~i^l %. v^/ .0^,\^ IMAGE EVALUAT50N TtST TARGET (MT-3) // ^/ %\ V^ #? ^ /A. y 1.0 ^i^ IIIIIM i.i 11.25 .If 1^ 2.2 2.0 1.8 U 111 1.6 Photographic Sciences Corporation ^v .^% W^\ ^- C/.A 6 h CIHM/ICMH Microfiche CIHIVI/ICMH Collection de microfiches. Canadian Institute for Historical Microreproductions / Institut Canadian de microreproductions historiques Technical and Bibliographic Notes/Notes techniques et bibliographiques The Institute has attempted to obtain the best original copy available for filming. Features of this copy which may be bibliographically unique, which may alter any of the images in the reproduction, or which may signfficantly change the usual method of filming, are checked below. D Coloured covers/ Couverture de couleur P"^ Covers damaged/ Couverture endommagie Covers restored and/or laminated/ Couverture restaur^e et/ou pelliculde Cover title missing/ Le titre de couverture nanque Coloured maps/ Cartes g^ographiques en couleur □ Coloured ink (i.e. other than blue or blackl/ Encre de couleur (i.e. autre que bleue ou no □ Coloured plates and/or illustrations/ Planches et/ou illustrations en couleur □ Bound with other material/ Ralii avec d'autres documents noire) D n Tight binding may causa shadows or distortion along interior margin/ La re Mure serree peut causer de I'ombre ou de la diotorsion le long de la marge intdrieure Blank leaves added during restoration may appear within the text. Whenever possible, these have been omitted from filming/ II se peut que certaines pages blanches ajouties lors dune restauration apparaissent dans le taxte, mais, lorsque cela itait possible, ces pages n'ont pas 6ti filmies. y L'Institut a microfilme lu meilleur exemplaire qu'il lui a eti ptssibli de se procurer. Les details de cet exemplaire qui sont peut-dtre uniques du point de vue bibliographique, qui peuvent modifier une image reproduite, ou qui peuvent exiger una modification dans la m^thode normale de filmage sont indiqu^s ci-dessous. □ Coloured paoes/ Pages de cou.'eur The to tl I I Pages damaged/ Pages endommagdes Pages restored and/or laminated/ Pages restaurdes et/ou pelliculdes Pages discoloured, stained or foxed/ Pages d6color6es, tachet^os ou piquees Pages detached/ Pages ddtachees Showthroughy Transparence Quality of prir Quality inigale de I'impression Includes supplementary materia Comprend du materiel supplementaire Only edition available/ Seule Edition disponible \ I Pages detached/ [""71 Showthrough/ I I Quality of print varies/ I I Includes supplementary material/ I I Only edition available/ The pos) oft! film Grig begi the I sion uthe first sion or ill The shall TINL whic Map\ diffei entir begir right requi meth D Pages wholly or partially obscured by errata slips, tissues, etc., have been refilmed to ensure the best possible image/ Les page? totalement ou partiellement obscurcies par un feuillet d'errata. une pclure, etc., cnt 6t6 filmies d nouveau de facon a obtenir la meilleure image possible. Additional comments:/ Commentaires suppl^mentaires; Various pagings. This item is filmed at the reduction ratio checked below/ Ce document est film* au taux de riduction indiqud ci-dessous. lO^L !*^ 18X 22X 12X / 16X 20X 26X 30X 24X 28X 32X The copy fiimed hero has bMn reproduced thanks to the gnneroeity of: Dana Porter Arts Library University of Waterloo The images appearing here are the beat quality possible considering the condition and legibility of the original copy and ir keeping with the filming contract specificationa. Original copies in printed paper covers are filmed beginning with the front cover and ending on the last page with a printed or illuatrated impres- sion, or the back cover when appropriate. All uther original copies are filmed beginning on the first page with a printed or illuatrated impres- sion, and ending on the last page with a printed or illustrated impression. The last recorded frame oa each microfiche shall contain the symbol '^^> (meaning "CON- TINUED"), or the symbol V (meaning "END"), whichever applies. Maps, plates, charts, etc., may be filmed at different reduction ratios. Those too large to be entirely included in one exposure are filmed beginning in the upper left hand corner, left to right and top to bottom, as many frtifmes as required. The following diagrams illustrate the method: L'exempiaire film^ fut reproduit grdce d la gtn^rosit^ de: Dana Porter Arts Library University of Waterloo Les images suivantes ont dt4 raproduites avec le plus grand soin, compte tenu de la condition et de la nettet« de l'exempiaire film*, et en conformity avec les conditions du contrat de filmage. Lea axemplaires originaux dont la couverture en papier est imprimte sont film^s en