts, it says shall, of course, because it speaks of the parties in the third person, and lays down the obligations imposed upon them by their own consent. This is a very simple law of language. But that is no reason why it should be overlooked by the great lights of jurisprudence. "In compacts," says Judge Story, "we ourselves deter mine and promise, what shall be done, before we are obliged to do it/ 7 No words could more admirably suit our purpose, or the facts of the case. For each State agreed to the compact of the Constitution, which pre scribes "what shall be done," before it was bound by it. That "no State shall emit bills of credit," and so forth, is precisely the style which, according to Judge Story him self, as well as according to all usage, would be employed in articles of agreement between the States ; and, hence, to argue for the use of shall, instead of will, that the Consti tution addresses the language of authority from the people of America to the States, is simply ridiculous. "In com pacts," says Story, "we ourselves determine and promise what shall be done, before we are obliged to do it." And yet, in the face of this obvious fact, he argues from the use of shall in the Constitution, that it is not what the States 110 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES "determined and promised/ but what they were com manded to do! that it is not, and can not be a compact between the States at all ! A and B enter into articles of agreement. These articles, according to good usage, say what A shall do, and what B shall do. What shall we say, then, of these articles? Shall we say that they do not form an agreement, or contract at all? Shall we say that A commands B, or "addresses to him the language of authority," as a law giver speaks to a subject? If so, then B also commands A, and each is evidently the master of the other! Precisely such is the profound logic of Mr. Justice Story ! CHAPTEE XIII ARGUMENTS IN FAVOR OF THE RIGHT OF SECESSION INTRODUCTORY IN the preceding chapters it has, I think, been clearly demonstrated that the Constitution of the United States was a compact to which the several States were the parties. This, as we have seen, was most explicitly the doctrine maintained by the fathers of the Constitution, and was unequivocally set forth by The Federalist in submitting that instrument to the people, and is confirmed by all the historical records of the country. If any proposition, indeed, respecting the Constitution can be considered as unanswerably established, it is the doctrine of The Federalist that the act by which it was ordained was "not a national, but a federal act," having been ratified "by the people of America, not as individuals composing one nation, but as composing the distinct and independent States to which they belong"; 1 that the Constitution, "the compact," was established by "the States regarded as distinct and independent sovereigns/ 72 It is, then, on this clear, broad, immutable foundation that the argument in favor of secession rests. ARGUMENT IN FAVOR OF SECESSION FROM THE DOCTRINE OF EESERVED EIGHTS It is frequently asked, by the opponents of secession, where is the right of a State to withdraw from the Union set forth or contained in the Constitution? But this question betrays a gross ignorance with respect to the origin of State rights. These rights are not derived from the Constitution at all; on the contrary, all the rights, powers, or authorities of the Constitution are derived from the States. And all the rights not delegated to the Federal Government by the States are reserved to the 1 The Federalist, No. xxxix. - Ibid., No. xl. 112 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES States themselves, the original fountains of all the powers of "the Constitution of the United States." This is the doctrine set forth by The Federalist in submitting that instrument or Constitution to the people. "The principles established in a former paper/ 7 says The Federalist, "teach us that the States will retain all pre existing authorities which may not be exclusively dele gated to the federal head." 1 In the former paper here referred to, it is said: "All authorities, of which the States are not explicitly divested in favor of the Union, remain with them in full vigor/ 2 In the ratifying Con vention of Virginia the same doctrine is set forth, as well known to every one at that day, by John Marshall, who was afterwards the illustrious Chief Justice of the Supreme \ Court of the United States. "The State governments/ I says he, "did not derive their powers from the general / government. But each government derived its powers I from the people, and each was to act according to the 1 powers given it." Would any gentleman deny this? He demanded if powers not given were retained by implica tion? Could any man say no? Could any man say that this power was not retained by the States, since it was not given away ? "For," says he, "does not a power remain till it is given away?" 3 Neither Marshall nor Hamilton, the author of the num bers of The Federalist just quoted, was ever suspected of a desire to lessen the authority of the Federal Union, or to magnify that of the States. Yet, as we have seen, both of them assume, as an undeniable principle, that every power which is not delegated by the States to the Federal Union is retained by them in full vigor. This principle results, indeed, from the fact that all the powers of the Federal Government emanate from the people of the sev eral States. The question of Marshall, "Does not a power ; remain till it is given away?" admits of but one answer. For if a principal delegates power to an agent of any kind, or for any purpose, the agent only possesses the > delegated powers, and all others remain with the principal. 1 The Federalist, No. Ixxxii. - Ibid., No. xxxii. 3 "Elliott s Debates," vol. iii, p. 389. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 113 Thus, according to the very nature of things, as well as according to the high authority of Hamilton and Marshall, the States retained all the powers which they had not delegated to the Federal Union. But however plain this principle, or however fully ad mitted by the advocates of federal authority, the States still insisted that it should be expressly incorporated in the written language of the Constitution. Hence, Massa chusetts, having ratified the Constitution, used the follow ing language: "As it is the opinion of this Convention that certain amendments and alterations in said Constitu tion would remove the fears and quiet the apprehensions of many of the good people of the commonwealth, and more effectually guard against an undue administration of the Federal Government, the Convention does therefore recommend that the following alterations and provisions be introduced into said Constitution : "First, That it be explicitly declared that all powers, not expressly delegated by the aforesaid Constitution, are reserved to the several States, to be by them exercised/ 1 In like manner, and for a like reason, Virginia recom mended the following "Amendment to the Constitution. 1st. That each State in the Union shall, respectively, retain every power, jurisdiction, and right which is not by this Constitution delegated to the Congress of the United States, or to the departments of the Federal Gov ernment." 2 North Carolina urged the same amendment to the Constitution, and in precisely the same words as those employed by Virginia. 3 In the first amendment, proposed by Pennsylvania, we find the following words: "All the rights of sovereignty, which are not by the said Constitution expressly and plainly vested in the Congress, shall be deemed to remain with, and shall be exercised by, the several States in the Union." 4 These recommendations, and others to the same effect, secured the tenth amendment to the Constitution of the United States, which is in these words : "The powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor "Elliott s Debates," vol. ii, p. 180. 2 Ibid., vol. iii, p 594 3 Ibid., vol. iv, p. 240. * Ibid., vol. ii, p. 503. 114 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States, or to the people." If reason, if authority, history, if the words of the Constitution itself can establish anything, then may we regard it as definitely and forever settled that every power, right, or authority, which is not delegated to the Federal Union, is reserved to the States, or to the people of the States. I ask, then, where is this great, inherent right of a State to resume the powers it has delegated, surrendered to the Federal Union? Where has this peerless right of sovereignty been ceded, surrendered, or given away? The people may rage, and the politicians imagine a vain thing, but I appeal to the great charter of American rights and liberties. Where, -then, in the Constitution of the United f States, is the sacred and inviolable right of a sovereign j State to resume the powers it has delegated to its agents, l^given away or surrendered? When the States entered into "the compact of the Constitution," they did so, as it is conceded both by Story and Curtis, at the moment they were "free, sovereign, and independent States." * Where, then, in that compact, did they delegate, surrender, or give away the sacred right to resume the powers which they delegated to their agent, the Federal Government; or, in other words, the right to secede from the Union? Let the place in which this right, this greatest of all the rights of sovereignty, has been given away to the Federal Union be pointed out in the Constitution; or it must be conceded that it remained with the States. Let it be shown where "the States are explicitly divested" of this right "in favor of the Union"; or it must be admitted that it "remained with them in full vigor." 1 Ignorance, or passion, or patriotism may "veil this right" ; but, nevertheless, the question is, where is this right given away in the compact of the Constitution? If it be not given away there, it still exists with the States in all the plenitude of its power. The stars do not cease to shine, or to exist, because they are concealed from view by exhalations from the earth, or by the blaze of noon. 1 The Federalist, No. xxxii. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 115 ARGUMENT FROM THE SOVEREIGNTY OF THE STATES Perhaps no subject has ever been considered with less steadiness of mind, or clearness of analysis, than "the sovereignty of the States," except "the sovereignty of the United States." The powers of the Federal Government are enumerated by one party, in order to show that it is sovereign or supreme; while the opposite party attempts to prove the sovereignty of the States by dwelling on the powers which belong to their governments. But all this is nothing whatever to the purpose. It merely deals with the branches, not with the roots, of the great subject under discussion; and, how long soever these branches may be beaten, it will only make confusion the worse confounded. In the contest about the significance of the particular powers of the Federal and of the State govern ments, the real principle on which the whole controversy hinges is overlooked, and the subject in dispute is darkened by words without knowledge, and buried far under floods of logomachy. Mr. Webster, for example, thus demolishes the doctrine of State sovereignty : "However men may think this ought to be, the fact is that the people of the United States have chosen to impose control on State sovereignties. There are those, doubtless, who wish they had been left without restraint, but the Constitution has ordered the matter differently. To make war, for instance, is an exercise of sovereignty, but the Constitution declares that no State shall declare war. To coin money is another act of sovereign power, but no State is at liberty to coin money. "Again, the Constitution says that no sovereign State shall be so sovereign as to make a treaty. These pro hibitions, it must be confessed, are a control on the State sovereignty of South Carolina, as well as of the other States, which does not arise "from her feelings of honorable justice/ The opinion referred to, therefore, is in defiance of the plainest provisions of the Constitution/ 71 Why, then, did he not wind up his unanswerable logic with a quod erat demonstrandum? 1 "Webster s Works," vol. iii, p. 322. 116 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES The truth is that the whole thing, from beginning to end, is a miserable sophism. His premises are false, and his conclusion, therefore, falls to the ground. The fact is that the people of the United States imposed no control whatever on the States, and had no power to do so. On the contrary, each State, for the sake of union, agreed that it would abstain from the exercise of the right to ^ wage war, to coin money, and to make treaties. She dele- t gated these high powers to the government of the Federal Union. She entered into the compact of the Constitution, as we have seen, in her character of "a distinct and independent sovereign," and was, therefore, "bound only by her own voluntary act." 1 All the powers of the Con stitution were delegated, and all its obligations assumed, by the free act of each sovereign State. All the control to which she was liable in the Union was self-imposed; and not one particle of it was laid upon her by any .authority but her own. The act, indeed, by which she entered into the compact of the Constitution, was an exercise, not an abridgment, of her sovereign power. If she could not enter into such a compact, she would be less than sovereign. It is supposed by some, certainly by none who have reflected on the subject, that if a State delegates a portion of her powers, or agrees to abstain from the exercise of them, her sovereignty is thereby limited, or abridged. To all such I would commend the words of Vattel : "Several sovereign and independent States," says he, "may unite themselves together by a perpetual confederacy, without ceasing to be, each individually, a perfect State. They will together constitute a federal republic: their joint deliberations will not impair the sovereignty of each member, though ihey may, in certain respects, put some restraint on the exercise of it, in virtue of voluntary engagements/ 2 Every one should be perfectly familiar with this principle of law. It has been clearly recognized and em bodied in the legislation of this country. In the thirteenth Article of the old Confederation, for example, it is ex- 1 The Federalist. 2 Vattel s "Law of Nations," p. 3. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 117 pressly declared that "the Union shall be perpetual" ; and yet, in the second Article, it is said that "each State retains its sovereignty, freedom, and independence." Thus, although the States, in and by those Articles, delegated many sovereign powers to the Federal Government; this, in conformity with the principle laid down by Vattel, did "not impair the sovereignty of each member." But since the new Constitution, or Articles of Union, contained no clause declaring it perpetual, or assigning any period for its duration, how much more clearly did each State in the "more perfect Union" retain its sovereignty unimpaired ! For, in such case, it is conceded, as we have repeatedly seen, by the great lights of American jurisprudence, that a State may secede at pleasure, or resume the powers she may have delegated to the Federal Government. Indeed, if a State could not thus delegate her sovereign powers, she would cease to be sovereign. She would resemble a minor, who is incapable of entering into con tracts. The State, or the people themselves, can not exer cise sovereign powers in person; and, hence, if she could not delegate them to her agents, representatives, substi tutes, or servants, her sovereignty would be a useless burden to her. Thus the very circumstance which is supposed, by superficial thinkers, to limit and control the sovereignty of a State, is indispensably necessary to the perfection of that sovereignty. The people are not the less sovereign, because they institute governments, and appoint them as agents to transact their business ; although they necessarily delegate a portion of their sovereign powers to these agents, or governments. On the contrary, this is the very highest exercise of sovereignty, and implies the right to alter, amend, or remodel their governments. Xay, it implies the right of a people to set their govern ment entirely aside, and to substitute another in its room. What, then, has all this talk about the powers dele gated to the State Governments, or to the Federal Gov ernment, to do with the great question of sovereignty? Those governments are not sovereign. They are subordi nate to the will of the people, by whom they were created ; and a subordinate sovereignty is a contradiction in terms. 118 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES The only real sovereignty is that which makes, and un makes, Constitutions and governments. Or, if any one is pleased to call any government, whether State or Federal, sovereign ; he should not forget that it is merely a delegated sovereignty. It is not original ; it is derived. It is not inherent; it comes from without; and, instead of being supreme, it depends on a power greater than itself. It is divisible, and may be divided among different govern ments, or agents of the supreme power. On the contrary, the sovereign power of a state, or, in other words, the power of the people of a State, is inherent, original, supreme, indivisible, and inalienable. This, at least, is the American doctrine; and it is to be deeply lamented that Americans should, in the ardor and struggle of debate, so frequently forget, or overlook, the very first lessons they have ever learned, and which they certainly do not mean to repudiate or discard. I have nothing to say, then, about the delegated powers of this or that government. They have nothing to do with the question. Others may wrangle about those powers, if they please, and .beat their brains over them ; all I want to know is, where resides the one power from which all such delegated powers proceed. The difference between this one power and the powers of the government it creates is the difference between the sun and its rays, or the creator and its manifold creations. Where, then, does this one sovereign power reside? It resides, as we have seen, in each State, and not in the people of the United States. The people of the United States, indeed, were not one people, or nation, in the political sense of the word, and were never clothed with any sovereign power whatever. The late war was, it is true, carried on "to preserve the life of the nation." But there was no such nation. Its substance was a sham, and its life was a lie. 1 As the one sovereign power, which makes, and therefore unmakes, Constitutions and governments, resides in each State, so each State had the right to secede from the Federal Government, As each State, however, only made or adopted that government for itself, so she could un- 1 See chap. xii. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 119 make it as to herself only. That is, she had no power to destroy the Federal Union, but only to withdraw from it, and let it move on in its own sphere. In the exercise of her original, inherent, indivisible, inalienable sovereignty she merely seceded from the Union to which she had acceded, and asked to be let alone. But she could not escape the despotic, all-devouring LIE by which her sover eignty had been denied, and her rights denounced as "a pestilential heresy." Nay, by which she had been stripped of her character as a State, and relegated to the rank of a county. Was that the purpose for which, as a sovereign State, she entered into "the more perfect Union?" "No man," says Mr. Webster, "makes a question that the people are the source of all political power. . . . There is no other doctrine of government here." 1 This is conceded. The people make, and the people unmake, Constitutions. This is the universally received doctrine in America. It is asserted by Calhoun as strenuously as by Webster. But the Constitution was made by the people of the several States, each acting for itself, and bound by no action but its own. Hence, as each State acceded to the compact of the Constitution, so each State may, if it chose, secede from that compact. If the premise is true,, the conclusion is conceded; and the premise has been demonstrated. In acceding to the compact of the Consti tution, each State made the Union as to itself; and, in seceding therefrom, it unmakes the Union only as to itself. And it does so by virtue of its own inherent, and inalien able sovereignty. If it should be said that the people of the several States made, but can not unmake, the compact of the Constitution, as to themselves, it would follow that the people of 1788 alone were sovereign. But the people of this generation are sovereign as well as the people of that generation. The attribute of sovereignty is, according to the American doctrine, inherent, and inalienable. The people of Vir ginia, then, in the year 1788, did not, and could not, absorb and monopolize the sovereignty of all subsequent genera tions, so as to deprive them of its exercise. If this could 1 "Webster s Works," vol. vi, p. 221. 120 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES be so, then the sovereign people of one age, or generation, might deprive the sovereign people of all ages and genera tions of their power and freedom. But this can not be. The living, as well as the dead, are sovereign. As the people of Virginia in 1788 acceded to the Union, because they believed it would be for their good ; so the people of Virginia in 1861 had a right to secede from the Union, because they believed it had been made to work their in sufferable harm. Deny this, and you assert the sovereignty of the people of Virginia of 1788, at the expense of the sovereignty of the people of Virginia for all future ages. Or, in other words, you take all power and sovereignty, and freedom from all other ages and generations, in order to concentrate and bury them with a part, departed, in experienced, and perhaps fatally deluded generation. The whole American doctrine of the sovereignty of the people is false, or else it must be asserted for the living as well as for the dead ; and, even if it is false, it is nevertheless the doctrine by which the right of secession should be tried. At the time the Constitution was adopted, or "the more perfect Union" formed, the people of New England took the lead of all others in their devotion to State sovereignty and State rights. Thus, in her Constitution of 1780, Massachusetts declared : "The people of this common wealth have the sole and exclusive right of governing them selves as a free, sovereign, and independent State ; and do, and forever hereafter shall, exercise and enjoy every power, jurisdiction, and right, which is not, or may not hereafter be, by them expressly delegated to the United States of America, in Congress assembled/ Precisely the same language, word for word, is contained in the Constitution of New Hampshire, which was made twelve years after that of Massachusetts. Thus, after the new Union was formed, New Hampshire, in the words of Massachusetts, declared herself a "free, sovereign, and independent State." "Paris," it has been said, "is France." It is more certain that "Massachusetts is New England." How did it happen, then, that Massachusetts, in 1780, and consequently New England, took the lead of all the members of the Union in her devotion to the doctrine THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES 121 of State sovereignty; and yet, in 1861, more fiercely denounced that very doctrine as "a pestilential heresy 5 than any other State in existence? The answer is plain. The mystery is easily solved. Or rather, it is no mystery at all to any one acquainted with the character, or the history, of Massachusetts. Never has she been in the ascendancy, as in 1861, or with the majority working the Union for her benefit, that it did not appear to her eyes, like the full moon, a great world of light full of inexpress ible beneficence and beauty. Nor has she ever been in the minority, feeling the pressure of the Union, or its demands upon her purse, that it did not rapidly wane, and appear to her emptied of all its glory. Hence, in 1861, so great was the glory of the Union to her enravished eyes, that it blotted out the States: just as the meridian sun blots out the stars. She forgets her primitive creed; or, if she remembers it at all, it is only to denounce it as the creed of "rebels and traitors." On the other hand, when, in 1815, Massachusetts felt the Union in her pockets, all its glory vanished, and the Eights of the States, and the Sovereignty of the States, came out to her keen vision like stars after the setting of the sun. This has been the great misfortune of the South, that the world did not turn around quite as fast at her end of the Union as it did in New England, and that it did not turn exactly in the same direction. The creed of the fathers, the creed of all sections in 1787, the creed of all the States for more than thirty years after the formation of the "more perfect Union," was substantially the creed of the South in 1861. There she stood. But, in the meantime, Massachusetts, and consequently all New England, having made one entire revolution, denounced her primitive creed still the creed of the South, that the States are "free, sovereign, and independent," as the in vention of rebels and traitors, designing to put the glorious Union out of joint. True, the South did dislocate the Union, and breed fiery discord ; but, then, this was simply by standing still, and refusing to follow the rapid revolu tion of New England. 122 THE WAE BETWEEN THE STATES ARGUMENT FROM THE SILENCE OF THE CONSTITUTION It is a remarkable fact that, in the Constitution of the United States, there is not a word relating to the perpe tuity or continuance of the government established by it. This momentous question is passed over in profound silence. NOT was this omission an act of forge tfulness. It was, on the contrary, the result of deliberate design. The existing Articles of _ Confederation expressly provided that the government established by them should be "perpetual," and should never be changed without the unanimous consent of all the States of the Union. This provision was deliberately struck out, or not permitted to appear in the new Constitution. In the act of receding from the compact of the Union, which had expressly pronounced itself "perpetual," the fathers had not the face to declare that the new compact should last forever. Time had demonstrated the futility of such a provision. The Convention of 1787 had been most sadly hampered by it in their design to erect a new form of government, as appears from the "Madison Papers," and other accounts of its proceedings. Hence they wisely determined to leave no such obstacle in the way of the free action of future generations, in case they should wish to new-model their government, It is certain that no such obstacle is found in the Constitution framed by them. Now what is the inference from this fact, from this omission? If the framers of the Constitution designed to make it perpetually binding, why did they not say so? Nay, why did they depart from the plan before them, and refuse to say so? Only one answer can be given to this question. They did not intend to repeat the folly of seek ing to render perpetual, by mere dint of words, those Articles of Union between Sovereign States, whose bind ing force and perpetuity must necessarily depend on the justice with which they should be observed by the parties to them, or on their adaptation to the great ends for which they were enacted. The perpetuity, or continuance, of the new Union was frequently alluded to and considered THE WAK BETWEEX THE STATES 123 in the Convention of 1787 ; and yet there is not one syllable on the subject in the Constitution made by them. This speaks volumes. It is argued, in The Federalist, 1 that as the old Articles of Confederation had utterly failed in consequence of defects which no one had foreseen; so the real objections to the new Constitution, whatever they might be, would in all probability remain to be disclosed by time and ex perience. Reasoning from the past, it was concluded that no one could foresee what its real defects were, or how great they might prove in practice. Would it not, then, have been infinitely absurd to pronounce it perpetual, or seek to stamp it with the attribute of immortality? The truth is that the new Constitution was designed by its authors to last just as long as it should be faithfully observed by the parties to it, or as it should answer the great ends of its creation, and no longer. On the failure of either of these conditions, then, in their view, the power by which it was ordained possessed the inherent and indefeasible right to withdraw from it. Otherwise there would be no remedy, not even in the sovereign power itself, for the greatest of all political evils or abuses. Otherwise we should have to repudiate and reject the great principle of American freedom, which has never been called in question by. any statesman of the New World, or over which the least cloud of suspicion has ever been cast by any American citizen. What, then, is the position assumed by those who deny the right of secession? In asserting that a State has no right to withdraw from the Union they declare that the Constitution, or Articles of Union, is perpetually binding. That is to say, by a forced construction, they introduce into the Constitution the very provision which its framers most deliberately refused to insert therein ! They refused to say that the new compact should be perpetual, and yet these interpreters declare that they designed to make it perpetual ! 1 No. xxxviii. 124 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES KEFERENCE Both Story and Webster admit, as we have repeatedly seen, that if sovereign States enter into a compact or Con federation, without expressly prescribing any period for the continuance of the Union; then any State has the right to secede at pleasure. This is the true inference to be drawn from the silence of the Constitution as to the continuance of the Union; an inference too clear and un questionable to be denied by either a Story or a Webster. If they have sought to evade its force, or obscure the right of secession, this is by assuming the ground, so fully exploded in the preceding pages, that the Constitution was not a compact between the States of the Union. "It is sometimes asked/ says Mr. Motley, "why the Constitution did not make a special provision against the right of secession. How could it do so?" 1 Why, simply, by transferring the words of the old Constitution to the new, and saying, "the Union shall be perpetual/ There is no impossibility in the case. The thing had been done once, and it might easily have been done again, if the framers of the Constitution had desired to do it. Many words, phrases, and provisions of the old Constitution were transferred by them to the new; and, if they had wished to do so, they might just as easily transferred those words, "the Union shall be perpetual," or last till all the parties consent to a separation. "How could they do so?" asks Mr. Motley; and I reply, how could he ask so silly a question? "It would have been puerile," says he, for the Consti tution to say formally to each State, thou shalt not secede." There was no necessity, perhaps, that the Convention should have been very formal in the language it addressed to the States. But would it have been puerile, or ridicu lous, if the Convention had said, "the Union shall be perpetual." Who can doubt that if these words had been inserted in the new Constitution that Mr. Motley would have wielded them as an unanswerable argument against the right of secession? Indeed, these words answer that 1 "Rebellion Records," vol. i, p. 214. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 125 purpose so well that Dr. Hodge borrows them from the old Articles of Confederation, and passes them off as "the very words" of the Constitution, in order to demonstrate the palpable absurdity of secession ; in order to show that secession is in direct and open defiance of "the avowed design of the compact" of 1787. These words were, indeed, the very ones he needed to demolish the right of secession ; and his need was so great that he came at them in no very ]egitimate way. Could anything be more feeble, or puerile, than Mr. Motley s attempt to account for the silence of the Convention on the momentous subject of secession? or more clearly illustrate the difficulty of get ting rid of the argument from that silence in favor of secession ? The truth is that the Convention, in its desire to secede from the old compact, was so greatly embarrassed by the clause declaring that "the Union shall be perpetual," that it deliberately removed that obstacle from the path of future legislation; and, whether it was intended by the Convention or not, the legal effect of this was to establish the right of secession under the new compact between the same parties. ARGUMENT FROM THE FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLE OF THE UNION "To render a Federation desirable," says Mr. John Stuart Mill, "several conditions are necessary. The first of these is that there should be a sufficient amount of mutual sympathy among the populations ."* This senti ment recommends itself to the good sense of every man in the world; nay, to every man who is not insane from the influence of passion. Even Mr. Greeley, before the war, could say: "We hope never to live in a Republic whereof one section is pinned to another by bayonets." Such is indeed the desire of every good man, nay, of every rational being ; for, as Mr. Mill says, no union of States is desirable, unless it be held together by the cement of good feeling, as well as of interest. 