ERSKINE ON THE LIMITS OF TOLERATION By THEODORE SCHROEDER, of the New York Bar * * * MONG English speaking people, Thomas Erskine is quite the only man who has rendered either conspicuous or effective service, in the forensic defense of a larger freedom of speech. Some of his ut- terances, upon this subject, are judicially quoted as au- thority upon the meaning of our constitutional guaran- tees for unabridged liberty of utterance. This raises the question how far may we properly quote Erskine as such an authority? What were his real convictions about the limits of toleration? Should it be considered hazardous to quote, as authority, isolated passages from Erskine's speeches, for the purpose of justifying the limi- tation of toleration, even though we could be positive that he was always untrammelled in the absolutely frank expression of his opinion upon this subject? It is regrettable that Erskine left no academic discus- sion freely and fully setting forth in unequivocal terms just what was his opinion about a legally limited tolera- tion. At least to lawyers, it must be manifest that in the defense of an accused, under conditions then existing for Erskine, the exigencies of professional duty usually would preclude any lawyer from defending a belief in wnabridged freedom of speech, even though he actually believed in it. Under the English system it would have been absurd to have based a defense upon the broad proposition that the unwritten constitution prohibited all laws anywise abridging freedom of utterance. In his contentions, as to what was the existing law under which he was serving a defendant, it became Erskine's plain duty to claim, or defend, no broader principles of liberty than were necessary for the acquittal of each particular I client. In and for the purposes of every case defended by him, his manifest obligation and interest was to as- sume for his client the least possible burden, and this obligation tended to induce the maximum of conces- sions, to the prosecution, consistent with the acquittal of his client. His duty to his client was to secure the most favorable interpretation of the existing laws then abridging freedom of speech and not to indulge in aca- demic discussions for their ultimate total abolition. These considerations impose the inference that even if Erskine had believed in unabridged freedom of utterance, its defense could hardly have been the essence of his fo- rensic discussions, and, if in these it found expression at all, it would be only in an inadvertent or incidental way. This brings me back to the question: Did Erskine really believe in the unabridged liberty for the utterance of ones opinions? If not, his opinions can not be prop- erly used as an aid to the interpretation of our constitu- tional guarantees. If he did believe in unabridged free- dom of speech, then, it seems to me, our courts have per- verted his sentiments in order to make them an author- ity for the curtailment of our liberty, in spite of our constitutions. May it not be that our courts have ignored Erskine's real opinions, to explain away our constitu- tional guarantees by quoting, from Erskine, isolated passages, dictated by expediency, or expressing only the facts of practice, under a system of limited liberty by permission, and so actually misrepresenting the real Erskine, by mistaking such utterances as general stand- ards by which to define and determine the existence of unabridged freedom of speech. It does seem to me that in this matter, if we content ourselves with such superficiality as our courts have used, it would be very easy to prove that Erskine did not at all believe in unabridged freedom of speech, and there- fore is not in the least an authority on the construction of the free-speech clauses of our constitutions. Did not Erskine successfully prosecute Paine's Age of Reason which no public prosecutor, or court, in America has ever asserted to be beyond the protection of our consti- 2: tutional guarantees of free speech? The editor of Er- skine's speeches, as published in 1810, commenting upon the apparent conflict between his speech prosecuting Paine’s “Age of Reason” and that other speech of his in defense of Paine’s “Right of Man,” and evidently wishing to establish for Erskine a reputation for gen- eral conservatism, said of his defenses of liberty that these “we can only consider as the argument of an advocate bound to give the best assistance to a client,” but that speech of Erskine's demanding the abridgment of freedom of the press, the editor assures us, “may be considered as containing his [Erskine's] own opinions and principles.” " When we thus find Erskine cited as an authority both for and against unabridged freedom of speech, we are forced to conclude that his real opinions on the limits of toleration must be found, if found at all, in those little incidental indiscretions of his