commenpant par la premier plat et en terminant soit par la derniire page qui comporte une empreinte d'impression ou d'illustration, soit par le second plat, salon le cas. Tous les autres axemplaires origiriaux aont filmte en commenpant par la premtAro page qui comporte une empreinte d'impreaaion ou d'illustration et en terminant par la derniire page qui comporte une telle empreinte. Un des symboles suivants apparaftra sur la derni^re image de cheque microfiche, selon le cas: le symbole -^ signifie "A SUIVRE", le symbole V signifie "FIN". Les cartes, planches, tableaux, etc.. peuvent dtre film^s d des taux de reduction diffdrents. Lorsque le document est trop grand pour dtre reproduit en un seul cliche, il est film* d partir de Tangle supirieur gauche, de gauche h droite, et de haut en bas. en prenant le nombre d'imagea n^cessaire. Les diagrammrs suivants illustrent la mithode. 1 2 3 1 2 3 4 5 6 ^VWSft*yWW*<»».*»i»!**»s>fB,«^. KANTIAN ETHICS AND THE ^ ETHICS OF EVOLUTION. i Ao^eu6au ia-co, ^^Xrcov ehac Ka\ Secu eVi acorvp^a ye r-n^ aXvOeia, kuI rh oUela ?.va.pdv, dXXco, re\al c\oov, 6vra,- d^^olv y^p Svrocu CKo,v Sacov vpoTtfiav rrjv dXijOeiav. Aristotle : Eth. Nic, I. 4. KANTIAN ETHICS AND THE ETHICS OF EVOLUTION. A CRITICAL STUDY BY J. GOULD SCHTJEMAN M.A. (LoND.), D. Sc. (Ediij.), Professor OF Logic and Metaphtsics in Acadia College WovA Scotia, nd late Hibbeet Travelling Scholar. ' Publtsfjrt 62 tfie J^ihhtxt Exmtm. WILLIAMS AND NORGATE, 14. HENRIETTA STREET, COVENT GARDEN,' LONDON- AND 20, SOUTH FREDERICK STREET, EDINBURGH. ' 1881. Owys, r<. ^ »i«>. , ^X nupuiiy ui iiitj Liurary University of Waterloo m^ "■'• •-'"■' "'-f' ^■'.^'"^-'"^mmm^mmmgmmmillllllfli 1 LON-DON : 0, NIIRMAN AND SON, PRlrnEHS. 3Q, MAIDEN LANE. COVENT GARDEN. PREFACE The following Easmj, which is now published by the Hibbert Trustees, was written in Germany about a year ago, during the author's tenure of a Hibbe.^t Travelling Scholarship. The Essay is a critical study of the two represen- tative systems of Ethics, with one or other of which the names of most thinkers in England and America are at present associated. Mill and Hamilton, the philosophical leaders of the last generation, have chiefly f historical interest for ours; and the undying dualism of metaphysical thought is propagated in Critical Idealism and Evolutionistic Realism. Kant laid the foundations of the one, just a hundred years ago; Mr. Herbert Spencer, in our own day, has laid the foundations of the other. The present Essay attempts an estimate of the ethical philosophy of each of these teachers. The author has not assumed the infallibility of either system, and then proceeded to refute the other from this dogmatic standpoint: he has, on the contrary, made an honest ^1 » i. « VI TREPACE. endeavour to discriminate between the truth and the error which his studies led him to believe each system contained. He can sincerely say he has sought nothing but truth. And, in the quest of it, he hopes ho has not been disrespectful towards either of the eminent thinkers whose principles ho hero criticizes. In addition to the obligations acknowledged in the Essay itself, the author naturally owes much to the dis- tinguished professors of philosophy, in Great Britain and Germany, whose lectures he had the privilege of attending. But to one man, whose friendship it is an honour to have enjoyed,-to the broad scholar and the keen, discerning critic,-to the classic historian of Greek Philosophy and the foremost thinker of modern Europe,-to Professor Eduard Zeller of Berlin, the author desires to express special obligations for much that need not here be specified, but not least for his constant exemplification of the candid, truth-loving spirit described in the Aristotelian motto of this Essay,-a spirit of which it is hoped some reflex may be found in the following pages. Acadia Colleqk, VVoLFviLLE, Nova Scotia. July, 1881. ^ed in the bo the dis- Jritain and I CONTENTS. 1. Intelliqiblb and Empirical Character 2. Freedom of the Will 3. The Moral Principle 4. EvoLUTioNiSTic Hedonism . PAGE. . ] . 20 , 49 9 i K 1 Liir asti mei earl oft fact in a whii COU( in c the ance wer( sens hoM Intu Subs sensi that expe act KANTIAN ETHICS AND THE ETHICS OF EVOLUTION. 