Grad. R. R. 3 B 2779 •W 42 AN INTRODUCTIONS MICAL PHILOSO 中 ​│   THE PHILOSOPHICAL LIBRARY OF PROFESSOR GEORGE S. MORRIS, PROFESSOR IN THE UNIVERSITY, 1870-1889. Presented to the University of Michigan. Grad. R. RE B 2779 W-2. гро THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. Я. G. §. Morris м so.1.168%. THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT: BEING 61313 AN INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF THE "CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON." refred Egles BY ARCHIBALD WEIR, B.A. 1 = As the world has never been, and, no doubt, never will be, without a system of metaphysics of one kind or another, it is the highest and weightiest concern of philosophy to render it powerless for harm, by closing up the sources of error."-KAnt. LONDON: W. SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & ALLEN, PATERNOSTER SQUARE. 1881. J ! : Butler & Tanner, The Selwood Printing Works, Frome, and London. KUKLAA 14 **** nba PREFACE. WHILST preparing a small book to serve as an intro- duction to the study of modern philosophy, I neces- sarily found it incumbent on me to write a chapter giving a brief but intelligible account of the Critical Philosophy of Kant. But when I attempted to per- form this part of my work I encountered obstacles which seemed insuperable in the present state of our Kantian literature. For my limits were narrow, and yet it was imperative that my readers should obtain a competent acquaintance with this speculation. To refer to any works now extant would have been a contradiction of my purpose, in that my introductory efforts would have simply amounted to an indication of the works to whose comprehension it was my object to lead the student. Nevertheless, I wrote what I conceived to be wanted for an introduction to the study of Kant, but the result was far too extensive to form a chapter in a work of the moderate compass which I contemplated. Convinced, however, that something of the sort is required, I have determined to publish it alone quite independently of my main plan. vi PREFACE. I am well aware of the difficulties attending any attempt to make Kant's philosophy, and indeed any philosophy worthy of the name, easy to beginners with brevity, and I cannot expect to have avoided them all; but their nature is so palpable that it is as need- less for me to enumerate them as it is for me to do more than remind my reader of the indulgence which their existence entitles me to. From the beginning the purpose of this brief ex- position has been kept in view, to wit, a preliminary aid not only to the "Critique of Pure Reason" but also to the English writings on the same. My obligations therefore are especially great to Professor Edward Caird's "Critical Account of the Philosophy of Kant,” so great that it would be difficult to express them at all adequately. But perhaps it may be sufficient to say that, considering the place which Professor Caird's book has taken in our philosophical literature, unless the acknowledgments due to it from a work of this kind were excessive, its production would have little relevancy. My references are made to Professor Meiklejohn's translation of the "Critique." * ENFIELD, April, 1881. CONTENTS. CHAPTER I. PAGE 1 HISTORICAL RETROSPECT CHAPTER II. KANT AND TRANSCENDENTALISM 15 CHAPTER III. THE TRANSCENDENTAL ESTHETIC: 1. THE ARGUMENT 2. TRANSITION TO TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC CHAPTER IV. THE CATEGORIES, AND THEIR TRANSCENDENTAL DE- DUCTION: 1. THE CATEGORIES FOUND 2. THE CATEGORIES TRANSCENDENTALLY DEDUCED 33 37 41 49 CHAPTER V. SCHEMATISM: AND THE PRINCIPLES OF THE PURE UNDERSTANDING 1. SCHEMATISM AND SCHEMATA 2. PRINCIPLES 62 • 29 64 67 viii CONTENTS. CHAPTER VI. PAGE THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC: 1. THE LOGIC OF ILLUSION 79 2. THE IDEAS OF REASON 82 3. CRITICISM OF RATIONAL PSYCHOLOGY AND OF RATIONAL COSMOLOGY 4. CRITICISM OF RATIONAL THEOLOGY 5. CONCLUDING REMARKS 87 98 107 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. CHAPTER I. HISTORICAL RETROSPECT. In the fulness of time the Thought of our era asserted its rightful autonomy and emancipated itself from the timorous coddling of its foster nurse Dog- matics. In the place of the Church and Aristotle the absolute doubt of Descartes obtained the intellectual supremacy. Aware that an entirely new beginning had to be made, philosophy repudiated the past as a tale of sophistries and illusions, and, true to itself, assumed the position of utter scepticism. But only provisionally. Descartes found in self-consciousness a fact which forced scepticism to eat its own words: to say that I doubt everything, even my own existence, is to assert that I think the doubt; and from this fact he tried to establish the validity of the rest of what we least hesitate to call knowledge. Unfortunately this movement of his was incompatible with the B 2 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. original sceptical rigour. To the question, how can there be any correspondence between the individual and the universal? how can there be any commerce between two such heterogeneous existences as mind and matter? how can we have any confidence in the result of such commerce? he could only oppose an appeal to the veracity of God. Yet the question is a crucial one, and its solution is imperative. In the absence of knowledge innate in the mind, all our knowledge is derived from the outside world. Unless therefore this can be shown to be legitimately and correctly obtained, all human beliefs, hopes and fears depending thereon will be vain. Now it is the business of philosophy to account for the grounds of our beliefs, and thus it must be occupied with the first principles of empirical cognition, and with our innate mental equipment, if we have any. The latter point first recommends itself to consideration on the score of its priority, and Descartes appeared to follow the logical order of truth in commencing with it. But history was to show that it was difficult to retain any such division, and that, if the distinction were retained, yet experience generally furnished the text in order of exposition; in any case, the relation subsisting between subject and object always proved to be at once the deepest and most pressing problem for subsequent speculation. This problem indeed has possessed this character at all times, as it ever must till solved, and its discussion is even now of supreme in- terest. Here however we desire only to give a rapid HISTORICAL RETROSPECT. 3 sketch of its history, from its statement by Descartes up to the time when our writer received it. The inadequacy of Descartes' explanation soon appeared in the endeavours of his followers. The somewhat imposing appeal to the veracity of God, (the proof of whose existence nevertheless depended on our possession of a certain non-empirical idea,) had to be converted ere long into the invocation of a perpetual. miracle. Occasionalism¹ was the only detailed expres- sion possible of Descartes' doctrine, and this was as good as a confession that the doctrine did no more than restate the difficulty. John Locke it was, however, whom tradition credits with the decisive attack on Cartesian thought. There seems now to be no doubt that the "Essay concerning Human Understanding" might well have been provoked by the theories current among Locke's countrymen, if we are unwilling to be satisfied with Locke's own profession of its origin, and that if its polemic was directed solely against Descartes much injustice was done in the statement of his views. Nevertheless, it is from this Englishman that history traces that antagon- istic line of thought which ran its course for a time independently of its continental precursor, till the two converged at the point to which we are moving. . ¹ Arnold Geulinx was the most thoroughgoing exponent of this theory. According to it, on every occasion (hence the name) of the exercise of our will, God caused a corresponding movement in our corporeal members; similarly, on every occasion of the affection of our organs of sense, God caused a corresponding cognition in the mind. 4 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. L The thesis which Locke sought to maintain, and in somewise to develop, was the empirical origin of all our ideas. The antithesis which he aimed at subvert- ing was the innate and non-empirical origin of the most fundamental of the same. Our attention here must be turned to what he understood to be the experience which produced these important results. In one word, he conceived it to be Sensation. From sensation he believed that all our ideas might origin- ate, and to show how this came about the constructive portion of his book was written. He supposed that the mind was primarily a blank, a tabula rasa, on which matter acted through the senses. Further, the mind was presumed to be able to work up these im- pressions into a stock of ideas, all of which, however irreducible they might appear, were accordingly trace- able to sensible impressions. The impressing matter was identified with the primary qualities of objects, viz. extension and resistance; while colour, etc., as secondary qualities, were supposed to be but modes of the affection of this matter. Thus all our knowledge resulted from sensation, itself the affection of matter on our minds. In this theory there were two heterogeneous ele- ments united in a mechanical fashion. Mental affec- tions, sensations, a subjective element, on the one hand; matter in space affecting the organs of sense, an objective element, on the other. The first repre- sented the particular aspect of knowledge, the second the universal aspect. Both are indispensable, and HISTORICAL RETROSPECT. 5 10 Locke did well to neglect neither, though he failed to relate them organically. The sequel, however, manifested the fault. As was inevitable, since their combination was quite external, one element was emphasised by Locke's successors to the exclusion of the other. Cruder thinkers, delighting in some- thing tangible, seized upon the materialistic side of the theory; but subtler minds, determined to make no assumptions, concentrated their attention on the subjective aspect, and refused to think of anything which they could not feel as their own sensation. The two parties came into collision, and the more conscientious investigators came off the victors. The French encyclopædists and their rough and ready enlightenment do not concern our purpose here (unless we notice their relation to that sentence of Kant's which we have taken for a motto), nor indeed do any of those writers who espoused the cause of materialism. We only mention this section in refer- ence to their threatening attitude, which called forth the examination of their central tenet by Berkeley. This writer asked pertinently enough what matter is, and how it served as the prius of sensations. Re- fusing to make the illegitimate assumption of an inde- pendent spatial world with minds and matter moving about in it, he demanded the reduction of Locke's doctrines to their lowest terms. Propounding for the first time that theory of vision which, with some ad- ditions, is now generally held by scientific men, he converted our perceptions of an external world into 6 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. sensations and inferences derived therefrom. In thus doing, the subjective element in Locke's theory ren- dered the objective one needless and, in fact, contra- dictory. The fratricide was logically justifiable, and in spite of coxcombs' grins and the protests of common sense the independent existence of matter became untenable on the then received principles. This exclusively subjective view of knowing and being greatly changed the character of the current sensationalism. The chaos of sense could never again be turned into our cosmos by reference to an objective order. Unless philosophy somehow shifted its position, order and objectivity would have to be derived from subjective sensation, and the individual would become the measure of the universe. The truth of our experi- ence from this point of view could only be determined by discovering the cause of the individual's sensations and the secret of their cohesion into a world. Yet this could only be properly done by reference to other sensations, themselves requiring explanation, unless something else were called in to fill up the gap. As is well known, Berkeley filled up the void to his own satisfaction by the introduction of the Great Spirit, and deftly replaced the matter he dreaded by the God he served. But a hypothesis is unable to quiet curiosity allied with acuteness and unscrupulousness. A man of this stamp was alone required, to test still further the intrinsic value of sensation; and before long such a man was found. David Hume had no prepossessions or tendencies to HISTORICAL RETROSPECT. 7 prevent him from taking an impartial view of the state of philosophy. He was a man of letters, with the talents and the will to take things as they were and sift them. Pursuant to his calling, he candidly examined our experience on the principles of sensationalism. In his writings for the first time appeared an indication of the real worth of sensation, freed from all assump- tions covert or otherwise, as the ground of our know- ledge; and the real worth proved to be only capable of supporting scepticism. Hume's earlier "Treatise" was more thorough than attractive of popularity, and subsequently he gave a more exoteric exposition of his speculations in his Essays. Of course the first work is the one by which he ought to be judged; but the later redaction, with its main theme, is the force which the history of philo- sophy especially takes cognisance of in its narrative. Causation was its chief topic, a relation on which depends the entire security of what we think to be knowledge. Unless we can be assured of necessary sequence as a law of our experience, all that we think to be knowledge becomes contingent and valueless for reason. Accordingly, on the hypothesis that know- ledge is secure, the adequacy of sensation on this point may serve as an indication of its adequacy on others. Conversely, supposing that sensationalism is a true philosophy, its verdict on causation will serve as an indication of the security of what we call knowledge. Hume himself supposed that sensationalism was a true philosophy; and having determined that causation was THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. merely contingent sequence, that belief in it was solely due to habit and to an irrational propensity to feign, we have no difficulty in understanding how he came to his conclusion of scepticism. The way by which he arrived at this verdict respecting causation is no less obvious. Sense in its ultimate nature is only a flux of momentary stimulations, and contains in itself no other order or coherence than what is involved in this definition. The sensation of the moment therefore is the only thing of which we can be sure, and any such conception as that of necessary sequence is entirely meaningless. Knowledge in any sense of the term becomes impossible; at most we can attain to probability, for any extension of inference from the momentary sensation must be precarious. Such is the worth of knowledge in general; for the nature of the subject cannot escape the same contingency which has overtaken the object. We are but bundles of ideas, and personality is a manifest fiction. Both subject and object are thus the fabrications of our fancy from a sense phantasmagoria, and neither can be appealed to for help against the disheartening conclusions of scepticism.¹ ¹ In this statement I have drawn on the "Treatise,” and have not confined myself to the " Essays." The sequel will justify this deviation from historical tradition. It is not sufficient to attribute Kant's awakening from his "dogmatic slumber" to the "Inquiry's" denial of a causal nexus between things, for a proper understanding of the "Critique's " argument. Whatever be the precise personal relation between Hume and Kant, it is necessary to bear in mind from the first the truth respecting HISTORICAL RETROSPECT. 9 Mr. Lewes pronounces this scepticism to be the terminal morass of all consistent metaphysics, and forgets to consider whether after all it be not due to want of sufficient care in the use of that potent instrument, analysis, of whose possible misuse he was himself so well aware. A similar opinion has always pervaded our indigenous thought, and common sense and surreptitious assumptions have saved it from wanting plausibility. But the question as to the legitimacy of taking sense by itself as the sole factor in experience was asked in another country, and de- cided in the negative. This country was Germany, whence all philosophy other than suicidal comes to us. Meanwhile, speculation had not been confined to England. A very different line of thought had also worked itself out on the continent. Descartes had despaired of finding any prime certainty except in the individual's thought, and had set the fashion of look- ing therein for first principles. Just as sensation in England usurped reality, so therefore thought arro- the ultimate nature of sense indicated in the former's earlier work. Otherwise Kant's reasoning can have little cogency, since it is based on a similar but consistent view of sense, and would be off the point if it were admitted that sense alone could make a thing at all. But of this we shall have to speak again very soon. The student who fails to find satisfaction in Professor Huxley's uncritical dogmatism (Hume: English Men of Letters series) must consult Professor Green's "Introduc- tion to Hume," for a thorough comprehension of the merits of this sensational scepticism. 10 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. gated to itself the criterion of truth abroad. But inasmuch as this thought was that of the individual no less than sensation was, similar difficulties were involved respecting the relation existing between sub- ject and object. We cannot therefore wonder at the opinions of a mind trained in this school, of too un- settled life to permit sustained and coherent inquiry yet too great to be completely blinded by narrow and partial views, if they present to the superficial observer a somewhat grotesque appearance. Such was the case with the author of the System of Monads and the Pre-established Harmony; and it is therefore not improbable that these apparently curious inventions may be the imperfect expression of what is intrin- sically profound. Spinoza, that man of peace and sincerity who is receiving among ourselves his meed of admiration in these days of bustle and chicanery, whatever doubt there may be concerning his speculative pedigree, certainly appreciated the difficulties of individualism and sought to correct them by his universalism. But in thus doing he completely lost sight of the in- dividualising aspect of the problem, which is as important as the other, so much so that the question. of perception never appears with him;¹ and this is 66 ¹ Mr. Pollock justly remarks, as Lessing had done before, that on Spinoza's principles this problem vanishes. Cf. 'Spinoza, his Life and Philosophy," p. 213, and Mr. Sime's 'Lessing," vol. ii. p. 297. Nevertheless, it is of questionable advantage to a system to cut a knot without trying to untie it, at least for the sake of other people. Since writing this CC HISTORICAL RETROSPECT. 11 at once the source of his religious grandeur and his matter of fact weakness. Whereas Leibnitz, on the contrary, by no means less jealous of the truth than his opponent Locke, was impelled to the endeavour to combine the particular and the universal, and, failing a symmetrical combination, to avoid neglecting either aspect of the truth at any cost. This makes us regret the less the small immediate effect of the "Ethica" com- pared with the popularity of the Leibnitzian philosophy, albeit this popularity was retained only by an eviscer- ating adaptation to vulgar tastes. Still, be the cause of the nugatory influence of Spinoza on the course of philosophy for so long a time what it may, it is certain that the dogmatism of Leibnitz was more calculated to urge to fruitful effort than the dogmatism of Spinoza. Conformably to these anticipations we find that the monadology of Leibnitz is not the fanciful theory it looks to be. It is in point of fact, as we have said, the forcible combination of different indispensable aspects of the truth. And what Lessing has said about Leibnitz (and it cannot be too often quoted for his interpretation) is the explanation of this appear- ance on the one hand and of this real significance on the other. 1 "Leibnitz's ¹ ideas of truth," said Lessing to Jacobi, "were so formed that he could not bear to remark I am glad to be able to refer the reader for a definite statement of this defect in Spinoza's philosophy to Mr. Gurney's able examination of Monism in Mind, April 1881. 1 This translation is taken from Mr. Sime's "Lessing," vol. ii. p. 298. · 12 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. see too narrow limits set to it. From this mode of thought many of his statements have flowed, and it is often hard for the most acute student to discover his real opinion. For that very reason I think so highly of him; I mean, on account of this great manner of thinking, not on account of this or that opinion which he appeared to hold or even actually held." And so from the theory of monads we may extract if we choose an indication of what an adequate philosophy ought to be, even if we do not find therein the philo- sophy itself. Every existence was a monad, and every monad was a self-contained existence, indeterminate from without; and yet this infinite multitude of monads formed a cosmos, through a pre-established harmony. Once for all the tenour of their lives had been so planned and contrived that they should work inde- pendently but harmoniously together, as clocks wound up and set in unison. They were without extension, but were points of force, and thus spatial difficulties were avoided. In this way the individual was not separated from the universal, for in its life omniscience could have seen reflected the universe, so intimately had its life been previously related to the rest of existence. The universal too was not sacrificed to the particular, for each individual was created accord- ing to its relationship to the universal, and only existed for it. Thus perception was but the occurrence in due time of a change in the monad corresponding to other changes without. In itself it was a kind of thought, confused thought, and required intellection to clear it HISTORICAL RETROSPECT. 