1 Representative Government," chap. xvii. 126 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES In like manner, John Quincy Adams says: "The indis soluble link of union between the people of the several States of this confederated nation is, after all, not in the right, but in the heart. If the day should ever come (may Heaven avert it!) when the affections of the people of these States shall be alienated from each other; when the fraternal spirit shall give way to cold indifference, or collision of interest shall fester into hatred, the bands of political associations will not long hold together parties no longer attracted by the magnetism of conciliated interests and kindly sympathies; AND FAR BETTER WILL IT BE FOR THE PEOPLE OF THE DISUNITED STATES TO PART IN FRIEND SHIP FROM EACH OTHER, THAN TO BE HELD TOGETHER BY CONSTRAINT. Then will be the time for reverting to the precedents which occurred at the formation and adoption of the Constitution, to form again a more perfect Union, by dissolving that which could no longer bind, and to leave the separated parts to be reunited by the law of political gravitation to the center." "Better," says Mr. Adams, "to part in friendship, than to be held together by restraint." History, it is said repeats itself. Some of the Greek States, wishing to part in peace from their confederates, were held together by force of arms. This, says Freeman, in his learned work on Federal Government, ultimately proved injurious to those who drew the sword of coercion. ARGUMENT FROM THE EIGHT OF SELF-GOVERNMENT The thirteen Colonies, in the Declaration of Independ ence, justified their separation on the distinct ground that \all "governments" derive "their just powers from the con- isent of the governed." It was in obedience to this great principle that the American Union became a free and voluntary association of States. This, by its very nature, excludes the idea of coercion. For, if States are compelled to remain in the Union against their will, this is sub jugation, and not a copartnership in honor, interest, free dom, and glory. It destroys the autonomy, annihilates the freedom, and extinguishes the glory of the subjugated THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 127 States. The system is transformed. It is no longer a sisterhood of free States, but the vassalage of some, and the dominion of others. This is so obvious that it was declared, at first, even by the most zealous advocates of President Lincoln, that no one .intended to coerce a State. What then ? Did they mean to let it go in peace? No, they neither intended to coerce a seceding State, nor let it depart! But how was such a thing possible? Why, these admirable casuists, by a most refined and subtle distinction, determined that they would not coerce a State, but only the people of whom it is composed! The State secedes. The citizens acknowledge their allegiance to the State, and determine to obey the ordinance of secession. And thereupon the Federal Gov ernment resolves to wage war, not upon the State itself, but only upon the people of the State! Happy State! Miserable people! The one may depart; but the other must come back ! But if the Federal Government had only waged war upon the State, how would it have pro ceeded otherwise than it did? The authors of this very nice distinction were evidently driven to assume such a position by the horror which Madison, Ellsworth, Mason, Hamilton, and other fathers of the Constitution, were known to have expressed at the idea of the coercion of a State. No I they would not coerce a State; they would not be guilty of the horrid thing so eloquently denounced by the fathers ; they would only wage war on the men, women, and children of whom the State is composed! How admirable the acuteness! How wonderful the logic ! In 1848, Mr. Lincoln had not forgotten his very first, and nearly his very last, lesson in the science of govern ment. He had read it in the Declaration of Independence ; he had heard it recited in school; he had heard it most eloquently spouted every Fourth of July. How, then, could he forget it, without some very powerful motive? No humble rail-splitter, no honest citizen could forget such a lesson. It requires a great politician, or a President, to forget, despise, and trample such things underfoot. Hence, in 1848, the humble citizen, Abraham Lincoln, like 128 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES every other American citizen, publicly declared that "any people whatever have a right to abolish the existing govern- men, and form a new one that suits them better. This is a most valuable, a most sacred right." Yes, any people whatever: the thirteen British Colonies; the Greeks; the States of South America; Poland; Hungary; any and every people under the wide expanse of heaven except the people of the South. But why except the South? The reason is plain. It was, indeed, most perfectly and fully explained by Mr. Lincoln himself. When asked, as Presi dent of the United States, "why not let the South go ?" his simple, direct, and honest answer revealed one secret of the wise policy of the Washington Cabinet. "Let the South go!" said he. "Where, then, shall we get our revenue?" There lies the secret. The Declaration of Independence is great ; the voice of all the fathers is mighty ; but then they yield us no revenue. The right of self-government is "a most valuable, a most sacred right" ; but in this particular case it gives us no revenue. Hence, this "most valuable, this most sacred right," may and should shine upon every other land under heaven ; but here it must "pale its in effectual fires," and sink into utter insignificance and con tempt in the august presence of the "ALMIGHTY DOLLAR." As the object of the Eepublican leaders, in wishing to retain the South, was not to lose revenue, so now [i. e., 1866] that they have the South the only use they have for her is to lay taxes and other burdens of government upon her. In open and shameless violation of the great principle of 1776, the South is united to the North by the tie of "taxation without representation." Is this "the sacred right" of self-government? The Union waged a seven years war to establish that right, and a four years war to demolish it. Every American citizen has taken in the idea of self- government with his mother s milk; has heard it from all his most venerated guides, teachers, and oracles ; has pro claimed it himself, perhaps, all his life as "a most valuable, and a most sacred right." Hence, he should not be re quired, all on a sudden, to proclaim the diametrically opposite doctrine. He should be allowed some little time, THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 129 at least, to clear his throat for the opposite utterance. Is it not quite natural, then, that his early and lifelong prejudice in favor of the right of self-government should have clung to the editor of the Tribune, the great organ of the Bepublican part} 7 , even while that party was preparing the way for its subversion? True, it was but an organ; yet had it so long, and so earnestly, proclaimed the great right of self-government that some little time, at least, should have been allowed for it to come right around to the diametrically opposite position. Accordingly, on the 9th of November, three days after Mr. Lincoln s election, that organ uttered the sentiments: "If the cotton States shall become satisfied that they can do better out of the Union than in it, we insist on letting them go in peace. . . . We must ever resist the right of any State to remain in the Union and nullify or defy the laws thereof. TO WITHDRAW FROM THE UNION IS QUITE ANOTHER MATTER ; and, whenever any considerable section of our Union shall deliberately resolve to go out, WE SHALL RESIST ALL COERCIVE MEASURES DESIGNED TO KEEP IT IN. We hope never to live in a Eepublic whereof one section is pinned to another by bayonets." Again, on the 17th of December, just before the secession of South Carolina, the same organ said : "If it [the Decla ration of Independence] justifies the secession from the British Empire of three millions of colonists in IT 76, WE DO NOT SEE WHY IT WOULD NOT JUSTIFY THE SECESSION OF FIVE MILLIONS OF SOUTHERNERS FROM THE FEDERAL UNION IN 1861. If we are mistaken on this point, why does not some one show us wherein and why? For our own part, while we deny the right of slaveholders to hold slaves against the iviU of the latter, we can not see hoir tirenty millions of people can hold ten, or even fire, in a detested Union with them by military force. ... If seven or eight contiguous States should present themselves authori tatively at Washington, saying, We hate the Federal Union; we have withdrawn from it; we give you the choice between acquiescing in our secession and arranging amicably all incidental questions on the one hand and attempting to subdue us on the other; WK COULD NOT 130 Tin-: WAR BETWEEN THE STATES STAND UP FOR COERCION, FOR SUBJUGATION, FOR WE DO NOT THINK IT WOULD BE JUST. WE HOLD THE RIGHT OF SELF- GOVERNMENT EVEN WHEN INVOKED IN BEHALF OF THOSE AVHO DENY IT TO OTHERS. So MUCH FOR THE QUESTION OF PRINCIPLE . . . . Any attempt to compel them by force to remain would be contrary to the principles enunciated in the immortal Declaration of Independence, contrary to the fundamental idea on which human liberty is based." On the 23d of February, 1861, after the cotton States had formed their confederacy., the Tribune used this language: "We have repeatedly said, and we once more insist,, that the great principle embodied by Jefferson in the Declaration of American Independence, that governments derive their just powers from the consent of the governed, is sound and just; and that if the slave States, the cotton States, or the gulf States only, choose to form an inde pendent nation THEY HAVE A CLEAR MORAL RIGHT TO DO so. Whenever it shall be clear that the great body of Southern people have become conclusively alienated from the Union, and anxious to escape from it, WE WILL DO OUR BEST TO FORWARD THEIR VIEWS." President Buchanan, from whose interesting book the above extracts have been taken, adds : "In a similar spirit, leading Bepublicans everywhere scornfully exclaimed, Let them go ; We can do better without them ; Let the Union slide, and other language of the same import." Before the war, it was indignantly denied that the abolitionists constituted more than a small minority of the Republicans. How is it since the war? Does not almost every man of them now claim that he has always been an abolitionist, and, as such, come in for his share of glory in the formed emancipation of the slaves? It is certain that, of all the men in the Union, the abolitionists of the Republican party were the most active asserters, and the most powerful promoters, of secession and dis union. They everywhere proclaimed, not only the right, but the sacred duty of secession. William Lloyd Garrison led the way. "In the expressive and pertinent language of Scripture," said he, "the Constitution was a covenant THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 131 with death, and an agreement with hell/ null and void before God from the first moment of its inception the f ramers of which were recreant to duty, and the supporters of. which are equally guilty." 1 Yet, how strange ! the men of this school enlisted in the ranks, and fought under the banner of Mr. Lincoln, w r ho was bound by his oath to support that "covenant with death and agreement with hell!" Did they fight for the Constitution? Did they heartily join in the cry for the Union ? Again, he said "the motto inscribed on the banner of Freedom is, no Union with slaveholders.- . . . Our motto is, no Union with slaveholders either religious or political. 3 In withdrawing from the American Union, we have the God of justice with us." 4 Did this man, then, or his followers, fight for the Union? "Circulate," he cried, "a declaration of DISUNION FROM SLAVEHOLDERS THROUGH OUT THE COUNTRY. Hold- mass meetings assemble in Conventions nail your banners to the mast." 5 Did these men, then, take down their banners, trample its motto in the dust, and join the loud war-cry for the Union of the fathers? If so, then it was not because they hated that Union the less, but because they hated Southerners the more. Now this man William Lloyd Garrison was an honest fanatic. He just came right down with a direct sledge hammer force on all slaveholders, and on all the poor, pitiful, puling hypocrites, who pretended to desire to pre serve the Constitution and the Union; and who, to that end, labored to explain away the provisions of that "sacred compact," as they delighted to call the Constitution. "Those provisions," said they, "were meant to cover slavery," yet "as they may be fairly interpreted to mean something exactly the reverse, it is allowable to give them such an interpretation, especially as the cause of Freedom will be thereby promoted."* In thus stating this hypo critical position, Mr. Garrison must have had Mr. Sumner in his mind s eye. But with honest scorn and contempt he tears the mean fabric to tatters, and scatters it to the 1 "Anti-Slavery Examiner," vol. xi. p. 101. - Ibid., p. 101 :t Ibid., p. 118. 4 Ibid., p. 1 H>. Ibid., p. 11!>. "Ibid., p. 104. 132 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES winds ! "This," says he, "is to advocate fraud and violence to one of the contracting parties, whose cooperation was secured only by an express agreement and undertaking between them both, in regard to the clauses alluded to; and that such a construction, if enforced by laws and penalties, would unquestionably lead to civil war, and the aggrieved party would justly claim to have been betrayed, and robbed of their Constitutional rights." 1 "Xo honest use can be made of it," says he, "in opposi tion to the plain intention of its framers, except to declare the contract at an end, and to refuse to serve under it."- It is of no use to lie, said he, the Constitution is "a con tract" between the States ; an "express agreement and undertaking" between the North and the South. He will not have this "express agreement" explained away. "Tt is objected," says he, "that slaves are held as property, and, therefore, as the clause refers to persons, it can not mean slaves. Slaves are recognized not merely as property, but also as persons as having a mixed character as combining the human with the brute. This is paradoxical, we admit; but slavery is a paradox the American Con stitution is a paradox the American Union is a paradox the American Government is a paradox and, if any one of these is to be repudiated on that ground, they all are. That it is the duty of the friends of freedom to deny the binding authority of them all, and to secede from all, we distinctly affirm"* Such were the sentiments of Mr. Lloyd Garrison, in 1844, delivered in their annual address to the Anti-Slavery Society of America, as its president. Precisely the same sentiments were entertained by the two learned secretaries of that society, namely, Wendell Phillips and Maria West on Chapman, as well as by all its leading members. They proclaimed the duty of secession from the Constitution, from the Union, and from the Government of America. They wished to have nothing to do with slaveholders. In the mild and conciliatory language of their president, 1 "Anti-Slaverv Examiner," vol. xi. p. 104. - Ibid. " Ibid., p. 114. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 133 they longed to get away and to live apart from those "incorrigible men-stealers, merciless tyrants, and blood thirsty assassins." 1 Such was the gentle and persuasive language, and such were the loyal sentiments, of the abolitionists from 1844 to 1861. The following resolutions were passed at a meet ing of the American Anti- Slavery Society : "Resolved, That secession from the United States Government "is the duty of every Abolitionist, since no one can take office or "deposit his vote under the Constitution without violating his "anti-slavery principles, and rendering himself an abettor to the "slaveholder in his sin." "Resolved, That years of warfare against the slave power has "convinced us that every act done in support of the American "Union rivets the chain of the slave that the only exodus of the "slave to freedom, unless it be one of blood, must be over the "remains of the present American Church and the grave of the "present Union." "Resolved, That the Abolitionists of this country should make "it one of the primary objects of this agitation to dissolve the "American Union." Yet of all the war-spirits in the country, these very men were the loudest and fiercest in their cries for a war of coercion to put down secession, as rebellion and treason. In its burning hate of the Union, the Tribune had become poetical, and addressed THE AMERICAN FLAG as follows : Tear down that flaunting lie! Half-mast the starry flag! Insult on sunny sky With hate s polluted rag! But, all on a sudden, that "polluted rag" became the most sacred ensign of freedom that ever floated between heaven and earth! The cry has gone forth: "This Union is a lie! The American Union is an imposition. ... I am for its overthrow. . . . Up with the flag of dis union, that we may have a glorious Eepublic of our own." But anon, and from the same person, the opposite cry is heard : "Down with the flag of disunion, and up with the 1 "Anti-Slavery Examiner," vol. xi, pp. 111-112. 134 THE WAB BETWEEN THE STATES flag of the Union, that we may preserve the life of the nation/ the glorious Kepublic of the fathers. Even the despised Constitution, "the antiquated parchment" of Henry Ward Beecher, becomes all at once young, and fresh, and beautiful again ! and that Reverend gentleman stands before the world at Exeter Hall as the grand representative of the "constitutional union" party of this country! Is there, in the history of the world, another instance of .a change so sudden, so complete, and so wonderful in the avowed sentiments of any great body of men, as that which took place among the abolitionists of the country in 1861 ? Now whence all this intense love of the Union, where recently there had been such deadly hate ? Whence this newborn desire to be forever associated with "the merciless tyrants, the bloodthirsty assassins" of the South ? The truth is they did not love the Union then, and they do not want the Union now (i. e., 1866). They raised the cry of "the Union"; because, as one of their leaders said, they believed they could "win on the Union. 7 And having ridden into power on "the Union," and consolidated their power in the name of "the Union," they now resist the persistent efforts of President Johnson to restore the Union. But Mr. Greeley has, in his "American Conflict," made a most awkward and unsatisfactory attempt to explain the course of the Union-hating and the Union-loving Tribune. It was, perhaps, a little difficult for him to speak out all that was in him on this delicate subject. The truth seems to be: 1. That the word which went forth from President Lincoln, "If we let the South go, where shall we get our revenue?" is one of the causes of the great change in question. Several books had, in 1860, been published to illustrate the subject of "Southern Wealth and Northern Profits," and, upon reflection, the North concluded that, after all, she had some use for the South. She was natu rally indignant at the thought of losing the bird which had so long laid for her the golden egg. 2. Secession offered a splendid opportunity, or occasion, on which to wreak a little wrath on the slaveholders of the South, on those "incorrigible men-stealers, merciless tyrants, and THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 135 bloodthirsty assassins/ who so richly deserved to die. But it would, of course, be much more respectable to kill them as "rebels and traitors/ than merely as slaveholders. Hence, the very men who had been foremost and fiercest in preaching the duty of secession and disunion, became, all on a sudden, the most clamorous for the blood of secessionists as traitors to "the glorious Union." As the cynic, Diogenes, trampled on the robe of Plato s pride with a still greater pride, so the abolitionists panted for the blood of "bloodthirsty assassins" with a still greater thirst. Hence,, more than any other class of men, they insisted that Mr. Lincoln, however reluctant, should "cry havoc, and let slip the dogs of war." 3. Secession furnished a fine pretext, a glorious occasion, for the forced emancipation of the slaves at the South. Hence, just be fore Mr. Lincoln publicly declared that he had neither the wish, nor the power, to interfere with slavery in the States, the word privately went forth from a member of his Cabinet, that secession should be punished with the emancipation of the blacks, and with the utter devastation of the South by fire and sw^ord. 1 This word was, of course, intended for "the faithful." For if, at that early day, such a design had been publicly avowed, it would have filled the North with amazement, horror, and disgust. But has it not been accomplished to the very letter? Such were the causes, especially the last two, by which, it seems to me, so wonderful a revolution was produced in the political view r s and aspirations of the Northern abolitionists. The change appeared like magic. "The antiquated parchment" was renovated ; the "polluted rag" was purified; and the Union became not orrly habitable, but the only fit habitation for free men. But, then, the Union was not to be "the most perfect Union" of the fathers; the Constitution was not to be the compact of 1787 ; and "hate s polluted rag" was to be consecrated and glorified by hate. On the contrary, the Union was to be cast into the furnace of war, seven times heated, and to come forth free from the sin of slavery, and cemented, 1 Perhaps that member of his Cabinet knew the design of Mr. Lincoln s administration better than it was then known to Mr. Lincoln himself. 136 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES not by "the mutual sympathy of its populations," but by their blood. It was to be a new Union; a bright and beautiful emanation ; not from the consent of the governed, but from the sovereign, the supreme, the sublime will of the Northern abolitionists. How lustily soever they joined in the war-cry for the Union, this was in order that they might the more effectually overthrow it, and ordain one of their own in its place. Is not this the true secret of their newborn love for "the glorious Union ?" Previous to the war, it was frequently alleged that the abolitionists constituted only a small minority in the Republican party. It is certain that they controlled the policy of Mr. Lincoln s administration. "The higher law,"" "the law written on the hearts and consciences of freemen/ was the rule of their conduct. For the Consti tution, for the compact of 1787, for that "covenant with death and agreement with hell," they cared less than nothing; except when it agreed with their own will, or could be made a pretext for their designs. The fact that there was not the shadow of an authority for coercion in the Constitution had not the least weight with them. Nay, if the power to coerce had been expressly denied to the" Federal Government in the Constitution, this provision would have been easily explained away, or overruled by "the law written on the hearts and consciences of freemen." It would have been but a "straw to the fire i ? the blood." President Buchanan could not find the power to coerce a State in the Constitution he had sworn to support. In like manner, Professor Bernard, of Oxford, England, finding no authority for the coercion of a State in the Constitution of 1787, pronounces it wrong. The same ground is taken by Mr. Freeman, of the same university, in his learned work on Federal Government. But if coercion is a wrong under the Constitution, then, surely, secession is a Constitutional right. Every man has the legal right to do anything which is not forbidden by the law of the land. He may not have the moral, but he has the legal, right to do it. A miserly act, for example, especially in a "rich man, is morally and socially wrong. But if there is no law against it, then, however rich the man may be, THE WAE BETWEEN THE STATES 137 he has the legal right to do it. We may despise the act; we may abhor it; and we may denounce it as bitterly as any one ever denounced secession. But still, in the case supposed, the act is done in the exercise of a legal right which every one is bound to recognize and respect. This ambiguity in the term right has, indeed, been the source of no little darkness and confusion in the discussion of moral and political questions. Mr. Buchanan seems to have been confused by this ambiguity, when he denied both the right of coercion and the right of secession. Surely, both positions can not be true, in the legal sense of the term right. For, if we say that coercion is a Constitutional wrong, or usurpation, is not this saying that the Constitution permits secession, or, in other words, that it is a Constitutional right? This appears so clear to my mind that when Mr. Buchanan denied the right of secession, I suppose he merely intended to condemn secession as a moral or social wrong. This is the way in which he must be understood, if we would not make him contradict himself. He may have dreaded, he may have abhorred the act of secession: and he may, therefore, have pronounced it wrong in the forum of conscience. But if the Constitution does not authorize coercion, then it permits secession; or, in other words, secession is a Constitutional right, which every power on earth is bound to respect as existing under the supreme law of the land ; a Constitutional right which the Federal Government could deny only by an act of usurpa tion. Coercion is unconstitutional. Coercion is wrong. Coercion strikes down and demolishes the great funda mental principle of the Declaration of Independence the sacred right of self-government itself. Coercion wages war on the autonomy of free States. Secession, on the other hand, asserts the right of self-government for every tree, sovereign, and independent State in existence. Virginia did not favor secession. But when the hour of trial came she stood in the imminent, deadly breach between trie secession of South Carolina and the coercion of Massachusetts ; receiving into her own broad bosom the 138 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES fatal shafts of war till she fell crushed, bleeding, and exhausted to the earth. I appeal to the universe, then, if her course was not noble, heroic, sublime. Massachusetts has, on the contrary, favored both seces sion and coercion by turns. The pilgrim fathers of Massa chusetts delighted in two things: first, in the freedom from persecution for themselves; and, secondly, in the sweet privilege and power to persecute others. In like manner, their sons have rejoiced in two things: first, in the right of self-government for themselves ; and, secondly, in the denial of that right to others. ARGUMENT FROM THE OPINION OF WELL-INFORMED AND INTELLIGENT FOREIGNERS The position that secession is a Constitutional right, flowing from the idea that the Constitution is a compact between sovereign States, is adopted by many impartial foreigners, who have been at the pains to examine our institutions for themselves. Thus says M. De Tocqueville, in his celebrated works on "Democracy in America" : "The Union was formed by the voluntary agreement of the States; and in uniting together they have not forfeited their nationality, nor have they been reduced to the condi tion of one and the same people. If one of the States chose to withdraw from the compact, it would be difficult to disprove its right of doing so, and the Federal Govern ment would have no means of maintaining its claims directly either by force or right/ 1 In like manner, Dr. Mackay says : "The Federal Government exists on suffer ance only. Any State may, at any time, Constitutionally withdraw from the Union, and thus virtually dissolve it. It was not certainly created with the idea that the States, or several of them, would desire a separation; but, when ever they choose to do it, they have no obstacle in the Constitution/ Mr. Spence also, to whom we ow T e this extract from Dr. Mackay, comes to the conclusion, in his 5 Vol. i, chap, xviii, p. 413. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 139 able work on "The American Union/ 7 that secession is a Constitutional right. Nay, he unanswerably establishes this conclusion by facts which lie on the very surface of American history, and which, however they may be con cealed or obscured by the influence of party passions at home, can not escape the scrutiny of impartial foreigners, who may simply desire to ascertain the truth in regard to such questions. After referring to the opinions of M. De Tocqueville and Dr. Mackay, Mr. Spence very justly re marks : "Here, secession is plainly declared a Constitutional right, not by excited Southerners, but by impartial men of unquestionable ability/ 1 An intelligent foreigner, as De Lolme, in his admirable treatise on the Constitution of England, observes, possesses some very decided advantages in the study of the funda mental institutions of a country. This is especially true in regard to ail questions which have been drawn into the vortex of party politics, and mixed up with the struggle for power and the emoluments of office. Xever has its justness been more forcibly illustrated than in regard to the conflicting theories of the Constitution of the United States. Though Lord Brougham, to select only one example, most profoundly sympathized with the abolitionists of the North; yet, in spite of all his natural affinities, the simple facts of history constrained him to adopt the Southern view of the Constitution. Hence, in his work on Political Philosophy, he says: "It is plainly impossible to consider the Constitution which professes to govern this whole Union, this Federacy of States, AS ANY THING OTHER THAN A TREATY." 2 Accordingly, he speaks of the American Union of States, as "the Great League." It required no great research, or profound logic, to reach this conclusion. On the contrary, it requires, as we have seen, the utmost effort to keep facts in the background, and all the resources of the most perverse ingenuity to come to any other conclusion. It is, indeed, only neces sary to know a few facts, with which every student of our 1 "The American Union," p. 201. - Vol. iii, chap. xxx. p. 336. 140 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES history is perfectly familiar, and which are well stated by Lord Brougham, in order to recognize the fundamental principle of the "Great League." "The affairs of the colonies," says he, "having during the revolutionary war been conducted by a Congress of delegates for each, on the restoration of peace, and the final establishment of their independence, they formed this Federal Constitution, which was only gradually adopted by the different members of the Great League. Nine States having ratified it, the new form of government went into operation on the 4th of March, 1798. Before the end of 1790 it had received the assent of the remaining States." These facts alone, it is believed, are absolutely decisive in favor of the position that the American Union was a voluntary association of States, or a compact to which the States were the parties. Hence it is that foreigners, whether impartial or prejudiced against the South, adopt the Southern view of the Con stitution, when they examine the subject with the least care. It is natural, indeed, that foreigners, before they examine the subject, should look upon the American people as one consolidated nation ; for that is the external appearance which they present to those who view the affairs ol this continent from a distance. But like a multiple star, which in the distance seems to be a single luminary to the naked eye, the American Union is no sooner ap proached, or more closely examined, than it is resolved into a constellation of sister States. Nothing but party passion, it is believed, can resist so plain a conclusion ; just as the clearest revelations of the telescope were vehemently denied by many of the most learned contempo raries of Gallileo. Hence it is that De Tocqueville, and Mackay, and Spence, and Brougham, and Cantu, 1 and Heeren, 2 as well as other philosophers, jurists, and his torians among the most enlightened portions of Europe, so readily adopt the Southern view of the Constitution, and pronounce the American Union a confederation of States. 1 "Historie Universelle," originally written in Italian, vol. xvii, p. 371. - "European States and Colonies," pp. 350-351. CONFEDERATE CHIEFTAINS THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 143 ARGUMENT FROM THE VIRGINIA ORDINANCE OF RATIFICATION A great many unfounded objections were urged against the Constitution by its enemies. Mr. Madison lias, in the thirty-eighth number of The Federalist, drawn a powerful picture of "the incoherence of the objections to the plan proposed"; that is, to the Constitution of 1787. Now this chaos of conflicting objections, which were raised by the enemies of the Constitution in order to defeat its adoption, could not truly reflect the nature and design of that plan for the government of the Union. Yet, however strange it may seem, Mr. Justice Story and Mr. Webster have, as we have seen, 1 selected one of these objections to show what the Constitution is; though this very objection had been most triumphantly refuted by Mr. Madison, both in The Federalist and in the ratifying Convention of Virginia. By the same sort of logic, if logic it may be called, they might have fastened almost any other absurd interpreta tion on the Constitution, as well as the construction that it was ordained by the people of America as one nation, and not by the several States. By appealing to the objections of Patrick Henry alone, as an authority, they might have proved that there was "not one federal feature" in the Constitution of 1787, as well as a dozen other glaring absurdities; and that the fathers of the Constitution did not know what they were about when they called the work of their own hands, (< Tl\e Federal Government of these Mates" In the ratifying Convention of Virginia, Patrick Henry frequently dwelt, with great earnestness, on the danger of entering into a new and untried Union, from which there might be no escape. Virginia is now free, said he, and the mistress of her ow r n destiny. But once in the new Union, the power of the general government may be wielded for her injury and oppression. This result was, in fact, elo quently predicted by Patrick Henry, George Mason, William Grayson, and other members of the same Con vention. This argument proceeded on the supposition, 1 Chap, ix, pp. 74-5. 