1. Intelligible and Empirical. Character. ^ The reform ivhich Kant inaugurated in Philosophy ho himself has likened tr ;he work of Copernicus. As the astronomer found himself unable to explain the pheno- mena of the heavens without attributing motion to the earth, which till then had passed for the motionless centre of the world; so the philosopher could give no satis- factory account of the fact of human knowledge, until, in association with a receptivity for v pressions of sensed which Empiricists rep.arded as the only condition, he conceived a spontaneity of intellect that manifested itself in combining and arranging those passive elements into the unity of an orderly experience. The laws in accord- ance with which this synthesis of thought was carried on were called Categories j and the forms into which the sensations fell, ere the Categories were applied to them, ho; ling partly of sense and partly of thought, were called Intuitions. Space and Time are Intuitions ; Causality and Substance are Categories. As distinguished from the sense-given elements of our knowledge, both are a priori: that is, they are constitutive of, and not derived from, experience; they are brought forth by the mind in the act of knowing, and not imposed upon it by the object 1 i i\ ^--■■■^ '"•'■■- - - -'I i'imiiiW»?»!«»»jeS»«^Bp»j^^ Ethics of Evolution. 3 Thus far of the Critique of knowledge, which is, how. ever, not the only problem of philosophy. The fact of morality also ne^ds an explanation, and Kant, as if pre- paring the way for his ethical investigations, endeavoured to show in his first Critique that the interpretation he had given the notion of causality did not necessarily conflict with the conception of human freedom.* He insists on the distinction between the practical and the theoretical sphere without attempting to diminish the claims of either. The "ought," he remarks, expresses a kind of necessity and connexion which meets us nowhere in nature. The moral law prescribes something that should be; the physical laws formulate what is, what has been and what must be. That enjoins a translation of thought into being; these are a rendering of being in terms of thought. Further, every event in nature is the effect of another event, which, like it, is a phenomenal appearance. Nowhere does a mere notion bring forth anything exis- tent. But the "ought" expresses a possible action, of which the ground is nothing but a mere conception (p. 379). It is true that the dutiful action must be one that is possible under the conditions of nature, but these concern only its appearance in the outer world, not its origin in the will. Hence reason asserts the necessity of cortam actions, which have not yet happened and which perhaps never will happen, but of which nevertheless it assumes it has within itself the causality. This assump- tion is even more conspicuous in the disapprobation we express regarding immoral acts already committed. We condemn the liar, no matter hov completely his offence be explicable from his nature and surroundings. We see that he would not have told this purticular lie at this * Werke, iii. 374-386 (Edition Hartenstein). 1 * is s i irIillMi' ^imiiifii''jiiBij Kantian Ethics and the ii ■ III i particular moment but for imperfect education^ evil com- panionship, a nature little susceptible to shame, a cha- racter light and unreflecting, and the peculiar temptations and circumstances in which be then found himself. Nevertheless the liar is condemned, not because of these or even of his evil life in the past, but because we assume that the man might have acted as though they had never been, because we believe that his action was wholly unconditioned by his previous life aisd habits, and that he might at that instant have begun, entirely from himself alone, a series of events in whicn lying would have found no place whatsoever. Our blame is grounded on a law of thought,, in accordance with which we regard reason as a cauae that could and should have determined a different course of conduct, even though all sensuous motives were in opposition. The liar in the moment of lying is guilty, even though the lie be determined by foregoing conditions, from which it might have been predicted with the certainty of a solar or a lunar eclipse. Every human action has accordingly two sides, from which arise contrary determinations regarding its causa- tion. Hence, in Kant's words, "the only question is whether it is possible, if- merely natural necessity be recognized in the entire series of all events, to regard that series, which, on the one side, is a mere product of nature, on the other side as a product of freedom.'