13 into true knowledge. Thought was the real, in short, and must be at once universal and particular: a great truth, fit to be the guiding idea of an adequate philo- sophy, and not to be contemned because it was ex- pressed in this case at the expense of the creation of a Great Monad to whom all difficulties were consigned. Suggestive as this quaint speculation is, the fol- lowers of Leibnitz altogether failed to appreciate their master's "great manner of thinking." The philosophy of Wolff, his most celebrated disciple, made, we are told, no attempt to reconcile differences or to fill up lacunce. Rather, the range of the monad became shut into the isolation of the atom. It aimed only at the formal explication of what was implied in the individual's thought, but the explication partook of disintegration more than of explanation. Later on we shall meet with some of this school's special doc- trines in connection with Kant's criticism of meta- physics; here, however, we need only notice the fruit- lessness of mere formal analysis. Thought is living and organically constituted; to treat it therefore as a thing belonging to the individual, to be dissected and separated into pieces for its better comprehension, is to destroy all life that it possesses. The vitality of the individual's thought consists in its relation to a world. What wonder then that the Wolffian philo- sophy, seeking the truth by analysing the subject's thought only as it pertained to the subject, and look- ing therein for the secret as if total disintegration could reveal the truth of an organism, failed to pro- 14 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. vide men with a living and sufficient account of them- selves and the universe? Thus it came to pass that thought fell a victim to the same tendency as sensuous experience had done. Whilst experience, decomposed into momentary feelings, vanished in a flux, thought, mechanically dissected, fell into lifeless formulæ. Happily, however, the points of truth recognised by Leibnitz could not be permanently disregarded. The great manner of thinking of another man prevented this misfortune. The import of his message, at times falteringly expressed, history has not yet fairly de- termined; yet this man, his doctrines and their signifi- cance, do next follow in the movement of history, and thus we have been brought to the point we desired. CHAPTER II. KANT AND TRANSCENDENTALISM. WE reached in our retrospect the point where our serious business commences; and, in truth, this point is thus characterized as serious for us, no less by the fact that we live in a certain epoch of thought than by the aim which these few pages happen to have in view. For pre-eminently the greatest philosopher of our speculative era is Immanuel Kant. Although his great work was published in 1781, and the revolution he effected followed closely on the effort of his thought, yet at this moment he is as great a thinker as he has ever been since the world first comprehended the drift of his inquiries.¹ Between then and now, it is true, an extraordinary outburst of speculative activity has manifested itself and again disappeared. The inter- vening century has seen the glory and disrepute of absolutism. Pretensions once welcomed as grand are now seldom countenanced, and never encouraged. But even if the student do chance to find in any of these ¹ In this connection the following note may be quoted from the Academy for April 23rd, 1881:-"We read in the Index that in America, as well as in Germany, it is proposed to hold a centennial celebration this year of the publication of Kant's Kritik der Reinen Vernunft.'" 15 16 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. attempts doctrines adequate or helpful to his wants, he must nevertheless have first assimilated the thoughts of the great thinker of Königsberg before he can have worked his way up to an eminence whence he could fairly estimate the merits of his choice. On the other hand, however, if these supervening growths are elimi- nated from serious consideration as so much sterile ingenuity, even then the would-be philosopher must reckon with Kant before he can pursue his way with ease and profit. So profoundly did Kant treat the problems of philosophy, even as they appear to us at this day. • But in point of fact it would seem, from recent movements in some quarters, that the value of Kant's work lies not only in its offer of a vantage ground or a propedeutic, but in the intrinsic worth of its own results. "No fact in the recent history of speculation seems of more importance in itself, or of greater signi- ficance for the future, than the revived study of the Kantian philosophy." Such is the opening sentence of Professor Adamson's instructive lectures, and his ensuing pages tender ample reasons for the announce- ment. Characterizing very briefly the influences work- ing to this event, he says: "The return to Kant on the part of English philosophy is but the logical result to which penetrating criticism or the natural development of its principles must inevitably lead; whereas in Germany the movement has been chiefly due to the pressure of speculative difficulties on scientific thinkers, who have felt the necessity for a KANT AND TRANSCENDENTALISM. 17 thorough investigation of the principles on which scientific cognition rests." For immediate proof of these assertions the reader must be referred to Pro- fessor Adamson's little book, since it is hardly worth while to transcribe his account of the merely statistical evidence, and the logical reasons for Kant's relation to contemporary thought perforce require some insight into Kant's speculations to be appreciated, as well as an acquaintance with the present scientific position; information to be only obtained from Professor Adam- son's special treatment of the question, or any other means affording a reliable knowledge of the Kantian philosophy and the radical tendencies of scientific thought. But the prima facie facts are fully sufficient to persuade any one about to study philosophy to qualify himself for efficient work by an inspection of this system, be it for the sake of positive knowledge, of a preliminary training, or of a stepping stone. And 2 1 "On the Philosophy of Kant," by Robert Adamson: pp. 1, 2. These lectures give a singularly succinct and lucid view of Kant's philosophy as a whole, in relation to the present speculative situation. 2 For a vigorous criticism of scientific method and doctrines, see Mr. Balfour's "Defence of Philosophic Doubt”; and for a thorough examination of the common metaphysics of science see also "Modern Realism Examined," by the late Mr. Her- bert. The former is the work of an acute, though not very sympathetic, critic; the latter is that of a philosopher, but not, I think, of a very profound one. The times too are not yet sufficiently advanced to render a perusal of J. Grote's con- scientious writing in his prolix "Exploratio Philosophica anything but instructive. C 18 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. it is in the hope of doing something towards facili- tating this, as well as to give to the general reader a brief account of the "Critique of Pure Reason," that the following pages are written. Kant united in himself the two partial and conflict- ing tendencies of thought which prevailed, as we have seen, the one in Germany, the other in England, at his time. The academic routine of his youth acquainted him with the claims of thought as then advanced. The philosophy of Wolff then reigned supreme in the schools. By his own exertions Kant ascertained its vanity; and it is interesting to follow the course of his opinions in this respect, a movement admirably traced by Professor Caird, till he had determined that formal logic could never by itself be productive of anything, and that experience must furnish the material of knowledge. But when English sensation- alism appeared to be the last and true alternative, his study of Hume apprised him of its inability to support the fabric of our experience as we conceive it to be. Hence he was especially qualified to effect a signal advance in the treatment of philosophy's problem. This advance necessitated a change of position, and we cannot do better then indicate at the very outset the nature of this change, for by this means the reader will be the more prepared for comprehending the aspect which the problem at first presented to Kant. Convinced that philosophy up to that time had failed, he suspected that its subject matter might have been KANT AND TRANSCENDENTALISM. 19 wrongly stated. To quote again his oft-repeated description of his innovation, he proposed to do "just what Copernicus did in attempting to explain the celestial movements. When he found that he could make no progress by assuming that all the heavenly bodies moved round the spectator, he reversed the process, and tried the experiment of assuming that the spectator revolved, while the stars remained at rest." ("Critique," p. xxix.) As Copernicus reversed with success the standpoint of the Ptolemaic system, so Kant hoped to succeed in solving the questions of metaphysic by abjuring both the individual's ideas and sensations as the ultimate truth of reality, and by assuming that, instead of the mind being formed by experience, the mind itself should form received experience according to its own laws. Thus the com- parison with Copernicus was literally correct; but if Kant achieved all that he laid claim to, the comparison might be legitimately extended far beyond these limits. As Tycho Brahe collected facts, as Kepler discovered his three laws, so did Kant get together facts and arrive at subsidiary truths in his pre-critical medita- tions. And as Newton by the help of his prede- cessors arrived at his grand truth of the formula of gravitation, so Kant after his prolonged inquiries arrived at the central point of all knowledge (as he maintained) in his synthetic unity of apperception or self-consciousness. But this is anticipating; let us 1 ¹ And indeed it would seem that Kant himself was willing to claim a Newtonian relationship to metaphysic. 20 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. notice a little more closely Kant's method before we proceed to consider its doctrinal results. The failure of philosophy hitherto caused Kant to suspect that a change of position was necessary. Pure thought, as till then conceived, he had found to be barren, and only capable of analysing what had been already given. This might be useful, but it could neither give knowledge nor account for it. Sensation also he had found to consist ulti- mately of a flux of momentary feelings, of perishing existences, one past before another was present, the present only existing and perishing as soon as it existed. This Hume had exhibited; and he had accordingly declared all knowledge derived from such a source to be precarious. But in mere consistency he should have driven his sceptical criticism to a far more destructive issue. Our knowledge cannot by any means be derived from such fleeting unrelated points alone. Of this Kant became aware, and thus learnt that it was impossible to account for the most simple of our experiences on such principles. Our knowledge, so far as it confessedly goes, is of a world in one space, in one time, organically constituted by interdependent relations: this world is real and differ- ent from what is only imaginary: our experiences of it are referred to permanent objects; and on reflection, as in scientific procedure, we are forced to think of it as containing one same sum of matter, and as possessing various other indispensable characteristics. Such being the indubitable fact, it is plain that sense KANT AND TRANSCENDENTALISM. 21 alone is quite insufficient for an explanation of it. Nay, not only is sense powerless to account for a cosmos, but it is incapable of accounting for any de- finite experience at all. The perishing existences of sense are intrinsically incognisable, for they are ever fleeting and never last long enough to become appre- ciable or to constitute an object. Kant, we have said, was aware of this impotence. Tradition tells that he got disabused of his beliefs in sensation by meeting with Hume's attack on causation. With this point in view we recurred in the last chapter to Hume in con- nection with causation alone. Nevertheless, although the tradition is founded on Kant's own words, there is much reason for us to believe that its report is more or less incomplete; at any rate, we should make a grievous error if we imagined that Kant's real diffi- culties regarding sense merely amounted to a mis- giving about necessary causation. In truth his whole work would be meaningless, and his words would be empty, if sense were supposed capable of giving a single definite experience. And this will become patent in the sequel. But here we must ask what is the implication contained in this fluxional nature of sense, what can we infer from this on the one hand, and our experience as it is on the other? We must suppose with Kant, for an experiment if for nothing else, that in our experience thought con- tributes sundry relations coordinating the data of sense, subject to which all our empirical knowledge must be received. Now if this prove to be the case, 22 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. these indispensable elements will be forms of syn- thesis or relation; and since experience is impossible without them, they will be a priori or prior to experi- ence itself. Kant calls such a priori elements trans- cendental; and it is the business of a transcendental philosophy to give a complete and systematic account of them. Kant himself does not propose to construct a system of transcendental philosophy, for this would include in its systematic exposition an account of our ana- lytic a priori, as well as of our synthetic a priori, knowledge (that is, an account not only of the main synthetic elements in knowledge, but also of the detailed deductions from them); and this would be a task too great for the limits of a single essay. But he aims at a transcendental criticism of pure reason, which will bring to light all the a priori principles of synthesis which serve as the ground plan of experience. Concerning the method of a critique of this kind, we may be sure that it must not proceed at haphazard. To ensure freedom from error and omission, the critique must be guided by some systematising idea. Now "reason is, in regard to the principles of cogni- tion, a perfectly distinct, independent unity, in which, as in an organized body, every member exists for the sake of the others, and all for the sake of each, so that no principle can be viewed with safety in one relation- ship, unless it is at the same time viewed in relation to the total use of pure reason. ("Critique,” p. KANT AND TRANSCENDENTALISM. 23 xxxii.)¹ That of an organism then is the idea which the "Critique of Pure Reason" should follow. It should proceed so that the whole organic process of knowledge may be laid bare, so that each distinguished element may be explained by its function in the whole, and so that the whole may be ever in view lest any element should escape. Concerning the results we may expect, it may be fairly supposed that when the critique's task has been performed we shall be in a position to make sundry judgments which must hold good for all experience, because otherwise experience would be impossible for us. Having detected the conditions of experience, we may deduce the various modes according to which they will condition experience. Thus equipped we shall be able to predict in certain respects the nature of experience. These judgments will be a priori, and, in Kantian terminology, synthetic: synthetic, that is, not in its former sense of acting as a bond or relation, but synthetic in the sense of adding to our knowledge. In this context, therefore, synthetic a priori judg- ments mean judgments increasing our knowledge an- tecedent to actual experience, e.g. mathematical judg- ments. We can now see why so much importance is attached to the question, How are synthetic judgments a priori possible? Kant contends that such are cer- 1 In a separate work, written as a popular explanation of the "Critique," "Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysic," Kant expresses the same opinion even more strongly. See Professor Mahaffy's translation, p. 13. 24 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. tainly made both in mathematics and physics, and concludes that an explanation of their possibility will afford a good insight into the process by which ex- perience, bound to conform to them, comes about. Significant as this question clearly is, it is after all subsidiary to the wider question, What are the a priori forms of synthesis (relations) involved in ex- perience? And this question again, on the supposition that sense alone is incognisable, is equivalent to the question, How is knowledge possible? The answer to the wider query will solve by implication the first one, for when the nature of the forms of synthesis has been determined it will become obvious how by their means judgments may be made anticipating necessary characteristics of experience. We may hope then to find out from our criticism something about pure mathematics and pure physics. Moreover, we may hope to arrive at an estimate of the position which metaphysics should occupy; having discovered the functions and capacities of reason, we shall be able to decide on its competency for apprehending the uncon- ditioned. In this way past failures may be explained, and a more secure, though possibly a more defensive, attitude may be found for the future. These formally prescribed aims and method of Kant's transcendentalism promise fair. Not only may we feel safe from one-sided partial views, which must inevitably lead to absurdities and sterilities, but we may feel assured that an answer will be obtained to the questionings of the speculative spirit. The same KANT AND TRANSCENDENTALISM. 25 reason that asks the question must also be able to answer it to the extent that it has been asked. Trans- cendental criticism alone is required to teach reason to what extent its questions and answers reach. The same criticism will also teach the worth and relation- ship of the several elements that compose our real experience. In short, criticism will provide us with an adequate philosophy. It has been incidentally hinted that this criticism. will be a process of distinction. But let not the unenviable associations attach themselves to this term which rightly belong to the scholastic distinguo. Transcendental distinctions are made with a view to showing the elements of knowledge in their intimate connection and coherence in thought as a whole; but the device of scholasticism was one of total separation for the better perpetration of quibbles and incon- gruities. Yet it is not impossible that the mere assertion of the possibility of distinguishing elements in the organic whole of reason may suggest difficulties. It may be contended, as Mr. Balfour has so energeti- cally done, that thoughts only exist as they are 1 In a chapter (which had been previously published in Mind), attacking transcendentalism in his "Defence of Philo- sophic Doubt." Professor Caird briefly replied to this attack in Mind for Jan. 1879, and Professor John Watson contributed a paper on the same subject to the same periodical for Jan. 1881. Mr. Balfour answered Professor Caird in the same number, and Professor Watson in that for April 1881. The latter controversy does not appear to be a very profitable one, through a vacillation in Professor Watson's paper which 26 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. thought, that is, as we are aware of them. It may be maintained that it is futile to talk about any thoughts or thought-elements which are not explicitly recog- nised, that "it is plain that so long as a thought is implicit it does not exist." In this case of course the method of transcendentalism would be vain, it would be absurd to try to see into what by the hypothesis can be known only as it appears outside. But it is not at once evident that thought may be entirely identified with awareness. In point of fact the identi- fication is quite arbitrary. And when we reflect on confuses the discussion of the point at issue, a vacilla- tion however for which Kant himself is partly responsible. The vacillation is respecting the facts from which trans- cendentalism starts. In truth, these facts must be immediate experiences, such as a perception of a coloured object. From these must be elucidated the principles involved in experience and which transcendentalism expounds as a system of know- ledge. But Kant sometimes speaks as if special sciences could stand as basal facts as indisputably as immediate expe- rience. It is uncertain how far he was aware of Hume's scep- tical suggestions; but it is plain that if the "Critique" started on such a wide assumption, little would remain for it to prove positively, and that most of Kant's labour would be superfluous. Therefore it is hard to understand Professor Watson's impa- tience with Mr. Balfour's scepticism, and harder still his different professions of the proper starting point for transcendentalism. Kant's utterances about the cognisability of the manifold of sense make it manifest also that he regarded immediate per- ceptions as the ultimate data for criticism to proceed from, in spite of his remarks about the de facto existence of sciences. The real crux is that concerning the possibility of under- thinking our admitted experience, and this Mr. Balfour fairly enough handles from his point of view. KANT AND TRANSCENDENTALISM. 