arguments, which are deemed indiscretions because unnecessary to the imme- diate purposes of his client's defense, and in the nature of a claim against his interests, because a claim of either too much or too little, for his client's good. At times such indiscretions are quite unavoidable to persons very much in earnest, and they arise out of the psychologic difficulty of adhering to the limitations of a special plea, when such limitations conflict with, or do not include all that is essential to a correct portrayal of the pleader's convictions. Did Erskine portray his real convictions by any such inadvertencies? To my mind, one of the essential tests of unabridged freedom of speech is this, that no man shall be punished criminally for any utterance of his, upon any subject, no matter how offensive, or how dangerous may be its tendency, when that tendency is only speculatively, pro- spectively and imaginatively ascertained. This admits the right to indulge, with impunity, even in the fruitless advocacy of “treason” and of course the lesser crimes, and demands that men should not be punished for a * Erskine's Speeches, Vol. 2, p. 183-184. --> • 3 mere psychologic offense, unconnected with criminal in- tent and with overt acts of invasion, or with any actually ascertained and resultant material injury.” How then did Erskine stand with reference to, un- abridged freedom of speech, according to this test, which requires that speech, merely as such, shall always be free, and that actual and material resultant injury, or an act with the imminent danger thereof, according to the known laws of the physical universe, shall be always one of the conditions precedent to the punishment of a mere speaker? Intent should be another. The following extracts from Erskine's published speeches are the answers to my question. These are the spontaneous inadvertencies which I believe portray his real convictions upon this issue now under consideration. The italics used are mine.” “I maintain that opinion is free, and that conduct alone is amenable to law. “The principle is this that every man, while he obeys the laws [prohibiting invasive acts], is to think for him- self, and to communicate what he thinks. The very ends of society exact this license, and the policy of the law, in its provisions for its security, has tacitly sanctioned it. The real fact is, that writing against a free and well pro- portioned government, need not be guarded against by laws. They cannot often exist and never with effect.” “ “I am not contending for uncontrolled conduct, but for freedom of opinion.” " “Chief Justice Wright (no friend to the liberty of the subject) * * * * interrupted him [The Attorney Gen- eral] and said, ‘Yes, Mr. Attorney, I will tell you what they offer, which it will lie upon you to answer; they would have to show the jury how this petition HAS *For a more complete statement and justification of this view see Central Law Journal, Mch. 26, 1909, and Mch. 7 to 28, 1910; MoTHER EARTH, June 1907-May 1910. These will be incorporated in “Obscene Literature and Constitutional Law” now in press. * Erskine's Speeches, Vol. 2, p. 104, Paine Case. “Erskine's Speeches, Vol. 2, p. 133, Paine Case. "Erskine's Speeches, Vol. 2, p. 159, Paine Case. 4. disturbed, the government, or diminished the King's authority.” So say I. I will have Mr. Bearcroft [the attorney, then prosecuting] show you gentlemen [of the jury] how this Dialogue [of the Dean of Asaph which was the basis of the charge] HAs disturbed the King's government, excited disloyalty and disaffection to his person, -and stirred up disorder within these kingdoms.” " } “It is easy" to distinguish where the public duty calls for the violation of the private one; criminal intention but not indecent levities, not even grave opinions uncon- nected with conduct are to be exposed to the Magistrate.”" . “Constructed by man to regulate human infirmities, and not by God to guard the purity of angels, it [the venerable law of England] leaves to us our thoughts, our opinions and our conversations and PUNISHEs on LY overt Acts, of contempt and disobedience to her authority. Gentlemen, this is not the specious phrase of an advocate for his client, it is not even my exposition of the spirit of our constitution; but it is the phrase and letter of the law itself.” " 4. “What is it that has lately united all hearts and voices in lamentation? What but these judicial execu- tions, which we have a right to style murders, when we see the axe falling, and the prison closing upon the genuine expressions of the inoffensive heart; sometimes for private letters to friends, unconnected with conduct or intention; sometimes for momentary exclamations in favor of royalty or some other denomination of govern- ment different from that which is established.”