* (p. 377.) An affirmative answer to this question Kant grounds on his distinction between phenomenon and noumenon. If we denote by " character " the law by which a cause operatec, then causality of the noumenon will have an intelligible character, that of the pheno- menon an empirical character. By the latter we mean «f*5»W«!''W«Wl«lw» ■ Ethics of Evolution. that every action of the subject stands in connexion with other actions and events, according to laws of nature, whence, as from its conditions, it may be deduced, and that it constitutes with these a single series of events in the order of nature. By the former we mean that the noumenal ego, which is not subject to the conditions of sensuous experience, may be the self- originating cause of actions which appear under those conditions. Man, as having an empirical character is determined, as having an intelligible character he is free. The exact relation between the empirical and the intelligible character is far from clear in Kant's account, which perhaps only reflects the confusion in Kant4 thought. We are, however, not left without one distin- guishing mark. As the noumenon is not subject to the conditions under which we know, its intelligible character indicates a -ausality that differs from that of the empirical character in being unconditioned by time. " It commences from itself its eff'ects in the world of sense, but in such a way that the action does not begin in itself." (p. 376.) This relation is described in various terms, without, however, receiving further elucidation. The empirical causality is called an eff-ect {Wirkimg) of the intelligible causality (p. 377) ; and the empirical character the manifestation (Erscheimmg), or the sensuous schema {sinnliches Schema) of the intelligible character (p. 376 and p. 383) . In virtue of this relation, Kant maintains that, though human actions are unchangeably determined in the empirical character of each individual, they are nevertheless free; for that empirical character, whence they flow, is itself the fi-eely- originated product of the intelligible character. Nor must frefiflnTTi ho (^onrpi^-prl n" ^^ --^A "■ « _„ „„ij, ^^, ^ y^^j ^^ iunic; inuupcnaence of empirical conditions; it is the faculty of beginning Is I •SI i r ^^^ttiHtt^M^^I^KiK,, 6 Kantian Ethics and the :!»(. !'!" from itself alone a series of events in the phenomenal world. This then is the hypothesis by which Kant seeks to show the possibility of morality under the Critical Philo- sophy. No better criticism can be made upon it than to trace its historical development. For, in general, it may be maintained that the full implication of any theory is not perceived by the age in which it appears, but is brought out only in the course of succeeding generations. Ihe abstract notions of Socrates must await the dis- cerning eye of Plato before they can manifest them- selves as the archetypal ideas of our unreal material universe. So Cartesianism full-grown becomes Spinozism. bo the Empiricism of Locke, become conscious of itself passes into = the Scepticism of Hume. And so, as we venture to think, the Determinism of Schelling and fechopeuhauer is the logical outcome of Kant's doctrine of intelligible and empirical character. This transition we must now briefly sketch. Schelling follows Kant in relegating freedom to the intelligible character which is subject to no relation either of causality or of time.* It can, therefore, never be determined by anything that has gone before, inas- much as It precedes, not in o^der of time, but according to Its notion, everything else which is or which happens in It. Free actions issue directly from the intelligible character. But this, did it determine itself from Le terminateness without any ground whatever, would not diifer from caprice, and freedom could have no other meaning than contingency or chance. It must, therefore before determining itself to any definite act, have in itself * Ueber das Wesen der memcJdichen Freiheit ■ Werkc v\\ ;iai.4l7 (Ed. Cotta, 1860). ^'^^ff, vn. «tmimi>*>mm0mmmimiftimmm\ht- Ethics of Evolution. a certain determinatiou ; and this cannot be anything else but its own essence, its own inmost nature, which is no indefinite universal, but the definite character of this particular individual. The intelligible essence can, accor- dingly, so certainly as its actions are absolutely free, as certainly act only in accordance with its own inmost nature ; for that alone is free which acts according to the laws of its own being, and is determined by nothing else either within or without. Individual action is accordingly the consequence of the inner necessity of a free being. But what is this inner necessity? According to Schelling, it is the product of freedom, man being what he is in virtue of kis own act. In the original creation, when the eternal yearning gave birth at once to God and nature, man, who now appears deter- mined, was an undetermined being, and by an act of his own he took to himself the definite character with which we now find him here. What he was to be, he alone could and did decide. The decision, however, does not fall in time : the act by which