27 the concave implied in the convex, on discreteness linked to continuity, on one end inseparable from another end, and the like, we must confess that the arbitrary identification seems to militate against plain facts. We must answer as Hegel, somewhat unwar- rantably and not a little flippantly, once answered Kant himself on the limitation of our thought. Scho- lasticus refused to venture into the water until he had learnt to swim; and those who insist upon starting with a preconception of the nature of thought, and determine what they can know and cannot know before they have tried to know, are no less timid and illogical. The truth is, we must look before we can make up our minds respecting what we can see. Now this is just the business of philosophy, or at any rate of transcendentalism, to look and see for itself what it can see involved in the truth of our experience. We are self-conscious beings and can to some extent return upon our thought; we must therefore suspend our judgment concerning what we can see till we have tried the experiment. Transcendentalism then is not antecedently chime- rical. It will endeavour to see for itself the elements of thought in their organic combination and functional capacity in the production of experience. The success of its endeavour can only be determined by the result. But how these elements will be brought to light we cannot be expected to announce beforehand. Yet it is to be presumed that bare perception, however acute, is not to be implicitly trusted. Not only must the 28 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. They elements be seen, they must be understood. must be viewed in their complete determination, in their precise situation and office in relation to the rest of the whole. From a passage of Kant already quoted, it would seem that the "Critique" would certainly not neglect this precaution. Nevertheless, such neglect is only too apparent. For Kant has a touchstone for the detection of the transcendental elements, and at times. speaks as if it were infallible. True, the touchstone is a good one and, if thoroughly free from alloy, would be unerring. But where can we find immediately and without previous examination anything free from alloy, either in things of the mind or in things of the world? To Kant his criterion is immediately certain. He obtains it by the application of the ideas of uni- versality and necessity. From the mere contingent repetition of experiences it would be impossible to conclude what is universal and necessary, and therefore whatever is of this character must be a priori. "Em- pirical universality is therefore only an arbitrary ex- tension of validity, from that which may be predicated of a proposition valid in most cases, to that which is asserted of a proposition which holds good in all; as, for example, in the affirmation 'all bodies are heavy.' When on the contrary strict universality characterizes a judgment, it necessarily indicates another peculiar source of knowledge, namely a faculty of cognition a priori. Necessity and universality therefore are infallible tests for distinguishing pure from empirical KANT AND TRANSCENDENTALISM. 29 knowledge, and are inseparably connected with each other." ("Critique," p. 3.) To this argument we may assent with the tacit reservation, if the tests can be applied. Now the endless controversy respecting what is universal and necessary shows that their application is difficult. By themselves, universality and necessity form a very precarious basis of proof. Such judgments may be made most unwarrantably, and there is no protection from arbitrary assertion and subjective caprice. Therefore their evidence should be accepted only provisionally till it has been confirmed by a more thorough comprehension of the attested element. Such a confirmation Kant calls a trans- cendental deduction. In short, the first criterion is. but a guide and one of problematical accuracy; a transcendental deduction is the real means by which the truth of its indications must be established. From these considerations we learn that if Kant uses necessity and universality as if they were self sufficient conductors, we must regard his behaviour as provisional, and forbear disputing his conclusions on those grounds alone. We must wait till we are in a position to contemplate the whole of his scheme of knowledge and the entire coherence of its parts, before we can finally pronounce judgment. As a matter of fact Kant does not by any means fulfil all the require- ments of a deduction of his doctrines. This will appear as we go on. Now, however, we are only concerned with preparing ourselves for their proper study. In addition to these prefatory remarks, a word must 30 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. ! be said respecting Kant's actual expository procedure. The "Critique of Pure Reason" was the hasty expres- sion of years of sustained thought. But though hasty, Kant was anxious that it should omit nothing that was of value. The book was therefore most inelegantly written. Yet this was not its only fault. Conscious that none but thinkers would notice investigations like his, Kant took no pains to render the comprehension of his views easy, but was willing to leave his readers to make out his whole meaning by pondering over the complete work and interpreting one portion by the light of another. This was due to his writing hastily, or as it came most easily to him. Naturally it reflected. in a manner the history of his long meditations; the commencement speaking in the tone of one just awake, and betraying no sign of the coming qualifications necessitated by the revelations of longer watching. Beginning from the same point of view as that assumed by the ordinary consciousness, and adopting the usual distinction of subject and object, the "Critique" starts from the opposition of the individual to the objective world. Then as the different a priori factors in ex- perience are discovered, they are picked up as bits externally united to the main scheme of knowledge; and not till later does their organic coherence, such as it is, appear. Meanwhile the original distinction be- tween subject and object has been much modified, and the careless reader feels at a loss how to interpret the whole consistently, difficulties being multiplied by Kant's own apparent forgetfulness of the significance KANT AND TRANSCENDENTALISM. 31 of his argumentation. This faultiness was inevitable to Kant's way of leading the reader along the same path he had himself trod; but the nature of his theme also involves difficulties peculiar to itself; exposition is linear, and adequate thought on such a subject is spherical. To express spherical thought by means of linear exposition necessarily tends to confusion, and the consciousness of this undesirable contingency caused Kant to strive especially after definiteness, (a definiteness the more ensnaring to him after his early Wolffian training,) and to follow the idea of a machine rather than that of an organism in his method of ex- position. Add to this the invention of a new termi- nology,¹ and it would seem that in every way this ¹ Nevertheless, let not the laborious student pity himself as a victim, or exalt himself as a hero. Kant himself tells us in the "Prolegomena " to consider that every one is not bound to study metaphysic and that some minds, otherwise able, cannot succeed in such investigations, and should accordingly apply their talents to other subjects. Sages of all times have wondered at Wisdom's retirement; those of the Hebrews "" especially. Spinoza concludes his "Ethica with the re- flection that a proper comprehension of the nature of self, God, and the world sane arduum debet esse, quod adeo raro reperitur. Qui enim posset fieri, si salus in promptu esset et sine magno labore reperiri posset, ut ab omnibus fere negligeretur? Sed omnia præclara tam difficilia, quam rara sunt." The perspicuous Hume warns his readers at the commencement of his "Treatise" that "if truth be at all within the reach of human capacity, 'tis certain it must lie very deep and abstruse,” and opines that there would be a strong presumption against a philosophy if it were so very easy and obvious. The student therefore may be expected 32 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. better way of philosophising was rendered as difficult as possible both to its expounder and his pupils. strenuous exertion if his He consciously chooses an commiseration for his self- to have prepared himself for inquiries are to be of any avail. arduous study and can claim no imposed toil, or admiration for following the bent of his idiosyncrasy; and the addition of literary and formal diffi- culties is nothing more than a natural implication in a recondite subject. CHAPTER III. THE TRANSCENDENTAL ÆSTHETIC. 1. KANT, we have said, starts from the position of the ordinary consciousness, and at first adopts the dualistic view of mind and matter in all its starkness. Ac- cordingly he commences the treatment of his problem by inquiring into the relation existing between the individual mind and the objective world in space. In other words, he begins with external sense intuition. But along with this form of sense intuition he also brought under consideration internal sense intuition. For it was a cardinal doctrine of his that the mind never beheld its own ultimate reality by mere intro- spection, but that it could only experience its phe- nomenal changes in a manner analogous to its experi- ence of external sensation. He therefore thought that these two kinds of experience, outer sense and inner sense, might be classed together, being both species of sensation. For these reasons the first part of the "Critique" seeks for a priori conditions of inner and outer sense. This quest for transcendental elements of a sensuous significance is accordingly called the Transcendental Esthetic. 33 D 34 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. Now what are the universal and necessary conditions of external intuition? Think everything away, ab- stract all that is variable and unnecessary from the outside world, and what remains? Pure space alone retains its persistence in thought. Conversely, think of what you will in the outside world, and it must be as situated somewhere in the same space. Similarly, look within. Whatever is perceived there is conditioned by time. No feeling or idea can exist except at some moment of time; to be perceived, every feeling must occupy some appreciable time; what is perceived can be known only as change, and change can only happen in time. In this case both kinds of sense participate in the conditioning element: internal sense directly does; external sense indirectly. For although time is not to be seen running in the outside world, we cannot perceive this world unless our per- ceptions are cognised as ours in time, precisely as internal perceptions are, according to what has been just said. : Space and time therefore are a priori forms of per- ception the former peculiar to external sense, the latter common to both kinds of intuition. Yet we must not think of these conditions of our sensibility as forms of receptivity by themselves. Space and time only exist in perception itself, and are nothing except as functional. Their priority is an ideal priority; they are logically prior to, but historically coincident with, experience itself. As regards their real worth, they are empirically real, real so far as our experience THE TRANSCENDENTAL ESTHETIC. 35 is concerned, since all our experience must conform to them. But, as they are not things in themselves, they cannot have an independent reality in the trans- cendental sense of the word. Therefore space and time, though empirically real, are transcendentally ideal.¹ The a priori nature of space and time further appears from the following considerations. If they are not a priori, they must be ideas possessed of an ineradi- cable persistence which had been formed from a vast quantity of temporal and spatial experience. But this cannot be; for no experience is possible without them, and to extract them from experience is a manifest hysteron-proteron. Again, unless they are a priori, how could the mathematical sciences possess their apodeictic certainty? Kant holds that mathematics are synthetic, and are not be reduced to identical pro- positions, augmenting our knowledge and not merely explicating it. By their means we confidently predict how certain phenomena will be apprehended by us. ¹ The reader may be interested to know that the propounder of this theory of space and time is also celebrated for anticipat- ing Laplace in the suggestion of that theory, respecting the origin of our planetary system, which goes by the name of the nebular hypothesis. Scientific thinkers seem to be no less unanimous in their approval of this doctrine than they are in their contempt for metaphysic. Yet the same mind was capable of originating the one, and feeling the need of and toiling at the other. For an account of Kant's work in astronomy, see the memoir prefixed to Mr. Abbott's “Kant's Theory of Ethics." 36 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. How could this be, unless they were founded on a priori conditions of perception, and drew their conclusions from intuited figures and series under these conditions, which accordingly afforded an indication of how objects must appear under these conditions? No such con- fidence would be justifiable if they were founded on contingent experience. Any other theory then could afford no safe basis for mathematics, and to be in- telligible would have to appropriate surreptitiously the very thing it seeks to explain.¹ ¹ Besides referring to the association school of psychologists, we may call the attention of the reader to another view to which these remarks apply. The late Professor Ueberweg in his "System of Logic and History of Logical Doctrines," now translated into English, seeks to found perception on an in- telligible basis. Like Trendelenburg, he objects to Kant's assignment of space and time to the subject, holding that space and time are independent realities. He supports his thesis by arguing (§§ 41-44) that "as our corporeal phenomena are to our mental reality, so other corporeal phenomena are to a strange mental reality (here accordingly presupposed)," and that from this reasoning we may arrive at a valid knowledge of "the co-existence and co-operation of a multiplicity of powers," which " necessarily involve some real order of coherence and succession," in other words, "some real existence in space and in time," which cannot be different to the space and time of sense. The reader will perceive that this argument assumes the point in question from the first, in the term "corporeal." Professor Ueberweg adduces additional evidence from psychical-physiological facts and the like, but a hypothesis which is virtually a petitio principii cannot be rendered luminous by any amount of considerations which themselves are full of the petitory vice, and as to proof the hypothesis is still as much a hypothesis at the end as it was at the begin- THE TRANSCENDENTAL ESTHETIC.. 37 In the dualism between subject and object, two of the chief apparent factors of the latter have now been transferred to the former. Yet we must not be in- duced to treat objective experience as an illusion. Rather, only on these terms can we have confidence in its reality such as it essentially is, only on these terms can we be certain that all our experience and that of all similar intelligences must be thus condi- tioned and so far real. Still, in this transference of these universal forms from the object to the subject it is clear that the object has been converted from a thing-in-itself into a phenomenon or appearance. The object, whatever it be, can only be apprehended in space and time, forms of our sensibility, and must therefore be in itself quite different to what we per- ceive. To this extent the object can only be phe- nomenal, though phenomenally real; it can only appear, but must always appear, under certain conditions. 2. The reader who has appreciated the true method of transcendentalism will not fail to notice that the doc- trine of the Æsthetic, as above summarised, is far from satisfying all requirements. We have seen that a really valid theory of the scheme of knowledge is only possible if, in addition to possessing apparent uni- versality and necessity, the distinguished elements are ning. It is fitting only to notice this one point here, but the reader will doubtless find for himself further matter for reflec- tion in Professor Ueberweg's learned contention. 38 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. shown to perform certain definite functions, and to be so related that without the co-operation of all there could be no knowledge whatever. In short, the theory must be spherically thought out, however the exigencies of exposition may necessitate a linear state- ment. Now this is as yet wanting for space and time. Their true relationship to the rest of thought and know- ledge has not been even mooted; they have been taken up as they first came to the hand of the in- vestigator, and their nature has been determined from their most obvious characteristics. Indeed, from Kant's distinction of them as perceptions from con- ceptions one might be tempted to think that any con- nection between them and the rest of thought was impossible. It is clear that, whatever elements are subsequently brought to light, those on the subject side must be derived from the understanding; for no more forms of perception are forthcoming. Now the property of the understanding is conceptions, which are fixed abstract ideas under which may be subsumed species and individuals. Perceptions, on the other hand, present an indefinite possibility of knowledge; they are capable of an endless specification and analysis. To this latter belong space and time. We can never exhaust their potentialities; they are no abstract conceptions capable of holding any number of individuals and powerless to create, but they are perceptions whose specific character we can never suf- ficiently learn. This disparity between space and time, as we have them, and conceptions, which we may find, THE TRANSCENDENTAL ÆSTHETIC. 39 threatens to prevent their organic union in the scheme of knowledge. At the best, it would seem that the two can only be juxtaposited in meaningless connec- tion; anyhow a proper transcendental deduction of space and time would be precluded. We must call to mind, however, what has been said concerning Kant's method of exposition. It may be that the isolation of space and time is an expository artifice. Perhaps, after all, their connection with the rest of the elements in the process of knowledge may appear, though on this point I warn the reader not to be too sanguine. Nevertheless, we may be certain that knowledge does not arise from the inexplicable action of unseen objects on subjects + space and time. Sense alone is a manifold, a multiplicity of chaotic un- connected moments; and Kant had this fact in view, as we have said, in the construction of his theory of know- ledge. Thus he could not have wished his readers to remain under the impression that his scheme of ex- perience simply consisted of a sensuous chaos emptied into a couple of quanta like space and time.¹ Agree- 1 This is a proper place to enter a caveat against a very pos- sible misapprehension. The reader will have observed a super- ficial resemblance between Kant's view of the ultimate nature of sense and the doctrines of science. Both theories resolve sense into units: the former takes sense to be a mere manifold of stimulations; the latter finds sensation to be presumably compounded of neurotic units consequent on external physical action, undulatory or chemical. Yet are they essentially dif- ferent. For whilst the first is out of space and time, the second is unintelligible save on the prior assumption of space 40 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. ably with this surmise we find him changing his point of view very considerably, other factors in experience are discovered, and accordingly we must reserve our judgment on the doctrines of the Esthetic till we have seen them in connection with the rest of the results of the "Critique." These coming qualifications we now pass on to in the Transcendental Analytic. and time, to say nothing of other implied factors. Thus their assimilation is impossible, although the attempt has been made to reconcile the Kantian ding an sich with the units of science. (See Adamson's Lectures, p. 77 and p. 167, for strictures on this theory. Mr. Spencer too, though strongly supporting the theory of the primordial unit, § 60, "Principles of Psychology," points out, § 62, the incongruity existing between an oscillating molecule and a unit of feeling.) 1 CHAPTER IV. THE CATEGORIES, AND THEIR TRANS- CENDENTAL DEDUCTION. 