144 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES either that Virginia would not have the right to secede from the Union, or else that this right would be denied by her oppressors. The debates in the Virginia Convention of 1788 are, indeed, replete with passages of burning eloquence, which predict the calamities that would fall on that noble State, as well as on other Southern States, from the oppressions of "the Northern majority." Hence, the people of Virginia, in their ordinance of ratification, took the precaution to guard against this danger by expressly reserving the right to resume the powers delegated to the Federal Government "whensoever the same shall be per- yerted by their injury or oppression." The view which Virginia has taken of her own ordinance is disputed. The words of this ordinance are as follows : "We, the delegates of the people of Virginia, duly elected, etc., . . . do in the name, and in behalf of the people of Virginia, declare and make known, that the powers granted under the Constitution, being derived from the people of the United States, be resumed by them whensoever the same shall be perverted to their injury or oppression/ Mr. Webster understood these words, "the people of the United States," precisely as he understood them in the preamble to the Constitution. Hence, he quotes the Vir ginia ordinance of ratification, in order to show that the Constitution was established, not by the States, nor by the people of the States, but by "the people of the United States in the aggregate," or as one nation. But, as we have repeatedly seen, this is a false view of the words in question. They were not so understood by the Virginia Convention of 1788. In that Convention, Mr. Madison most clearly and fully explained these words, precisely as he had previously done in The Federalist. The powers of the new government are derived, said he, from the people of the United States, "but not the people as composing one great society, but the people as composing thirteen sovereignties." Such was the meaning of the words in question, as explained by James Madison, to whom the Convention looked for in formation on the subject, and by whom they were led to adopt and ratify the Constitution. Yet these words arc THE WAR BETWEEN" THE STATES 145 quoted by Webster, Everett, and other politicians of Massachusetts, in order to show that, in the opinion of the Virginia Convention of 1788, the Constitution of the United States was ordained by the people of America as one nation; and that the people of America as one nation may, therefore, resume the delegated powers "whensoever they shall be perverted to their injury or oppression. 7 To this interpretation and inference there are several insuper able objections. In the first place, the Constitution was not to be estab lished by the people of America as one nation, or by "the people of the United States as one great society"; and this fact was perfectly well known to the Virginia Con vention of 1788. It has already been sufficiently demon strated that the Constitution was ordained, not by the people of America as one great society, but by each People acting for itself alone, and to be bound exclusively by its own voluntary act, It would be a gross solecism in language, as well as in logic, to say that the people of the United States as one great society might resume powers which were not delegated by them. The sovereignty which delegates is the sovereignty which resumes, and it is absurd to speak of a resumption of powers by any other authority, whether real or imaginary. In the second place, the evil intended to be remedied shows the true meaning of the words in question. The Virginia people did not fear that the people of the United States might pervert the powers of the Federal Govern ment for their own oppression. Their fears were for the weak, not for the strong ; not for the people of the United States in the aggregate, but for the Southern States in the minority; and especially for the State of Virginia. They feared, as the burning eloquence of Henry, and Mason, and Monroe, and Graysori evinced, that the new government would "operate as a faction of seven States to oppress six" ; that the Xorthern majority would, sooner or later, trample on the Southern minority. They feared, in the language of Grayson, that the new Union would be made "to exchange the poverty of the North for the riches of the South." In the words of Henrv, "This 140 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES Government subjects everything to the Northern majority. Is there not, then, a settled purpose to check the Southern interest? We thus put unbounded power over our property in hands not having a common interest with us. How can the Southern members prevent the adoption of the most oppressive mode of taxation in the Southern States, as there is a majority in favor of the Northern States? Sir, this is a picture so horrid, so wretched, so dreadful that I need no longer dwell upon it/ 71 Did the Convention of Virginia, then, seek to quiet these dreadful apprehensions, by declaring that the people of the United States, "as one great society, " might resume the powers of the Federal Government whensoever they should be perverted to their oppression? By declaring that this one great society, or rather the majority of this society, might resume the powers of the Federal Government whensoever they should be pleased to use them for the oppression of the minority? Could any possible interpre tation render any legislation more absolutely ridiculous? It puts the remedy in the hands of those from whom the evil is expected to proceed ! It gives the shield of defence to the very power which holds the terrible sword of destruction ! The Convention of Virginia spoke "in behalf of the people of Virginia, 77 and not in behalf of the overbearing majority, by whom it was feared these people might be crushed. They sought to protect, not the people of America, who needed no protection, but the people of Virginia. Hence, as the people of Virginia had delegated power to the Federal Government, they reserved "in behalf of the people of Virginia, 1 the right to resume those powers whensoever they should be perverted to their injury or oppression. Now this reservation enures to the benefit of all the parties to the Constitutional compact; for as all such com pacts are mutual, so no one party can be under any greater obligation than another. Hence, a condition in favor of one is a condition in favor of all. This well- known principle was asserted by Mr. Calhoun in the great 1 "Elliott s Debates," vol. iii. p. 312. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 147 debate of 1833, with the remark that lie presumed it would not be denied by Mr. Webster; and it was not denied by him. Hence any State, as well as Virginia-, had the express right to resume the powers delegated by her to the Federal Government, in case they should be per verted to her injury or oppression. But, it may be asked, were the powers of the Federal Government perverted to the injury or oppression of any Southern States? It might be easily shown that they were indeed perverted to the injury and oppression of more States than one; but this is unnecessary, since the parties to the compact, the sovereign States by whom it was ratified, are the judges of this question. 1 1 See Virginia Resolutions of 98 : Kentucky Resolutions of 98 and 99; the Virginia Report of 1800, etc. CHAPTER XIV ARGUMENTS AGAINST THE RIGHT OF SECESSION HAVING considered the arguments in favor of the right of secession, it is, in the next place, proper to analyze and discuss those which have been most confidently urged against that right. Among these, none have been relied on with greater confidence than those which are supposed to flow from the express language of the Constitution. This class of arguments shall, therefore, occupy the first place in the following examination and discussion. ARGUMENT FROM "THE VERY WORDS " OF THE CONSTITUTION Xow this argument comes directly to the point. Let us see, then, these "very words and avowed design of the compact" 1 of 1787, by which the right of secession is repudiated and rejected. "The contracting parties," we are told, stipulate that "the Union shall be perpetual." 2 Again, the same writer says, "these States are pledged to a perpetual Union"; quoting, as he supposes, the very words of the Constitution. But, unfortunately, for his confident argument, these words are not to be found in the Constitution at all. They are evidently taken from the old Articles of Confederation! Would it not be well, if learned doctors of divinity would only condescend to read the Constitution before they undertake to interpret it for the benefit of their confiding flocks? Especially should they not take some little pains to ascertain "the very words" of the compact" of 1787, before they erect on its very words the grave charge of treason against their "Southern brethren ?" The Constitution, says an English writer, does "ex pressly .prohibit the States from entering into any treaty, 1 "The Rev. Dr. Hodge on the State of the Country," p. 24. 2 Ibid., p. 25. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 149 alliance, or confederation, such as the so-called Southern Confederacy. " 1 This argument is relied on with great confidence. It may be found in all the books, pamphlets, and publications with which the opponents of secession have flooded the English public on the "American Ques tion." Yet, as it appears to me, it clearly admits of two perfectly satisfactory replies. In the first place, the Constitution, or the new "Articles of Union,** is obligatory only upon the members of the Union. No one supposes that the States could, while remaining in the Union, form any other "treaty, alliance, on confederation. * But their duty while in the Union is one thing, and their right to withdraw from the Union is quite another. In the articles of any partnership, whether great or small, a clause may be inserted forbidding the parties to enter into any other partnership of the same kind, or for the same purpose. Indeed this is often done. But who. for a moment, ever imagined that such a clause would render the partnership perpetual, or forever prevent any of its members from withdrawing from the firm? In the second place, the words in question were trans ferred from the old to the new "Articles of Union. * Thus, says the old Articles : "No two or more States shall enter into any treaty, confederation, or alliance whatever between them." 2 Now this clause was binding as long as the Confederation continued. But did it prohibit "any two or more States " from withdrawing from the Union, in order to establish "a more perfect * one? By no means. It is, on the contrary, perfectly notorious, that some of the States did withdraw from that Union in order to form the Union of 1787. Hence, nothing but the blind force of passion can render this clause more obligatory in the new "Articles of Union" or in the Constitution, than it was in the old one. Nay, if words could have made any union of States per petual, the old Articles of Confederation would still form the supreme law of the American Union. For the thir teenth Article expressly declares that "the articles of this 1 Ludlow s "History of the United States." - Art. vi. 150 THE WAR BETWEEX THE STATES confederation shall be observed by every State, and the Union shall be perpetual; nor shall any alteration at any time hereafter be made in any of them,, unless such altera tions be agreed to by a Congress of the United States. and be afterward confirmed by the Legislatures of every State." Yet, in spite of these words, some of the States did withdraw from that "perpetual Union," and formed a new one. The people of 1787 refused to be bound by the people of 1778. They deemed themselves no less sovereign than their predecessors. Hence, in the words of the English writer above quoted, "the plan of course failed, like all similar attempts to fetter future legislation." 1 Xo words, and no principle of law or justice, could render such Articles of Union forever binding on free, sovereign, and independent States. Nothing but passion, or brute force, could have compelled the millions of 1865 to bend their necks to the legislation of 1787 against their will. The Union of 1787 owed its existence to secession from a voluntary association of States ; and, being itself a voluntary association of States, it could not escape from the law of its creation. The right of secession was, indeed, the law both of its origin and its existence. The English writer, who argues so confidently against the right of secession from the words of the Constitution, does not seem to have been at all aware that those words were borrowed from the old Articles of Confederation, or that the Convention of 1787 had understood them very differently from himself. The people of this country were bound by the legislation of 1787, not by Mr. Ludlow s mistakes and blunders respecting that legislation. The right of coercion is sometimes deduced from that clause of the Constitution which contains the President s oath of office, and which requires him to "preserve, pro tect, and defend the Constitution of the United States. This is, indeed, the great argument against secession from the words of the Constitution. But it is a gross solecism : a petitio principii as plain as possible. For, if by and under the Constitution, a State has a right to secede from the Union, then the President is sworn to preserve, not 1 Ludlow s "History of the United States." pp. 143-4. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 151 to destroy, this Constitutional right. Hence, when it is argued that the President is -bound to coerce in order to preserve, potect, and defend the Constitution, it is assumed that, in view of the Constitution, secession is wrong and coercion is right ; which is very clearly to beg the question. It takes the very point in dispute for granted. Such an argument, such a fallacy may have satisfied those who were passionately bent on coercion; but, in the eye of reason, it is wholly destitute of force. If a State had the Constitutional right to secede, and did secede, then she was out of the Union ; and the President had no more power to execute the laws of the United States within her limits than he had to enforce them in the dominions of Great Britain, or France, or Eussia. The President s oath of office requires him, not to usurp any power, but only to exercise those which are conferred on him by the C Constitution. ARGUMENT FROM THE WISDOM OF THE FATHERS An argument against the right of secession is deduced from the wisdom of the framers of the Constitution. It is supposed that men, who were so remarkable for their sagacity and wisdom, would not have undertaken to erect a grand Confederacy of States, and yet have been so absurd as to allow a State to secede from it. It is argued that they could not have intended to astonish the world with the "extraordinary spectacle of a nation existing only at the will of each of its constituent parts." 1 This argument, which is urged by Judge Story, and others, amounts simply to this, that the fathers of the Constitution could not have been such fools as to make a compact between the States. For it is conceded that this extraordinary spectacle, this wonderful exhibition of weakness, results from the doctrine that the Constitution is a compact between the States. The conclusions, says Mr. Justice Story, "which naturally flow from the doctrine that the Constitution is a compact between the States," u go to the extent of reducing the government to a mere 1 Story s "Commentary on the Constitution," book iii, chap. iii. 152 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES confederacy during pleasure; and of thus presenting the extraordinary spectacle of a nation existing only at the will of each of its constituent parts." Hence, in the opinion of Judge Story, all that is wonderful in this spectacle resolves itself into the most unaccountable fact, that the fathers should have framed "a compact between the States!" A thing which has been frequently done in the history of the world, and which, as we have seen, was actually done by the Convention of 1787. It is impossible, exclaims Judge Story; we simply reply, it is a fact. A learned doctor, in one of Moliere s plays, argues that, after taking his remedy, it was impossible that his patient should have died. But the poor servant, who was not blessed with half the doctor s learning or ingenuity, was weak enough to believe that the fact of his death was some little evidence of its possibility. The question is not what the fathers, in the opinion of one of the sons, ought to have done, but what they have actually done. The son in question, for example, is shocked and astonished at the "extraordinary spectacle of a nation existing at the will of its constituent parts." If this very learned son had only possessed a little more wisdom he would never have discovered, perhaps, this wonderful spectacle of "a nation" with "its constituent parts," or subordinate fractions. He would, on the contrary, have seen that the sovereign States which he calls "the contituent parts," or the fractions, of his imaginary nation, are really the units of a confederation. I am rather inclined to doubt, therefore, whether such a son is the fittest of all possible tribunals before which to try the wisdom of the fathers. After all, perhaps, it was no want of wisdom in the fathers, but only the conceit of wisdom in ourselves, which causes their work to present so "extraordinary a spectacle." Indeed, if we infer the nature of their work, not from an examination of what they have actually done, but from their wisdom, do we not reason from our own notions of wisdom? And are we not in danger of interpolating their conceptions with our own devices? The better method is to listen to the <rreat teacher. Time, which THE WAB BETWEEN THE STATES 153 estimates their wisdom from the nature of their work, and not the nature of their work from their wisdom. The question is, not what the fathers, as reasonable men, ought to have done, but what they have actually done. Perhaps their wisdom, even if perfect in itself, was some times held in abeyance by the prejudices, the passions, and the interests by which it was surrounded. But, for the sake of argument, let us suppose that the new Con stitution was made perpetually binding on the States, that the right of secession was excluded; and then ask ourselves, what sort of spectacle would such a work present to the minds of reasonable men? Would it not appear far more extraordinary than if the right of secession had been recognized? Let us examine and see. The scheme of a perpetual Union, excluding the right of secession, proceeded on the supposition that a perpetual peace, good faith, and good-will would subsist among the States. This was the idea of Madison. The predictions of George Mason and others, in which they foretold the wrongs and aggressions of the Northern States, if armed with the formidable powers of the new government, 1 Mr. Madison just set aside as unfounded and uncharitable suspicions. 2 Now, in regard to this point, we need not ask who was the wiser of the two, George Mason or James Madison, nor need we try the question by any imperfect notions of our own ; for Time has pronounced its irre versible verdict in favor of the wisdom of George Mason. Again, as each State bound its citizens to render alle giance to the Federal Government by its own voluntary act, namely, the act of accession to the Constitution, so, if by her own sovereign will in the same way expressed, she may absolve them from that allegiance ; we can well under stand the reasonableness of the arrangement. But if she may not secede or withdraw the allegiance of her citizens from the Federal Government, then it would be impossible for them to escape the crime of treason. For, although the State should be driven by oppression to withdraw from the Union, her citizens would, according to such a "Elliott s Debates," vol. iii. pp. 30, 146, 149, 156, 161, 164, 173, 174. 590. -Ibid., 580-562. 154 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES scheme, be indissolubly bound by a double allegiance. Hence, if they should follow or obey their own State, they might be pursued and hunted down as traitors to the Federal Government. Or, if forsaking the State to which their allegiance was originally and exclusively due, they should adhere to the Federal Government, they would be traitors to their own State, and so regarded. There would be no possible escape for them. Xow, were such a scheme wise, or reasonable, or just? Would it not, on the contrary, present a monstrous spectacle of cruelty and oppression? Can we believe that the fathers, in order to secure the liberty of their descendants, erected such an engine of tyranny? Can we believe that they intended, in any event, to crush and grind their posterity thus between the upper and the nether millstones of the two governments? But whatever they may have intended, or designed, such is the horrible character of the two govern ments in one, as explained by the very learned son in question. If his explanation be true, then it must be admitted that the fathers, with all their wisdom, first constructed one of the most horrible engines of oppression the world has ever seen, and then pronounced it a scheme to "secure the blessings of liberty to themselves and their posterity." But I have too much respect for the wisdom of the fathers to construe their work into any such tremen dous and terrific engine of oppression. On the contrary, T believe that as the allegiance of the citizen was originally and exclusively due to his State, and was extended to the Federal Constitution only by a sovereign act of his State, so, by a like sovereign act, the State may reclaim his supreme allegiance. Otherwise the machine invented by the Convention of 178? would divide the citizen from himself, putting the noblest and warmest affections of his heart on the one side, and his highest allegiance on the other ; so that, in case of a conflict between his State and the Federal Union, he must be inevitably lacerated and torn by the frightful collision. The fathers always admitted that the noblest and warmest affections of the citizen would cluster around and cling to the State in which he was born, and to which his THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 155 allegiance was, at first, exclusively due. 1 Did they mean, then, that in case of a conflict between a State and the Union, and the secession of the former, the strongest affections of the citizen should be with the one, and his supreme allegiance with the other. I have too much respect for the wisdom and the goodness of the fathers to impute so horrible an intention to them; or that they designed, in any event, to set the citizen against himself, and rend him asunder by such a conflict between the elements of his nature. 1 believe, on the contrary, that it is the intention of the fundamental law instituted by them that the allegiance of the citizen should go with his affections, and cling to the sovereign will of the State in which he lives, whether that leads him into or out of the Union. "It is not easy," said one of the most sagacious of the fathers, "to be wise for the present; much less for the future." How true ! and especially with reference to the institution of a new government ! Perhaps, if the fathers had only had a little more of this wisdom for the future, they would have more profoundly considered the great question of secession, and settled it beyond the possibility of dispute in the Constitution framed by them. If, for instance, in the solemn compact between the States, they had expressly declared that any one of the sovereign parties to it might secede at pleasure, this would, it is believed, have produced the most happy result. The known and established fact, that the Union depended on the will of its members, would certainly tend to beget that mutual forbearance, moderation, good-will, and sympathy, with out which no federation of States is desirable. The wisdom of the fathers might, in such case, have appeared far less conspicuous to some of the sons; and yet it might have saved the sons from the terrible war of words, and deeds, and blood, by which the civilization of the nineteenth century has been so horribly disgraced. It might have appeared a most "extraordinary spectacle" in theory ; and yet, in practice, it might have spared the world the infinitely more extraordinary spectacle of the war of 1861. 1 See The Federalist. Nos. xvii, xviii. xix, etc. 156 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES I shall conclude my reflections on this argument with the following judicious observations of Mr. Spence : "It would appear," says he, "the true policy of such a confed eration to remove all doubt, and carry out clearly the principles of its origin, by openly declaring the right of secession. Had this been done from the first there would probably have been no secession this day. The surest way to end the desire for any object is to give unlimited command of it. Secession has mainly occurred because it was denied. How beneficial the consequence had it been an admitted right for the last forty years ! In place of the despotic use of political power, in contempt of the feelings or interests of other portions of the country, whether of the slave owners or monopolists, there would have been all along a tempering., moderating influence. Abolitionism, in all its extremes of virulence, has been permitted by the North because the South was considered to be fast. It might writhe under it, but it must abide. But for this unfortunate belief, the intelligence of the North would have said, If to gratify your passionate opinions, you indulge in such language as this, addressed to your fellow-citizens, they will separate from us ; we will not have the Union destroyed at your bidding and pleasure. In like manner, when the manufacturers desired to increase protection to outrageous monopoly, that intelligence of the North would have said to them, Our sister States shall not be driven from the Union in order to increase your profits. The same rule will apply to external affairs. Texas would not have been annexed and beslaved, no Mexican spoliations no war of 1813 no Ostend mani festoes need have defaced the history of the country. Throughout the range of political affairs there would have been present that influence so constantly absent consider ation for others. The sovereignty of the people is a despotism untempered by division or check. The denial of secession has invited it to act despotically to do simply as it listed, regardless of those supposed to have no escape from endurance. The more the subject is examined the more plainly it will appear that, under an admitted right of secession, there would never have grown up to THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 157 dangerous magnitude those causes which now produce and that in so terrible a form the disruption of the Union. Without those causes, had the feelings and in terests of others been fairly and temperately considered, the Union might have existed as firmly this day as at any former period of its history/ 1 ARGUMENT FROM THE OPINION OF MR. MADISOX In the Biographical Memoir of Daniel Webster, prefixed to his works, Mr. Everett says : "The opinion entertained of this speech [the speech of 1833], by the individual who, of all the people in America, was the best qualified to estimate its value may be seen from the following letter of Mr. Madison, which has never before been published : MONTPELIEB, March 15, 1833. MY DEAR SIR: I return my thanks for the copy of your late very powerful speech in the Senate of the United States. It crushes nullification, and must hasten an abandonment of secession. Xow on what ground Mr. Madison could have based this opnion, at least in so far as it relates to secession, it is difficult to conceive. The fundamental premise of Mr. Webster that "the Constitution is not a compact between sovereign States/ and which is adopted as the title of his speech, was certainly not approved by Mr. Madison ; for this premise, besides being in direct opposition to the doctrine of his whole life, is denied again in the very letter in which the above compliment is found. Mr. Webster has, indeed, very little to say against secession. His argu ment is almost exclusively directed against "nullification," the point then in debate between himself and Mr. Calhoun. But the little he has to say against secession is based on the idea that the Constitution is not a compact between sovereign States. Every argument, and every assertion levelled by him against secession (and they are but few in number) have no other than this false foundation. 1 "American Union." pp. 245-<>. 158 THE WAB BETWEEN THE STATES Hence, Mr. Madison could not have approved or applauded the argument of Mr. Webster against secession, because he regarded his premise as sound; for he was most pro foundly convinced that it was false. On what ground, then, could Mr. Madison have admired this argument? If the Constitution is a compact between sovereign States, as Mr. Madison always contended it was, then Mr. Webster admits, as we have seen, that the right of secession follows. Thus this right is conceded by Mr. Webster to flow from the premise which Mr. Madison always regarded as perfectly and unquestionably true. How, in the face of such a concession, Mr. Madison could have pronounced the opinion that Mr. Webster s argument "must hasten the abandonment of secession," it is exceedingly difficult to conceive. The acknowledgment that the right of secession flows from a position too plain to be denied would tend, as one would suppose, to hasten its adoption, rather than its abandonment. How then could Mr. Madison have said otherwise? The truth seems to be that Mr. Madison was more solicitous to preserve the integrity of the Union than the coherency of his own thoughts. He commends Lycurgus for having sacrified his life to secure the perpetuity of the institution he had taken so much pains to establish. 1 For the same purpose Mr. Madison sacrificed, not his life, but his logic. Is it not truly wonderful that Mr. Madison who, on most subjects, sees so clearly and reasons so well, should fall into such inanities about secession ? From his con duct, as well as from his confession in The Federalist, 2 it is evident that he considered it a duty to veil the idea of this right, unless a proper occasion should arise for its assertion. But how imperfectly his arguments and opinions perform this high office of concealment! He would, no doubt, have done better if better arguments against the right of secession could have been found or invented. As it is, the ineffable weakness of his views, in opposition to the right of secession, shows how high and impregnable is the position which that right occupies. 1 TJu Feilfralitt, No. xxxviii. - No. xliii. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 159 Mr. Madison greatly feared that Virginia and Xew York would, in their ordinances of ratification, expressly reserve the right to secede from the Union. This apprehension is most vividly set forth in his correspondence with Mr. Hamilton in regard to the proposed conditional ratifica tion of Xew York, from which it has been most confidently inferred that neither Virginia nor Xew York did reserve such right. But what Mr. Madison desired, and what those States did, are two very distinct things. If we really wish to know what those States did we should, it seems to me, look at their recorded acts, rather than at what Mr. Madison desired them to do. The conditional ratification of Virginia was in direct opposition to the wishes of Mr. Madison. His wish, then, however great his influence, could not always control the action of his own State, much less that of Xew York. Hamilton and Madison both desired a strong "national government." It was owing to their influence that the first resolution of the Convention of 1787 in favor of such a government was passed. But, as we have seen/ although that resolution w r as afterward set aside by the Convention, Mr. Webster and Judge Story argue from its momentary existence that the Convention of 1787 actually established "a national government." In like manner, it is most confidently inferred from the wish of Mr. Madison, ex pressed in his private correspondence, that neither Vir ginia nor Xew York expressly reserved the right of secession in its ordinance of ratification! Was Mr. Madi son s wish the law of Virginia and of Xew York? And if we want to know what those States actually did, must Mr. Madison s wish pass for everything, and their solemnly recorded acts for nothing? Mr. Madison, as his correspondence shows, was extremely anxious to prevent a conditional ratification of the Con stitution in Xew York, as well as in Virginia. He even went so far as to advance the extraordinary proposition that a conditional ratification would be "no ratification at all, and would "not make Xew York a member of the new Union." But after Virginia had ratified the Consti- 1 Chap. iv. 160 THE WAE BETWEEN THE STATES tution on the express condition that its powers should not be perverted to her injury or oppression, and had reserved the right to resume the delegated powers in case that condition should be violated, Mr. Madison retraced his steps, and freely admitted that Virginia was really in the Union ! He writes to Hamilton at once, and to Wash ington, in order to do away with the impression that a con ditional ratification is "no ratification at all," and would not make any State a "member of the new Union." In regard to the conditional ratification of Virginia, he says it contains "some plain and general truth that do not impair the validity of the act." Now, from these words of Mr. Madison it has been strenuously argued that Virginia did not reserve the right to resume the powers she had delegated to the Federal Government! It is true, as Mr. Madison said, that the plain truths referred to did not impair the validity of the Virginia act of ratification. No one has ever doubted the validity of that act, or that it made Virginia a member of the new Union. Nor could any one ever dream of doubt ing such a thing, unless he had previously embraced Mr: Madison s most extraordinary proposition that a condi tional ratification is no ratification at all. But, while there is no question whatever as to the validity of the act, it is denied that it was unconditionally and eternally binding on the State of Virginia, or that it could never be repealed by the sovereign power by which it was enacted. Is it not wonderful, then, that Mr. Madison s words merely assert ing the validity of the act in question, which no one has ever denied, should be so confidently quoted to prove that the act must, in any event, stand forever, unrepealed and unrepealable, by the power by which it was ordained? Now what is "the plain and general truth" to which Mr. Madison refers as contained in the Virginia ordinance of ratification? It is the truth that the powers delegated to the Federal Government may be resumed in case of their perversion, and that they may be resumed by the authority which delegated them. This was a plain truth then, and this is a plain truth now. It is, indeed, uni versally conceded. Neither Story, nor Webster, nor Everett, THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 161 nor Motley has one syllable to say against this plain and incontestable truth. Hence, if Virginia delegated powers to the Federal Government, then Virginia, and Virginia alone, had the right to resume those powers. This would have been the case, even if no express reservation of that right had been contained in her ordinance of ratification. But did Mr. Madison deny that the powers in question were delegated by the State of Virginia? If so, then he denied a plain fact, and a fact, too, which he invariably and earnestly proclaimed from the beginning to the end of his career. Even if he denied that fact by implication, this would have proved only his inconsistency, and fur nished another instance of the blinding influence of his extreme desire to veil the right of secession. ARGUMENT FROM THE OPINION OF HAMILTON "However gross a heresy," says Hamilton, "it may be to maintain that a party to a compact has a right to revoke that compact, the doctrine itself has had respectable advo cates." 