his earthly life was determined belongs to eternity. Everyone feels that he is what he is from all eternity, and that he has not merely become such in time. Hence, although the necessity of all our actions is undeniable, our moral conceptions prove that this necessity is the outcome of our own freedom. That Judas betrayed Christ neither he himself nor any other creature could have prevented ; nevertheless the betrayal was not a necessity, but an act of perfect freedom. The radical evil in human nature is in this life wholly unalterable by any exercise of freedom ; though it is, originally, man's own act— an act of which, though all memory be vanished, a consciousness yet remains in his self-accu- sations and his repentance. I S3 8 Kantian Ethics and the Ml This is the essence of Schelliug's doctrine, in which, notwithstanding a cunning interweaving of the myths of Plato and the effusions of Jacob Bcihme, the thought of Kant will be seen to have undergone a development that has carried it almost, if not quite entirely, over into its opposite. Only a Schopenhauer is needed to deduce and formulate the system of necessity with which the doctnne is already big. And Schopenhauer showed himself equal to the task.* The central point of his philosophy is the treatment of the will. Kant had set over against the phenomenal world we know, as ground and source of it, a noumenal world of which we know nothing. By the help of this distinction he was able to maintain the freedom of the will— the ffeedom of the intelligible character as opposed to the necessity of the empirical character. Schopen- hauer, undoubtedly following hints that had already appeared in Schelling, converts the entire noumenal world into an all-pervading will, which, in its blind movement towards existence, flings the unreal shadow of our seemingly real universe of thought and things. The intelligible character is this will in so far as it appears in a particular individual in a definite degree ; the empirical character is this appearance itself as it is seen in the mode of action in time and the bodily con- figuration in space. But this wiU is not inseparable from knowledge ; on the contrary, it exists and manifests itself in all nature, from the animal downwards, without it. Knowledge is a secondary phenomenon accompanying its higher objectivation ; and, being dependent for its appearance on an animal organism, it is physical rather * D/e TFcK als Wil/e and VorsteUung, Bks. ii. and iv.j Lie heidcn Grunilivohhmc der lit 'tin;. !-tfi>xm'mfmmm«>»»ii^t^ Ethics of Evolution. than metaphysical. Knowledge is therefore conditioned by will, not will by knowledge. But the intelligible character is the manifestation of will; our character therefore precedes our knowledge, which is only the glass that shows us what we are. Our notion of will is the only one among all possible notions that does not arise from our perceptions, but from an immediate consciousness of our own being before as yet the forms and conditions of knowledge have any existence, when the knowing subject and the known object still retain the unity of their primitive condition. This will is the only reality in a world of appearances and mere images of the brain. Natural causes are, to use Malbranche's term, only the occasion for a manifestation of the one reality. Nothing in the world has an absolute cause of its existence, but merely a cause of its existence now and here. Such causes are of three kinds : forces in the inorganic world, irritation m the organic world, and motives in the animal.world. In all these cases the causation is essentiallv the same. Here as there it is the one groundless will, which, appearing hi different degrees of manifestation, is itself subject to no laws or conditions. No cause can deter- mine the character of anything, but only the manifesta- tion of the character already there. Thus motives may nifluence the outer form of a man's life, but thoy leave untouched its inner meaning and content. Our acts may be determined by our surroundings, so far as their specific nature is concerned ; but their source and their general character are changelessly the same. Dir kannst du mcht entfliehen is, as Goethe assures us, the oracle of sibyls and prophets. The notion of freedom is negative. When we say the h S I i 10 Kantian Ethics and the 'III wil 18 free, we mean merely that the one indivisible reahty which manifests itself in all phenomena, is not subject to the causal relation by which these are neces- sanly determined. Man, like every other part of nature, IS objectivation of the one blind and groundless will. He IS stocked with forces and qualities, which react definitely when