.” e These statements of general principle, made by Erskine, and usually quite outside the necessary issues of the cases in which they were uttered, I believe give us warrant for asserting that he believed in unabridged freedom of speech as a natural right, and that by "Erskine's Speeches, Vol. 1, p. 205, St. Asaph's Case. "Erskine's Speeches, Vol. 2, p. 343, Frost Case. "Erskine's Speeches, Vol. 2, p. 346, Frost Case. * * Erskine's Speeches, Vol. 2, p. 353, Frost Case. • * sº - 5 l unabridged freedom of speech he meant substantially the same thing as that for which I have contended. However, it must be admitted that, notwithstanding his repeated clear enunciation of the general principle that no guilt can be predicated except upon overt act and criminal intent, it was not always consistently reaffirmed by him in all particular cases. The prosecution of aine's “Age of Reason” is an example. The exi- É. of professional obligation adequately explains is seeming inconsistency, and it is possible that his religious and emotional nature also had something to do with the seeming inability to make conclusive deductions from his general principles to every specific case that came within them. The English governmental machinery certainly left Erskine quite helpless, in his efforts to secure the adoption of these general principles into the juridical system. Only two methods were open. The one was to secure a written constitution, such as it was once supposed obtainable in America, inhibiting all legislative abridgment of freedom of speech; and the second was to secure a universal acceptance of his general principle and its application to every conceivable case, such as is essential to make a constitutional prohibition effective, and which principle might occasionally be made effective without a written constitution, if juries could be per- mitted to rejudge the law for themselves. Erskine lived long enough to see, in America, the passage of the Alien and Sedition law, in spite of the restraint of our American constitution, and this showed him how useless are paper constitutions, if the people do not possess an enlightened view of the pernicious power which such constitutions are intended to destroy. Perhaps he even foresaw this in 1793 when he made his famous statement before the “Friends of Liberty of the Press,” wherein he, seemingly at least, abandoned his oft repeated demand for absolute certainty in the criteria of guilt.” In this carefully prepared statement * For this demand see, in the edition of 1810, as follows: Vol. 1, pp. 72-73-77-78-129-182-186-331-333-334-337; pp. 143-162-190-268; 6 he said this: “The extent of the genuine Liberty of the press on general subjects, and the boundaries which separate them from licentiousness, the English law has wisely not attempted to define; they are indeed in their nature undefinable; and it is the office of the jury alone to ascertain them.” ” This statement was made in support of his contention that juries should be author- ized to decide the law as well as the facts. I said Erskine seemingly abandoned this demand, but it was only seemingly, for in this same paper he again denounces the uncertainty of the laws for seditious libel, and the infamous system of spy-societies which then, as now, inflict their unctuous piousity on a dull, and consequently patient, public. So then I conclude that Thomas Erskine was a true believer in a real unabridged liberty of utterance, where no man could be punished so long as the mere verbal portrayal of his ideas is the only factor involved. In England, about a century ago, Thomas Erskine, with such a record, was made Lord High Chancellor. In America, at the present time, such statements would put him only in the class “undesirable citizen” to be specially criticised, and denounced as an anarchist especially by many of those claiming to be “liberals” or “radicals,” of the “respectable” type. Thus we have another illustration that English royalty a century ago was less afraid of real liberty than the American mass of today; and herein we also see how the very essence of tyranny thrives under the forms of democracy. With us every stupid policeman, fanatical judge, or moralist for revenue, can successfully abridge freedom of speech by the lawless use of power, and the hysterical mob of pretending lovers of liberty and democracy will stand by and applaud, so low have we fallen since our American Constitutions were written. Vol. 3, pp. 338-356-439-497; Vol. 4, pp. 436–437. For my own litera- ture on this subject see “Due Process of Law in Relation to Statutory Uncertainty and Constructive Offenses,” and Cent. Law Journ., Dec. 18, 1909. All these and other articles of mine with appear soon in “Obscene Literature and Constitutional Law.” * Erskine’s Speeches, Vol. 4, p. 439. 7 * & “. . MOTHER EARTH PUBLISHING ASS'N zio EAST 13th STREET, NEW YORK . . . - 1911 y * ** *- • * e * * * * g! 4- ass" * : * * * * s s ty * *** * * •. •º #. 3. e t t sº