1 This, it should be observed, is said in relation to the old Articles of Confederation, which are universally admitted to have formed a compact between sovereign States. It was, then, the opinion of Hamilton that a State had no right to secede from a confederacy of States, or from the compact by which they are united. If he means to assert that it has no natural or moral right to secede at pleasure from a compact, I have at present no controversy with him. But if he means that it has no legal, or Constitutional right to do so, then his own opinion is "a gross heresy," which has but few respectable advocates at the present day. For, as we have already seen, both Story and Webster concede that the Constitutional right of secession belongs to States which are united by a compact. Now, after such a concession, is it not too late to quote the opinion of Hamilton to prove that the very inference conceded is "a gross heresy"? Yet this is done by Mr. Justice Story. In one paragraph he admits that if the Constitution is a 1 The Federalist, No. xxii. 162 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES compact between the States, then each State may secede from that compact at pleasure; and yet, in the very next paragraph, he proves out of The Federalist? that "even under the confederation/ which is admitted to have been founded on a compact between the States, 2 "it was deemed a gross heresy to maintain that a party to a compact has a right to revoke that compact"; 3 or to set it aside at pleasure. Thus the very inference which he admits in one breath he pronounces a gross heresy in the next, and proves it to be such by the authority of Hamilton ! The doctrine which both Story and Webster have been constrained to admit is no doubt entitled to more consid eration than the naked and unsupported opinion of Ham ilton. This opinion seems, indeed, to have grown out of his deep and intense desire to consolidate the Union, rather than form his legal studies and knowledge. He was only thirty years of age when The Federalist was written ; and his life, with the exception of four years, had been passed in the active duties of the camp, or in his college studies. Hence, however great his powers, his knowledge of juris prudence, and of the opinions of the learned, must have been exceedingly limited, when compared with those who have devoted their lives to this study. If, then, Story and Webster are constrained to admit the right of a State to secede from a confederacy bound by a mutual compact, this may surely be taken as an indication of the real, teachings of the law on the point in question, and regarded as a higher authority than the bare opinion of Hamilton. This would be so, even if no progress had been made in the science of international law since the time of Hamilton ; but, in fact, there has been great progress in this science during the present century, especially in regard to the doctrine of compacts between States. Enlightened by the principles of that doctrine, Mr. Justice Story could not deny the right of one of the parties to secede from such "a compact." Hence, he attempted the more than herculean labor of recasting the whole political history of his country, and moulding it in con formity with his wonderful hypothesis that the Constitu- 1 Vol. i, p. 288. 2 No. xxii. 3 Vol. i, p. 290. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 163 tion of the United States is not a compact between States at all. He first asserts truly that a State may secede from such a compact, and then proves out of Hamilton that his own assertion is "a gross heresy I" "That gross heresy/ says Hamilton, "has had respectable advocates." Mr. Justice Story himself is one of these advocates. Nor is this all. The Convention of 1787 advocated the same heresy; and, moreover, embodied it in their legislation. Hamilton insisted in that Convention that the States had no right to revoke the existing compact between them, or to secede from it in order to form another, without the consent of each and every State in the Union. But his opinion was overruled by the Convention; and the States did, in pursuance of the decision of the Convention, withdraw from the existing compact to form a new one. Mr. Hamilton may have been right, and the States may have been wrong ; but, however this may be, their decision established the supreme law of the land. The advocates of the right of some of the parties to a compact between States to revoke that compact, or to withdraw from it, may not have been as respectable as the opponents of this doctrine ; it is certain that they prevailed in the Convention of 1787, and embodies their own views in the legislation of the United States. That legislation should be our guide, not the defeated opinion of Mr. Hamilton. Or, at least if we happen to believe that legislation to have been right, and if, in conformity with the opinion of Mr. Justice Story, we happen also to believe that a State may secede from a compact between States, may we not humbly hope that this will not be deemed so "gross a heresy" as to be treated as treason and rebellion? ARGUMENT FROM THE VERY IDEA OF A The "very idea of a nation," it is said, is utterly incon sistent with the right of secession. But what is a nation ? "It is a body politic," we are told, "independent of all others, and indissolubly one. That is, indissoluble at the mere option of its constituent parts/ 1 Thus the whole 1 "Rev. Dr. Hodge on the State of the Country," p. 24. 164 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES question is begged, and the whole controversy completely settled by the definition of "the very idea of a nation." How great the triumphs of such logic, and how wonder ful the displays of such genius ! Setting out from "the very idea of a nation" in the abstract, and, absolutely unembarrassed by any other idea or knowledge in the wide world, this argument just reaches, at one simple bound, the conclusion that "as the Abbeville district can not secede from South Carolina, so South Carolina can not secede from the United States" ; a profound view and striking illustration which the President from Illinois borrowed from the Preacher of Princeton. 1 ARGUMENT FROM THE PURCHASE OF LOUISIANA, FLORIDA, ETC. It is, we are told, absurd to suppose that the people would have expended so much money for the purchase of Louisiana, Texas, and Florida, if those States could secede from the Union. 2 It is not at all probable that those territories were purchased under the belief that they would desire to secede, whether they possessed the right to do so or not. And besides, it might be easily shown, that long being before those States did secede, the government of 1 Enlightened by the profound view of his reverend guide, Mr. Lincoln with a naive originality all his own, might well have asked, what is the difference between a county and a State? Is not a county a little State, and a State a big county? One striking difference must have occurred to him in the course of his reading ; the difference, namely, that a State is spelt with a large S, and a county with a small c. He must also have observed that a State is sometimes called "Sovereign." But whether it is called Sovereign because it is spelt with a large S, or spelt with a large S because it is called Sovereign, is one of the nice questions in the science of government which he does not seem to have very fully considered or positively decided. He had evidently discovered, for he tells us so himself, that a State is usually larger than a county in the extent of its territorv ; a discovery which, perhaps, led to the profound and original reflection that the United States have been, and must continue to be, one State or Nation, because their territory is one. It is to be hoped, indeed, that these sovereign States or counties, as the case may be, shall continue to be united, and that order, tranquillity, and happiness shall once more bless their Union. But if so, must not something beside the one territory help to produce the happy result? Have not simple con federations existed on the same territories? Nay, have not some twenty distinct nationalities long existed on the territory of Europe? We may, then, hardly trust the reflection, however profound, that one territory is in itself a sufficiently active and powerful cause to produce one very big State, or county, covering a whole continent. 2 "Hodge on the State of the Country," p. 28. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 165 the United States had realized far more from them than she gave for them, which was only a few millions of dollars. Hence, even on the theory and the practice of secession, the purchase was far from being absurd. On the contrary, it was a highly profitable bargain ; and, in order to justify it, or to show that it was reasonable, it is not at all necessary to suppose that the sovereign peoples of those States, with their Constitutional rights and privileges, were also purchased with the pitiful sum paid for their annexation to the United States. They were admitted as sovereign States, with all the rights of the original parties to the compact, and as such were entitled to the full benefit of all its provisions. Indeed, this ad captandum argument appears exceed ingly weak, if not absolutely ridiculous. Can any pur chases made by any parties to a compact alter the terms of that compact, or make it more binding than it was before ? If a State retained its sovereignty in the Union, and, conse quently, had a right to resume the powers which it had delegated to the Federal Government, this right was not affected by the purchase of Louisiana, or Florida. To pur chase those territories is one thing, and to sell the sover eignty of each and every State in the original Union is quite another. If any State should withdraw from the original compact, and thereby dissolve the Union as to itself, then the purchase of such territories should be con sidered in the final settlement between the parties. But to argue that they were indissolubly and eternally bound to gether because they made such purchases seems, to say the least, a little ridiculous. ARGUMENT FROM ANALOGY How wonderful soever it may seem, Mr. Justice Story argues from analogy as follows: As an indivdual has no right to secede from a State government, so a State has no right to secede from the government of the Union. Now this argument proceeds on the supposition that a sovereign State bears the same relation to the Federal Government, which it concurred with other States in creating, that a 166 THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES county,, nay, that an individual, bears to a State. Mr. Justice Story was far too learned to endorse so monstrous a heresy explicitly; but it is, nevertheless, tacitly assumed as the basis of his argument from analogy against the right of secession. His whole theory of the Constitution points, it is true, to the conclusion so openly avowed by the Eev. Dr. Hodge and Mr. Lincoln, which views a State as merely a county of one great consolidated nation; but he never reached this conclusion himself, except surrep titiously, as in the above argument from analogy. But even admitting this false conclusion as a postulate, the argument of Judge Story is by no means as conclusive as it appears to his own mind. For the right of an indi vidual to secede from a State government is daily exer cised by some one or other in every part of the world. An individual can not, it is true, remain under the govern ment of a State, continuing to enjoy its protection, and, at the same time, refuse to obey its mandates. But this were nullification., not secession. The only way in which an individual can secede from a State is to withdraw from the limits of its dominion, and this right is daily exercised in every part of the civilized world, without being called in question by any one. The Puritans themselves, by whom Massachusetts was originally settled, withdrew from the government of Great Britain, and quietly marched off, undisturbed by his Majesty, first into Holland, and then into the New World. Now sup pose this right had been denied to them? Suppose fire and sword had been used to compel the Pilgrim Fathers, those meek and holy apostles of freedom, to remain under the government they detested, would they not have made the world ring with their outcries at the perpetration of such injustice and tyranny? But they were allowed to withdraw to the New World, and there set up the govern ment of their choice. The colony of Massachusetts Bay, then, owed its existence to the acknowledged right of indi viduals to secede from the government of a State, and enjoy one whose "powers are derived from the consent of the governed." THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES 167 But a State, united in a confederacy with other States, can secede from the government of the Union without the necessity of changing its location. This makes a difference in the exercise of the right, though not in the right itself. It is, indeed, quite impossible for a whole State, or people, to change its location, or abandon their homes. If the Southern States could have done so, the exodus would, no doubt, have been most gratifying to some of the descendants of the Pilgrim Fathers of New England. This is evident from the eloquent address of Mr. Henry Ward Beecher to the excited thousands of Exeter Hall in 1863. In reply to the question, "Why not let the South go ?" he exclaimed, "0 that the South would go ! but then they must leave us their lands." If they had only left their lands and homes, and plunged into the Gulf of Mexico, this great enemy of secession would have hailed the event as one most auspicious for the spread, the aggrandizement, and the glory of the race to which he belongs. It would have appeared to him, no doubt, like the herd of swine which, being possessed of devils, madly rushed into the sea, and disappeared from the world. But when they seceded, without proposing to leave their lands behind, this made all the difference imaginable; being an out rageous violation of one of the great fundamental articles of the Puritan creed, which, in early times, was expressly set forth by the Colony of Connecticut in solemn conclave assembled. It was then and there decided that "the earth is the inheritance of the saints of the Lord"; the saints having, in their declaration, as is believed, an eye to the beautiful locations and lands of the Indians. It is certain, if we may judge from the speech of Mr. Beecher in Exeter Hall, that some of the most influential of the saints had a longing and passionate eye for the beautiful lands of the sunny South. The truth is that every Constitutional compact, whether between the people of a single State, or between sovereign States themselves, forms a voluntary association; the one between individuals, and the other between sovereign States. Hence, if the right of secession be denied in either case, and the denial enforced by the sword of 168 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES coercion, the nature of the polity is changed, and freedom is at an end. It is no longer a government by consent, but a government of force. Conquest is substituted for com pact, and the dream of liberty is over. No man has contributed more to this dire result than Mr. Justice Story, who not only exhausted all the stores of his own erudition, and exerted all the powers of his own mind, to prove that the Constitution was not a compact between the States, but also enlisted the great powers and eloquence of Mr. Webster in the advocacy of the same monstrous heresy. This concealed the great fundamental principle of the Constitution, and kept out of view the all-important truth, laid down by Mr. Mill, that the very first condition necessary to a desirable federation of States "is a sufficient amount of sympathy among its popula tions." Nor is this all. His theory of the Constitution fell in with the corrupt and the corrupting tendency of the age; the tendency, namely, to deny the sacred obli gation of "THE COMPACT OF THE CONSTITUTION." For how can any compact be held sacred which is held not to be a compact at all, but only the emanation, or creature, of the sovereign will by which its restraints are abhorred? May not the creator do what he pleases with his own ? May not the one great nation, the one sovereign people of American take some little liberties with the work of its hands, instead of being scrupulously bound by it as a com pact between the States? Fay, may it not take some little liberties with the rights of the States themselves ; since the States, as well as the Constitution, were created by its own sovereign will and pleasure? May it not, in short, treat the States as counties? It is possible, indeed, that no learning, or logic, or elo quence could have resisted this terrible tendency, or stemmed the mighty torrent of corruption it continually fed and augmented. But this is no reason why learning, and logic, and eloquence should have favored its progress. That progress was slow, but sure. All power slowly gravitated toward the federal center, and was there con solidated by false theories of the Constitution. In the towering audacity of that central power (assuming to itself THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 169 all the glories of the one grand nation, it was gradually forgotten that honor, and justice, in the observance of the original compact, no longer regarded as a compact) and mutual sympathy among the peoples it was intended to unite, are the indispensable conditions of a free and happy Federation of States; and for these sacred ties of "the glorious Union" were substituted the sacrilegious bonds of fraud, force, and ferocity. It is no wonder, then, that secession should, in the end, have been regarded as the greatest of all crimes, since the Union was then held together, not by the mutual sympathy or the conciliated interests of its peoples, but by "the co hesive power of public plunder." Mr. Justice Story, be it said to his eternal shame, took the lead in constructing the theory of that tremendous scheme of despotic power, and the politicians of Massachusetts in reducing it to practice. John C. Calhoun, on the contrary, lived and died in op posing all the powers of his gigantic intellect to its over whelming torrents, both in theory and practice. CHAPTER XV WAS SECESSION TREASON? INTRODUCTORY THE doctrine of secession consists of two propositions: the first asserts that the Constitution was a compact between the States; and the second that a State, or one of the parties, had a right to secede from such a compact. The second proposition is simply an inference from the first. Now, if secession is at all tainted with treason, the crime must lurk in the one or the other of these propositions. WITHDRAWAL FROM A COMPACT NOT TREASON Is it treasonable, then, to assert that the Constitution was a compact between the States, or the members of the Union? No one, it is presumed, will venture on so bold an assertion; for, as we have seen, this was the doctrine of the fathers of the Constitution themselves. It has been shown, by an articulate reference to their writing, that it was clearly and unequivocally the doctrine of Madison, and Morris, and Hamilton, as well as of other celebrated architects of the Constitution. Who, then, will pronounce it treason, or treasonable? The Federalist, in submitting the Constitution to the people and in pleading the cause of its adoption, did not hesitate to say, as a fact then per fectly well and universally known, that the Constitution was "the compact" 1 to which "the States as distinct and independent sovereigns" 2 were the parties. Did The Federalist espouse treasonable sentiments ? Both Hamilton and Madison, the two great architects of the Constitution., most earnestly and eloquently recommended it to the people in The Federalist and elsewhere as THE COMPACT BETWEEN THIRTEEN SOVEREIGN AND INDEPENDENT STATES. 1 No. xxix. - No. xl and No. Ixxxv. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 171 Is that doctrine treason., then? Is there the least sign, or symptom, or shadow of treason connected with that senti ment of the fathers ? Are those "untrue to their country" who say, with all the most illustrious fathers of the Union, that the Constitution was a compact between the States? On the contrary, are not those untrue to themselves, to their country, and to their God, who, in the midst of so many unquestionable proofs on all sides around them, can assert that the Constitution is not a compact? Is it "the dialect of treason" to say that "the States acceded to the Constitution?" In other words, is the language of Wilson, and Morris, and Bandolph, and Franklin, and Jefferson, and Washington to be renounced as "the dialect of treason?" Is it treason to understand the Constitution as it was understood by the great patriots and statesmen from whose wisdom it proceeded? Is it treason to adhere to their views, sentiments, and language? Or is it loyalty to depart from their views, sentiments, and language, de nouncing them as the inventions of modern rebels? No one can, or will, venture to answer this question in the affirmative. Ignorance and passion may have done so in times past. But who can read the history of his country, who can behold the great fact that THE CONSTITUTION is A COMPACT BETWEEN THE STATES BLAZING ALL OVER ITS AMPLE PAGES, nay, written there by the fathers of the Eepublic themselves, and then deliberately pronounce it a treasonable sentiment? Can any man do so? Has any man sufficient strength of continence for such an achieve ment? If so, then indeed .must his front of brass, and his heart of iron, forever remain an incomprehensible mystery to all reasonable men. Nay, if any party or majority, aided by the united strength of all their countenances, should pronounce such a fact treasonable, this would only prove that they must have been ignorant of the history of their country. But, whether f^om ignorance, or from malice, or from both, shall it ever be the lot of American citizens to live in a land in which truth shall be treason, and history rebellion? Shall it ever come to this ye blessed spirits of departed heroes 172 THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES and patriots! shall it ever come to this, that a dungeon and a halter awaits the man who may have the most devoutly cherished thy sentiments, and the most implicitly trod in thy footsteps? No ! it will be admitted that the doctrine of the fathers is not treason. Whether that doctrine be true or false, it will be admitted that it is entitled to the respect of all who respect the founders of the Eepublic. Even if the fathers did not understand their own work a thought which is itself almost akin to treason it is certainly not an unpardonable heresy to agree with them, or to adopt their view of the Constitution of the United States. Will it be said, then, that it is treasonable to assert that a State may secede from a compact between States? If so, then Story and Webster were both traitors; for, as we have over and over again seen, these most admired ex pounders of the Constitution expressly concede that a State may secede at pleasure from such a compact. But, here again, even if Story and Webster were mistaken in this principle of law, it is surely absurd to denounce such an error as treason or rebellion. Nor is this all. Precisely the same inference is drawn by another great expounder of the Constitution, namely, by William Eawle, of Philadelphia. The legal opinion of Mr. Eawle is entitled to great respect. Mr. Buchanan, late President of the United States, speaks of him as follows : "The right of secession found advocates afterwards in men of distinguished abilities and unquestioned patriotism. In 1825 it was maintained by Mr. William Eawle, of Philadelphia, an eminent and universally respected lawyer, in the 23d [32d] chapter of his View of the Constitution of the United States. In speaking of him his biographer says that in 1791 he was appointed District Attorney of the United States 7 ; and the situation of Attorney General was more than once tendered to him by Washington, but as often declined/ for domestic reasons." 1 Now, Mr. Eawle wrote his "View/ 7 not as a partisan, but simply as a jurist in the calm and impartial investigation of truth, having no conceivable motive to reject the plain teachings of his- 1 "Buchanan s Administration," p. 88. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 173 tory and law. Indeed, as we have seen, he agreed with Story and Webster in regard to the principle of law, and differed from them only in regard to facts. Hence, if they had not denied that the Constitution was made by the States, they would have been compelled, like Mr. Eawle, to admit the right of secession. "The Union is an association of republics," says Mr. Kawle. . . . Again, "we have associated as republics. . . . But the mere compact, without the means to enforce it, would be of little value." 1 Having announced the truth, that the Constitution is a compact between republics, he drew the inference from this which is ad mitted to follow by Story and Webster. That is, he in ferred the right of secession; just as if there could be no question on so plain a point of law. "It depends on the State itself," said he, "to retain or abolish the principle of representation, BECAUSE IT DEPENDS ON THE STATE ITSELF WHETHER IT CONTINUES A MEMBER OF THE UNION." Again, he says, "THE STATES MAY WITHDRAW FROM THE UNION, but, while they continue, they must retain the character of republics," as well as comply with every stipu lation of the Constitutional compact. "... The secession of a State from the Union," he continues, "depends on the will of the people. The Constitution of the United States is to a certain extent incorporated with the Constitutions of the several States by the act of the people. . . . Nothing is more certain than that the act [secession] should be deliberate, clear, and unequivocal. The perspicuity and solemnity of the original obligation require correspondent qualities in its dissolution." Now this is the language of a man, of an eminent jurist, who was the contemporary and friend of Wash ington. He lived before the rise of those new ideas, and dazzling images of power, which afterward obscured "the perspicuity and solemnity" of the act by which each State had acceded to the compact of the Constitution. Was not this man of "distinguished abilities and unquestioned patriotism," then, right both in regard to his premise and to his conclusion ? He took, as we have seen, precisely the 1 "Rawle on the Constitution," chap, xxxii. 174 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES - same view of the Constitution as that taken by all his great contemporaries, the fathers of the Constitution themselves; and he only inferred from this view the right of secession, which, according to Story and Webster, is a legitimate inference? But even if he was not right, if Rawle, and Story, and Webster were all in error as to the justness of this inference, still were it not the very height of absurdity to pronounce such an opinion treason? If, then, any poor benighted son of the South was really guilty of treason on account of secession, this must have been either because he understood the Constitution no better than those who made it, or because he knew the law of compacts no better than the most celebrated jurists of America? On which horn of this dilemma shall he be hanged? Shall he be tried and found guilty of treason for not understanding the Constitution better than Morris, and Madison, and Hamilton, and Washington; or for not knowing the law of compacts better than Eawle, and Story, and Webster? If found guilty on either ground it is to be hoped that his counsel will move an arrest of judg ment, that such distressing ignorance was his misfortune, not his fault. MASSACHUSETTS AND THE HARTFORD CONVENTION The facts, proofs, and authorities going to establish the right of secession are, indeed, so redundant, so overflow ing, nay, so absolutely overwhelming that many of them have been necessarily omitted in the foregoing argument. One of them is, however, quite too important and striking to be entirely neglected. Hence it shall be introduced in the present place. The Virginia Resolutions ,of 7 98 were submitted, as the reader is doubtless aware, to the Legislatures of every State in the Union. These Resolutions contained, as we have repeatedly seen, the very doctrine so eloquently denounced by Mr. Webster in 1833 ; the doctrine, namely, that the Constitution is a compact between the States of the Union. This doctrine was, in fact, made the ground work of that celebrated manifesto. Now it is a remark- THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 175 able fact that not one of the Legislatures, who replied to the Resolutions of 98, called this great fundamental position in question. No one at that early day, so near the origin of the Constitution, seems to have dreamed that such a doctrine was tainted with heresy, much less with treason. Not a single Legislature seems to have imagined, for one moment, that the United States, or the States United, did not form a Confederacy, or that its Constitution was not a compact. In the answer of the Legislature of Massachusetts, Mr. Story s and Mr. Webster s own State, by far the most able and elaborate of all the replies to the Resolutions in question, there is not one syllable or sign of opposition to the doctrine that the States formed a Confederacy, or that their Constitution was a compact between them. On the contrary, Massachusetts, then and there, in her great manifesto in opposition to that of Virginia, expressly recognized the truth of that doctrine. That is, in con formity with the uniform and universal usage of the day, she spoke of the desire of Massachusetts to "COOPERATE WITH ITE CONFEDERATE STATES"; 1 and also of "THAT SOLEMN COMPACT WHICH IS DECLARED TO BE THE SUPREME LAW OF THE LAND." 2 Massachusetts was not, then, one of that mighty cloud of witnesses, composed alike of "friends and foes," which Mr. Webster, with his great dark eye "in a fine frenzy rolling," fancied that he saw in the air, all uniting in the solemn declaration, as with the voice of doom, that COMPACT is no more, that CONFEDERACY has fallen, and that henceforth THE SOVEREIGN WILL OF THE ONE GRAND NATION, THE PEOPLE OF AMERICA, SHALL REIGN FOREVER AND EVER ! On the contrary, poor, simple- hearted Massachusetts, of 1799, imagined that a compact, that even a "solemn compact," not only might be, but actually was, "the supreme law of the land," and that it was under or by virtue of that solemn compact that she had, only eleven years before, "confederated" with her sister States ! Nor is this all. Massachusetts continued, for some years longer, true to the first great article in the creed of the 1 "Elliott s Debates," vol. iv, p. 563. 2 Ibid., p. 560. 176 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES fathers. Indeed circumstances greatly favored her fidelity, and deepened the fervor of her faith. The acquisition of Louisiana, which added a vast empire to the Southern end of the Union,, produced a profound dissatisfaction throughout Massachusetts and the other New England States; causing "the glorious Union" to wane, and the sovereignty of the States to wax mightily in their eyes. "At an early period after the formation of the Consti tution," as Mr. Buchanan truly says, "many influential individuals of New England became dissatisfied with the union between the Northern and Southern States, and wished to dissolve it." "This design," according to Mr. John Quincy Adams, "had been formed in the winter of 1803-4, immediately after and in consequence of the acquisition of Louisiana." 