1. By themselves space and time cannot make know- ledge out of sense data, but only render such a fabri- cation possible. They are but possibilities of the re- presentation of objects; unable to arrest the flux of sense and form it into an orderly experience, they yet provide conditions under which such co-ordination be- comes possible. Some other agency therefore must be found working along with them to make even the illusion of what we think knowledge possible; the fact of order in the minutest detail of our experience implies the presence of other factors. Let us therefore begin our next advance by asking ourselves what are the most general features of what we mean by know- ledge. Now when we say that we know anything, in contradistinction to fancying or imagining it, we mean that what we think or perceive is real. What then is done when our thoughts and perceptions are received as real? The reality of the former we take to consist in its conformity to possible perceptions, and so per- 41 : 42 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. ception contains in itself the criterion of reality. A perception is taken to be real when it is judged to be due to an object. "When we say that a perception refers to an object, we mean that under certain con- ditions the same perception might always be had; that, in other words, certain data of sense are fixed in reference to the other data, or have a certain definite place in the content of experience” (Caird, p. 283). On this view of reality hang all our transcendentalism and its prophets. Its importance is so great that I must cite at length its positive justification by the same eminent expositor. "In all cases we can trans- cend the immediate sensation, and refer it to an object, only in so far as we connect its content with the con- tent of other sensations. If it were otherwise, refer- ence to an object would mean merely reference to an unknowable something; and even if that were pos- sible, it would be no gain for knowledge. Now if this be so, if definite connection of the data of sense and objectivity are only two different aspects of the same thing if we cannot think of a sensation as a fixed and definite thing or quality of a thing, except so far as we distinguish from, yet relate it to, other sensa- tions: then it is obvious that all knowledge depends on the mind bringing with it principles of combination, in conformity with which the content of sensation is referred to objects." The justification has brought with it an explanation, an explanation which gives the clue to those other a priori elements which co-operate in the formation of real experience. CATEGORIES, AND THEIR TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION. 43 "To explain the fact of experience, we must con- ceive the understanding as combining the matter of sense, which in itself is an unconnected manifold, by means of certain conceptions, which we may indiffer- ently call 'forms of synthesis' or 'conceptions of objects in general,' according to the aspect in which we choose to regard them. Only in so far as the flux of sensation is arrested, and the retained content of it is organically connected by means of such conceptions, can such a thing as knowledge or experience come into existence." (Caird, p. 284.) If this account of reality be correct, it is very clear that our next movement must be towards the under- standing. We must extract from it these forms of synthesis, and then we shall be in possession of other elements of experience, to wit, those which combine and arrange in the formal possibilities, space and time, the chaos of sense. And when this is done we shall be able to predict with certainty the nature of experience to the extent of these general principles, since unless it conformed to them sense would remain unknown. The search for these forms of synthesis is an im- portant one therefore, and should be pursued with every care. In accordance with our idea of the organic unity of thought, it will be necessary to find them all in their purity and primitiveness, and when found they must be shown to be indispensable factors in experience and essentially related to one another in the organic totality. Only in this way can we be sure 44 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. that nothing has been omitted or slurred over, and that what have been found are correctly estimated. But such a result would be worth trouble. As we have just said, the a priori general laws of science would be manifested, and in default of some other source of knowledge we should not only become aware of the significance of this empirical knowledge, but of knowledge in general, and should be able to discover in this way our proper attitude towards the great questions beyond experience, concerning the destiny of man and the universe. Such a quest however does not appear to have occasioned much trouble to Kant. He wanted a system of the judgments by which the manifold of sense was brought under conceptions and thought as objective experience. Now the faculty of judgment is the understanding, and all of us know something already about its functions in one respect. Formal logic treats of the pure functions of the understanding, apart from the matter on which they are exercised, and expounds the nature of the understanding and the methods of its procedure in simple reasoning. From this point of view the understanding needs no further investigation. The received formal logic is the only science that is really complete, and it has been thus adult ever since its birth. If therefore formal logic is in any way connected with this other kind of logic, whose judgments realize objectively the data of sense, we may expect considerable aid in our search. This logic which we seek for may be aptly termed trans- CATEGORIES, AND THEIR TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION. 45 cendental logic, since it will give an account of the transcendental judgments in experience. Now Kant believed that he did find ready to his hand a guide to transcendental logic in formal logic. It must be borne in mind that in emancipating him- self from the Wolffian philosophy he had come to the conclusion that formal logic was only analytic and was incapable of doing more than explicating what had been implicitly given. It is plain that there must be a great difference between this analytical instrument and the synthetic agency whereby sense becomes in- telligibly combined. It was possible to have main- tained, and it can well be maintained now, that no such difference really exists, that thought never moves analytically, but that all thought, quá thought, is synthetic. But Kant did not entertain any such opinion either in the Wolffian or Hegelian sense, and yet regarded formal logic as the guiding thread to transcendental logic. He was led to connect the two logics in this manner by reflecting that transcendental logic was in fact not only a list of conceptions which the understanding possessed and superimposed on the manifold of sense, but that in truth it constituted the understanding itself. For the understanding is the faculty of judgment, certainly in the analytical fashion of formal logic; but inasmuch as no analysis can take place without previous synthesis, it is evident that analytical judgments must have been preceded by synthetical judgments, and their interdependence must be so close that, in a sense, the two may be said 46 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. to be different movements of the same thing, identical in short, and together to constitute the understanding. The understanding must in mere coherence contribute both; and thus every form of synthetic judgment must originate from the understanding and make a correlate to every form of analytic judgment. Con- versely, every form of analytic judgment will possess a synthetic correlate, and thus if we know the former we may ascertain the latter. Formal logic, as it left Aristotle's hand, was to Kant a perfect science, and he took without question its received classification of judgments. Accordingly from Aristotle's list he felt himself warranted to draw up the table of synthetical judgments (or categories in his nomenclature); and this table would be ex- haustive and not redundant. Formal logic had, he presumed, missed no form of judgment, and had brought them all down to their lowest terms, else two thousand years must have detected the irregularity. So instead of discovering and working out his trans- cendental logic by means of some supreme idea, Kant in the end took up the old formal logic just as it was, and straightway derived the categories from it, leaving both to rest all claims to accuracy on prescriptive right. Yet the question must arise whether this logic. was so complete as to justify this implicit trust in it as a guiding thread. In point of fact, Kant had some difficulty in getting all he wanted out of the old logic as it was, and was forced to introduce some distinc- tions material to transcendental logic, as he said, CATEGORIES, AND THEIR TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION. 47 though of no significance to formal. But these points are proper to more mature study than ours. To secure clearness, we have continued in the above to maintain the opposition of the two logics in words. But what we have been expounding is in truth only a part of transcendental logic, that part occupied with the discovery of the categories, and is technically termed the transcendental analytic. "That part of transcendental logic, which treats of the elements of pure cognition of the understanding and of the princi- ples without which no object at all can be thought, is transcendental analytic" ("Critique," 53). After- wards we shall come to another division of trans- cendental logic, also with its counterpart in formal logic, but this may be left till then; for the present we need only guard against confusing the terminology in this division. In order that the reader may not be compelled to refer to the text of the "Critique" for the table or categories I insert here the list with their typical judgments. Judgments. I. QUANTITY. Universal. Particular Singular II. QUALITY. Affirmative. Negative Infinite • Categories. Unity. • Plurality. Totality. Mathematical. Reality. Negation. Limitation. 48 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. III. RELATION. Categorical. Hypothetical. Disjunctive. IV. MODALITY. . Of Inherence and Sub- sistence. Of Causality and De- pendence. Of Community (reci- procity between the agent and patient). Problematical . . Possibility.-Impossi- Assertorial bility. Existence. Non-exist- ence. Apodeictical . . . Necessity.-Contin- gence. "This then is a catalogue of all the originally pure conceptions of the synthesis which the understanding contains a priori, and these conceptions alone entitle it to be called a pure understanding; inasmuch as only by them it can render the manifold of intuition conceivable, in other words, think an object of intui- tion. This division is made systematically [?] from a common principle, namely, the faculty of judgment (which is just the same as the power of thought), and has not arisen rhapsodically from a search at hap- hazard after pure conceptions, respecting the full number of which we could never be certain, inasmuch as we employ induction alone in our search, without considering that in this way we can never understand wherefore precisely these conceptions, and none others, abide in the pure understanding. ("Critique" p. 64.) Dynamical. CATEGORIES, AND THEIR TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION. 49 2. Hitherto Kant has only employed in his investiga- tion into the pure forms of synthesis of the under- standing the ordinary logic as a guiding thread, and this logic only as a guiding thread and not as a proof in the sense that a transcendental criticism requires. Now therefore we come to by far the most difficult part of his work, that part occupied with the deduc- tion of the categories, or the proof of their validity, indispensableness, and scope. So far the question of fact has only been treated, now the question of right has to be discussed. "Teachers of jurisprudence, when speaking of rights and claims, distinguish in a cause the question of right (quid juris) from the question of fact (quid facti); and while they demand proof of both, they give to the proof of the former, which goes to establish right or claim in law, the name of deduction." ("Critique,” p. 71.) First then, supposing the categories are legitimately derived conceptions, how are they related to sense and possible knowledge? It might be that not only did they arrange the data of sense, but also that in them- selves they possessed a substantial content, and might thus by their own agency originate supra-sensuous knowledge. On this point Kant is quite decided. He is convinced that just as sense is meaningless unless brought under conceptions, so are conceptions void of significance unless filled with sense. Sense alone is incognisable, because of its fleeting chaotic E 50 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. nature; conceptions alone are unrealizable, because they are merely general ideas. Therefore "thoughts without content of perceptions are empty, perceptions without conceptions are blind." In respect of sense, this is clear enough after what has gone before; but as regards conceptions, this peculiarity of theirs will be made more manifest by a remark on what we mean by our experiences. Our experiences are only of some specified thing or other, and although from their situation we may feel ourselves warranted to draw certain general conclusions from these specific experiences, these conclusions obtain all their contained truth from the experiences themselves. These specific experiences are possible only from the co-operation of sensuous particulars and general conceptions. But inasmuch as experiences must be specific, the general conceptions cannot be experienced unless sensuously particularised. And general conceptions can be particularised only by sense; otherwise they are incapable of specific content, and thus their meaning extends no farther than sensuous experience. This much for the extent of application possible to the categories. A wider view of experience will bring us to a point whence we may contemplate the deduction itself of these conceptions. Our space will be well employed by quoting the description of Pro- fessor Caird in the following passage: "Experience is always, even to the ordinary consciousness, a system; a system, it may be, only in its most general out- lines, but still so far systematic. Even when the sense CATEGORIES, AND THEIR TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION. 51 of law and order is most defective, common experience is to this extent organized, that all objects are repre- sented as existing in one space, arranged, that is, with reference to each other, in definite relations, which correspond to the relations of different parts of space; and that all events are represented as taking place in one time, arranged with reference to each other in definite relations, which correspond to the relations of different parts of time. Further, while the unity of space and time is thus presupposed as conditioning all the objects of experience, on the other hand, pre- supposition is also made, tacitly if not explicitly, of the identity of the self which is the subject of it. Any one may see this, if he will only attempt to make the contrary supposition, that the self to which all his experiences are referred does not continue the It is evident that, in that case, there would be a complete break of connection between the two suc- cessive series of experiences which are referred to the two different selves, and that no bridge could be thrown from one to the other. The identity of the self is, in fact, but the subjective counterpart of the unity of the world as one whole, space and one time." (Caird, p. 333.) dividual regards himself as one of the objects of this world, occupying a place in its system, and receiving from this world experiences in accordance with its systematic character. same. existing in one Again, the in- The question arises now, how much of this system can the individual, as an individual, know? And 52 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. secondly, where does his knowledge cease of this world, which he is already conscious of as a systematic whole? Kant takes up both sides of the question, and aims at vindicating the knowledge of the individual so far as it goes, and fixing the limit to his experience which is imposed on his self-consciousness. Kant in his second edition of the "Critique" en- deavoured to expand and supplement his first one, and offered another form of the deduction of the cate- gories. Both deductions come to the same thing; but as the first one possesses value as an additional help to beginners, a glance must be bestowed on that before we proceed to the officially final exposition. This form takes the "path of ascent," and beginning with mere sense endeavours to show that only on the Kantian theory of knowledge is its cognition explic- able. As long as sense is nothing more than a flux, as long as one unit has to die before another lives, so long the momentary unconnected stimulation has to take the place of experience. And this is as good as saying that there is no experience whatever. For momentary unconnected stimulations, incapable by themselves of relation and distinction, are to thinking beings as good as nothing. Only when the flux is arrested and referred to an enduring self, can anything thinkable as an experience be obtained. This self, however, must be out of time; in other words, must be enduring and not flowing with the moments of time in all their 1 The translation of this deduction is to be found in Appen- dix A to Professor Mahaffy's translation of the "Prolegomena." CATEGORIES, AND THEIR TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION. 53 discreteness. This self Kant calls the transcendental unity of apperception. It is never cognisable, but, as its name explains, it is an enduring point, inferred to exist necessarily behind the field of phenomena, and it is self-conscious, so that taking up the fleeting moments. of sense and combining them, it refers them to itself as its own experience of a world in which it lives. Now it is plain that, for this to be done, fleeting sense must be combined, must be grasped in a synthesis; and in order to manage this we must presume the activity of the imagination, which retains one unit of sense till others come to permit the completion of the perception. This faculty, therefore, has to reproduce the moment- ary sense stimuli, and present the past and present together, thus converting perishing existences into some kind of appreciable total. This much imagination can do, but no more, and indeed scarcely this. can do no more than just allow the association of sensations anyhow and without order; in fact, it is but a possibility of association, if association as we must understand it presupposes some kind of affinity and arrangement. Much more is required to convert sense into objects. Not only must the sense stimuli be retained alongside of one another, but they must be rendered objective. This requirement, as we have seen, involves in the end simply definite relationship and interconnection in the world, and constant refer- ence to an identical self. And to provide this, no accidental association as that of bare imagination will suffice, but the synthesis of the imagination must be It 54 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. conditioned by certain definite rules of the understand- ing; and these rules will be the categories. In short, by means of the categories the ego brings the data of sense under general conceptions, thus bringing out of chaos the phenomenal order and regularity of nature ; and in virtue of the ego's self-consciousness the cate- gorised sense is apprehended as part of the world of which the self is another part, and this implies that this part of the world would be apprehended in like manner as an object by all similar intelligences, that is, it is objective experience and not subjective illusion. We e now move on to the account of the deduction of the second edition. In this the order of procedure is inverted. Instead of beginning with the fleeting incognisable data of sense, it is assumed that sense is somehow given, and the question arises, how come these sensuous perceptions to be apprehended as objective experience? Now the manifold of sense is incapable of objective relation without the spon- taneity of the understanding. In itself, sense possesses no power of synthesis or relation, but requires the activity of the subject to convert it into definitely related objective experience. The condition however involved in synthesis brings us at once to the com- mencement of the process of knowledge from the point of view of the second edition. Synthesis requires the identity of the self, to which the ever-changing manifold may be referred in the certain fixed forms. "The I think' must accompany all my representa- tions, for otherwise something would be represented < CATEGORIES, AND THEIR TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION. 55 "" in me which could not be thought; in other words, the representation would either be impossible, or at least be, in relation to me, nothing." ("Critique,' p. 81.) Kant thus maintains that there must be a per- manent subject as a basis for all our mental operations; not only just for remembering and expecting specific experiences, but for the bare possibility of acquiring a single experience, and consistently argues that the ego must remain identical to admit the apprehension of a diversified manifold as a perception of its own. But it must not be supposed that we are conscious of this self in its repose, and independently of its activity. The ego never sees its self. Nevertheless the identity of the ego. is an indispensable condition in all experience; but inasmuch as this condition, self- consciousness, attends experience alone, self-conscious- ness is in some way the product of the process of experience. Now the manifold of sense evidently cannot provide a permanent subject. Therefore it must be found in the activity of the subject; in other words, self-consciousness is possible only through synthesis, which synthesis refers itself back to its transcendental unity. Again, it is by synthesis that our perceptions are referred to objects, as in the investigation for the cate- gories was established. Moreover, we are conscious of self only in contradistinction from objects. Qur understanding is not intuitive, that is, it does not provide the material for its own activity, but depends on external intuition for the evolution of its potential 56 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. self-consciousness in the activity of synthesis. In short, it is synthesis of the sensuous manifold which coincidently posits subject and object, the self and the world. And as our knowledge presupposes one self, so it presupposes one world, and the two unities are twin products of the understanding's synthetic activity. It is of consequence not to forget at this point that in Kant's view the manifold of sense is an indispensable factor in objective experience, and that this manifold is given externally. Thus the development of subject. and object is, from another point of view, dependent on the operation of a ding an sich, or thing-in-itself, independent of either subject or object as we know them. The evolution of subject and object, however, modifies it to an extent which renders it unknowable in its self, and it never reaches us as anything more than the unknown, unaccountable, cause of the de- veloped phenomenon. It is necessary to keep in mind the opposition between these two views. Kant always entertains both, and is ready to take either point of view; and to forget this would occasion much con- fusion in following him. The next thing is to determine the nature of this synthesis which we have just been talking about. Synthesis means subsumption under conceptions, and to determine the nature of a synthesis it is necessary to determine the nature of the conceptions and their manner of subsumption. These conceptions are, says Kant, the categories. If we revert once more to judgment, we shall see how this is the case. When we CATEGORIES, AND THEIR TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION. 57 judge we do not affirm an accidental and subjective association, but in subsuming a subject under a pre- dicate in a judgment we affirm a unity of perceptions objectively valid and true for all similar intelligences in like situations. And this is just what synthesis does. It too subsumes the manifold under conceptions, and affirms a unity between them valid for all similar intelligences, thus determining it as objects in an objective world. Calling to remembrance the affinity between these transcendental judgments and those of formal logic, we see how we can find the forms of this synthesis. From the table of formal logical judgments there may be derived the table of the functions of synthesis of the understanding, and these are the cate- gories themselves. And therefore the synthesis, which evolves the subject and object by the help of the ding an sich, is completely described in the table of cate- gories. As regards the determination of sense by the categories, we are prepared for its explanation by our remarks on the first edition deduction. The imagina- tion intervenes between them, and by its agency it becomes possible for the data of sense to be arrested, collected from fleeting continuity, and combined according to the rules of the understanding. Not that the imagination is to be regarded as a new faculty invented to meet the emergencies of a mediation beween thought and sense; it is not a thing by itself, even to Kant, and this will appear more palpably in the sequel. 