acted upon. This series of reactions makes up his empmcal character, which is as inexorably determined by the mtelligible character as this by the groundless will. Beneath the changing hull of his years and rela- t^ons of his knowledge and opinions, lies, like a crab in Its shell, the identical individual self, changeless and unchangeable. His actions indicate both to himself and to others what he really is. Oj^erari sciuitur esse. A change in his actions follows a change in his motives: and as these work through the medium of knowledge, in that alone is given the possibility of a better life. No other change is conceivable: the heart of stone cannot become a heart of flesh. The moral consciousness, how- ever, does not excuse the transgressor or cast the blame on his motives; it sees th.t objectively regarded a very different action was quite possible, indeed would have occurred, if he had been only another person. But that he IS such an one as the action shows him, and no other -that IS what is inexcusable : here, in his esse, is the spot which the sting of conscience pricks. The operari IS the occasion for self-accusation, the esse the ground of it. ° Woe is me, that I am me and not another ! With this vain lamentation we may not unfitly characterize the death-wail of the intelligible freedom It was excogitated by Kant to rescue the will from the causal necessity of the world of phenomena; it becomes *-■';" '^mw^^*mi§m'ff^^ii^^t^^ Ethics of Evolution. 11 indivisible lena, is not 3 are neces- t of nature, s will. He it definitely ikes up his determined groundless and rela- 3 a crab in jeless and iniself and >' esse. A motives ; fledge, in life. No ne cannot less, how- the blame ed a very »uld have But that 10 other, '6, is the 3 operari ) ground unfitly "reedom. from the becomes in Schopenhauer's hands the foundation of a system of Determinism, in which, if the name freedom is still preserved, it is only to express the groundless mani- Testation of a blind force, that discloses itself in the thought and life and being of the world we know, establishing always, whether in man or in matter, a determinate character, which intellect may bring to light but which it can neither alter nor destroy. This so- called will is a one-sided development of the intelligible world in the Kantian system. It lacks the rational element, in virtue of which the noumenal character is a law unto itself. But it is not only in opposition to Kant's philosophy, it is also contradicted by the facts of our own consciousness. We are conscious of a will that is accompanied by ideas, which, considered in relation to a volition, may be called its motives. But an unknown force that moves at random into determinate existence, blindly manifesting itself now in this direction and now in that, without the guidance of knowledge or any light of reason, has nothing in common with that which we call will, and the application of that name can only lead to confusion of thought, which no apparent comprehen- siveness of treatment can escape or conceal. A will that precedes intellect is no will ; it can be at best but blind desire. But if Schopenhauer's additions to Kant are of a suspicious character, his developments of Kant are essentially logical and consistent. He brought out clearly all that lay in germ in the doctrine of intelligible and empirical character. And, as we have seen, it turns at his touch into a system of Determinism. The stai-ting- point with him as with Kant is the assertion that the intelligible or noumenal will is not, like the empirical s 1 if! W*P^^^«siK- 12 Kantian Ethics and the will, subject to the conditions imposed by the intuition of time. Empirical volitions, as falling in time, constitute a succession, the members of which, according to Eant, are causally related to other events in time. Taking a concrete case, it may bo said that the resolve of tho Ilussian Nihilists to blow up the Winter Palace was as necessarily determined by the preceding acts and events of their lives, as the explosion itself by tho lighting of the match, the firing of tho train, and the other cir- cumstances which made up the totality of its causation. ,^nd as the like must hold of every act of will, from the first of their volitions up to the moment of that fatal resolve, it would seem apparent that the theory makes no provision for freedom, however desperately it clings to the name. Tho case is clear : everything that falls in time is caused by what has already happened in time ; volitions occur in time; ergo, volitions are determined. From this conclusion there would seem to be no escape ; and Schopenhauer maintains that Kant was not in earnest in his attempt to evade it.