1 The embargo and non- intercourse laws, which were designed to bring England to terms without the dire necessity of war, augmented the already great dissatisfaction of New England, because they affected her commercial interests, and thereby touched her in by far the most sensitive portion of her frame. She cried aloud for war ! She cried, down with all your embargo and non-intercourse laws, and up with the flag of armed resistance! Impatient at the slow movements of the South, she taunted her with cowardice, and courteously as well as elegantly declared that the South could not be "kicked into a war with England." But she was mistaken; she did not fully comprehend the South; the South is, perhaps, too easily "kicked into a war." It is certain that the South in the persons of her two young, ardent, enthusiastic, and chivalrous representatives, Henry Clay, of Kentucky, and John C. Calhoun, of South Carolina, responded to the loud, vehement war-cry of New England. Their eloquence shook the nation. The spirit of armed resistance was roused, and the war with Great Britain proclaimed. But, alas ! this did not help the commerce of New England. The remedy proved worse than the evil. Her ravenous pockets, instead of being filled with gold and satisfied, became still more and more alive to the dreadful state of things, and, thereupon, she 1 "Buchanan s Administration," p. 86. THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES 177 endeavored to "kick the South" out of the war with Great Britain. In this the dark hour of her agony and distress she suddenly discovered that war is, at best, a most unholy and unchristian thing; not to be entered on lightly, or without counting the cost. She also discovered that, after all, the number of her seamen, impressed by the tyranny of Great Britain, had been greatly exaggerated (by whom?) ; and that consequently the cause of quarrel was far too small to justify so unholy and so unchristian, that is to say, 50 unprofitable a war. In the dark hour of her distress the glorious rights of the States came out, and showered down their radiance on all JSTew England, like the stars at night. The sovereignty of her own beloved Massachusetts, indeed, then totally eclipsed the full moon of the once "glorious Union/ just as completely as if Massachusetts had been "the whole earth." I speak from the record; from that secret, silent record of the Hartford Convention, in which all the pro found dissatisfaction of New England with the Union cul minated; and into which her sons, in spite of all their prying curiosity, have no desire whatever to look. Mr. Webster, for example, in his great debate with Mr. Hayne, of South Carolina, in 1830, solemnly declared that he had never read the proceedings of that famous Convention. No wonder ! "Where ignorance is bliss, tis folly to be wise." "Events may prove," says the Journal of the Hartford Convention, January 4, 1815, "that the causes of our calamities are deep and permanent. They may be found to proceed, not merely from blindness of prejudice, pride of opinion, violence of party spirit, or the confusion of the times; but they may be traced to implacable combinations of individuals, OR OF STATES, to monopolize power and office, and to trample without remorse upon the rights and interests of the commercial sections of the Union/ n Now, if we only substitute the term agricultural for commercial in the above passage, how admirably will it express the 1 Page 5. 178 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES complaint of the South, which, for long years of endurance, was treated with such imperial scorn and implacable contempt by the States of New England ! "Whenever it shall appear," continues the Journal, "that these causes are radical and permanent, a separation by equitable arrangement will be preferable to AN ALLIANCE, BY CONSTRAINT, AMONG NOMINAL FRIENDS, BUT REAL ENEMIES, INFLAMED BY MUTUAL HATRED AND JEALOUSIES, AND INVITING, BY INTESTINE DIVISIONS, CONTEMPT AND AGGRESSIONS FROM ABROAD." 1 Precisely thus, and not otherwise, reasoned the South in 1861; and asked for "a separation by equitable arrangement," instead of "an alliance by contrast" with "nominal friends, but real enemies, inflamed by mutual hatred and jealousies." But the great boon was contemptuously refused, because the sentiments of New England had undergone a radical and total revolution. The reason is that those were the senti ments of New England in the minority, and these the sentiments of New England in the majority. Holy, indeed, was her horror of "an alliance by constraint," when she was the party in danger of being constrained ; but no sooner had she acquired the power to constrain than such an alliance appeared altogether pure and just in her un selfish eyes ! The Journal of this Convention has much to say about "the Constitutional compact"; and hence, if it had only been read by Mr. Webster, he must have been familiar with this mode of expression, which so seriously offended him in the resolutions of Mr. Calhoun in 1833, and called forth his fine burst of eloquence in defence of the rights of that "noun substantive," the CONSTITUTION. He must have discovered also that, in the opinion of Massachusetts in 1815, the rights of sovereign States are at least as important as those of any noun substantive in the language. For, in the words of that Convention, the power of con scription is "not delegated to Congress by the Constitution, and the exercise of it would not be less dangerous to their liberties, THAN HOSTILE TO THE SOVEREIGNTY OF THE STATES. 2 ... It must be the duty of the State to 1 Page 5. 2 Page 8. THE WAE BETWEEN THE STATES 179 watch over the rights reserved, as of the United States to exercise the powers which were delegated/ * The Hartford Convention, towering in the strength of its State-rights sentiments, continues thus: "That acts of Congress in violation of the Constitution are absolutely void is an undeniable position. It does not, however, consist with the respect from a CONFEDERATE STATE towards the general government to fly to open resistance upon every infraction of the Constitution. The mode and the energy of the opposition should always conform to the nature of the violation, the intention of the authors, the extent of the evil inflicted, the determination mani fested to persist in it, and the danger of delay. But in cases of deliberate, dangerous, and palpable infractions of the Constitution, AFFECTING THE SOVEREIGNTY OF THE STATE, and liberties of the people, it is not only the right, but the duty, of such State to interpose its authority for their protection in the manner best calculated to secure that end. When emergencies occur which are either beyond the reach of judicial tribunals, or too pressing to admit of delay incident to their forms, STATES, WHICH HAVE NO COMMON UMPIRE, MUST BE THEIR OWN JUDGES, AND EXECUTE THEIR OWN DECISIONS/ 2 Now, if possible, this comes more directly and plainly to the point than the Resolutions of ; 98. It not only sets forth the great doctrine, it sometimes employs the very language of those Resolutions. Having finished its work, and appointed commissioners to lay the complaints of New England before the Govern ment of the United States, the Convention resolved, that "if these should fail/ 7 it would be the duty of the New England States to hold another Convention at Boston, on the 3d Thursday of June, with such powers and instruc tions as so momentous a crisis may require. 3 No such Convention ever assembled at Boston, or elsewhere; for, in the meantime, the great trouble had come to an end. How, or by what means? Mr. Webster, though he con fesses ignorance as to the proceedings of the Hartford Convention, is nevertheless perfectly ready with an answer 1 Page 7. 2 Pages 10-11. 3 Page 21. 180 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES to this question. In his senatorial debate with Mr. Hayne, in 1830, he tells the world that Massachusetts gave up all opposition as soon as the Supreme Court of the United States decided the laws of which she complained to be Constitutional; thus showing her loyalty under the most severe and trying circumstances ! This was, perhaps, a thrust at South Carolina, who, as Mr. Webster supposed, stood far apart from Massachusetts in the heresy that, in great and trying emergencies, "the States, who have no common umpire, are to be their own judges, and to execute their own decisions." How little he knew the history of his own State ! Hence, he could fondly imagine that Massachusetts had always been willing and ready to bow to the Supreme Court as the common umpire between the States, and proudly pointed to her conduct in 1815, bending and groaning under the burden of the laws, and yet loyally submitting to the high tribunal by whom it was fastened upon her shoulders ! The truth is, as we have just seen, that Massa chusetts had resolved to take that very emergency into her own hands; to be her own judge, and to execute her own decision. She cared, indeed, as little for the Supreme Court, in such an emergency, as she did for the other Courts of the Union ; whose decisions had been repeatedly treated with contempt, and resisted with impunity, by her very loyal citizens during the great trouble of the war. Why, then, did Massachusetts submit at last? Why did so great a change come over the spirit of her dream? The answer is a very simple one. It is told in the printed proceedings of the Hartford Convention. The story is certainly not so well adapted to the purposes of poetry, or of oratory, as the fine fiction invented by Mr. Webster, but it has, at least, the homely merit of truth. Harrison Gray Otis, T. H. Perkins, and W. Sullivan, the commis sioners appointed by the Convention to lay the grievances of New England before the Government of the United States, reported that they had declined to do so, "because they found, on their arrival at Washington, that peace had been concluded/ * That was the secret of the submission 1 "Proceedings of Hartford Convention," p. 33. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 181 of Massachusetts. The war with Great Britain was at an end; the embargo and nonintercourse would, of course, no longer vex her righteous soul; she could unfurl the wings of her commerce to every breeze, and bring in harvests of gold from every quarter of the globe. That was the secret of her great-hearted loyalty and submission. She no longer had anything to submit to ! Sidney Smith complains of "exegesis/ that it spoils so many fine sermons; not allowing the preacher to ramble in his rhetoric, or to nourish at random, without regard to the real sense of his text. The same complaint may be urged against the simple truth of history. How many splendid orations, and grand soaring flights of rhetoric, will it not spoil for the people of New England ! How many self -flattering and glorious illusions will it not dispel ! "That their object was/ said Mr. John Quincy Adams, "and had been for several years, a dissolution of the Union, and the establishment of a separate Confederation, he knew from unequivocal evidence, although not provable in a court of law ; and that, in case of a civil war, the aid of Great Britain to effect that purpose would be assuredly resorted to, as it would be indispensably necessary to their design/ 1 This design, says Mr. Adams, he had communicated to Mr. Jefferson, in 1809. Again, while President of the United States, Mr. Adams said: "That project, I repeat, had gone to the length of fixing upon a military leader for its execution; and, although the circumstances of the times never admitted of its execution, nor even of its full development, I had no doubt in 1808 and 1809, and have no doubt at this time that it is the key of all the great movements of the Federal Party in New England [and that party was then in the ascendancy in New England], from that time forward till its final catastrophe in the Hartford Convention." 2 "It is but fair to observe/ says Mr. Buchanan, "that these statements were denied by the parties implicated, 1 Letter of Dec. 30, 1828, in reply to Harrison Gray Otis and others. 2 "Buchanan s Administration," p. 87. 182 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES but were still adhered to and again reaffirmed by Mr. Adams." 1 True, it is but fair that their denial should be known, and estimated at its true value. But who could expect any men to acknowledge their complicity in such a design? If, in the dark hour of their country s trial, engaged in a war with the greatest nation upon earth, they could conceive the idea of deserting her standard, and even of invoking the aid and the arms of her powerful enemy to make their desertion good, is it to be supposed that, after the scheme had failed or blown over, they would have pleaded guilty to such a design? Nor is this all. What did they mean by appointing another Convention to be held at Boston ? Did they mean nothing? Or if they had any honorable design any design which need not shrink from the light of day why lias it never been avowed by them? The truth is, if any one shall carefully examine the proceedings of the Hartford Convention, and the previous history of New England which culminated in that Convention, he can hardly fail to perceive that the positive testimony of John Quincy Adams is most powerfully corroborated by circumstances. The conclusion of Mr. Buchanan appears perfectly true ; "that this body [the Hartford Convention] manifested their purpose to dissolve the Union, should Congress refuse to redress the grievances of which they complained." Four years before the date of the Hartford Convention, Mr. Josiah Quincy, an influential member of Congress from Massachusetts, publicly declared the right of seces sion. The extract from his speech on the 14th of January, 1811, is hackneyed; but it is, nevertheless, significant of what was then passing in the mind of Massachusetts. It is also exceedingly significant, because it was uttered in opposition to the admission of Louisiana into the Union as a State. "If this bill passes/ said he, "it is my delib erate opinion that it is virtually a dissolution of the Union ; that it will free the States from their moral obligation, and, as it will be the right of all, so it will be the duty of some, definitely to prepare for separation, amicably if they can, violently if they must/ Nay, upon the purchase of 1 Letter of Dec. 30, 1828, in reply to H. Gray Otis and others. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 183 Louisiana, in 1803, the Legislature of Massachusetts passed the following resolution: "Resolved, That the annexation of Louisiana to the Union transcends the Constitutional power of the Government of the United States. It formed a new Confederacy to which the States, united by the former compact, are not bound to adhere." Thus, as we have seen, Massachusetts from the founda tion of the Federal Government down to 1815, held the Constitution to be a compact between the States, and the Union to be a Confederacy. In her ordinance of ratifi cation in 1788; in her reply to the Eesolutions of ? 98 ; in her own resolution of 1803-4 she most distinctly an nounced this doctrine. Hence, it seems impossible to doubt the statement of John Quincy Adams, 1 that the Hartford Convention deduced the right of secession from the fact that the Constitution was a compact between the States of the Confederacy. This was a clearly legal inference. Kawle, Story, and Webster all admit it to be such. Thus the fathers, one and all, laid down the great premise or postulate of the doctrine of secession at the very foundation of the Union; and the New England States, in 1815, deliberately drew the inference, and asserted the right of secession. Yet these States, in 1861, took the lead of all others in the fierceness and the bitter ness of their denunciation of secession as treason and rebellion ! The first to assert for themselves, and yet the first to persecute in others, this great right ! It is thus that Josiah Quincy, the Webster of 1815, as serted the fundamental principle or postulate of secession : "Touching the general nature of that instrument called the Constitution of the United States, there is no ob scurity; it has no fabled descent, like the palladium of ancient Troy, from the heavens. Its origin is not confused by the mists of time, or hidden by the darkness of past, unexplained ages; it is the fabric of our day. Some now living had a share in its construction; all of us stood by, and saw the rising edifice. There can be no doubt about its nature. It is a political compact/ Is this the same Josiah Quincy, or was it his son, who, in 1861, made him- 1 Letter of Dec. 30, 1828, to H. Gray Otis, etc. 184 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES self so conspicuous by denouncing secession as treason? It is certainly the same Josiah Quincy. who, in 1811, was called to order in Congress for asserting the right of secession, and voted to be in order. How rapidly the New England world turns upon its political axis ! In 1815, as secession was the right of all, so it was the duty of some of the States; and, in 1861, it was treason and rebellion ! DID THE SOUTH CONDEMN SECESSION IN 1815? The South, it has been repeatedly asserted, condemned the secession of 1815 as treason, and is, therefore, estopped from complaining of the same sentiment in 1861. "This," it is urged, "may be said to be res adjudicate. All parties are committed against the right of secession." Now, even if the facts were as alleged, still this would be a one-sided logic. For if the South, in 1815, con demned secession, it was the secession which New England had approved; and if the North, in 1861, denounced secession, it was precisely the right which the South had asserted. Hence, it is just as true that all parties were committed for, as that all parties were committed against, the right of secession. If, as is supposed, the minority was, in both instances, in favor of the right of secession, and the majority opposed to it, this would have been nothing very strange or wonder ful. It would only have illustrated the saying of Aristotle, which all history confirms, that "the weak always desire what is equal and just, but the powerful pay no regard to it." But the facts have not been accurately stated. It is true that the South, as well as other portions of the Union, vehemently condemned the Hartford Convention. No Convention, or assembly, was ever more odious to the great body of the people of the United States. But its proceedings were secret; and, till the appearance of Mr. Adams letter of December 30, 1828, its precise object or design was not generally known. It may be doubted, indeed, if it was ever condemned by any portion of the South, on the simple ground that it claimed for the New THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 185 England States merely the right to secede from the Union, and to be let alone. It was, however, known to the South that the New England States had insisted on a war with Great Britain in order to defend and secure the rights of their seamen. It was also known that, while the South was engaged in this war, the New England States not only failed to do their duty, but denounced the war they had instigated, and the government by which it was carried on. It is true that, by these proceedings, the wrath of the South was awakened, and that she denounced them as treason, because they gave "aid and comfort" to the enemy. From all that had preceded, how could the South know, indeed, but that the Hartford Convention had formed the dark design of appealing to arms against the Government of the United States, and of joining Great Britain in the war against the people of this country ? Even if the South had known that New England merely designed, in 1815, to secede from the Union, still her indignation would not have been without just cause. For, having got the South into a war with Great Britain, was that the time for her to desert the standard of her country, and leave the other States exposed to the full brunt of its fury? The clearest right may, indeed, be exercised in such a manner, and under such circumstances, as to render it odious. The right of secession has, no doubt, been made to appear treasonable by its association with the Hartford Convention of 1815. Far otherwise was the conduct of the South. She held no secret Conventions. All her proceedings were as open as the day. The United States were at peace with all the world. It was under these circumstances that the States of the South, each in its own Convention assembled, with drew from the Union, and asked to be let alone. But the South was not permitted to enjoy the government of her choice. On the contrary, she was subjugated, impover ished, and ruined with the avowed design to bring her back into the Union ; and, now that she is knocking at the door of the Union, she is not allowed to enter. What, then, is left to her sons and daughters but to weep over the inconsistency and wickedness of mankind; and, if possible, to pray for their enemies? 186 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES THOMAS JEFFERSON ON THE EIGHT OF SECESSION Though Mr. Jefferson was not one of the architects of the Constitution; yet has more stress been laid on his supposed opposition to the right of secession than upon that of any other statesman of America, especially by foreign writers. We are gravely told, with the usual information of such writers, that "Mr. Jefferson was, in after-life, the foremost champion of States rights." 1 We are also informed that "he would certainly have turned away with abhorrence from the consequences to which these [rights] have since been driven." 2 This last senti ment is, perhaps, conformed to the general opinion at the North on the same subject. But is it true ? It is certain, in the first place, that Mr. Jefferson him self deduced the right of nullification from the doctrine of States rights; not "in after-life," but in 1799, before he was President of the United States. Mr. Everett, I am aware, insinuates that Mr. Jefferson never favored the doctrine of nullification. "Such, in brief," says he, "was the main purport of the Virginia and Kentucky resolu tions." The sort of interposition, indeed, was left in studied obscurity. Not a word was dropped of secession from the Union. Mr. Nicholas 7 resolution in 1709 hinted at "nullification" as the appropriate remedy for an un- constituional law, but what was meant by the ill-sounding word was not explained. 3 Now this statement is of a piece with the main substance of that grand, swelling oration of the great Massachusetts declaimer. It is utterly devoid of truth. In the first place, Mr. Jefferson himself, in his corre spondence, replied to the inquiry of the son of Mr. Nicholas, that his father was not the author of the reso lutions in question. Mr. Jefferson says : "I drew and delivered them to him." 4 Nor is this all. "Two copies of these resolutions," says the editor of Mr. Jefferson s works, "are preserved among the manuscripts of the author, 1 "History of the United States," by J. M. Ludlow. 2 Ibid. * "Rebellion Records," vol. 1, p. 20. 4 "Jefferson s Works," vol. vii, p. 229. THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES 187 both in his own handwriting. One is a rough draft, and the other very neatly and carefully prepared. The probability is that they are the original of the Kentucky Kesolutions on the same subject." 1 Let us see, then, the very language of these Eesolutions, and the manner in which they "hinted at nullification." The first resolution is in these words: "Resolved, That the several States composing the United States of America are not united on the principle of unlimited submission of their general government, but that, by a compact under the style and title of the Constitution of the United States, and of amendments thereto, they constitute a general gov ernment for special purposes; and that whensoever the general government assumes undelegated powers its acts are unauthoritative, void, and of no force; that to this compact each State acceded as a State, and is an integral party, its co-States forming, as to itself, the other party; that the government created by this compact was not made the exclusive or final judge of the extent of the powers delegated to itself, since that would have made its dis cretion, not the Constitution, the measure of its poiuers; BUT THAT, AS IN ALL CASES OF COMPACT AMONG POWEES HAVING NO COMMON JUDGE, EACH PARTY HAS AN EQUAL RIGHT TO JUDGE FOR ITSELF, AS WELL OF INFRACTIONS AS OF THE MODE AND MEASURE OF REDRESS." 2 So much for the postulate. The conclusion is in these words : "Resolved, That . . . where powers are assumed which have not been delegated, a nullification of the act is the rightful remedy; that every State has a natural right, in cases not within the compact \_casus non fcederis], to nullify of their own authority all assumptions of power by others within their limits; that, without this right, they would be under the dominion, absolute and unlimited, of whosoever might exercise this right of judgment for them; that neverthe less, this commonwealth, from motives of regard and respect for its co-States, has wished to communicate with them on the subject; that with them alone it is proper to communicate, they alone being the parties to judge in the 1 "Jefferson s Works," vol. ix, p. 464. 2 Ibid., vol. ix, p. 464-5. 188 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES last resort of the powers exercised under it, CONGRESS BEING NOT A PARTY, BUT MERELY THE CREATURE OF THE COMPACT, AND SUBJECT AS TO ITS ASSUMPTIONS OF POWER TO THE FINAL JUDGMENT OF THOSE BY WHOM, AND FOR WHOSE USE ITSELF AND ITS POWERS WERE ALL CREATED AND MODIFIED/ etc. Such is the language of Thomas Jeffer son ! Is it merely a modest "hint at nullification" ? Some alterations were made in the Eesolutions, as penned by Mr. Jefferson, before they were passed by the Legisla ture of Kentucky. But the first resolution above given was not altered at all; it was passed precisely as it came from the pen of Mr. Jefferson, with only one dissentient vote! In the Eesolutions as passed by the State of Ken tucky, we find these words : "That the principle and con struction contended for by sundry of the State Legislatures, that the general government is the exclusive judge of the extent of the powers delegated to it, stop nothing short of despotism since the discretion of those who administer the government, and not the Constitution, would be the measure of their powers: That the several States who formed that instrument, being sovereign and independent, have the unquestionable right to judge of the infraction; and, THAT A NULLIFICATION BY THOSE SOVEREIGNTIES, OF ALL UNAUTHORIZED ACTS DONE UNDER COLOR OF THAT IN STRUMENT, IS THE RIGHTFUL REMEDY/ 71 Such is the language which Mr. Everett so very modestly calls a "hint at nullification" ! He must be a dull logician, indeed, or a partial one, who does not see that both nullification and secession flow from the great fundamental doctrine of the Virginia and the Kentucky Eesolutions. If, according to that doctrine, stated in the very words of Massachusetts, "the States, who have no common, umpire, are to be their own judges, and to execute their own decisions," then most assuredly they may pronounce in favor of either nullification or secession. Any State may, it is true, bring reproach on this right of sovereignty by the manner in which it is exercised. I have, indeed, always doubted whether nulli fication was a wise, or judicious, exercise of the right of 1 "Elliott s Debates," vol. iv, p. 571. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 189 State sovereignty. It is certain that Mr. Webster, as well as many others, has pointed out so many inconveniences, not to say absurdities, connected with the act of nullifi cation, that the right has usually been rejected with contempt. But the exercise of a right is one thing; and the existence of that right is another. A man may, in his own affairs, judge unwisely; but does that prove that he had no right to judge for himself? In like manner, it does not follow that a sovereign State has no right to be her own judge, because she may judge unwisely. It is, then, false reasoning to conclude that a State has no right to nullify, because the act of nullification is full of in conveniences, or even absurdities. Yet this kind of sophistry is precisely the amount of all the logic which has been urged against nullification. If a man, who has the right to judge for himself in his own business, makes an unwise decision, shall the right, therefore, be taken from him, and given to another ? Shall his decision be declared null and void, and the decision of some other person substituted in its place ? Nothing could be more unjust and despotic. Nor will any sovereign State submit to be treated in a similar manner by any un authorized power on earth. The act of nullification has, no doubt, brought reproach on the doctrine of State rights, and especially on the right of secession; but, then, this has been just because men have failed to think accurately and profoundly on the subject. They have confounded the propriety or judiciousness of an act with the right of the party to do the act, than which a worse solecism could hardly be perpetrated. Nullification is, however, but indirectly connected with secession. This right flows, as we have seen, directly from the doctrine of Mr. Jefferson, "that as in all other cases of compact, among parties having no common judge, each party has an equal right to judge for itself, as well of infractions as of the mode and measure of redress." To say that a State has the right to judge of infractions of the compact of the Constitution by the Federal Gov ernment, and also of the mode and measure of redress, and, at the same time, that it has no right to decide upon 190 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES secession as the proper remedy, is, it seems to me, simply a contradiction in terms. Now the question is, was Mr. Jefferson guilty of this act of glaring inconsistency, or self-contradiction ? He "would have turned away with abhorrence," it is said, "from the consequences" which have been deduced from the doctrine of State rights. In this bold assertion, the writer had special reference to the right of secession, which his history of the United States, as it is called, was written to demolish. Hundreds have, indeed, attempted to throw the great weight of Mr. Jefferson s authority in the scale against the right of secession, by means of the following extract from his works: "If to rid ourselves of the present rule of Massachusetts and Connecticut we break the Union, will the evil stop there? Suppose the New England States alone cut off, will our nature be changed? Are we not men still to the South of that, and with all the passions of men ! Immediately we shall see a Pennsylvania and a Virginia party arise in the residuary confederacy. What a game too will the one party have in their hands, by eternally threatening the other that unless they do so and so they will join their Northern neighbors ! If we reduce our Union to Virginia and North Carolina, immediately the conflict will be established be tween the representatives of these two States, and they will end by breaking into their separate units." Now this partial extract, which has gone the rounds of the civilized world, gives an utterly false view of Mr. .Jefferson s opinion. The context to the above passage, which is sometimes permitted to accompany it, shows that Mr. Jefferson really believed in the right of secession, and only argued against the intemperate and too hasty exercise of that right. "If," says he, in the sentence im mediately preceding the above extract, "on the temporary superiority of one party, the other is to resort to a scission of the Union, no federal government can exist." How perfectly true! If, for so trifling a cause, any union of States should be dissolved, it would soon be re solved into its original units. The union would not long exist, and it would not deserve to exist if its members THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 191 were such fools as to resort to the right of secession "on the temporary success" of every party therein. But to argue, as Mr. Jefferson does, against the too hasty and intemperate exercise of the right is to acknowledge the existence of the right itself. In the Declaration of Independence, Mr. Jefferson said "that long-established governments should not be changed for light and transient causes/ Nor, however clear the Constitutional right, would he have dissolved the Union for such causes. But does he say that he would not advo cate a scission of the Union for any cause whatever? That in no event whatever he would resort to the right of secession? There is no such doctrine in his writings; no such glaring self-contradiction in any portion of his works. On the contrary, in consultation as to what the Ken tucky Eesolutions of 98 and 99 should contain, he wished the following sentiments to be incorporated therein : "Ex pressing in affectionate and conciliatory language our warm attachment to the union with our sister States, and to the instrument and principles by which we are united; THAT WE ARE WILLING TO SACRIFICE TO THIS EVERYTHING BUT THE RIGHTS OF SELF-GOVERNMENT IN THOSE IMPOR TANT POINTS WHICH WE HAVE NEVER YIELDED, AND IN WHICH ALONE WE SEE LIBERTY, SAFETY, AND HAPPINESS." 1 Is it not perfectly obvious, from this passage, that Mr. Jefferson had not been so dazzled by the glories of the new Union as to forget the immortal principles of the Declaration of Independence? Devoted to the Union, but still adhering to the great principles of 1776, he immediately adds that we are "not at all disposed to make every measure of error, or of wrong, a cause of scission." Could language more clearly, or more necessarily, imply that there are measures of error, or of wrong, which he would make a ground of scission, or secession from the Union? Or could any doctrine be more clearly asserted, than is the opinion of Mr. Jefferson, that the States, and the States alone, are to be the judges whether the measure of error, or of wrong, which justifies her secession, has been filled or otherwise? 1 "Jefferson s Works," vol. iv, p. 305-6. 