58 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. Finally, our experience could only be as it is if it was determined by the categories as functions of unity belonging to the transcendental unity of apperception. All our experience, all objects, are situated in many cases somewhere, and always in some portion of time. Now this peculiarity cannot be due to the imagination, which is an irresponsible possibility; neither can it be due to space and time themselves, for they are but individual perceptions, though pure, and are not sys- tematising unities. But it must be due to the unity of our transcendental self. "The unity of space and time can consist in nothing else than the reference of their manifold to the one transcendental self, and the manifold of perception cannot be brought in relation to this unity of self, or determined as objective, except through the categories. Hence the forms of synthesis. of the manifold of objects in general, in relation to the unity of self-consciousness, are necessarily also the forms of synthesis of the manifold of our sense in time and space.' (Caird, p. 366.) " The result of this deduction, as touching the sound- ness of Kant's own theory, rests of course on its own truth and calls for no comment in a brief exposition of the "Critique"; but as touching practical conclusions the result is twofold, as we have anticipated. First, our knowledge, so far as it goes, is valid for us and all similar intelligences; it is subject to a certain process by which alone we can acquire experience, and thus we may have perfect confidence in our knowledge as long as it is confined to experience. Further, by in- CATEGORIES, AND THEIR TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION. 59 vestigating the a priori conditions of our experience in the forms of pure perception, i.e. in mathematics, and by examining our faculty of cognition by criticism, we may be able to anticipate to a certain extent the na- ture of our experience.¹ Secondly, of things-in-them- selves, freed from the conditions of thought, we can know nothing; to know is to think, to think is to condition, and every attempt to know the unconditioned destroys forthwith its unconditioned nature and hides. it from our view. This limitation, to be hereafter more fully expounded in the Dialectic, is immovable. But the deduction permits our self-consciousness to con- tinue indefinitely to realize itself in sensuous experi- ence, although the supra-sensible is relegated to the unknowable. The unknowableness of noumena, or things-in- themselves, suggests to us a question respecting the manner of our cognisance of a very important nou- menon, to wit, self. In the course of the above we omitted a digression on this point, for the sake of con- tinuity. In opposition to other thinkers, and systems of psychology in general up to his time, Kant denies that we can perceive the true unity of self. exists only as the transcendental subject, necessarily involved in our systematic experience, but empirically unknown. To assert experience of it is to confound CC Self ¹ Kant has deduced, from the principles expounded in the Critique of Pure Reason," the universal laws of physics in his treatise, "The Metaphysical Principles of Natural Science." 60 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. common inner sense with self-consciousness. Because we can perceive an inner experience it does not follow that we can perceive the inner self. Although we are undoubtedly conscious of self, it is not after the analogy of an inner experience, and to identify the two in any way is sheer confusion of thought. Our self-consciousness exists only in distinction from an objective world (not, be it noted, an external spatial world only, but a world which is cognised as objective in contradistinction to the cognising subject), and the objectivity of this world is the result of the synthetic activity of the unity of apperception. Therefore the consciousness of self is also the result of this self's activity in its synthetic apprehension of a sensuous manifold. And it is by means of the imagination that we become conscious at pleasure of ourselves as objects. in a world. Through it the synthetic activity of the understanding is called into play, object and subject are posited, let the affection be what you will, of inner sense or outer sense, and thus we become conscious of self in distinction from not-self. But this conscious- ness is no more than a mere thought, the trans- cendental subject remains hidden, if indeed as Kant asserts there be one at all, and we become aware of ourselves as simply existing from the synthetic activity itself. And what our perception must always be, in truth, is some phenomenal sensuous state, depending on the activity of thought and the form of sense, coincidently correlated with a subject. The true self must be out of time and space; but a perception. CATEGORIES, AND THEIR TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION. 61 must be in one or both, and therefore to perceive self is impossible. I hope that this compression of Kant's doctrine has not rendered it too too obscure. This part of the "Critique" is notoriously difficult, and any expansion of this account, to be of any use, would require some little space. Moreover, a detailed exposition may be confidently sought for in Professor Caird's book, to which I am perhaps more indebted in this part than in any other. ? CHAPTER V. SCHEMATISM, AND THE PRINCIPLES OF THE PURE UNDERSTANDING. WHEN the Esthetic was engaging our attention, we observed the disparity existing between the pure forms of perception (time and space) and the pure forms of the understanding. During our progress from that point, the attentive reader may have noticed for him- self the introduction of a clue to the reconciliation of perceptions with conceptions. The imagination has been found to be the faculty required for the arrest of sense and the possibility of its combination by the categories. And when this much had been settled, it may have almost seemed as if there was nothing more to be done in the matter. True, time and space would not have been transcendentally deduced in the highest sense of the term. They would still have retained their unaccountable character and only a de facto existence. Necessary they would be, as things happen to be, but wherefore this necessity would not appear. But waiving in their favour the stringencies of trans- cendental rigour, the fact that the imagination is apparently sensuous, and yet has commerce with the conceptions of the understanding, may have seemed to 62 A SCHEMATISM, AND THE PRINCIPLES. 63 have promised relief from further trouble on that score. The mediation, such as it is, would be certainly mechanical, and the imagination would rank no higher than a tertium quid called in from without. But, in point of fact, as we warned the reader in the begin- ning, Kant always proceeds as if a machine was his guiding idea. And now we may frankly add, what- ever the shock may be to the reader's lofty ideal of a transcendental criticism, and whatever may have been Kant's real intentions, that this desire for obtaining perspicuity in arrangement, this forced concession from spherical thought to linear exposition, completely defeated itself and led Kant into the perpetration of genuine mechanical iniquities, till it sometimes seems as if the conception of an organism was as effete a supersti- tion as it now is to the method of molecular physics, so that bewilderment possesses the intelligent student in- stead of light. When we have discharged our duty in thus describing Kant's actual procedure in contradis- tinction to what he ought to have done, the reader will probably feel that in truth the tertium quid has solved the opposition between perception and conception as far as Kant's "Critique" is concerned, and that his labours are at an end regarding this point, although the philosophy he desiderates requires something higher and more profound. If he does think this, we can only excuse ourselves again on the ground of duty and tell him that he is greatly mistaken. For the invocation of imagination does not complete the explanation, even on the Kantian method in its actual operation. 64 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. 1. Just as our sensibility and understanding are re- stricted to rules, it may be that the synthetic process in the imagination is likewise subject to rules. Now since these rules would presumably be of importance in determining the final product, experience, for they would evidently acquaint us with a priori laws more akin to experience, and therefore more available for concrete application, (because the abstractness of con- ceptions would be tempered by their connection with the forms of sense,) it is obligatory on a criticism which aspires to adequacy to discover if possible the presence and nature of any such rules. It is this quest in which we now proceed to follow Kant. Of the two pure forms of perception, time alone is common to all experience. In point of fact, spatial cognition is secondary to temporal, for, so to speak, it has to be translated through time. If therefore any rules are found obtaining between the categories and the forms of sense, the principal interest will attend those respecting the determination of time by the understanding. There must be a process of deter- mination subsisting between the two, and this process Kant calls “schematism," and the rules themselves schemata. Our object therefore will be to understand the schematism of the categories, and to discover the schemata. Now schematism, since it is the mediation between sense and understanding, must be partly sensuous and SCHEMATISM, AND THE PRINCIPLES. 65 partly intellectual. These requisites are provided by imagination. In fact, "the schema is, in itself, always a mere product of imagination" ("Critique," p. 109). Evidently, therefore, imagination demands more atten- tion from us than we have hitherto bestowed upon it, and Kant assigns to it a very important function. The bone of contention between Nominalists and Realists he hands over to the imagination. In it we possess the general ideas through which much of our reasoning is done, and which we can concretely realize at pleasure. For example, in it I possess the idea of dog in general. By means of this I can ratiocinate with confidence, for through it I am conscious that I could construct a dog in particular. In short, in the imagination there is a power by which abstract in- determinate concepts are formed, and become applic- able at pleasure to concrete realizations. The attribu- tion to the imagination of this power of possessing concepts involves the attribution of another kind of concepts. Supposing, as we must, that schematism does take place, and takes place according to rules, the schemata will be rules of a precisely similar character to these general ideas. By means of them the understanding becomes related to time and space. They will be general rules according to which time and space are related to the understanding, so that particular experi- ences will have to be so far formed in obedience to them. Thus the schema is neither an intuition nor an image, but a general rule obtaining between intuition F J 66 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. and understanding (just as the idea of dog in general obtains between my mind and particular dogs), accord- ing to which all cognitions must be apprehended. And these rules are not the categories, which are the understanding itself, but rules obtaining between the categories and sense, and so are other than the cate- gories, though partaking of their abstract nature as well as of the special character of sense. The nature of these schemata will perhaps however become clearer after they have been enumerated. The categories under the head of quantity are schematised by number. Both in time and space all objects are quanta; and these quanta are formed by the successive addition of homogeneous units: in other words, number is the schema of quantity. The categories under quality are reality, negation, and limitation. Now reality is the presence, negation the absence, of content in time. And this content must be sensuous. Sensation may be more or less intense in degree, from infinity to nothing, without reference to the length of time it occupies. Yet it must be in time. Degree therefore is the schema of quality. Substance The schemata of relation are as follows. is schematised as that which remains permanent through all change, and its schema is thus the "substratum of the empirical determination of time." Causality is schematised as invariable sequence, or "the succession of the manifold, in so far as that succession is subjected to a rule." And reciprocity, or "the reciprocal causality SCHEMATISM, AND THE PRINCIPLES. 67 as in- of substances. in respect of their accidents," variable coexistence, or coexistence according to a universal rule. Modality contains possibility, actuality, and neces- sity. The first is schematised simply as freedom from contradiction in existence so far as time is concerned; actuality as existence at some definite time; and necessity as existence at all times. Schematism therefore is really the restriction laid upon the categories by the form of inner sense, and the schemata are the specific restrictions themselves. "Schemata are nothing but a priori determinations of time according to rules; and these, in regard to all possible objects, following the arrangement of the categories, relate to the series in time, the content in time, the order in time, and finally to the complex or totality in time." And these "schemata of the pure conceptions of the understanding are the true and only conditions whereby our understanding receives an application to objects, and consequently signifi- cance ("Critique," p. 112). Accordingly, these schemata indicate a priori conditions of possible objects, in other words, a priori laws of nature. "" 2. The schematism of the categories has treated of the sensuous conditions under which alone the pure conceptions of the understanding can be employed in the production of experience. Now we come "to treat of those synthetical judgments which are derived 68 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. a priori from pure conceptions of the understanding under those conditions, and which lie a priori at the foundation of all other cognitions, that is to say," we come to "treat of the principles of the pure under- standing." ("Critique," p. 106.) The Principles then will be the subject of this section. And inasmuch as they are synthetical judgments derived directly from the operation of the categories on the forms of sense, their practical interest greatly exceeds that of the schemata. The schemata only indicated the rules to which all possible objects must conform; the prin- ciples lay down the judgments themselves proceeding from these rules, and applicable to every day experi- ence, by which perception is invested with a signifi- cance without which our ordinary thinking process, and therefore scientific method, would be devoid of foundation. Corresponding therefore to each cate- gory and schema there will be a principle, their resultant, whose empirical importance will demand, in some cases, care on the student's part, and excuse for obscuring anxiety on Kant's. The list of the categories, as the reader will have noticed, was divided into two groups. The first group, comprising those under Quantity and Quality, was marked off as mathematical; the second group, comprising those under Relation and Modality, was distinguished as dynamical. Whilst engaged with their discovery, it did not seem expedient to notice Kant's incidental remarks concerning the peculiarities of his table of categories. But now we must call SCHEMATISM, AND THE PRINCIPLES. 69 attention to this natural grouping and Kant's obser- vation thereon. He said that the first group related "to objects of intuition-pure as well as empirical; the second, to the existence of these objects, either in relation to one another, or to the understanding." ("Critique," p. 67.) This distinction becomes material when applied to the principles. Briefly, it comes to this. The mathematical principles are those controll- ing the imagination (here literally) of objects in space and time, irrespective of their existence. The dyna- mical ones are those determining objects as existent, or in certain definite relations to the rest of the world. In other words, the two groups deal respect- ively with possibility for imagination and posited existence. Taking them in their order, the mathematical prin- ciples are: I. Axioms of Intuition; II. Anticipations of Perception. The first is that: "All intuitions are extensive quantities." This follows from the fact that all objects must be represented in time and space. These are extensive quanta, of one and three dimen- sions respectively; therefore, all perceptions are ex- tensive quanta also. The second is that: "In all phenomena the real, that which is an object of sensa- tion, has intensive quantity, that is, has a degree." This is proved by the necessity of time for the matter of all phenomena to appear in; and on this account the sensation must be conceived to have de- veloped intensively from nothing to what it is in time, and therefore to have degree. 70 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. The practical application of both principles con- sists in their justification of mathematics. But of the second one even more may be added, to wit, the im- possibility of proving the existence of a vacuum. For a vacuum, with no intensive quantity in it, would be inconsistent with the a priori conditions of experience, and therefore can never be perceived. And it is not legitimate to argue from variations in the intensity of our perceptions to absolute non-existence of the matter, since we cannot tell whether the variations may not be due to the variations of the matter itself in its qualitative intensity. So much for the mathematical principles. The dynamical principles will detain us somewhat longer; but this we need not regret, for the first class refers to points of especial interest for these times. Their greater importance is due to the fact that they deal with the conditions of knowledge and existence for us, and not with the conditions of imagination; thus they are more likely to excite controversy and provoke sceptical attacks, whilst some of them, or at any rate their theses, are indispensable for the rele- vancy of scientific doctrines. The two classes are: III. The Analogies of Experience; and IV. The Pos- tulates of Empirical Thought. The first analogy, for here it is worth while to draw out each one belonging to the three categories, is the principle of the permanence of substance, and runs thus: "In all changes of phenomena, substance is permanent, and the quantum thereof in nature is neither SCHEMATISM, AND THE PRINCIPLES. 