* Certain it is, that Kant at times assigns a role to the empirical character that ex- cludes the possibility of freedom. "It is according to this alone,'' he says, " we regard man, when we wish merely to observe, and, as in Anthropology, to inquire physiologically into the moving causes of his action." (ill. 381.) If the moving causes of man's actions are thus determined, what place have we left for an in- telligible causahty? Even more explicit is the following: " The real morality of actions (desert and guilt), even that of our own conduct, remains wholly concealed from us. To the empirical character alone can we refer our accountahiUty." (p. 881, note.) Accordingly, not only * Grundprohhmc tier Ethik, p. 71. ****?^(M^™^S»ta5,. , Ethics of Evolution. 13 our observation but our judgment of conduct as well must proceed upon the empirical basis. The judge on the bench, not less than the physiologi cal psycho Fogist must Ignore the intolligiblo character. But then, when the ono has analyzed a crime into its detormiuants, it is not easy to see why the other should sentence the culprit, whoso only guilt is the misfortune of having been the meeting.point of the contending forces, tlie" successive developments of which were determined by their ante- cedents, and by these alone. Kant sought to turn the edge of such objections, and doubtless succeeded, but only by involving himself in contradiction. Rather than surrender freedom, as his doctrine of causality requires, he predicates of some acts at least a causation partially, if not wholly, originating in the intelligible character. This view we may briefly examine before passing to others ; for Kant attempted, in more than one way, to form a conception of how freedom or the causation of the in- telligible character was really operative. That the view just stated was not altogether in con- sonance with his critical results Kant seems to have been aware, if we may attach any significance to the unusual caution with which he expresses himself: "Some- times we find or think that we find," he circumspectly observes, "that the ideas of reason have a real causality m the phenomenal conduct of men, and that their actions are determined not by empirical causes, no, but by grounds of reason.'- (p. 381.) In the note from which we have already quoted he virtually surrenders this exclusive causality of reason, remarking that no one can fathom how much is due to the action of freedom, how much merely to nature and to favourable or unfavourable temperament and constitution. But if, as Kant is never Cv'wU' I 34^^b>iiJ^>«^M^ *Mr*^'«*f»'« 14 Kantian Ethics and the wearied of remii-aing us, "all human actions are detor- ra'ned according to the order of nature by the empirical character and the co-operating conditions/' and if from these they "might with certainty be foretold and necessarily deduced". (p. 380), is it not a work of super- erogation to seek any other causality for them, a contra- diction to assign it to a sphere above " the order of nature," and an impossibility to conceive its action upon what is already unchangeably determined without it? Yet it is just this that Kant attempts. Surely a curious task for the criucal philosopher ! It might, however, have been avoided had Kant at the outset only made clear to himself the full import of his Coperuican notion. For if the mind legislate for nature and create; f^om its categories, intuitions and feelings the world we know, is it not evident that the mind itself cannot be conditioned by the conditions it imposes on things ? As you cannot predicate of the spider the geometrical relations he has spun in net-work round him, neither can you apply to mind the categories it has set in the loom of .time as warp for the weaving of an intelligibly-patterned world. Causality is a relation of things,— a thought-bond between two objects, but it has no meaning when applied to thought itself, by which things are made and constituted what they are. And- this view, which is implicit in Kant's principles, though* dnmbly articulated by Kant himself, is also the view of tb- rr.tural coH^ciousness of mankind. Unbiassed men do not identify, as Schopenhauer did, volition and causa- tion. Whoever reflects that a motive is merely an idea, and that an idea has no existence aj t from the subject that has it, must object to the comparison of man and his motives to a balance and its weights. J- he lOrmcr is a W^rmtmif^mmim Ethics of Evolution. luivr IS a — ___^ "* merely idoal the latteTTT^duality. Man is nothing apart ^rom h,s .dea, ; but the weights and the bulanc! ha e each an independent ,.xistence. Thus vohtion or w,ll,ng according to motives is by no means neeessitatic ■. And ,t was here that Kant failed to.see the (nil signifi. cance of h,s fundamental notion, whilo contending for an empty shadow which was scarcely even tue ^host of our hvmg freedom. If freedom be not found in our voil- ion ^Uh motives and not without them, it dwell, not with man, it is nowhere to bo found. But to return from this digression. Wo have seen tha the intelligible character cannot co-operate „Z pi^duetion of actions, which are wholly gro„„ded in the empirical character. There is, however, a second eon! ception of their relation by which Kant hopes to save the freedom of the will. Grant that human .