192 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES THE POLITICAL CREED OF THE STATE-EIGHTS PARTY The Virginia Eesolutions of 98 and the Kentucky Eeso lutions of 98 and 99, the former from the pen of "the father of the Constitution/ and the latter from the pen of the author of the Declaration of Independence, consti tuted, for at least forty years, the political creed of the great State-Eights party. They were, as every one knows, the manifestoes on which Thomas Jefferson went before the people, in 1800, as candidate for the Presidency of the United States. They were also inscribed on the banners of the party by which Madison, and Monroe, and Jackson, and other candidates, were supported for the same high office. Were they, then, at that time, deemed treasonable by the people, or by their leaders? Let us glance at the record and see. In 1800, Mr. Jefferson beat his opponent, John Adams, then President of the United States, by a majority of eight votes in the electoral college, or by a vote of 73 to 65. In 1804, Mr. Jefferson, the champion of State Eights, beat his opponent by the overwhelming majority of 162 votes to 14. In the Northern States alone, Mr. Jefferson received 85 votes, and his opponent only 9. In 1808, Mr. Madison beat his opponent by a vote of 122 to 47 ; and, in spite of the dissatisfaction of the New England States, he received from the whole North a majority of 50 to 39 votes. In 1812, he defeated DeWitt Clinton, a distinguished citizen, and formerly Governor of New York, by a major ity of 128 to 89 ; receiving in the Northern States only 40 votes to his rival s 80. In 1816, James Monroe, of Virginia, received 183 votes, and his opponent only 34 ; and more than one-half of these 183 votes were given by Northern States. In 1820, Mr. Monroe was elected over John Quincy Adams, of Massachusetts, by the majority of 231 votes to 13. Two other candidates were in the field at the same time, Crawford and Jackson, both of whom together re ceived only 11 votes. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 195 This vote, however, can hardly be regarded as a test of the popularity of the doctrine of State Eights, since this was, in 1820, professed by all the candidates for the Presi dency. Yet this fact shows that the opposite party had been so often and so completely defeated that it refused to nominate a candidate. But James Monroe, the suc cessor of Jefferson and Madison, and well known as an ardent advocate of the doctrine of State sovereignty, swept the whole country, and carried everything before him like a tornado. Henceforth all aspirants for the Presidency bowed down to that great symbol of political truth and power, the Virginia Resolutions of 98. Even Mr. Webster approached them with evident signs of awe, and never ventured to speak of them otherwise than in terms of marked respect, if not of veneration. No living soul dared breathe the suspicion that any one of their doctrines was treasonable. How, then, did it happen that those doctrines were afterward arraigned by Story and Webster as at war with the Constitution of the United States? How did it happen that, without the most distant allusion to the Virginia Resolutions, under which so many battles had been fought and so many victories won, the great orator of New England had the audacity to declare that all the fathers of the Constitution, that all the publications of friends and foes, denied the Constitution to be a compact between sovereign States? The foregoing brief sketch of the progress of opinion in regard to the nature of the Con stitution would be incomplete without an answer to this question ; without some notice of the causes by which so marvelous a revolution was produced. THE DECLINE or THE DOCTRINE OF THE SOVEREIGNTY OF THE STATES AND ITS CAUSES Mr. Dane says: "For forty years one great party has received the Constitution, as a federative compact among the States, and the other party, not as such a com pact, but in the main national and popular." 1 Now, as 1 Quoted in Story s Commentaries, vol. 1, p. 288, note. 196 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES we have seen in this chapter, the above statement is not true. The Federal party itself, with Hamilton at its head, admitted the Constitution to be a compact between the States. The State of Massachusetts, the great leading State of that party, always held the Constitution to be such a compact previous to the year 1830. She held this doctrine, as we have just seen, in 1788, in 1799, in 1803 ; and she continued to hold it until, in 1815, it culminated in the avowed right of secession. There is, then, no truth in the statement that for forty years one great party denied the Constitution to be a federative compact among the States. One great party, it is true, showed a strong dis position to deny the sovereignty of the States in the Union, and to assert the sovereignty of the Federal Government. But the doctrine imputed to it was not one of its heresies. Neither Mr. Dane, nor Judge Story, who quotes his words, is pleased to inform the reader that "the great party," which is asserted to have sanctioned their own heresy, was swept from existence by the other great party. It sank so low, in fact, after the war of 1812, and became so odious, that none was so humble as to do it reverence. Nor did they inform the reader that the great leaders of this very party in Xew England became, in 1815, when in distress, the warmest of all existing advocates for the rights and the .sovereignty of individual States. They do not even drop a hint that those leaders, those staunch advocates of the sovereignty of the Federal Government, were the first to insist on the right of secession; a fact which would have detracted very much from the weight of their authority against the doctrine of "a federative compact among States/ 7 even if they had ever rejected that doctrine. History acquits the old Federal party of the monstrous heresy imputed to it. Having been chief agents them selves in framing "the federative compact" for the States, and having anxiously watched the States as, one after another, each acceded to that compact, such a heresy, such a perversion of the facts falling under their own observa tion, would have been utterly beyond their power. How, then, and why, did the heresy in question raise its head in the Northern States? THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 197 This question is easily answered. 1. The doctrine of a compact is attended with one great inconvenience; the inconvenience, namely, that if it be violated by one of the parties, the other parties are absolved from its obligations. This great inconvenience is set forth by Dr. Paley ; to whose chapter on the subject, in his "Political Philosophy," Mr. Justice Story refers. Now this doctrine makes the stability of the Federal Compact depend on the good faith of all the parties, which seemed quite too frail a foundation for the Union. Hence, the doctrine of a federative compact, which, for forty years had been held by both the great parties of the United States, was explained away, and the will of the strongest substituted in its place. According to his theory, then, the Union rested, not on the justice of the parties, but on the despotic power of the dominant faction. He thus placed the Union, by his construction, on what he conceived to be a more solid foundation "than a federative compact between the States." But this, as we have seen, was to subvert the foundation laid by the fathers of the Union; and, in order to make good his theory, he had to falsify the whole political history of the United States during the first forty years of the existence of the new Union; espe cially the views and the authority of its founders. 2. The right of secession had never been seriously con sidered by any party, so long as the Union was prosperous and happy. But, during the period from 1803 to 1815, the great leaders of New England, regarding their section as grievously oppressed in the Union, revolved the great theme in mind, and, for the first time in the history of parties, deliberately asserted the right of secession. In view of this alarming event, it became still more important, in the opinion of Mr. Justice Story and other con- structionists, to deny the doctrine of a federative compact, from which, as he saw and admitted, so frightful a con sequence necessarily resulted. 3. This denial became the more indispensable, in Judge Story s opinion, because Mr. William Eawle had, in 1825, asserted the right of secession in his work on the Consti- 198 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES tution. Mr. Justice Story alludes to the opinion of Mr. Rawle, and, deploring it, he bent all his energies and erudition to demolish the doctrine of a federative compact, from which that right necessarily results. Thus, accord ing to his theory, the Union was to be hooped with bands of iron, and not trusted to the mutual sympathy and good faith of its members. 4. But, however great and commanding the influence of Story s opinion, or view of the Constitution, it would have been comparatively feeble if it had not been aided by public events. South Carolina, feeling herself and some of her sister States grievously oppressed in the Union, by the tariffs of 1824 and 1828, planted herself on the great platform of State Rights, and nullified the act of Congress. The indignation of the North was aroused. Nullification, it was said, led directly to secession, or a dissolution of the Union. The New England States, which had only fifteen years before advocated the right of secession, now led the tierce crusade against its advocates. John C. Calhoun, the great nullifier, was the mark of their fury. It was in this contest, as every one knows, that the great orator oi New England, Mr. Webster, put forth "the greatest intel lectual effort of his life," if not of the human mind. The whole North was electrified by his eloquence, and became intoxicated with his fictions. Much has been said about the Northern and the South ern theories of the Constitution. The true word is, how ever, the theories of the majority and of the minority. For the Southern theory, as it is called, originated in New England ; and, passing from minority to minority, found a permanent resting place in the South. Yet it may, with truth, be called the Southern theory, since the South has always been in the minority in the new Union. Mr. Webster lived to pronounce a splendid eulogy on the virtues, the patriotism, and the genius of John C. Calhoun, with whom he had long served in the Senate of the United States. But the successors of Mr. Webster have, for more than eighteen long months, held the bosom friend and the peer of John C. Calhoun in prison at THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 199 Fortress Monroe, as if he were already a convicted felon and traitor. Yet is it, as we have seen, his only crime, that he sat at the feet of Thomas Jefferson, "the immortal author of the Declaration of Independence," and there learned the right of secession ? Shall the people, then, who sang loud hozannas to the great master, follow the equally great disciple with the cry of crucify him, crucify him.? Or shall it be said that they voted the Presidency for the one, and a prison for the other ? CHAPTEE XVI THE CAUSES OF SECESSION INTRODUCTORY IN the preceding chapters the Constitutional right of secession has, it seems to me, been demonstrated. If so, then, in the eye of reason, the Southern States are ac quitted of every offence against the Constitution, or the supreme law of the land. But, however clear a legal or Constitutional right, it may not be always proper to exer cise it. If the Southern States exercised the right of secession merely because they possessed that right, or merely because they were beaten at an election, or for any such "light and transient cause," then they committed a great wrong. Then, although they violated no law of the land, they committed a great and grievous wrong against the moral law of the world, by a capricious exercise of their sovereign right and power. Hence, the vindication of the Southern States in the forum of conscience, as well as in that of the law, demands an exposition of the causes of secession. It would require a volume to do justice to this subject; and yet, at present, a brief sketch is all that can be attempted. THE BALANCE OF POWER From the foundation of the American Union to the present day the provision of its Constitution for the frac tional representation of slaves has been more talked about, and less understood, than any other clause of that "sacred instrument." One would suppose that if any one really desired to ascertain the reason or design of this "singular provision," as it is called, he would look into the debates of the Convention by which it was inserted in the Consti tution. In these debates, as reported in "The Madison Papers," the reason or design of the fathers in the enactment of THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 201 that clause is as clear as the noonday sun. Yet, in all that has been written by the North on the subject, there is not even a glimmering of light as to that reason or design. "Men make books," says old Burton, "as apothecaries make medicines, by pouring them out of one bottle into another." This has most emphatically been the way in which men have made books on "the American Question"; and, in the case before us, the bottles were originally filled, not at the pure fountains of historic truth, but from the turbid streams of ignorance, falsehood, and misrepresentation. Yet, for three-quarters of a century, has all this stuff been continually poured out of one book into another! Accordingly, we find it in a hundred books on both sides of the Atlantic, uttered with just as much confidence as if the authors had some knowledge on the subject. Thus are we gravely told, and with great confidence, that "the weakest point in the Constitution lies elsewhere. It lies in that truckling to the slave-power which is obvious in it. It lies especially in that singular provision for what is termed black or slave 7 representation, whereby alone, amongst all species of property, that in human flesh is made a source of political power." 1 Xow, if anything in history is certain it is that, after a protracted debate! > the Convention of 1787 agreed that population^and popuj lation alone, should constitute Jhe basis_of representation^. V The slaves were not represented at all as property^ This is evident, not only from the debates of the Convention of 1787, but from the very face of the Constitution itself. "Representatives," says that document, "shall be appor tioned among the several States which may be included within this Union, according to their respective numbers ffjnot one word is said about property], which shall be determined by adding to the whole number of free persons, including those bound to service for a term of years, and excluding Indians not taxed, three-fifths of all other persons/ Thus, in this very clause, the slaves are called "persons," and are to be represented as such, not as property. Hence, when Mr. G-reeley, in his "American Conflict," wishes to prove that the Constitution regards 1 "History," by T. M. Ludlow, pp. 44-5. 202 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES slaves as "persons/ 3 he quotes the clause in question. Nay, Mr. Ludlow himself, when it suits his purpose, can recog- t nize the truth that the Constitution "never speaks of the [, slaves as a property, but as a person/ 1 If, indeed, slaves I had not been regarded as persons, they would not have been admitted into the basis of representation at all. Now, did the North truckle to the South, in conceding that slaves are "persons"? Mr. Patterson, of New Jersey, and some other Northern members, endeavored to ex clude slaves from the basis of representation on the ground that they were "property" ; but Mr. Butler and Mr. C. C. Pinckney, both of South Carolina, insisted that they were "persons," that they were a portion of the laboring and productive "population" of the South; and, as such, should be included in the basis of representation on a footing of equality with other "inhabitants." The Con vention decided that they were "persons." Was this decision correct? Or was it, on the contrary, a mean "truckling to the slave power"? In the declamations on this subject it is usually taken for granted by Northern writers, as well as by Mr. Lud low, that free citizens or voters alone are included in the basis of representation for the North, while three-fifths of the slaves are embraced in it for the South. Hence, this is vehemently denounced as a "singular provision," as a "strange anomaly," as a most undue advantage to the South. But the fact is not so. The assumption is utterly false. By the decision of the Convention, and by the very terms of the Constitution, "the whole number of free persons," whether men, women, children, or paupers, are included in the bases of representation. All "persons," of every age, color, and sex are included in that basis. Hence Mr. Ludlow is mistaken in calling the clause in question "the provision" for "black" representation. The blacks, as such, were included in the general provision, and ranked as equal to the whites. In like manner, Professor Cairnes errs in saying the clause under consider ation "is known as the three-fifths vote." 2 No such thing as a "three-fifths vote" is known to the Constitution of the 1 Page 51. - "The Slave Power," chap. vi. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 208 United States, and the name is the coinage of ignorance. The three-fifths clause has nothing to do with votes or voting. No slave could cast the three-fifths, or any fraction, of a vote. The free blacks were, in most cases, denied the exercise of the elective franchise. It was in counting the number, not of those who should vote, but only of those who should make up the basis of representa tion that five slaves were to be reckoned equal to three white persons, or three free negroes. Now, why was this? Had the Convention any rule of vulgar fractions by which a slave was shown to be only the three-fifths of a person ? And if they had, did not the clause in question result from a mathematical calculation, rather than from a "truckling to the slave power"? or, if that was treated as a question of vulgar fractions, why did the Convention stop there? Why not raise other questions of the same kind? Why not consider the problem, if a full-grown slave is only the three-fifths of a person, what fraction of a person is the infant of a day old, before the power of thought, or of local motion, has even begun to infold itself in him or her? The truth is that the Convention of 1787 indulged in no such trifling with the great, practical questions demanding a solution. The States were exceedingly jealous of "the sovereignty, freedom, and independence/ 7 which they had expressly retained under the Articles of Confederation. The Federal Government claimed, on the other hand, an augmentation of its powers; a claim eloquently urged by the tongues and pens of many of the ablest men in America. Hence arose the great conflict between the States and the central Power; which, from that day to this, has agitated the minds of the Anglo-Americans. In approaching this conflict, the Convention first determined, in outline, the form of the General Government. It was readily agreed that it should be a Eepublic, with a Legislature consisting of two branches, a Senate and House of Eepresentatives, a Judiciary, and an Executive. The next question was, what powers shall the States delegate to this General Government, this grand Bepublic? After debating this question for some time, the Convention discovered that it 204 THE WAE BETWEEN THE STATES had begun at the wrong end. None of the parties were willing to say with what powers the new Government should be invested, until it was ascertained what share they were to have in the exercise of those powers. Hence the Convention found it necessary to retrace its steps, and begin with the question of the distribution of power among the various members of the Union. In this contest for power each and every party, of course, claimed "the lion s share. " But each and every party could not have "the lion s share." Hence the two memorable quarrels or controversies of the Convention of 1787 ; the one between "the large and the small States," and the other between "the North and the South." Much is known about the first of these quarrels, but the history of the last yet remains to be written. Its very first chapter is still enveloped in the most profound obscurity. I speak advisedly, and with the proofs on all sides around me, when I say that the Americans themselves have not studied this first chapter in the history of the great quarrel between "the North and the South." Let us look into it, then, and see what it teaches. In order to adjust and settle the two quarrels above mentioned, Mr. Madison laid down the general principle that "wherever there is danger of attack there should be a Constitutional power of defence." No principle could have* been more reasonable or just; since the object of all government is to protect the weak, or those most exposed to danger, against the aggressions of the powerful. The Convention, without difficulty, agreed to the above prin ciple when only stated in general terms; but, as usual in such cases, a great difference of opinion arose in regard to the application of the principle. The small States, for example, fearing lest the large States should "annex" them, or swallow them up in some other way, refused to increase their power in the Union. They insisted that each State, whether small or great, should have precisely the same power in both branches of Congress. This would have placed all the powers of the Federal Legislature in the hands of the small States. They were willing, nay, they were eager, to possess them all; THE WAE BETWEEN THE STATES 205 just as if they had not the least fear that they could ever be tempted to do the least injury to the large States. But the large States, not having this perfect confidence in the justice of their little neighbors, refused to entrust them with the supreme control and destiny of the Union. Hence they refused "the lion s share" to the small States. They contended, however, for this share for themselves. They contended that each State should, in each branch of the Federal Legislature, have a power exactly proportioned to its size or population; an arrangement which would have given the absolute control of the whole government of the thirteen States to three States alone. Yet those three States (Massachusetts, Pennsylvania, and Virginia), with a perfect unanimity and a burning zeal, contended for this supreme dominion in the new Union. The small States, till then equal in Constitutional power with the large ones, resented this as a design to degrade and enslave them. This contest was the most obstinate and violent one of the Convention of 1787. "The truth is," said Alexander Hamilton, in regard to this very quarrel, "it is a contest for power, not for liberty." Each party, in its eagerness to grasp the supreme power, neglected the rights and interests of the other. This violent contest, which threatened to break up the Convention and blast all hope of a "more perfect Union," was finally settled by one of "the compromises of the Con stitution." It was agreed that the States should retain their equality in the Senate, each having two representa tives in that body, and that they should be represented in the other branch of Congress in proportion to their popu lations. Thus the small States controlled the Senate, and the large ones the House of Eepresentatives. Hence neither party could oppress the other. As no law could be passed without the concurrence of both Houses of Con gress, so it must obtain the consent of the small States in the one, and of the large States in the other. Each class of States had a check upon the power of the other. Thus, where "there was a danger of attack," there was, on both sides, given "Constitutional power of defence." This was, in deed as well as in word, to "establish and ordain THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES liberty." Hence the most violent contest of the Convention of 1787 ceased to agitate the bosom of the new Union. This admirable arrangement was proposed by Oliver Ells worth,, of Connecticut, and recommended on the ground that, in a Kepublie, it is always necessary to protect the minority against the tyranny of the majority. The same principles and policy governed the Conven tion in its attempt to adjust and settle the great antago nism between the North and South. Mr. Madison was so deeply impressed with the importance of arming each of these sections with a defensive power against the other, that he proposed "the numbers of free white inhabitants 7 as the basis of representation in one House of Congress, and the whole population, including blacks as well as whites, as the basis of representation in the other. This distribution of power would have given the North a majority in one branch of the Legislature, and the South a majority in the other. But the proposition failed. Mr. Madison did not urge it, indeed, because, as he said, it presented a cause of quarrel which was but too apt to arise of itself. After the States were made equal in the Senate, each having two representatives in that body, the North had the entire control of it. As there were eight Northern States (Delaware was then considered a Northern State), and only five Southern States, so the North had a majority in the Senate of 16 to 10. Hence, if the South was to have any defensive power at all it should have had a majority of representatives in the other branch of Congress. Accordingly, Southern members insisted on the full repre sentation of the whole population of the South, as well as of the North, in order that their section might have a majority in one branch of the common Legislature. The North, on the contrary, insisted that the slaves should be entirely excluded from the basis of representation ; which would have given that section a decided majority in both branches of Congress. Thus, while the South contended for a power of self-defence or protection, the North aimed at no less than absolute control and dominion. The South would not submit. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATKS 207 The North and the South were then,, as they afterward appeared to De Tocqueville, "more like hostile nations, than rival parties, under one government." The fierce con test for power between them resulted in the compromise of the three-fifths clause of the Constitution. In proposing this clause, Mr. Wilson, of Pennsylvania, said it could not be justified on principle, whether property or population were regarded as the basis of representation, but that it was deemed "necessary as a compromise between the North and the South." As such it was seconded by Mr. C. C. Pinckney, of South Carolina, and as such it was adopted by the Convention. This clause was, then, a compromise, not between abstract metaphysical principles of govern ment, but between the opposite and conflicting claims of the two rival sections. Did the North, then, "truckle to the slave power"? It is certain that she grasped at and gained a majority in both branches of the common Legis lature. For, in spite of the clause in question, the North had a majority of 36 to 29 in the House of Eepresentatives, as well as of 16 to 10 in the Senate ; a share which cer tainly ought to have satisfied any ordinary lion. But it is the fate of a democracy to be governed more by words than by ideas, more by "telling cries" than by truth. The cry has always been that the slaves, who had no wills of their own, were represented in Congress; and that this "singular provision," this "strange anomaly," had resulted from a base "truckling to the slave power." But for this provision, says Professor Cairnes, 1 there seemed to be nothing in the Constitution "which was not calculated to give to numbers, wealth, and intelligence their due share in the government of the country." Did the general clause, then, which places idiots, paupers, free negroes, and infants of all ages, in the basis of representa tion, provide for nothing but a representation of "the intelligence and wealth of the country"? The truth is that none of these clauses were represented in Congress; they were merely considered in the difficult question of the distribution of power among the States and the sections. The only persons really represented were the 1 "The Slave Power," p. 164. 208 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES voters, who had the legal right to choose their own repre sentatives. It was in this way, and in this way alone, that the Convention sought to secure a representation of the "wealth and intelligence" of the country. But who cared for the truth? The telling cry, that slaves were represented in Congress, inflamed the passions of the North, and served the purpose of demagogues infinitely better than a thousand truths. Hence the world has been filled with clamors about "the slave representation of the South." The deceivers are, however, careful to conceal the fact that all classes of "persons," except the slaves, are reckoned at their full value in constituting the basis of representa tion. The women and children of the North alone, many of whom were born in foreign countries and had never been naturalized in America, have been the source of far greater political power than that which has resulted from the whole population of the South. Is it not much nearer to the truth, then, to say that the South has been governed by the women and children of the North,, than that "the North has been governed by the slaves of the South" ? Immense, indeed, has been the advantage of the clause in question to the South ! Only let Mr. Ludlow, or one of his school, estimate this advantage, and it is sufficient to astonish the world ! Is gives to "every poor white" at the South, "however ignorant and miserable," "ten times the political power of the Northerner, be he never so steady, never so wealthy, never so able." 1 How wonderful the disparity ! And, considering that "all men are created equal," how infinitely more wonderful that the wealthy and the able Northerner should have so long and so patiently submitted to such an amazing inequality ! What ! The rich Northerner, the merchant prince, or the great lord of the loom, only the one-tenth part of the political power of the "poor white" at the South ! Is it possible ? Mr. Ludlow proves the whole thing by figures ; and "figures," it is said, "can not lie." Let us see, then, this wonderful proof of the wonderful fact. "Suppose," says Mr. Ludlow, "300,000 be the figures of population required to return a 1 "History," P- 49. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 209 representative, then, whilst 300,000 freemen of the North are required for the purpose, 30,000 Southerners, owning collectively 450,000 slaves, or 15 on an average (many plantations employing hundreds) are their equals politic ally, and every poor white/ however ignorant and miser able, has his vanity gratified by standing at the ballot-box the equal of his richest slaveholding neighbor, whilst each of them is equally invested with ten times the political power of the Northerner, be he never so steady, never so wealthy, and never so able." But he must, indeed, have been a most "ignorant and miserable" white, if he could have had his vanity gratified, or his judgment swayed, by any such logical process or conclusion. This specimen of logic, or rather of legerdemain, only assumes that none but "the 30,000 Southerners," with their "450,000 slaves, or fifteen on an average," are included in the basis of repre sentation. But since, in fact, all persons are included in that basis, Mr. Ludlow should have taken some little pains to explain to his poor ignorant readers how it is possible for eight millions of whites to own only four millions of blacks, and yet for each white to own, "on an average/ as many as "fifteen slaves." It would seem, without much calculation, that, in such a case, there could be only one slave to every two whites. If so, then, if the slaves had been regarded as whole "persons," the Southerner would have had only one and a half times the power of the Northerner. But as, in fact, the slave was counted as little more than the half of a person, so the Southerner possessed only a little more than one and a quarter times as much political power as his Northern neighbor. There was, then, no reason why the vanity of the poor, ignorant white of the South should have been so highly gratified, nor why the pride of the rich nabob of the North should have been so deeply wounded. But this whole way of viewing the subject is, in reality, perfectly puerile. What has the political power of the indi vidual to do with such a question? There is the broad fact, acknowledged by all the parties and all sections, that, at the time the Constitution was formed, the South was superior to the North both in wealth and population. 210 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES Hence, if either wealth or population had heen made the basis of representation, and fairly carried out in practice, the South would have had the majority in one branch of Congress. As it was, however, the North resolutely fought for and secured the majority in both branches thereof. Was not this, then, sufficient to gratify the pride of the North, as well to humble that of the South ? Suppose that in a society of ten millions of people, eight millions are united by one interest, and the remaining two millions by another interest. Suppose, again, that in order to get the two millions to enter into such a society, each individual of them had been allowed two votes, or twice as much power as an individual of the eight millions. Would this render the two millions secure? Would this give the minority a "defensive power" against the majority? "Ignorant and miserable," indeed, must be the individual in such a minority, if his vanity could be gratified by the possession of twice as much power as an individual of the majority, while that majority had the power to rob him of both his purse and his good name: The only strange thing in the transaction is, why the South should have consented to enter into so unequal a union with the North ; why she should have entrusted her rights, her interests, her honor, her glory, and her whole destiny to the care and keeping of a foreign and hostile majority. This seems the more wonderful, because, at that time, every statesman in America regarded nothing as more certain than the tyranny of the majority. "Com plaints are everywhere heard/ said Mr. Madison, in The Federalist., "from our most considerate and virtuous citi zens . . . that measures are too often decided, not according to the rules of justice, and the rights of the minor party, but by the superior force of an interested and overbearing majority." 