71 increased or diminished." Its proof may be epitomised thus. All experience is varying in one time. Unless the unity of time were presupposed, change could not be experienced. But time in itself cannot be an ob- ject of perception, but is a mere form given to the relations of perception, which presupposes that they are otherwise related. Therefore this unity must be sought for elsewhere. time, so all changes must be in one permanent object. The conception of the permanence of the object is im- plied in all determination of its changes." (Caird, p. 454.) And therefore the principle of the permanence of substance is necessary for all experience. "As all times are in one Mr. Balfour carps at the pretended cogency of this argument because, as he says, Kant himself has given us the means of avoiding the transcendental necessity. Although it is contended that the experience of change is impossible without a permanent substratum, Kant remarks that: " employing an expression which seems somewhat paradoxical, we may say that 'only the per- manent (substance) is subject to change; the mutable suffers no change, but rather alternation, that is, when certain determinations cease, others begin."" ("Cri- tique,” p. 140.) Now it is no part of mine to en- deavour to maintain the integrity of Kant's argument, but I must ask the reader to peruse carefully this passage and its context before he concedes to Mr. Balfour that it is virtually a surrender of the main argument, in that alternation is admitted as a possible experience and therefore, it is to be presumed, as a • 72 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. possible substitute for change in a permanent sub- stratum, thus overthrowing the transcendental ne- cessity. It will appear to him, as I think, that Kant was here abstracting from the substratum, and was referring to its varying determinations alone, in calling them the mutable and the alternating, and never in- tended it to be thought that either the mutable or the alternating ever really existed even for us by itself, and were other than the varying determinations of substance. The observation may have been un- necessary, but this is no reason for lightly attribut- ing to any writer, and to Kant least of all, such self-stultification as this would amount to, and which after all could be easily suggested by an emphasis on the definite article before "mutable" and neglect of the context. As a consequence of this analogy, it follows that the creation and annihilation of substance are im- possible for experience, and unthinkable in themselves. The law of causality is the subject of the second analogy. Its thesis is that: "All changes take place ac- cording to the law of the connection of cause and effect." The proof of this, as expounded by Kant. himself, is so confused and misleading that it will be better to neglect the original entirely, until its genuine import has been learnt from other sources. In fact, if we strictly adhered to Kant's own words we should have to accept two contradictory arguments without any means of reconciling them. So we will be content here with that one which the followers of Kant's way SCHEMATISM, AND THE PRINCIPLES. 73 of thinking believe to be sound, and this may be summarised in the following manner.¹ on. As in the first analogy, the proof depends on the judgment of sequence. The sequence of perceptions involves the relation of the first to the second and so And this relation must be precisely that of the moments of time to one another, viz. the first must pre- cede the second and not vice versa. We might think then that in sequence events were simply related by being dated in connection with the moments of time as they occurred in time. But this cannot be. Time per se is incognisable and not a thing by itself, and therefore cannot serve as the index of sequence. It follows then that events must be directly related to one another in an irreversible order, in other words, as cause and effect. The understanding therefore can only apprehend sequence through the schema of invariable succession according to a rule, and this is just the principle of causality. Otherwise, cognition would be impossible, since sequence requires an irre- versible order like the moments of time, but which order time itself cannot give, and which the under- standing, appropriately schematised, can only provide by means of the causal judgment. In fact, our uni- verse as it rests between the unity of self-conscious- ness and the thing-in-itself, is necessarily of such a nature that "the subsequent state of the world is the effect of the previous state." ¹ Professor Adamson has bestowed special attention on Kant's view of causality. See "On the Philosophy of Kant," p. 56. 74 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. ¡ What significance this view may have for science and its laws of nature we must decline to consider here. As it stands, it is clear that scientific laws can get little or no help from it, unless it is established that there are ascertainable threads running through the phases of cosmic succession, and. that in these threads like events do occur, to be followed by like consequents. Science herself can never do more than throw an air of probability on such a conjecture; but we may permit ourselves to indicate, though with some scruple regarding the integrity of our limits, that this analogy gives a clue to the process of our thought which may possibly be applied with success to the clearing up of scientific method. We must bear in mind that, according to Kant's general argumenta- tion, the universe, as we know it, is in its general features a product of thought, and to this extent may be investigated a priori. It is not unlikely, therefore, that thought in a more extended analysis may find in itself the truth, more and more detailed and intimate, of the world; that this extension may be found finally to issue in our ordinary scientific procedure; that, in fact, science may prove to be the realization to itself of thought which constitutes the world; that, in fine, pure thought will find its correlate, or rather identity, in the universe; and that thus from this analogy the justification might move on to the establishment of present empirical laws on a rational basis through their traceable connection with its thesis. Be it understood however that these words, liable as they SCHEMATISM, AND THE PRINCIPLES. 75 are to misconstruction, do not suggest any theory for constructing science a priori, or for re-thinking the thoughts of the Creator, but merely indicate a move- ment from the doctrine of this principle to our actual scientific procedure, whereby our empirical generalisa- tions might be supported by a manifest and valid con- nection with our transcendental necessity. And this, we mean to hint, can only be done by a logic which manifests the universe in all its complexity as thought and the knowledge thereof as thought's self-realization. But we feel that we have strayed, and must return to our business. Our exposition of Kant's doctrine on this point has been necessarily curtailed. It does not pretend to ex- pound him literally; such I think would be impossible, if we desired to preserve our respect for him. But the above gives the argument to be extracted from his writings on this point which his abler expounders undertake to maintain or think to tend to edification. : Its The third analogy treats of reciprocity. thesis is "All substances, in so far as they can be perceived in space at the same time, exist in a state of complete reciprocity of action." The proof resembles the above, mutatis mutandis, that is, space is introduced in the place of time. Professor Caird's account of it is so appropriate for our present purpose that we quote it entire. "We cannot represent objects as co-exist- ing, by a direct reference of them to space; for space is not perceived by itself, and objects are perceived as in space only when they are related to each other, as 76 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. the parts of space are related. The relation of spaces must therefore be perceived in objects, if these objects are to be perceived as in space. But the parts of space are necessarily represented as reciprocally deter- mining each other. Hence, only in so far as phe- nomena are represented as reciprocally determining each other, can they be referred to objects in space. The same necessity, therefore, with which each space is represented as determined by all other spaces, must be found in the relations of objects, for only as it is found in the relations of objects can it be found in the relations of the spaces which they occupy" (p. 456). After what has been said on the preceding analogies, nothing can be required to be added to this exposition of the last one. And so we turn to the principles under the head of modality. "" The postulates of empirical thought are: 1. "That which agrees with the formal conditions (in- tuition and conception) of experience is possible.' 2. "That which coheres with the material conditions of experience (sensation) is real." 3. "That whose coherence with the real is determined according to universal conditions of experience is (exists) neces- sary. The following remarks of Kant sufficiently manifest their significance. 'The categories of modality possess this peculiarity, that they do not in the least determine the object, or enlarge the con- ception to which they are annexed as predicates, but only express its relation to the faculty of cognition. Hereby the object itself is not more definitely "" SCHEMATISM, AND THE PRINCIPLES. 77 determined in thought, but the question is only in what relation it, including all its determinations, stands to the understanding and its employment in experi- ence, to the empirical faculty of judgment, and to the reason in its application to experience. For this very reason, too, the categories of modality are nothing more than explanations of the conceptions of possi- bility, reality, and necessity, as employed in experience, and at the same time, restrictions of all the categories to empirical use alone, not authorising the transcend- ental employment of them." ("Critique," p. 161–2.) Our knowledge of Kant's thought already obtained, and the coming extension of it in the Dialectic, render any commentary on these points of possibility, reality, and necessity quite superfluous. We will note, how- ever, that it is in this connection that Kant introduces his formal refutation of idealism, that is, of the pro- blematical idealism of Descartes. In it he combats the doctrine that external objects as determined in space. are indirectly known, but asserts that the knowledge of them is even prior to that of internal phenomena. The coherence of the reasoning of the refutation with the rest of Kant's argumentation is, to say the least, very doubtful; and as in truth a survey of his Critique" is quite complete without it, there is no occasion for us to perplex ourselves with it.¹ (( 1 For the critical exposition of this point see Caird's Philosophy of Kant," p. 475, and Adamson's "Lectures," p. 66. As these pages are going to press I have become acquainted with Professor Watson's new book, "Kant and his 78 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. + This really concludes the Transcendental Analytic. We have now rapidly exhibited the elements of Kant's logic of truth. We have seen him start from the standpoint of the ordinary consciousness, we have followed him with long strides as he detected first the pure forms of sense intuition, then in his quest for the pure forms of synthesis in the understanding, in his transcendental deduction of them when found and demonstration that they were functions of unity be- longing to the transcendental ego, and in his recogni- tion of the office of the imagination and its schematic forms. Finally, we have arrived with him at the principles, and have discretely acquainted ourselves with his proofs of these necessary elements in all experience. And this has brought us to the end of the logic of truth. The process of thought thus ex- hibited is that which Kant believes to make truth for us from incognisable sense, and apart from which nothing whatever can be known by us. So far as this is correct, Kant has a good right to call it the logic of truth, and in some sense a philosophy. Yet the student's labour has not herewith ended. English Critics," in which this discussion is renewed in re- lation to recent controversy on the subject. In the same work a more literal interpretation is given of Kant's proof of causation than that adopted above, and may be profitably consulted by readers interested in Kantian exegesis; see especially p. 214 ff. # CHAPTER VI. THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 1. t"སྡུ 29 In the course of the foregoing part of the "Critique we have been incessantly reminded that each of the elements therein distinguished is meaningless unless connected with the rest of the factors in experience, including the manifold of sense. In fact, the utmost that we can know, according to the doctrine of the Analytic, is what we might sensuously perceive if only our organs of perception were fine enough, and which we become cognisant of by inference from facts that we have perceived. Nevertheless, it is a remarkable peculiarity of the human spirit that it refuses to be confined in its activity to the acquisition of mere sensuous experience and inferences of a similar nature. On the contrary, the ablest minds have devoted them- selves to the study of the supra-sensible, and the most vulgar souls are not destitute of some theory or other respecting the unseen and unfelt. It is useless, there- fore, or at any rate not very persuasive, to point to our logic of truth and stigmatise all that does not precisely conform to it as idle dreaming. The facts of the case are such that he who fashions a logic of 79 80 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT, truth limited to the empirical must be ready with a logic of illusion to account for man's persistent devia- tion from the world of experience. Error is as integral a part of this world as truth, and demands as justly an explanation. And accordingly this duty Kant saw to be no less incumbent on him than the construction of his logic of truth. The execution of the one is equally characteristic of him as that of the other. In- deed he is quite as celebrated for the one achievement as he is for the other; one class of thinkers honouring him for his explorations into the logic of truth, another class for his iconoclastic zeal in his logic of illusion. We have surveyed the first; we now come to its suc- cessor, and happily the difficulty of its consideration will prove to be less severe than that of the task which has hitherto occupied us. In preparation for the logic of illusion, the Trans- cendental Dialectic, Kant towards the end of the Analytic discusses the status of supra-sensible know- ledge. The very slightest philosophy has at all times been sufficient to convince men with a turn for reflec- tion that our experience is phenomenal, that what appears to us is only appearance, and that the real thing in itself, the basis and cause of the appearance, is unperceived by us and unperceivable, since we can only perceive what appears. Thus has been instituted the contrast between our unsubstantial world of phenomena, the transient existence of the worldling, and the real unseen world of noumena, the true reward of the pious and the thoughtful. To such a point has THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 81 the contrast been extended, that to die for the one has been pronounced to be life for the other. Yet if our logic of truth is correct, not only must such notions. be erroneous, but it seems hard to account for the existence of such an idea as this one of noumenon. Certainly it cannot be due to any of the elements which the logic of truth has brought to light; but nevertheless, though thus denied universality and necessity, it has at times been a widely prevalent tenet. The Analytic has proved that this idea cannot be apprehended under the categories, for these are im- palpable if void of sense, and a noumenon is essentially non-sensuous, even if no other characteristic can be given of it than this negative one. Still, alike to the vulgar and the thinker, the philosopher and the re- ligionist, such an idea has always seemed intelligible if not quite correct. The fact is, says Kant, that the notion entirely proceeds from a confusion of thought; and he professes to place his finger on the point of transposition and indicate the source of the whole delusion. His words are: "Apperception, and with it thought, precedes any possible definite arrangement of our ideas. Hence we think of an object in general and give it a sensuous determination; but at the same time we distinguish the object, taken in abstracto, from the particular mode in which we apprehend it by And though it be true that such bare thought is but a logical form without content, yet in this case it seems to be a mode in which the object exists in itself, apart from the limits of our sense perception." sense. G 82 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. (Caird, p. 500; "Critique," p. 207.) Kant concludes therefore that the idea of noumenon is entirely illusive, and is generated by an excusable equivoque, the more excusable because, as he points out, it calls attention to the limitation of our experience. The worth of this explanation is not a question to detain us here. We must hasten on to the Trans- cendental Dialectic itself. This being Kant's logic of illusion has for its object to trace the consequences resulting from this pseud-idea of noumenon, to grapple with it in its systematised and developed forms, and to define precisely its true value and transcendental function after its pretensions have been exhibited and eviscerated. 2. These fallacious developments are the property of what is called metaphysic. Metaphysic aims at a knowledge, and claims not a little, of what is beneath and beyond the sensible, in short, of noumena. The Dialectic will therefore be a criticism of the various branches of metaphysic, which criticism, to be relevant and effective, must also make manifest the source of all this illusive thinking and its true significance. Now just as the ordinary logic served as a guiding thread to the logic of truth, so we may hope that it will give the clue to that illusive movement of thought which brings man into this region of noumena metaphysic. This surmise we shall find to be correct, and the prosecution of our investigation need suffer or THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 83 no delay. Logic treats not only of apprehension and judgment, but also of reasoning. Reasoning is medi- ate inference, the movement from one term to another by means of a third one. This third term acts as a principle, under which the others are subsumed and so connected. This in its turn is also liable to be sub- sumed under a higher principle, and so on in a series of prosyllogisms till a supreme principle is reached. In default of this, reason urges to the questionable satisfaction of an infinite regress. As this is the scheme of formal ratiocination, so it is the plan of the growth of real knowledge. We can never be con- tent with a fixed proposition founded on contingent experience. We are ever anxious to pass on from one proposition to another in a series of prosyllogisms, searching for the ground of the last and again for the ground of this. And this onward tendency is not the syllogistic craze of a monomaniac. Reason has a vague but sure belief in an existent goal to which she presses; her strivings have definite objects in view, intangible though they be; her efforts are not aimless : in short, she is guided by ideas. These ideas at which reason aims we may slightly characterize beforehand. First, they will be such as to afford to the categories of the understanding an all-embracing unity. Of the categories themselves, that of reciprocity is the high- est; but this entirely fails to satisfy the desire for unity which moves reason. Reciprocal determination is merely a relation subsisting between co-existing objects, and in no way approaches that ideal eminence ! 