1 It was the grand object of the Convention of 178? to correct this tendency, this radical vice, if not this in curable evil of all democratic republics. The evils under which the country labors, it was said in that Convention, are, on all hands, "traced to the turbulence and violence of 1 No. x. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 211 democracy/ to the injustice and tyranny of the majority. "To secure the public good, and private rights," said The Federalist., "against the danger of such a faction [i. e., of such "an interested and overbearing majority"], and at the same time to preserve the spirit and the form of a popular government, is then the great object to which our inquiries are directed. Let me add that it is the great desideratum, by which alone this form of government can be rescued from the opprobrium under which it has so long labored, and be recommended to the esteem and adoption of mankind." 1 Did the South, then, with her eyes open, willingly put her neck in the yoke of such a majority? If, as every Southern statesman knew perfectly well, "it is of great importance in a republic to guard one part of society against the injustice of another part," 2 did the South really fail to demand such a safeguard? Did she place herself under the rule of the North, without taking any security for her protection, without claiming any "Con stitutional power of defence" ? Nothing was further from her thoughts. If she had been seduced into the Union by the idea, by the immense advantage, that each of her citizens would have a little more power in one branch of Congress than those of the Xorth, she would have been the weakest and most contemptible of creatures. The citizen of a small State, such as Delaware or Rhode Island, might have had ten, or twenty, or thirty times the power in the other House of Congress, which a citizen of Pennsylvania or Virginia possessed ; and yet this would not have satisfied him unless the small States could have controlled that branch of the Legislature. This control of the Senate was demanded for the small States, as one of the indispensable conditions of Union, and this demand was conceded to them ; in order that the minority might, in this instance, enjoy that freedom, and independence, which it had resolutely refused to hold at the mercy of the majority. By all the principles, then, of the Convention of 1787, by the great object for which that Convention assembled, 1 The Federalist, No. x. - Ibid. 212 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES by the very nature and design of all Constitutional republics, they were bound to protect the minority against the majority. They were, especially, bound to protect the South against the North; the weaker and the richer sec tions against the stronger and the more rapacious. Ac cordingly, this was the grand object of the Convention. The design was good, but the execution was bad. The South insisted on the three-fifths clause, and some North ern members resisted its enactment; because it was be lieved, on both sides, that this would ultimately give the South a majority in the House of Representatives. It would, as every one knew, give the North the majority at the outset; but population was, before the adoption of the new Union, so much more rapidly increasing at the South than at the North, that the Convention believed that the South would soon gain the ascendancy in the lower House of Congress. The debates of the Conven tion bear ample and overwhelming testimony to the prevalence of this belief. The speeches of Madison, Mason, Pinckney, Butler, and others from the South, as well as of Morris, King, Wilson, and other from the North, con clusively show that the Convention intended to allow the South the prospect of a majority in one branch of Con gress. Such was the object and design of the three-fifths clause. Such was the reason of the Convention for ad mitting a fraction of the slave population into the basis of representation. From this point of view, that provision appears as reasonable and just to every thinking man, as from any other it seems strange, singular, anomalous. It was, as Rufus King, of Massachusetts, declared in the Convention, due to the South, as a Constitutional power of defence, or protection, in the new Union. This "singular provision/ 7 then, about which so much has been said and so little known, did, according to the design of its authors, lie at the very foundation of the Constitution of the United States. Neither the large States nor the small States, neither the North nor the South, would agree to enlarge the powers of the common government, until they could first see how those powers were to be distributed among themselves as the principal THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 213 parties to "the compact of the Constitution." Neither the North nor the South would, for one moment, have dreamed of entering into the new Union, if it had believed that the other would continue to have a majority in both branches of the Federal Legislature. Neither would have consented thus to hold its rights and interests at the mercy of the other. Each was, as the debates show, perfectly willing to hold the reins of empire and dominion over the other. But while each was thus perfectly willing to rule, it had some little objection against being ruled. It could easily trust itself, but not its rival, with the control of the supreme power, and it was, no doubt, amply prepared to bear with becoming fortitude any hardship or danger which might result to its ally from such an arrangement in its own favor. Hence the absolute necessity of the compromise in question. On no other terms, or conditions, could the new Union, with its vastly augmented powers, have arisen between the two great sections, which were so violently agitated and repelled by similar electricities. That "com promise," then, that "singular provision," that partial admission of slaves in the basis of representation was introduced and enacted to adjust the balance of power between the North and the South. It was one of the fundamental principles of the Constitution, without which "the more perfect Union" could not have been formed between the sections. The three-fifths clause or compromise, then, intended to give the one section, as well as the other, a defensive power in the new Union, was absolutely indispensable to the formation of that Union. Such a defensive power was, indeed, deemed by a majority of the fathers of the Con stitution, absolutely indispensable to the safety, freedom, and independence of each of the sections in the Union. Yet, however strange it may seem, no public man in America has, from that day to this, taken the pains to make himself acquainted with the reason and design of that fundamental provision of the Constitution of the United States! The author of the "American Conflict" regards slaves as "human beings"; and quotes the clause in question, 214 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES "three-fifths of all other persons," to prove that the Con stitution regards them in the same light. Why, then, says he, were they not represented "like other human beings, like women and children, and other persons, ignorant and humble, and powerless, like themselves?" The answer is very easy. Although the Convention did, as their pro ceedings show, adopt population as the basis of repre sentation ; yet was the majority more bent on the possession of power, than on the preservation of their logical con sistency. If, instead of compromising the difficulty, the South had persisted in pushing the principle adopted by the Convention to its logical conclusion, then would the great design of that body of legislators have been spoiled, and all prospects of the "more perfect Union" blown into thin air. So much for one horn of his formidable dilemma. "If, on the other hand," says he, "you con sider them property mere chattels personal why should they be represented any more than ships, or houses, or cattle? Here is a nabob, who values his favorite high bred horse at five thousand dollars, and five of his able- bodied negroes at the same amount. Why should his five negroes count as three men in apportioning the representatives in Congress among the several States, while the blooded horse counts for just nothing at all?" Here, again, the answer is perfectly easy. The slaves were not counted as property at all : and, consequently, there was no inconsistency in excluding horses, or other quadrupeds, from the basis of representation. Thus, neither horn of the dilemma is quite as unanswerable as the author imagines it to be, and utterly fails to show the absurdity of the clause in question as one of the "unsightly and anomalous" excrescences of the slave power. In reply to the two questions of his own dilemma the author says : " We can only answer that Slavery and Reason travel different roads, and that he strives in vain who labors to make these roads even seem parallel." Such is his profound commentary on one of the most important clauses, one of the most indispensable provisions, of the Constitution of his country. He is, in the same spirit, pleased to speak of this provision of the Constitution, as THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 215 if it had been hastily adopted by the Convention, "with out much debate or demur 7 ; T and that, too, just after he had quoted the undeniable words of one of the most cele brated members of the Convention, which show that it had "been settled 77 only "after much difficulty and delib- ration." 2 Roger Sherman was right; and Horace Greeley was wrong. The Convention had something more to do than merely to "split the difference 77 between two hairs, or abstractions; they had to adjust the balance of power between the two great rival sections of the United States ; a problem which lay at the very foundation of the new Union, and upon the satisfactory solution of which the whole superstructure was destined to depend. It is absurd, as well as untrue, to say that such a question was settled without much difficulty. It exercised, to the utmost, all the sagacity and wisdom of the Convention of 1787. That wisdom is, no doubt, utter foolishness to the radical re formers, who never fail to condemn Constitutions and laws without even knowing, or caring to know, the reasons on which they are founded. "Slavery and Reason" have, it is true, often traveled "different roads. 77 But, in the case before us, the South would have been glad to travel the same road with Reason, and follow the principle of the Convention to its logical conclusion. But the sturdy North would not listen to that conclusion. Hence if the South departed from the road of Reason at all, it was in order to meet the hard demands of the North, and join in the Union, which has proved her ruin. Jt proved her ruin; just because the balance of power, which the fathers intended to establish between the two sections, was overthrown and destroyed. That equilibrium, or balance of power, was, in the opinion of the fathers, indispensable to the safety, freedom, and independence of each section in the Union; and its destruction has illustrated and confirmed the wisdom of their decision. On this subject a distinguished Northern writer, in 1860, used the following language: "At the time of the adoption of the Federal Constitution the condition of slaves was very different at the South 1 "The American Conflict," p. 46. -Ibid., p. 43. 216 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES from what it has since become. At that time there was, as we have shown in a previous chapter, no large branch of industry to engage the blacks, and their future fate was matter of anxiety. The progress of the cotton cul ture has changed that, and the interests of millions of whites now depend upon the blacks. The opinions of statesmen of that day were formed upon existing facts; could they have seen fifty years into the future their views upon black employment would have undergone an entire change. The blacks were then prospectively a burden ; they are now an absolute necessity. They then threatened American civilization; they are now its support. With multiplying numbers they have added to the national wealth. They have become the instruments of political agitation, while they have conferred wealth upon the masses. "From the moment of the formation of the Federal Union there commenced a struggle for political power which has not ceased to be directed against the Slave States. The instrument of union, while it provided for the extinction of the slave-trade, which then formed so large a portion of Northern traffic, contained also a pro vision for black representation in the Southern States, stipulating that that representation should not be changed until 1808, and thereafter only by a vote of three-fourths of all the States. That provision has been the ground-work of that constant Northern aggression upon Southern inter ests which has so successfully gained on the Federal power until now it imagines the desired three-fourths is within its reach, ivlien the South, with its interests, will be at the feet of the abolitionists. The South has stood steadily on its defence, but while the circle has narrowed in upon it, the North has not ceased to clamor against Southern ag gression ! Like Jemmy Twitcher, in the farce, who, having robbed a passenger, loses the plunder, and exclaims, "there must be some dishonest person in the neighbor hood! . . . The original thirteen States that adopted this Consti tution were all Slave States with the exception of Massa chusetts, which, although it then held no slaves, had an THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES 217 interest in continuing the slave-trade, in opposition to the wishes of the Slave States. The struggle in the Convention in relation to the discontinuance of the slave-trade was between the New England States, that desired the traffic, and Virginia and Delaware that wished no more slaves, while those Southern States that had but a few blacks desired to import them without tax. On the vote New Hampshire and Massachusetts voted to continue the trade until 1808, and Virginia and Delaware voted "nay," or for its immediate discontinuance. No sooner had. the Constitution been adopted, however, than the annexation of Louisiana became a necessity, in order to give an outlet to the sea for the produce of the West, but, notwithstanding the great advantage which the annexation was to confer upon Massachusetts, she opposed it to the point of threatening to dissolve the Union if it was carried out. That, after the great rebellion of Shay within her border, was the first disunion threat, and the motive was fear of the political increase of Southern strength. Those fears were like all party pretences, short sighted, since that territory has given more Free than Slave States to the Union. This threat of disunion was made while yet Massachusetts was engaged in the slave- trade, that the State had voted to prolong to 1808. The same cry was renewed in respect to Florida, and again, with greater violence, in the case of Missouri ; to be again revived in respect to Texas; and once more, with circum stances of greater atrocity, in the case of Kansas. It is remarkable that while Free States come in without any great struggle on the part of the South, the safety of which is threatened by each accession, the admission of Slave States is the signal of so much strife, and this resistance to a manifest right of the South is denounced as "Southern aggression." The gradual abolition of slavery in the old Northern States, and the rapidity with which Eastern capital, fol lowing migration, has settled the Western States, has given a large preponderance to the free interest in the national councils. Of the 26 senators that sat in the first Congress, all represented a slave interest, more or less; 218 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES with the States and territories now knocking for admis sion there are 72 senators, of whom 32 only represent the slave interest. That interest, from being "a unit" in the Senate, has sunk to a minority of four, and yet the majority do not cease to complain of Southern "aggres sion." With this rapid decline in the Southern vote in the great "conservative body" of the Senate, the repre sentation in the lower House^has fallen to one-third. How long will it be before the desired three-fourths vote, for which a large party pant, will have been obtained, and, when obtained, what will have become of those Southern rights which are even now denied by party leaders to be any rights at all? In the last 30 years 11 Free States have been prepared for the Union; a similar progress in the next 30 years, and the South will have fallen into that Constitutional minority which may deprive it of all re served rights. This circle is closing rapidly in upon it, amid a continually rising cry of abolition, pointed by bloody inroads of armed men*. This is called Southern "aggression." 1 The balance of power was overthrown. The South lost, more and more, her original equality in the Union; and the just design of the fathers was despised and trampled underfoot by the Northern Demos. Every cen sus showed that her power had diminished, as her dangers had increased; and she no longer found herself in the original Union of equal sections. On the contrary, she found herself in a minority, which the Southern men of 1787 would have shunned as the plague, and threatened by a vast majority as cruel as death, and as inexorable as the grave. This was not the Union of the fathers, but the warped and perverted Union of unjust rule and domina tion. The States of New England never failed to threaten a dissolution of the Union whenever, in their jealous imaginations, there seemed even a prospect that the balance of power might turn in favor of the South in only one branch of Congress. Yet the more this balance was actually turned in their favor, and the South, contrary to the design of the fathers, reduced to a hopeless minority, 1 "Southern Wealth and Northern Profits." p. 130-4(1. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 319 the more imperiously they demanded her implicit sub mission to Northern rule, and the more fiercely was de nounced here every struggle to maintain her original equality and independence as "Southern aggression." From a table in the work above quoted it appears that, at each succeeding census, the relative increase of the two sections in the House of Representatives was as follows: Before Census 1700 1800 1810 1820 1830 1840 1850 North, 35 57 77 104 133 141 135 144 South, 30 53 65 79 90 100 88 90 Majority, 5 4 12 25 43 41 47 54 Thus, in one branch of the Legislature, the Northern majority, counting Delaware as a Southern State, had increased from a majority of five to a majority of fifty-four representatives. The South, as every reader of American history must know, never would have entered into so un equal a Union with the North; and the North would not have continued in the Union, if she had not always retained the balance of power in her own hands, and in both branches of Congress. As the North had so great a majority in the House, it was the more important that the South should, at least, retain her original share of power in the Senate. But even this she was not allowed to do. In order to gain the complete and uncontrolled ascendancy in the Seriate, as she had done in the House, the North began to exclude all slaveholding States from the Union. This she at tempted in regard to Missouri, and persisted in her un constitutional attitude until she was defeated by the votes of a few Northern democrats, who sacrificed themselves to save the Union and their own party. After the restoration of the Democratic party, and dur ing its reign, the rights of the States were so clearly vindi cated, and so firmly established, that few ventured to claim for Congress the power to exclude a State from the Union, because she held slaves. Hence the Republican party changed its tactics, and endeavored to effect the same un constitutional design in another way. Not daring to say, as their predecessor had done, that Congress could exclude 220 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES a slaveholding State from the Union, they determined that no more such States should be formed. For this purpose, they resolved to exclude the South from all the territories of the Union; so that no addition should ever be made to her power, while that of the North was allowed to increase with still greater rapidity. The North resolved, in fact, that every new State formed, and admitted into the Union, should be an accession to her own overgrown power. The South might object and complain; but what could she do ? Was she not already in a helpless minority ? If we count Delaware as a Southern State, then the North, instead of a majority of one State in the Senate, had a majority of three States, or of six votes, before the first Southern State seceded from the Union. There were eighteen Northern, and only fifteen Southern States repre sented in that branch of Congress; which was designed to act as a check on the majority in the House of Eepresentatives. Nor was this all. For there were, at that time, nearly ready to come into the Union Kansas, Minnesota, Oregon, Washington, Nebraska, Utah, and New Mexico, which would have made the Northern majority as overwhelming in that body as it was in the other branch of the Federal Legislature. If the tables had been turned, if the picture had been reversed, the North would have laughed such a Union to scorn. She could not even tol erate, indeed, the bare thought, or imagination, that the South might gain the ascendancy in the Senate in only one branch of the Federal Legislature. Thus, while the greedy North continued to grow in power, and in a determination to crush the South beneath her feet, she filled the earth with her clamors about "the aggressions of the slave power" ; appealing to the preju dices and passions of mankind in her crusade against an unknown and despised people. The South simply stood on the defensive. The one struggled for empire, for dominion ; the other for independence, for existence. The one struggled to preserve her original equality in the Union; the other to destroy that equality. The one directed all its efforts to uphold the balance of power established by the authors of the Constitution, and deemed THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 221 by them the only safeguard of freedom in the Union ; the other bent all its energies to break that balance, and grind its fragments to powder. Hence the South became extremely sensible of the dangers of her position in the Union. All hope of a "Constitutional power of defence 7 therein had been wrested from her grasp. That safeguard of her freedom and inde pendence, which the founders of the Eepublic deemed so essential to both ends of the Union, no longer existed for the South; and she held her rights and interests at the mercy of the North, as it was never intended she should hold them. She could see, therefore, as clearly as Pro fessor Cairnes, that the extinction of her freedom and independence was, sooner or later, her inevitable destiny in the Union. That dark destiny, however, she beheld with far other eyes than those with which it was contemplated by the Professor of Jurisprudence. Beholding, with delight, the ultimate ruin of the South in the Union, he denounced secession as treason and rebellion; but it is to be hoped that, in the estimation of mankind, it will not be deemed an unpardonable offence, if she was not entirely devoid of the natural instinct of self-preservation. Jefferson Davis, in the name of the South, gave utter ance to this natural instinct in the Senate of the United States in 1850. "The danger," said he, "is one of our own times, and it is that sectional division of the people which has created the necessity of looking to the question of the balance of power, and which carries with it, when dis turbed, the danger of disunion." Such was the treason of Jefferson Davis in 1850 ! But far bolder language had been used by Northern statesmen, and by Northern Legislatures, in behalf of the North ; not because the North was in a present or real, but only because she was in a future and purely imaginary, minority. The treason of the weak is the patriotism of the strong. THE BELATIVE DECLINE OF THE SOUTH IN THE NEW UNION It is a remarkable fact that from the first settlement of the country the South continued to increase in population THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES and wealth more rapidly than the North, till the new Union was established. In the Convention of 1787 it was, on all sides, conceded that the South surpassed the North both in population and in wealth. But from that event, from the inauguration of the "more perfect Union," her relative decline began. This fact has always been ascribed, by the enemies of the South, to the malign influence of the institution of slavery. But slavery existed before the new Union without producing any such effect. Hence, how ever great the evil influence of slavery may have been, it was not sufficient to counteract the great natural advan tages of the South, until the new Union came to its aid. The action of the Federal Government was, in the opinion of many impartial judges, the great cause of this relative decline of the South, in spite of the resources which nature, with a large and liberal hand, had lavished on her teeming soil and beneficent climate. The influence of this cause is well explained by a devoted friend to the Union. Eice and indigo were, says he, the great staples which, under the protection of the British Crown, had been the sources of the superior wealth of the South before the Eevolution. But under the protection, or rather under the neglect, of the Federal Government, these great interests languished, and these great staples were finally crushed out of the markets of the world by the hostile legislation of foreign powers. The decline of the South would have been as hopeless as it was rapid, if the cultivation of cotton, in consequence of several well- known improvements and inventions, had not become sufficiently remunerative to stand alone without the aid or support of the Federal Government. This great staple and source of wealth caused the South to revive. It not only arrested the sort of "galloping consumption" under which she was fast sinking into comparative insignificance, but it also restored her to something of the fulness and the glow of her former prosperity. But the North fixed her eagle eye on the rising prosperity of the South, and soon planted the talons of her tariffs deep in its very vitals. "The tariff question," says Mr. Ludlow, "may be easily disposed of." 1 He certainly disposes of it with very great 1 "Histoi-y," p. 305. THE WAR BETWEEX THE STATES 223 ease. A few prudently selected, and carefully trimmed, extracts from Mr. Benton are among the facile means he employs for the purpose. Let us, then, hear Mr. Benton himself, not in garbled extracts merely, but in the full, round utterance of great historic truths. Mr. Benton was no friend to the institution of slavery, or to its extension. In regard to this last most exciting question, he was decidedly with the North. But yet, unlike Mr. Ludlow and his school, Mr. Benton could both see and feel that some thing else beside slavery exerted an evil influence in the United States of America. Accordingly, in 1828, he uttered the following words in the Senate : "I feel for the sad changes which have taken place in the South during the last fifty years. Before the Eevolution it was the seat of wealth as well as of hospitality. Money and all it commanded abounded there. But how now? all this is reversed. Wealth has fled from the South and settled in the regions Xorth of the Potomac ; and this in the face of the fact that the South in four staples alone has exported produce since the Eevolution to the value of eight hundred millions of dollars; and the Xorth has exported com paratively nothing. Such an export Avould indicate un paralleled wealth, but what is the fact? In the place of wealth a universal pressure for money was felt not enough for current expenses the price of all property down the country drooping and languishing towns and cities decaying and the frugal habits of the people pushed to the verge of universal self-denial for the preservation of their family estates. Such a result is a strange and wonderful phenomenon. It calls upon statesmen to en quire into the cause." How did slavery produce this wonderful transformation ? How did slavery work all this ruin? Slavery, it is well known, existed before the Eevolution, as well as afterward ; and accompanied the South in the palmiest days of her prosperity, as well as in the darkest and most dismal hour of her adversity. Hence it was not, and could not have been, the one cause of so great and so sudden a change. And besides, instead of having ceased to produce, the fair and faithful South continued to pour forth, in greater 224= THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES abundance than ever, the broad streams of national pros perity and wealth. Hence she was impoverished, not because the fountains of her former supply had been dried up, or even diminished in volume, but because the great streams flowing from them did not return into her own bosom. Into what region of the earth, then, did these streams empty themselves? Mr. Ben ton answers this question! and though his answer is diametrically opposed to the views of the Bright and Cobden school, he is the great authority whom Mr. Ludlow himself had brought upon the stand. Under "Federal legislation," says Mr. Benton, "the exports of the South have been the basis of the Federal revenue. . . . Virginia, the two Carolinas, and Georgia may be said to defray three- fourths of the annual expense of supporting the Federal Government; and, of this great sum annually furnished by them, nothing or next to nothing is returned to them in the shape of Government expenditures. That expenditure flows in an opposite direction it flows northwardly in one uniform, unin terrupted, and perennial stream. This is the reason why wealth disappears from the South and rises up in the North. Federal legislation does all this. It does it by the simple process of eternally taking from the South and returning nothing to it. If it returned to the South the whole or even a good part of what it exacted, the four States south of the Potomac might stand the action of the system, but the South must be exhausted of its money and property by a course of legislation which is forever taking away and never returning anything. Every new tariff increases the force of this action. No tariff has ever yet included Virginia, the two Carolinas, and Georgia, except to increase the burdens imposed upon them.* Nor was Mr. Benton alone in this opinion. The politi cal economists of the North, such as Carey, Elliott, Kettell, and others, who had studied the sources of national wealth in America, gave precisely the same explanation of the sudden and wonderful disappearance of wealth from the South. The North might easily satisfy its own con science, by making slavery the scapegoat for its sins; but THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 225 thinking men, even at the North, were not so readily deceived. Hence, in an able work, entitled "Southern Wealth and Northern Profits/ the author does not hesi tate to tell the people of his own section that it was gross injustice, if not hypocrisy, to be always growing rich on the profits of slave-labor; and, at the same time, to be eternally taunting and insulting the South on account of slavery. Though it was bitterly denounced as "the sum of all villainies," it was, nevertheless, the principal factor in Northern wealth. In like manner, Professor Elliott, though a Northern man, and an enemy to slavery, yet, as a political econo mist, and teacher of the science in a Northern college, he denied that it had impoverished the South. On the con trary, he has, in a work styled "Cotton is King," shown that slave-labor has been one of the great sources of Northern wealth. Is it any wonder, then, that the think ing men of the South should have entertained the same opinion? Is it any wonder that they should have agreed with Benton, and Kettell, and Elliott, and other Northern writers that it was legislation, and not slavery, which had impoverished the South? It is certain that such was the conclusion of the thinking men of the South, in view of her sad and frightfully altered condition. "Such a result," says Mr. Benton, "is a strange and wonderful phenomenon. It calls upon statesmen to enquire into the cause ; and if they enquire upon the theater of this strange metamorphosis they will receive one universal answer from all ranks and ages, that it is Federal legis lation which has worked this ruin." If, under such cir cumstances or belief, the South has been satisfied with the action of the Federal Government, her people must have been the greatest of all simpletons, or the most patient of all saints. They were neither; they were merely human beings, who had some little regard for their own interests, as well as for those of their neighbors. Hence, the tariffs of the United States, by which one portion of the people was impoverished for the benefit of another portion of the people, left in the minds of the most influential men of the South a deep and abiding sense of the injustice of Northern legislation. 