84 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. from which the universe might be gathered up into one or two formulæ. But reason aims at some supreme unifying principle, combining the forms of the understanding much as they combine the mani- fold of sense, where its regressive urgencies may cease. And, secondly, these ideas must be ideas of the unconditioned. If they were not such, but were themselves conditioned, reason would fail to find therein rest, but would forthwith struggle on after the next condition, and so on for ever. The unconditioned therefore is the object of reason. Again, inasmuch as a movement from conditioned to unconditioned cannot be due to mere analysis, since from the conditioned analysis can only extract a condition of the same limited nature and not an unconditioned condition, it follows that synthesis will be required to attain to the unconditioned, that reason must introduce some- thing additional from somewhere or other; and, fur- ther, since this something cannot possibly be derived from experience, this synthesis must be transcendent (not transcendental), must be due to that which trans- cends experience; in short, a synthesis of pure thought must be implied in the movement of reason. which attains its final object. The inspiring ideas of reason will therefore be unifying, will be uncondi- tioned, and will be pure. We must now inquire what these pure ideas are. Kant again has recourse to formal logic, and finds that to each of the forms of the syllogism there must cor- respond an idea. "To the number of modes of relation THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 85 which the understanding cogitates by means of the categories, the number of pure rational conceptions will correspond. We must therefore seek for, first, an unconditioned of the categorical synthesis in a subject ; secondly, of the hypothetical synthesis of the members of a series; thirdly, of the disjunctive synthesis of parts in a system. There are exactly the same number of modes of syllogisms, each of which proceeds through prosyllogisms to the unconditioned: one to the subject which cannot be employed as a predicate, another to the pre-supposition which supposes nothing higher than itself, and the third to an aggregate of the members of the complete division of a conception." ("Critique," p. 226; cf. Caird, p. 523.) Hence from the categorical, hypothetical, and disjunctive syllogisms we may arrive at a complete enumeration of the pure ideas. Moreover, a similar result may be secured by referring to the three supposed metaphysical sciences, (then of some repute, but not much heard of since,) which take the most general aspects of existence for their themes. Cor- responding to the idea of the categorical syllogism, rational psychology treated of the unconditioned sub- ject of all our thought and feeling; rational cosmology of the unconditioned unity of cosmic existence, to the same end as that indicated by the hypothetical syl- logism; and lastly, after the last syllogism, rational theology of the Unconditioned Being in whom alone the others have their being. Self, the world, and God, in their essence and unity are then the ideas of reason. Whatever is may be referred to one of these existences, • 86 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. and reason therefore endeavours to gather up existence under these ideas; and by investigating the ideas themselves metaphysic strives to obtain a knowledge of all that most deeply touches man's thought and destiny. Now if the Analytic has given us a complete and accurate description of our knowledge as it is, and its possible extension, it is clear that these metaphysical sciences are vain and baseless. To make objects of knowledge of pure ideas is impossible for an intelli- gence such as we are said to possess. Our knowledge is confined to the empirical, and non-empirical objects, even if they existed, are as good as nothing to us. Nevertheless, we cannot summarily dismiss these ideas from all further serious consideration on account of their nonconformity to empirical conditions. They exist, in their number and in their nature, to some extent at least, necessarily from the rules of our intelligence. Thus they are transcendental, and as such must meet with their due at the hands of a trans- cendental criticism. It may be that, though to posit them as objects of knowledge is an error, yet their true functions may be discoverable and well worth investigating. This we must therefore try to do. But first the pretensions of their scientific develop- ments must be examined. In this way we shall be sure to miss nothing that can be said in their favour; and at the same time it is not unlikely that their true value may appear, and what transcendental necessity they possess may be incidentally exhibited. Kant THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 87 Our therefore subjects in turn rational psychology, cos- mology, and theology to a critical examination. business now is to follow him, as far as we can, in this investigation. "" 3. To begin with rational psychology. This must not be confounded with empirical psychology, which studies the nature and relations of so-called states of con- sciousness, and whose data are mental phenomena qua phenomena, calling in all available anatomical and physiological knowledge to co-operate with introspec- tion in its investigation into the mental life. Rational psychology, on the contrary, is thoroughly metaphysical and has nothing to do with what is empirical. It is concerned with the nature and existence of the soul, the subject of all our thought and experience, the "I think in its simplicity apart from every passing state, and the a priori conclusions to be derived from this transcendental unity. The gist of its method con- sisted, according to Kant, in concluding, "from the transcendental conception of the subject which contains no manifold, the absolute unity of the subject itself, of which I cannot in this manner attain to a concep- tion" ("Critique," p. 236). This dialectical argu- ment he calls a paralogism, and he devotes a chapter to the exposure of the paralogisms of rational psy- chology. But since the ulterior conclusions arrived at on the assumption that the "I think وو may be 88 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. determined by the categories are not of much interest to us here, and since it would therefore betray us into too great elaboration to enumerate them with Kant's · exposure of their latent paralogisms, we must be con- tent with a general indication of their fallacious nature. This can be best obtained by quoting the following passage from Professor Caird, which must be quite clear to the reader after what has been said respecting the transcendental ego at the end of the deduction of the categories: "The supposed science of rational psychology is based on a confusion between the trans- cendental subject and the object of inner sense, and upon a transference to the latter, as real predicates, of the logical characteristics which belong to the former. The syllogisms of rational psychology are therefore paralogisms (sophismata figurae dictionis), in which the middle term is taken in two different senses; what is asserted in the major of objects of possible perception, being applied in the minor to the trans- cendental subject, which is not and cannot be an object of any perception. In this way the categories, which can be applied only to the former, are transferred to the latter, and the universal conditions, under which objects are thought, are turned into universal predi- cates of thinking beings as objects." (P. 541.) Ac- cordingly no such science as rational psychology is possible. No answer can be given to its questions, for the questions treat of that which cannot be known and only arise from sheer confusion of thought. A flat denial that the subject can be made an object of THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 89 thought is the only way of meeting its assertions, un- less of course we choose to follow Kant in pointing out in detail the fallacy lurking in its main doctrines. The psychological idea, therefore, provides no basis for the construction of an a priori science, but it is of a regu- lative use in giving unity to our knowledge of inner phenomena; and this is its true transcendental value. Rational cosmology calls for more attention. In certain respects its case differs remarkably from that of rational psychology. For whilst the latter is simply a onesided illusion, and merely requires light to dis- sipate it, the problems of cosmology are started by the dominant tendency of thought and result in pairs of antithetical solutions. The cosmological ideas, pursuant to reason's demands, are of course the un- conditioned conditions of the world in one space and time. It so happens that each class of the categories initiates one form of the unconditioned. For each category, in so far as it is generative of a serial move- ment, tends to a terminus, and it thus turns out that there are only four cosmological ideas, corresponding with the four titles of the categories. Now, as we shall find, these ideas eventually take the form of dilemmas, each horn of which is apparently equally eligible; and reason gives us no criterion to aid us in the choice of one alternative rather than another. Kant therefore decides that the only chance of a re- conciliation lies in a free and unrestrained conflict be- tween them; and this he proceeds to arrange forthwith. We too will, thanks to his care, become spectators of 90 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. : the fray, and as each duel comes on we shall see what manner of combatants are engaged.¹ The first antinomy (for such is Kant's name for these conflicts) springs from quantity. All phenomena are extensive magnitudes either in respect of space or time, and thus the question is provoked: What is the last. conditioning phenomenon in time and in space? and if there is no last, what is the sum of the series. composing the cosmic totality? In answer to this, the thesis may be maintained that "the world has a beginning in time, and is also limited in regard to space." To prove this, it may be said that if the world had no beginning in time, then at any given moment we must say that an eternity has elapsed, and this is the same thing as saying that what can never be com- pleted has been completed, which is absurd. Again, if the world has no limit in space, it must be an infinite given total: but a total, not given within certain limits of an intuition, cannot be given except by the com- pleted successive addition of its parts; and if the total be infinite, the addition could never be completed, and thus this denial also ends in an absurdity. There- fore the thesis has been established. But the antithesis to this may be maintained with equal cogency. It may as reasonably be contended that "the world has no beginning, and no limits in 1 If this abridgment of the antinomies appear to the reader over curt, he may consult the original without fear. As usual, Professor Caird's exposition is as perspicuous as it is adequate. • THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 91 space, but is, in relation both to time and space, in- finite." For if the world had a beginning, it must have begun in an empty time, in other words, at a time when there was no reason for it to be rather than not to be, and therefore could never have come into being at all. Similarly, limitation in space means limitation by space; but space is merely the possibility of external phenomena, and therefore cannot serve as a thing by itself to limit the world. In both respects, therefore, the world cannot be limited. Under the title of quality comes the question re- specting the intensive quantity of the matter of phe- nomena. It is required to reach an ultimate constitu- ent of this matter, or, if this does not exist, the sum of the infinite series of parts within parts composing it. The thesis, which first claims our attention, is that 'Every composite substance in the world consists of simple parts; and there exists nothing that is not either itself simple, or composed of simple parts." In proof of this it may be argued that, if there were no simple parts, then composition must itself be a sub- stantial existence: but composition is merely a rela- tion; therefore, simple parts must exist and constitute aggregates.¹ This argument is a curious deviation 1 Professor Caird remarks in a note on this antinomy, "Kant's statement of this argument is very obscure. It is unravelled by Hegel (Werke, vol. iii., p. 208). Hegel remarks that the word 'composite' is not in its proper place here; for it is merely tautology to say that the composite, as such, is made up of simple parts. What Kant means is rather 'the continuous.' 92 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. from the line pursued in the first antinomy; the pecu- liarity is due to the hold which the Leibnitzian doctrines still retained on Kant. The antithesis is no less urgent. It is clear that "no composite thing in the world consists of simple parts; and there does not exist in the world any simple substance." For inasmuch as space is made up of spaces and not of simple parts, therefore things in space cannot be made up of simple parts; and from the nature of the necessary manifold, it also follows that nothing either external or internal can be per- ceived as simple, because it must be manifold, and it is not legitimate to reason about things except as they may be perceived, as phenomena. The causal series is the theme of relation, and thus the third antinomy is brought about by the demand for a first uncaused cause, or, in default of this, for the sum of the infinite series of causes. On the one hand it is asserted that "Causality according to the laws of nature, is not the only causality operating to originate the phenomena of the world; a causality of freedom is also necessary to account fully for these phenomena." Since the law of causality postulates a sufficient a priori determined cause for every event, and since the causal series merely traces a regressive movement indefinitely extensible, it follows that, to save the law of causality from contradiction, there must exist an absolute spontaneity of cause originating causal series of phenomena. On the other hand it is retorted that "there is no THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 93 such thing as freedom, but everything in the world happens solely according to the laws of nature." In the light of the law of causality, a first uncaused cause is a contradiction in terms. It is contradictory to the law of causality to suppose a cause not itself causally determined; it is "destructive of the possibility of the unity of experience, and consequently a mere fiction of thought." Freedom therefore is as unsatis- factory as an infinite regress. The last antinomy is about the existence of a neces- sary Being. According to the categories of modality all phenomena are either contingent or only hypothe- tically necessary. We must therefore find a necessary Being to substantiate the hypothesis, or sum up the series of contingent phenomena into a necessary aggre- gate. Taking the first alternative, we propound the thesis: "There exists either in, or in connection with the world, either as a part of it, or as the cause of it, an absolutely necessary Being." For the contingent pre- supposes the necessary as its ground of existence, and therefore phenomena must be grounded on a necessary Being. But this necessary Being must be in the world; otherwise it could have no commerce with its temporal phases. Therefore there must be in the world a ne- cessary Being. "" The antithesis contends that "an absolutely neces- sary Being does not exist, either in the world, or out of it, as its cause. For if the contrary were correct, as regards necessary existence in the world, then "first, there must either be in the series of cosmical changes 94 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. a beginning, which is unconditionally necessary, and therefore uncaused, which is at variance with the dynamical law of the determination of all phenomena in time; or secondly, the series itself is without begin- ning, and although contingent and conditioned in all its parts, is nevertheless absolutely necessary and un- conditioned as a whole-which is self-contradictory. For the existence of an aggregate cannot be necessary, if no single part of it possesses necessary existence.' ("Critique,” p. 284.) And, on the other hand, the contrary cannot be true as regards a necessary Being out of the world, for a similar reason to that given in the thesis, viz. because it could have no commerce with the world save in time, and this would bring it into the world. Therefore there is no necessary Being in the world. "" Having arranged this conflict of assertions, Kant goes on to consider critically the situation, and begins with the following prefatory remark. "We have thus completely before us the dialectical procedure of the cosmological ideas. No possible experience can pre- sent us with an object adequate to them in extent. Nay, more, reason itself cannot cogitate them as ac- cording with the general laws of experience. And yet they are not arbitrary fictions of thought. On the contrary, reason, in its uninterrupted progress in the empirical synthesis, is necessarily conducted to them, when it endeavours to free from all conditions and to comprehend in its unconditioned totality, that which can only be determined conditionally in accordance THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 95 with the laws of experience. These dialectical pro- positions are so many attempts to solve four natural and unavoidable problems of reason. There are neither more, nor can there be less, than this number, because there are no other series of synthetical hypo- theses, limiting a priori the empirical synthesis." ("Critique,” p. 290.) Criticism must tell the secret of all this confusion. But, before we proceed to this, it is interesting to observe that the theses of the antinomies constitute one form of dogmatic philosophy, while the antitheses constitute an antagonistic form. While the former is calculated to edify the moral and religious conscious- ness, the latter recommends itself to the restlessness and enterprise of the scientific mind. While the one expounds definite and eternal truths, the other, always with one foot in the air," simply consists in a possibility of strenuous exertion. Thus both illustrate dominant tendencies of the human spirit; and though both are fallacious if taken absolutely, it may be that some sort of compromise may be ultimately effected between them. << After what has been said in a previous page on phenomena and noumena, it is not hard to see that an amphiboly is the source of our antinomian dogmatics. From the fact that all phenomena are conditioned, it is concluded that the unconditioned is necessarily im- plied. But, in truth, this is reasoning as if phenomena were noumena, or at any rate might be treated as such. In point of fact, however, a phenomenon is 96 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. only as it appears, and does not logically involve the unconditioned. All we can say is that a regressive movement is demanded for the better comprehension of phenomena, but we have no right whatever to understand more than this from their conditioned nature. Slipping from the conception of conditioned phenomena into the conception of conditioned noumena. is then the cause of these cosmological antinomies. Thus, in regard of the ideas issuing from the mathe- matical categories, neither thesis or antithesis is true. For instance, space is neither finite or infinite, but indefinitely extensible: that is, our perception of space is of such a character that it may be indefinitely extended, but we are not warranted to affirm a limit or assert its infinity as if it were a thing-in-itself. But the dynamical categories generate ideas which do not result in such hopeless antinomies as the mathe- matical. The falsity of the mathematical ideas is irredeemable, and there is nothing to be done for them except to point out where they err. The dynamical categories, however, are to this extent peculiar; they do not treat of homogeneous elements, but of possibly heterogeneous terms. Thus it is possible that while the thesis may apply to the noumenal world, the antithesis may apply to the phenomenal world. It may be quite true that there is no free cause in the phenomenal world, yet there may be a free cause in the noumenal world. But this is altogether uncertain on these principles. Both are untrue if taken abso- lutely as regards our world as it is, but it will be THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 97 possible to assent to the demonstration of free causes and necessary beings if such demonstration proceeds on noumenal principles, which noumenal principles, though discredited by the "Critique of Pure Reason," Kant takes care to observe may be reinstated on practical grounds.¹ We are now in a position to estimate the precise value of the cosmological ideas. Constitutive they are not in any sense. In no way can they be said to co-operate as integral factors in the formation of our knowledge. At the outset we saw that they would. have to be synthetic and pure if they were to compass their end, and since then no such claim has been established for them. So they cannot add anything to our knowledge. But like the psychological idea they are regulative, that is, they are guiding ideas for the extension of our empirical knowledge. The antinomies resulted from taking the onward move- ment of reason for a movement towards an already determined end. Now the movement cannot be ex- plained away; the notion of the end, therefore, as we have shown, is the real mistake. Conversely, the movement is the genuine characteristic of reason, the true function reason performs in knowledge. In short, these cosmological ideas of reason are regula- tive; they direct and stimulate inquiry, and lead the understanding to its fuller realization within the 1 For this part of Kant's speculations see the translations given in Mr. Abbott's "Kant's Theory of Ethics," and the ex- position in Professor Adamson's book. H 98 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. bounds of experience by means of an indefinitely extensible advance, just as the psychological idea focuses our knowledge of internal phenomena. 4. In the last section we have followed Kant's deriva- tion and criticism of the ideas proceeding from reason's treatment of the subject and object respect- ively. Now we come to his criticism of rational theology, or the idea of the Being in whom the two other worlds exist. This idea, as will be remembered, was also assigned to the movement of reason; cor- responding to the disjunctive form of the syllogism, it was pronounced to be the idea of the unconditioned aggregate of the members of a complete division of a conception. Since this relation to formal logic is not at once so obvious as in the case of psychology and cosmology, a word or two is necessary to explain the technical derivation. When we know an object as existent, we determine it as related to the whole of existence. Involved in an existential judgment is a reference to the totality of being, and only so far as we are guided by such an idea do our judgments obtain objective validity. The reference or relation to this idea must be positive or negative; either the object is positively related to every possible predicate, or it is negatively so. Thus the "either or "" of the disjunctive syllogism precisely typifies the kind of determination which an object involves in relation • THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 99 to the total of existence, when it is judged to be existent.