226 THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES What less could have been anticipated? All majorities are, in fact, unjust, despotic, and oppressive. Hence, in the opinion of the Convention of 1787, if either section should have the majority in both branches of Congress, it would oppress the other. As this opinion was founded on the experience of the past, so it was afterward confirmed by the history of the future. Indeed, if the North, with a majority in both branches of Congress, had not op pressed the South, it would have been unlike every other unchecked power in the history of the world. There have been, no doubt, lets, hindrances, and pauses in this onward march of the triumphant power of the North. But it has always had its eye fixed on one object of supreme desire, namely, on absolute dominion and control. It had already become absolutely overwhelming in one branch of Congress, with the certainty of soon be coming equally overwhelming in the other. There was not a member of the Convention of 1787, who, if his own section had been in the minority, would not have shrunk from such a Union with horror. He must, indeed, have been profoundly ignorant of the sentiments of the fathers, as well as of the character of all interested majorities, who, could have supposed, for a moment, that the South might have been free, or safe, or happy in such a Union. What ! is that freedom which is held at the mercy of another? Is that safety which depends on the will of an interested majority ? What was to have been expected from such a majority is well described in the speeches of John C. Calhoun; in the "Essay on Liberty," by John Stuart Mill; and in the celebrated work of De Tocqueville on "Democracy in America." Both De Tocqueville and Mill are advocates of democracy; and yet, if possible, they draw more fright ful pictures of the tyranny of an unchecked majority than has John C. Calhoun himself. "The majority in that country [the United States]," says M. De Tocqueville, "exercise a prodigious, actual authority, and a moral influence which is scarcely less preponderant; no obstacles exist which can impede, or so much as retard its progress, THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 227 or which can induce it to heed the complaints of those whom it crushes upon its path." 1 But if such was the unprejudiced conclusion of a great philosophic observer, in 1833, what was to have been ex pected from a sectional majority, growing continually in greatness, in power, and in hatred of the sectional minority? Had the South no reason for her fears? If not, then De Tocqueville, and Mill, and Calhoun were the veriest simpletons that ever lived. If not, then the founders of the Republic had all read the history of their own times wrong, and wrote libels on the character of unshackled majorities ? M. De Tocqueville has told the exact truth. "This state of things," said he, in 1833, "is fatal in itself, and dangerous for the future. ... If the free institutions of America are ever destroyed that event may be attributed to the unlimited authority of the majority. Anarchy will then be the result, but it will have been brought about by despotism." 2 THE FORMATION OF A FACTION There is a vast difference between a political party and a faction. The one is legitimate, healthful, and conserva tive; the other is the fatal disease of which nearly all republics have perished. The one is united by principles, or designs, which persons in any part of the Republic may freely adopt and cherish; the other is animated by a "common interest, or passion," which is hostile to other interests of the same community. Now, the great object of the legislation of 1787 was to provide a remedy for the fatal effects of faction. "Among the numerous advantages," says The Federalist, "promised by a well-constructed Union, none deserves to be more accurately developed than its tendency to break and control the violence of faction. The friend of popular governments never finds himself so much alarmed for their character and fate, as when he contemplates their pro pensity to this dangerous vice. He will not fail, therefore, 1 "Democracy in America," vol. i, p. 301. 2 Ibid., p. 317. THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES to set a due value on any plan which,, without violating the principles to which he is attached, provides a proper cure for it." 1 Mr. Madison, the author of the above words, used still more impressive language on the same subject, in the Virginia Convention of 1788. "On a candid examination of history," he there said, "we shall find that turbulence, violence, and abuse of power, by the majority trampling on the rights of the minority, have produced factions and commotions, which, in republics, have, more frequently than any other cause, produced despotism. If we go over the whole history of ancient and modern republics, we shall find their destruction to have generally resulted from those causes. IF WE CONSIDER THE PECULIAR SITUATION OF THE UNITED STATES, AND WHAT ARE THE SOURCES OF THAT DIVERSITY OF SENTIMENT WHICH PERVADES ITS INHABIT ANTS, WE SHALL FIND GREATER DANGER TO FEAR THAT THE SAME CAUSES MAY TERMINATE HERE, IN THE SAME FATAL EFFECTS, WHICH THEY PRODUCED IN THOSE REPUBLICS." 2 Here, then, was the rock on which the new Republic was in the greatest danger of being dashed to pieces. Hence, Mr. Madison well adds: "This danger ought to be wisely guarded against." Otherwise the great republic must in evitably split on the rock of faction, and go to the bottom with the republics of the past. It was, therefore, the great object of the legislation of 1787 to guard the new Republic against the rise, or for mation, of a faction. This, as we have already seen, is well stated in The Federalist, as follows : "When a majority is included in a faction, the form of popular government en ables it to sacrifice to its ruling passion, or interest, both the public good and the rights of other citizens. To secure the public good, and private rights, against the danger of such a faction, and at the same time to preserve the spirit and the form of a popular government, is the great object to which our inquiries are directed. Let me add that it is the great desideratum by which alone this form of gov ernment can be rescued from the opprobrium under which it has so long labored, and be recommended to the esteem, and adoption of mankind." 3 1 No. x. - "Elliott s Debates," vol. iii, p. 109. No. x. THE WAE BETWEEN THE STATES 229 By what means, then, did the .legislators, of 1787 hope to remedy the evils of factions ; to subdue, if not to eradi cate, that fatal disease of republics ? Mr. Madison replies : "Perhaps, in the progress of this discussion, it will appear that the only possible remedy for those evils and means of protecting the principles of Eepublicanism, will be found in that very system which is now exclaimed against as the parent of despotism." 1 That is, in the new Union of 1787. Now where, and how, did the new Union provide "the only possible remedy" against the evils of faction? Ac cording to the view of Mr. Madison, and of the majority of the Convention of 1787, neither the North nor the South would be able to form itself into a dangerous faction; because, as they said, each section will have a majority in one branch of Congress, and thereby hold a Constitutional check on the power of the other. But this remedy, as every one knows, proved a total failure. The other great remedy against the evils of faction, which, as the legislators of 1787 supposed, existed in the new system, would be found in the great extent of the Union, in the great number and diversity of its interests, which would prevent "any one party being able to out number and oppress the rest." 2 This remedy against fac tion is repeatedly urged by Mr. Madison. Thus, he speaks of the new Union "as the proper antidote for the diseases of faction, which have proved fatal to other popular gov ernments, and of which alarming symptoms have been betrayed by our own"; 3 because "the influence of factious leaders," who "may kindle a flame within their particular States," . . . "will be unable to spread a great con flagration through the other States." 4 Now this great remedy also proved a failure. Factious leaders did kindle a conflagration through all the Northern States; and the great North, animated by one "passion, or interest," did form itself into the most terrible faction the world has ever seen, and point all the lightnings of its wrath at the devoted South. 1 "Elliott s Debates," vol. iii, p. 109. 2 The Federalist, No. xiv. 3 Ibid. 4 Ibid., No. x. 230 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES The fact is not denied by many of the great champions of the Northern power. On the contrary, it was made a ground of exultation and boasting by some of her most eloquent orators. Thus, it was said "no man has a right to be surprised at this state of things. It is just what we have attempted to bring about. It is the first sectional party ever organized in this country. It does not know its own face, and calls itself national; but it is not national it is sectional. THE REPUBLICAN PARTY is A PARTY OF THE NORTH PLEDGED AGAINST THE SOUTH/ JI Nothing could have been more true. Thus, under and in spite of the Constitution designed for the protection of all sections and of all interests alike, the North did form itself into a faction, and seize all the powers of the Federal Govern ment. This may have been rare sport to the leaders of the faction; it was the death-knell of the Republic. It was the founders of the Union themselves being the judges the fall of the Republic, and the rise of a despotism. This faction, it is said, did "not know its own face." Perhaps it was a little ashamed of its own face. It is certain that it was very loud in its professions that all its designs were national and Constitutional; even while it avowed the purpose to "use all Constitutional means to put an end to the institution of slavery." But no such means were known to the Constitution, which, as the leaders of that faction perfectly well knew, was estab lished and ordained to protect all the institutions of the South, as well as of the North. Use all Constitutional means indeed ! Why, the very existence of such a faction was an outrageous violation of the whole spirit and design of the Constitution of 1787. It was, in one word, the last throe of the mighty Republic, as it succumbed to the fatal disease of which so many republics had previously per ished. Conceived in profound contempt of the wisdom of Washington, who, in his "Farewell Address," had so solemnly warned his countrymen against the dangers of a sectional party, or faction, it just marched right onward in the light of its own eyes over broken Constitutions, and laws, and oaths; trampling on all alike with imperial scorn and proud disdain. 1 Wendell Phillips. THE WAE BETWEEN THE STATES 231 The South was advised to "wait for some overt act." But if one finds himself in company with a strong man armed, who is both able and willing to crush him, is it wise to "wait for the overt act," or to withdraw from his society as soon as possible? If the strong man armed should make his withdrawal the occasion of his ruin, that would only prove that the companionship was neither safe, nor desirable. The South, it is true, did not better her condition by her withdrawal from the North. But is not all history replete with similar instances of failure in the grand struggle for freedom, safety, and independence? In the golden words of The Federalist: "Justice is the end of government. It is the end of civil society. It ever has been, and it ever will be, pursued until it be obtained, or until liberty be lost in the pursuit." 1 It was thus, in the pursuit of justice, that the South lost her liberty. If she had not engaged in the pursuit she would have deserved to lose her liberty. The South, it was said, had nearly always been in the possession of the Government; and it was right, there fore, that the North should take possession of it in her turn. But this is one of the fictions of the North. The South never had possession of the Government at all. All the great powers of the Government are, for the most part, lodged in the Congress of the United States, in neither branch of which did the South ever have a major ity. She was, indeed, when she entered into the new Union, promised a majority in one branch of Congress; but that promise, like an apple of Sodom, soon turned to dust and ashes in her hands. Nor had the South, as such, ever had a President of the United States. The great Democratic party generally selected its President from the South, but this did not make them sectional Presidents. Neither Washington, nor Jefferson, nor Madison, nor Monroe, nor Jackson, nor Polk was a sectional President. On the contrary, so little was there of a sectional nature in their characters, or designs, that each and every one of them was elected to 1 NO. n. 232 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES the Presidency of the United States by a large majority of the Northern votes. Mr. Lincoln, on the other hand, who was a sectional candidate, and put forth on purely sectional grounds, did not receive a single Southern vote. He was, then, the candidate not of a legitimate party, but of the great unconstitutional and anti-republican faction of 1861 ; that is, the candidate of "the party of the North pledged against the South." The North, with a majority in both houses of Congress, was perfectly protected against every possible danger of oppression. If, then, a statesman from the South had always filled the office of President, still her situation would have been far more precarious and unprotected than that of the North. The President could introduce no bill into Congress; he could only veto those which he might deem unjust and oppressive. Surely, a most feeble and uncertain protection to the South; since no man stood the least chance for the Presidency, who was not known to favor the wishes and the interests of the mighty North. The North, then, in possession of both branches of Congress, and the dazzling prize of the Presidency to influence the leading politicians of the South, was suffi ciently secure in the Union ; even if all the Presidents had come from the South. But all this did not satisfy the North. On the false plea that the South had nearly always been in possession of the Government, she deter mined to take possession of all its departments, the supreme Executive, as well as both branches of the Federal Legis lature. Nor is this all. She determined to take and to keep possession of them all in the name of the North, alleging that the South had enjoyed them all long enough ; and to wield them all by the terrible faction of "the North pledged against the South." Nor was this all. The great leader, or the great tool, of this faction declared that he was not bound by the decisions of the Supreme Court of the United States ; that he would enforce the Constitution as he understood it, and not as it was understood by that high judicial tribunal. Indeed, this mighty faction was got up and organized in direct opposition to, and in open THE WAE BETWEEN THE STATES 233 contempt of, the decisions of the Supreme Court of the United -States; both in the Dred Scott case, and in the case of Prigg vs. the Commonwealth of Pennsylvania. Its own will was its only law. The decision of the Supreme Court in the case of Prigg, which authorizes the master to seize his fugitive slave without process in any State of the Union, was the first object of attack by the great leaders of this faction. The Court was denounced as having been corrupted by pro- slavery sentiments ; though this very opinion was delivered by a Northern abolitionist, by Mr. Justice Story himself. Mr. Justice Story could, as we have seen, go great lengths in his advocacy of the Northern cause ; but yet, as a Judge of the Supreme Court of the United States, he could not decide in direct and open violation of his oath of office. This instance of his integrity, in which other Northern Judges concurred, brought down the indignation and contempt of the great leaders of the Republican party upon the Court, whose opinion he had delivered. It was then threatened by those factious leaders that the Supreme Court of the United States should be reorganized, and made to conform to the wishes and sentiments of the North; a purpose which was sure of its fulfilment after the election of Mr. Lincoln, and which would have capped the climax of the lawless designs of the Northern faction "pledged against the South." Mr. Madison, "the father of the Constitution," believed that such a faction would never arise in the new Union. But he never doubted, for a moment, that if it should arise therein, this would prove that the Federal Government had failed to answer the great end of his creation. For, as we have seen, it was, in his own words, the great object of that Government, "to secure the public good, and private rights against the danger of such a faction," by providing against the possibility of its appearance in the bosom of the Republic. This is the great desideratum, which, ac cording to the legislators of 1787, is necessary to remove "the opprobrium under which that form of Government has so long labored," and "to recommend it to the esteem and adoption of mankind" ; and which they supposed had 234 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES been supplied by their legislation. But their remedies were too weak. Their practice was not sufficiently heroic. Hence the fatal disease of republics, the rise of faction, was not only engendered, but developed to a degree which is without a parallel in the history of the world. The design was good, but the execution defective. The fathers, in one word, did not begin to foresee the weakness, the folly, the madness of their descendants. Hence, their sublime attempt to "establish justice, ensure domestic tranquillity, promote the general welfare, and secure the blessings of liberty to their posterity" proved an awful failure. Indeed, if they could only have witnessed the gigantic and terrific faction of 1861, they would have pronounced their own "grand experiment" a disastrous failure. It was so regarded by the South; and, for that reason, the South wished to make an experiment for her self. But, unfortunately, she was already in the clutches of a relentless and a remorseless faction. Factions have no heart, no conscience, no reason, no consistency, no shame. Would you reason with such a remorseless monster ? You might just as well read the riot act to a thunderstorm. Would you appease its wrath? Would you soothe its rampant and raging ferocity? Would you appeal to all the tender mercies of our holy religion? You might just as well sing a lullaby to the everlasting roarings of the Pit. The South did not enter into the "new Union" to be governed by any such faction. She entered into the new Union, on the contrary, in order to secure her freedom, her independence, her happiness, her glory ; and she lost them all except her glory. Even Mr. Madison, with all his devotion to the great work of his own hands, never became so blind an idolater as to resemble that epitome of meanness and climax of servility "an unconditional Union-man." On the con trary, still breathing the spirit of a freeman, he said : "Were the plan of the Convention adverse to the public happiness, my voice would be, Reject the plan. Were the Union itself inconsistent with the public happiness, it would be, ABOLISH THE UNION. ?n Even as late as 1830, 1 The Federalist, No. xlv. THE WAE BETWEEN THE STATES 235 he declared that "it still remains to be seen whether the Union will answer the ends of its existence or otherwise." If he had lived till 1861 he would have seen that the Union, having failed to prevent the rise and reign of fac tion, had not answered "the great object" of its creation; and, consequently, no longer deserved to exist. Hence, in 1861, he would either have unveiled the right of seces sion, or else he would have belied all the great principles, and sentiments, and designs of his life. OTHEE CAUSES OF SECESSION The foregoing grounds or causes of secession are, it seems to me, amply sufficient to justify the South in the exercise of a Constitutional right; for which she was amenable to no tribunal on earth, except to the moral sentiments of mankind. But there are still other and powerful causes of secession, which it is unnecessary to discuss in the present work. All the grounds of secession, including those above considered, may be stated as follows : the destruction of the balance of power, which was originally established between the North and the South; and which was deemed by the authors of the Con stitution to be essential to the freedom, safety, and happi ness of those sections of the Union. Secondly, the sectional legislation, by which the original poverty of the North was exchanged for the wealth of the South; contrary to the great design of the Constitution, which was to establish the welfare of all sections alike, and not the welfare of one section at the expense of another. Thirty, the formation of a faction, or "the party of the North pledged against the South," in direct and open violation of the whole spirit and design of the new Union ; involving a failure of the great ends for which the Eepublic was ordained. Poiirthly^ the utter subversion and contemptuous dis regard of all the checks of the Constitution, instituted and 236 THE WAK BETWEEN THE STATES designed by its authors for the protection of the minority against the majority; and the lawless reign of the Northern Demos. ^HW^fj the unjust treatment of the slavery question, by which the compacts of the Constitution made by the North in favor of the South were grossly violated by her; while., at the same time, she insisted on the observance of all the compacts made by the South in her own favor. Sixthly, the sophistry of the North, by which she attempted to justify her injustice and oppression of the South. Seventhly, the abuse and slander heaped on the South by the writers of the North. Eighthly, the denial of the right of secession; the false statements, and the false logic by which that right was concealed from the people of the North; and the threats of extermination in case the South should dare to exercise that right. These, it is believed, are the principal causes by which the last hope of freedom for the South in the Union was extinguished ; and, consequently, she determined to with draw from the Union. Bravely and boldly did she strike for Liberty ; and, if she fell, it was because, as the London Times said, "she had to fight the world." CHAPTEE XVII THE LEGISLATOES OF 1787 AS POLITICAL PROPHETS INTRODUCTORY "EVERY particular interest," said Mr. Madison, in the Convention of 1787, "whether in any class of citizens, or any description of States, ought to be secured as far as possible. Wherever there is danger of attack there ought to be given a Constitutional power of defence." But he contended that the States were divided into different interests, not by their difference of size, but from other circumstances; the most material of which resulted partly from climate, but principally from the effects of their hav ing or not having slaves. These two causes concurred in forming the great division of interests in the United States. It did not lie between the large and small States. It lay between the Northern and Southern; AND, IF ANY DEFENSIVE POWER WERE NECESSARY, IT OUGHT TO BE MUTUALLY GIVEN TO THESE TWO INTERESTS. 1 In this opinion of the leading member from Virginia, the leading member from Massachusetts fully concurred. For Mr. King "was fully convinced that the question concerning a difference of interest did not lie where it had been hitherto discussed, between the great and the small States, but between the Southern and the Eastern. For this reason he had been willing to yield something in the proportion of representation for the security of the Southern/ 72 That is, for the protection of the Southern interest, he had, as we have seen., been willing to vote for the fractional repre sentation of slaves. Such was, indeed, the opinion of the Convention. But while the legislators of 1787 agreed in this opinion, they looked into the future with very different eyes. Considered as political prophets they may, in fact, be divided into three classes. 1 "The Madison Papers," D. 1006. 2 Ibid., p. 1057. 238 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES JAMES MADISON At the head of the first class there stands James Madi son, "the father of the Constitution." Seeing, as he did, that the great difficulty before the Convention was to ad just the antagonism between the Forth and the South, he must have known that the perpetuity of the new Union would depend on the manner in which this difficulty should be settled by their labors. Just before the meeting of the Convention, indeed, this great antagonism had given birth to a tremendous conflict between the North and South, by which the Union was shaken to its foundations. Hence, Mr. Madison had good reason to fear the violence of this antagonism for the future: and he did fear it. For he tells us that there ought to be given a Constitutional power of defence to each of these sections, so that neither could take advantage of the other. He hoped, he fancied, he predicted that this had been done. The South, he said, would soon have a majority in the House of Bepresentatives, in consequence of the rapid increase in her population, by which she would hold a check on the power of the North. But this adjustment of the great difficulty in question rested on the unstable and fluctuating basis of population. It soon proved to be a foundation of sand. The hope and the prediction of Mr. Madison soon appeared to have been a delusion and a dream. He staked the freedom, the safety, and the happi ness of the South on the happening of a future event, which never came to pass. Indeed, he did not urge his plan for the adjustment of the formidable antagonism in question, because, as he said, it suggested a difficulty which was too apt to arise of itself. It was, therefore, never adjusted at all, on any solid foundation, or secure principle; and, consequently, it did continue to arise of itself, and disturb the new Union with convulsions from the beginning of its career to the grand explosion of 1861. Mr. Madison always feared the effects of this great and imperfectly adjusted antagonism between the North and the South. It seems, indeed, as if he wished to hide it from THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES 239 his own eyes, as well as from those of the people. It is a very remarkable fact that although, in the secret Conven tion of 1787, he pronounced the antagonism between the Northern and the Southern States the greatest of all the difficulties they had to deal with; yet, when, in The Federalist, he enumerated the difficulties the Convention had to encounter, no allusion whatever is made to this stupendous one. He seems to have imagined that, since it is so apt to arise of itself, the less that is said about it the better. This would, no doubt, have been very wise and prudent, if a great danger might be remedied by simply closing one s eyes upon its existence. Nothing more easily disturbed his patience than any allusion to the great danger created by the fearful antago nism in question. In The Federalist how unlike his usual style ! he pours forth the following strain of lachry mose philanthropy or patriotism : "Hearken not to the unnatural voice, which tells you that the people of America, knit together as they are by so many cords of affection, can no longer live together as members of the same family; can no longer continue mutual guardians of their mutual happiness. . . . No, my countrymen, shut your ears against this unhallowed language. Shut your hearts against the poison which it conveys. The kindred blood which flows in the veins of American citizens, the mingled blood which they have shed in the defence of their sacred rights, consecrates their union, and excites horror at the idea of their becoming aliens, rivals, enemies." 1 Yet, in spite of all this, Mr. Madison himself must have had serious misgivings with respect to his beautiful dream of a perpetual peace. For he knew, as we have seen, that there was a danger of a collision between the North and the South. It is certain that the voice which he pro nounced unnatural was the voice of truth. For American citizens did become aliens, rivals, enemies; and mingled their blood far more freely and fearfully than they ever had done in the defence of their common rights. But Mr. Madison knew that, in order to secure the adoption 1 No. xiv. 240 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES of the new Union, it would be necessary to persuade the people that the very first condition of such a Union would always obtain; namely, "a sufficient amount of sympathy among its populations." Hence, perhaps, his dream of peace was not all a dream, but partly rhetoric. OTHER PROPHETIC VIEWS The second class of prophets seems to have been with out a head. Indeed it may, perhaps, be doubted whether they spoke as prophets, or as diplomatists. It is certain that they encouraged the notion of Mr. Madison and other Southern legislators that the South would certainly have a majority in the House of Eepresentatives. Several of the most influential of the Northern legislators seemed quite confident that such would be the good fortune of the South; and none more so than Mr. Gouverneur Morris. But were they always sincere in their belief ? Or did they sometimes flatter the false hopes of the South in order to be able to drive a better bargain with her? No finite mind can, perhaps, answer these questions ; or tell whether the legislators in question always spoke as prophets, or sometimes as diplomatists. It is certain that the expecta tion held out to the South, that she would be able to control one branch of Congress, was the promise, the prospect, the bait by which she was entrapped into the new Union; into that tremendous dead-fall, by which, in 1861, she was crushed to the earth. Patrick Henry stood at the head of the third and last class of prophets. No man ever more clearly foresaw, or more confidently predicted, the future than did Patrick Henry the calami ties which have fallen on his beloved Virginia. With some of the passages from this class of prophets, I shall con clude this little book. General Pinckney, of South Carolina, declared, that "if they [the Southern States] are to form so considerable a minority, and the regulation of trade is to be given to the General Government, they will be nothing more than over seers for the Northern States/ 1 1 "The Madison Papers," p. 1058. THE WAB BETWEEN THE STATES 241 In like manner,, Mr. Williamson, of North Carolina, said: "The Southern interest must be extremely endan gered by the present arrangement. The Northern States are to have a majority in the first instance, with the means of perpetuating it." 1 George Mason said : "He went on a principle often ad vanced, and in which he concurred, that a majority, when interested, would oppress the minority. This maxim [than which none is more just] had been verified in the Legislature of Virginia. If we compare the States in this point of view, the eight Northern States have an interest different from the five Southern States; and have, in one branch of the Legislature, thirty-six votes against twenty- nine, and in the other in the proportion of eight to three. The Southern States had, therefore, grounds for their suspicions." 2 Mr. Henry said : "But I am sure that the dangers of this system are real, when those who have no similar inter ests with the people of this country [i. e., Virginia and the South] are to legislate for us when our dearest interests are to be left in the hands of those whose advantage it will be to infringe them." 3 In the same Convention, Mr. Grayson, after declaring that it was a struggle between the North and the South for empire, proceeded to say : "Are not all defects and corruptions founded on an inequality of representation and want of responsibility? My greatest objection is that it will, in its operation, be found unequal, grievous and op pressive. If it have any efficacy at all, it must be by a faction of one part of the Union against another. If it be called into action by a faction of seven States, it will be terrible indeed. We must be at no loss how this combina tion will be formed. There is a great difference of cir cumstances between the States. The interests of the carrying States are strikingly different from those of the productive States. I mean not to give offence to any part of America, but mankind are governed by interest. The carrying States will assuredly unite and our situations will 1 "The Madison Papers." p. 1058. - Ibid., p. 1387. "Elliott s Debates." vol. iii. p. 2X0. 242 THE WAR BETWEEN THE STATES then be wretched indeed. We ought to be wise enough to guard against the abuse of such a government. Kepublics, in fact, oppress more than monarchies/ "The voice of tradition," said Henry, "1 trust will in form posterity of our struggles for freedom. If our de scendants be worthy .of the name of Americans, they will preserve and hand down to the latest posterity the trans actions of the present times, and, though I confess my ex planations are not worth the hearing, they will see I have done my utmost to preserve their liberty ." Tyler responded, "I also wish to hand down to posterity my opposition to that system. British tyranny would have more tolerable." THE END 14 DAY USE RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED LOAN DEPT. This book is due on the last date stamped below, or ltnrrhnriiinliii-1 im| Renewed to iate recall. MAR 7 196J NQV 1 6 Iflfig^O Q ^ JUN 467-fcSpM PfeS* C9 LD 4. HAY 12 64-8PM LD 21A-50w-12, 60 (B6221slO)476B General Library University of Califc Berkeley OI92 RETURN TO the circulation desk of any University of California Library or to the NORTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY Bldg. 400, Richmond Field Station University of California Richmond, CA 94804-4698 ALL BOOKS MAY BE RECALLED AFTER 7 DAYS 2-month loans may be renewed by calling (510)642-6753 1-year loans may be recharged by bringing books to NRLF Renewals and recharges may be made 4 days prior to due date DUE AS STAMPED BELOW 5 2004 DD20 15M 4-02