¹ 2 But this total is after all but an idea. Yet inasmuch as we do not conceive the extension of our knowledge to be a process of creation, but to be the discovery of the already determined relations between the object and the total of existence, we conceive this idea of totality to be a thing-in-itself and, naturally, the ground of all things. Hypostatising this idea we arrive at a notion of a Supreme Being, and thus from the ideal of pure reason get to the conception of the God of theology. This realization of a guiding idea is of course quite a delusion, and by this time we know pretty well what Kant's verdict will be on such a proceeding. To him the step is perfectly un- authorised. But conformably to his usual tactics he goes on to add that: "It is not sufficient to circum- scribe the procedure and the dialectic of reason; we ¹ Compare the following passage from Prof. Jevons. "The criterion of false reasoning, as we shall find, is that it involves self-contradiction, the affirmation and denying of the same statement. We might represent the object of all reasoning as the separation of the consistent and possible from the incon- sistent and impossible; and we cannot make any statement except a truism without implying that certain combinations of terms are contradictory and excluded from thought. To assert that all 'A's are B's' is equivalent to the assertion that 'A's which are not B's cannot exist.”—The Principles of Science: a treatise on Logic and Scientific Method: 3rd ed., p. 32. 2 Here we see the transcendental value of the theological idea, its true function in the process of knowledge. 100 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. must also endeavour to discover the sources of this dialectic, that we may have it in our power to give a rational explanation of this illusion, as a phenomenon of the human mind. The question hence arises: how happens it that reason regards the possi- bility of all things as deduced from a single possibility, that, to wit, of the highest reality, and presupposes this as existing in an individual and primal Being?" ("Critique," p. 358.) The answer has been already given. Sensuous objects are given to us, and yet become objects to us only through their determination in relation to a totality, and by a natural illusion this ideal totality is taken for a given reality. This sum total of all reality is hypostatised "by changing the distributive unity of the empirical exercise of the understanding into the collective unity of an empirical whole, a dialectical illusion, and by cogitating this whole or sum of experience as an individual thing, containing in itself all empirical reality," which whole is then "substituted for our notion of a thing which stands at the head of the possibility of all things.' ("Critique," 359.) So much for the general character of the theological illusion; now for its scientific ex- pression. "There are only three modes of proving the exist- ence of a Deity, on the grounds of speculative reason. All the paths conducting to this end begin either from determinate experience and the peculiar con- stitution of the world of sense, and rise, according to the laws of causality, from it to the highest cause. THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 101 existing apart from the world; or from a purely inde- terminate experience, that is, some empirical existence; or abstraction is. made of all experience, and the existence of a supreme cause is concluded from a priori conceptions alone. The first is the physico- theological argument, the second the cosmological, the third the ontological. More there are not, and more there cannot be. As regards the order in which we must discuss these arguments, it will be exactly the reverse of that in which reason, in the progress of its development, attains to them, the order in which they are placed above. For it will be made manifest to the reader that, although experience presents the occasion and the starting point, it is the transcendental idea of reason which guides it in its pilgrimage, and is the goal of all its struggles." ("Critique,” 363–4.) We begin therefore with the examination of the ontological argument. The idea of God includes His existence; therefore, says this argument, He exists; in other words, we cannot think of Him except as existing, therefore He must exist. To illustrate this, such a conception as that of a triangle was frequently adduced, and just as three angles were seen to be necessarily involved in its conception, so, it was contended, existence was involved in the conception of God. True for both of them, replies Kant, if they existed; but the necessity of a judgment is quite independent of the necessity of a thing, and thus the very point at issue is avoided by the argument. A • 102 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. triangle may not exist, and so may not God. But perhaps it is maintained, "that there is one and only one conception, in which the non-being or annihilation of the object is self-contradictory, and this is the conception of an ens realissimum. 1 It possesses, it is said, all reality, and it is considered justifiable to admit the possibility of such a being. Now the notion of all reality embraces in it that of existence; the notion of existence lies therefore in the conception of this possible thing" ("Critique," 366). Here the copula is confounded with the verb of existence. Now the synthetic sense of the latter cannot be extracted from the analytic sense of the former; and thus to argue from the connection between a thought subject 1 The connection between God and the ens realissimum is in this way. God is conceived to be a necessary Being. Now, starting from our ordinary experience, we never arrive at anything absolutely necessary, but only hypothetically so on the existence of something else. And so we might go on for ever. But it is clear that if we could gather up the conditions of all that is possible, we should get that which was necessary in itself, because no conditions of its existence would be left out of account. This is the conception of the ens realissimum. And thus if we wanted to give the most probable definition of God, the necessary Being, we should refer to the ens realissimum as being the most appropriate and inclusive conception. The ens realissimum and the necessary Being might be used then as convertible terms, unless indeed the necessary Being were shown to partake of finitude, which is not inconceivable. Such a possibility, however, effectually prevents any demonstrative identification of the ens realissimum with the necessary Being. THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 103 and a thought predicate to the absolute position of both, when both may be suppressed without contradic- tion, is absurd, and therefore existence is not involved in the conception of the ens realissimum. In short, from a mere conception existence cannot be deduced. The ontological argument is an invention entirely due to the subtlety of the schools; but the cosmo- logical argument, formally starting from experience, promises a far more tangible result. "It is framed in the following manner: If some thing exists, an abso- lutely necessary being must likewise exist. Now I, at least, exist. Consequently, there exists an absolutely necessary being." ("Critique," 371.) In point of fact, however, this argument when turned to theological purposes contains the weakness of the ontological one with faults peculiar to itself. It makes an illegiti- mate extension of the category of cause (which is only of empirical validity) from experience to things-in- themselves, when it asserts that the existence of something must be grounded on a necessary being; it converts a mere idea into an object of knowledge. Then when it proceeds to identify the necessary being, thus obtained, with the ens realissimum (or God), the ontological fallacy is repeated; for in reasoning that the conception of the ens realissimum is the only con- ception by and in which we can cogitate a necessary being, we must presume that the two-the conception and the being-are convertible, and the ontological argument might then as well support the whole thesis and expiate the fallacy alone. 104 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. We now come to the stock argument of popular theology. "If, then, neither a pure conception nor the general experience of an existing being can pro- vide a sufficient basis for the proof of the existence of the Deity, we can make the attempt by the only other mode, that of grounding our argument upon a determinate experience of the phenomena of the present world, their constitution and disposition, and discover whether we can thus attain to a sound conviction of the existence of a Supreme Being. This argument we shall term the physico-theological argument." ("Critique," 381.) "The chief momenta in the physico-theological argument are as follows: 1. We observe in the world manifest signs of an arrangement full of purpose, executed with great wisdom, and existing in a whole of a content indescribably various, and of an extent without limits. 2. This arrangement of means and ends is entirely foreign to the things existing in the world; it belongs to them merely as a contingent attribute; in other words, the nature of different things could not of itself, whatever means were employed, harmoniously tend towards certain purposes, were they not chosen and directed for these purposes by a rational and disposing principle, in accordance with certain fundamental ideas. 3. There exists, therefore, a sublime and wise cause (or several), which is not merely a blind, all-powerful nature, producing the beings and events which fill the world in an unconscious fecundity, but a free and intelligent cause of the world. 4. The unity of this cause may be THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 105 inferred from the unity of the reciprocal relations existing between the parts of the world, as portions of an artistic edifice, an inference which all our observa- tion favours, and all principles of analogy support." ("Critique," 384.) Now the above argument depends on the con- tingency of the form, but not of the matter, of the world, in reasoning from the analogy of human art. But at the most this can only demonstrate the exist- ence of an architect of the world, and not a creator of the world.¹ It is therefore quite insufficient to prove the existence of an all-sufficient being. And even then the architect can only be credited with powers proportionate to his work. Now unless the idea of God. is defined by absolute totality, the conception of Him cannot be determinate, since otherwise we should but speak of Him relatively to our own empirical notions. But it is manifestly illegitimate to conclude, from our knowledge of the world, to perfect wisdom or any other totality. Therefore of the architect a God can never be made. And if a leap is made from the architect to a necessary being, then the defects of the cosmological argument are introduced; and if, further, from the ¹This concession waives the objection that any such relation is an illegitimate application of the category of cause. Kant is probably referring to this in his remark that it is “ a con- clusion which would perhaps be found incapable of standing the test of subtle transcendental criticism," when it is de- clared that "the internal possibility of this freely-acting nature (which is the source of all art, and perhaps also of human reason) is derivable from another and superhuman art." 106 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. necessary being the ens realissimum were deduced, then the fallacy of the ontological argument would be committed. "The physico-theologians have therefore no reason to regard with such contempt the trans- cendental mode of argument, and to look down upon it, with the conceit of clear-sighted observers of nature, as the brain-cobweb of obscure speculatists. For if they reflect upon and examine their own arguments, they will find that, after following for some time the path of nature and experience, and discovering them- selves no nearer their object, they suddenly leave this path and pass into the region of pure possibility, where they hope to reach, upon the wings of ideas, what had eluded all their empirical investigations." ("Critique," 386.) Our A speculative theology then is impossible. investigations have found no room for it, and have exhibited the vanity of its fallacious attempts. Yet room has been left for a proof of the existence of God by the practical reason. It may be that the moral law presupposes a Deity; and in that case our criticism avails nothing against it. But this belongs to another sphere of thought. "The result of all the dialectical attempts of pure reason not only confirms the truth of what we have already proved in our Transcendental Analytic, namely, that all influences which would lead us beyond the limits of experience are fallacious and groundless, but it at the same time teaches us this important lesson, that human reason has a natural inclination THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 107 to overstep these limits, and that transcendental ideas are as much the natural property of the reason as categories are of the understanding. There exists this difference, however, that while the categories never mislead us, outward objects being always in perfect harmony therewith, ideas are the parents of irresistible illusions, the severest and most subtle. criticism being required to save us from the fallacies which they induce." ("Critique," 394.)¹ Incidentally, through our summary of this criticism, we have noticed the real worth of these ideas. They are regulative, and not constitutive. They introduce life and unity into our knowledge, but do not stand for any real objects. 5. With the Transcendental Dialectic ends the Doctrine of Elements, and with this the critical examination of pure reason. The Doctrine of Method adds nothing more to this aspect of Kant's speculations, and, for the rest, touches only his practical philosophy." ¹ It has seemed undesirable to pursue Kant's further de- termination of the function and worth of these ideas in this summary: but the curious reader will find much valuable instruction on this point in the books of Professors Caird and Adamson. 2 In concluding my exposition here I have restricted the title of Critical Philosophy from conventional reasons only, and would be sorry to have it inferred that I acquiesce in the contrast between the criticism of this "Critique" and the dogmatism of Kant's subsequent writings. 108 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. On looking back, we can, without any very deep scrutiny, detect sundry points wherein the require- ments of transcendentalism are ignored. We have already noted the want of a proper deduction of space and time. The thing-in-itself is likewise left in a problematical position. Why the forms of perception are just what they are it is impossible to tell, and things in themselves are unknown and unknowable. How then can we be certain that we have rightly understood their nature? The unsatisfactory relation of these to the rest of the scheme of knowledge is sufficient to cast suspicion on the professed integrity of the whole; a suspicion which is confirmed by the very evident want of coherence among the categories. In tracing them back to the basis of their functional activity, nothing more than a hint, a hint not sufficiently prominent to warrant its introduction into our text, has been given respecting their inner con- nection and relationship, and to the last their detailed enumeration retains a fortuitous appearance. Yet Kant himself has taught us that contingent dis- coveries of this kind are useless, or at any rate incon- clusive for an adequate philosophy. The Dialectic criticises relevantly enough what it does criticise, but the speculative status of its subjects is never considered from any other point of view than that sanctioned by the logic of truth in its crudest inter- pretation. When however doubt is cast upon the adequacy of this logic, it becomes an obvious step to question the relevancy of the criticism which it sup- THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 109 ports, and to dispute the applicability of a dualistic method to our highest and most intimate spheres of thought. With the dark sayings of the religionist and the mystic in our ears, of Paul and Boehme, we can only allow the results of the Dialectic their final claims on sufferance, and must hesitate before we decide that the speculative reason is altogether incapable of coping with the ultimate mystery of things. Nevertheless, we do but poorly appreciate the significance of Kant's innovation if we think of its failings alone. We have seen him work his way from individualism to a higher point of view, within sight of an eminence whence the dualism of subject and object would be resolved into an all-embracing unity. First bringing over to the subject side time and space as forms of perception, then discovering in the subject's understanding the forms of thought which constitute our world, and then connecting these forms together as functions of a hidden unity (no longer the subject in its original literal sense), nothing but the influence of old habituations could have hidden from him the anomalous character of the ding an sich to which he held so firmly. The inevit- 1 ¹My remarks respecting Kant's thing-in-itself are entirely confined to his doctrines in the "Critique of Pure Reason." Of course they do not contemplate his later views in the two succeeding critiques. Whatever these may amount to, it is nevertheless necessary to emphasise the unsatisfactory position of the thing-in-itself in this his first and most im- portant work, both for the sake of present safety and future enlightenment. 110 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. able suggestion that all knowledge is a self-contained system seems so irresistible, the elimination of an unaccountable matter looks so probable, the need for coherence and interdependence is so imperative, the antagonism between thought and being becomes so transparent, that it appears at first strange that Kant did not cast about for some idea to guide him in thinking out more continuously the movement of synthetic thought whereby the old opposition of mind and matter might be entirely robbed of its destructive influence, in its comprehension in a higher unity. Thus he led up to a radically new way of regarding the problem of philosophy, yet persistently retained, with little modification, the old statement of it from which he started. Still we are not rashly to blame him on this ac- count. When Hegel sneers at him for refusing to enter the water because he had not learnt to swim, ani- madverting on his conduct in proposing to find the limits of our possible knowledge before he had really made the effort to think the Absolute, we cannot but recognise great unfairness in this and much similar usage. Kant did try to think out the movement of spirit whereby our world is what it is, as the foregoing has amply shown; but it was im- possible for the first man to do more than break the ground in this direction. Indeed it is wonderful that he did so much. Thought is a cryptograph, and a very recondite one too. A single philosopher, of the greatest power, could not distinguish and elucidate all · THE TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. 111 its intricacies at once. It is probable that different aspects, elements, and relations may be brought to light at different periods in the history of philosophy, but it is not likely that any such radical movement will ever come to pass again as that originated by Kant. Gradually mankind may come to read more clearly the enigma of the world-idea, but to Kant will be due the credit of first providing the means of making any progress whatever. He himself, we have said, did not truly comprehend the effect of his invest- igations. With great toil he worked out each point as it appeared to him, but the windings of his road hid from him the direction which he had been pursu- ing. While he has given us a clue to the solution of the dualism between subject and object, between God and the world, his "Critique of Pure Reason" often assumes a tone respecting the ineffaceable distinction between the mind and its experience, and the limits of our possible knowledge, which resembles both in word and propriety the language of Locke's essay. Nevertheless his effort was a genuine one and worthy of all admiration and respect, and a splendid repre- sentative of that great manner of thinking of which Leibnitz had been the last exponent. But our task is neither to criticise nor systematise, and what it was has been performed, however imper- fectly. By this time the reader can judge for himself whether there is much to be done in this line of inquiry, and can determine on his own responsibility whether it is worth while to study Kant more closely, or whether 112 THE CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF KANT. the better plan will be to proceed directly to succeed- ing systems, or whether it is the part of a wise man to relinquish for good all such speculations. But what we said at first will be found correct; that, be the decision what it may, Kant must be either consulted as a sage or reckoned with as a foe. Whether the reader derive benefit from the former course or fare successfully in the latter one, the time spent will not be wasted; in any case we may wish him prosperity, for with exposition we have done and with indoctrina- tion we do not deal. Butler & Tanner, The Selwood Printing Works, Frome, and London. * J 1/2