^tions are the necessary consequences, of the empirical character, deter- mined by it as uniformly as any effect in nature by its cause, what then is this empirical character itself ? May ^ not be the freely-caused product of the intelligible? Andlvant, as we ha.e seen, calls it the manifestation the effect of the intelligible causality." But from this account Schelhng and Schopenhauer have drawn the only admissible mference, which, as is well known, was dlrecriy the reverse of Kanfs. At every moment ;f our hves we have an empirical character which determines our conduct and excludes freedom. To protect freedom we excogitate an unconditioned causality of the intel- ligible character, but that carries us out of this life for which alone morahty, and therefore freedom, have'any woHh or interest Kant would of course remind us that the intelhgiblu character is not subject to the conditions L fmm^m0»m:/miiiim^^^m:. 16 Kantian Ethics and the of time, and cannot therefore be assigned to a life that precedes this life. To which there is but one reply : the logic of facts thrusts it out of this life. So long as we have an empirical character, which is the ground of all our actions, so long must we assert they are determined ; and as the empirical character is ours from the beginning of our lives, so must its supposed cause— the freely-acting intelligible character— fall without the limits of our earthly life. And Schelling, who also maintains that the intelligible character precedes the empirical merely according to its- notion and not in order of time, really draws no other conclusion ; for he transfers freedom from the earthly sphere back to the creat^n of the world, at which time we, by an act of our own volition, determined the character of our being and the course of our lives. To add that creation is a timeless act, an eternal now, is merely to play with words. Besides, if, as Schelling asserts, neither Judas himself nor anyone else could have prevented his betrayal of CHrist, is it not manifest that the creation, in which Judas took to himself his definite character, was not the work of that moment, must have preceded that moment, and in so far, therefore, was not timeless and eternal. This unavoidable inference from Kant is clearly stated by Schopenhauer, though with him ^ too we ai-e asked to believe that our character was deter- mined by the manifestation of a blind will, which, as preceding inte'.ect, falls outside the conditions of our knowledge, and hence is not in time. But worthless as the metaphysic of Schelling and Schopenhauer may be, both agree in one important truth, that Kant's distinc- tion between intelligible and empirical character cannot deliver this earthly life from the bonds of necessity. A third view, though not independent of the preceding, Ethics of Evolution. 1^ -PPears^7^Z~7r^^~;;;;ii^ble character'^;;^3 we have seen, descend from its transcendental height to aid in the determination of specific actions; and if turther. Its causation of the empirical character, whence our actions flow, must fall outside this present life, with which alone ethics is concerned, might not freedom still find a sheltered place on the ''other side" of actions, which in themselves are phenomenally necessary ? In short what in the empirical character is precisely deter- mined and absolutely necessary may be in the intelligible character free and unconditioned. The necessity of the one may not exclude the freedom of the other The action, m so far as it is to be attributed to the intel- hgible character or pure reason, does not follow the empirical laws in accordance with which both condition and consequence appear in our experience; but it takes Its place in the series of our actions, while its conditions remain unchangeable in the transcendental sphere beyond The change has been brought forth by the mtelhgible character without implying any change in it. For the condition, which has its seat in reason, is not sensuous and does not therefore begin .o be. Accord- ing y we here find, what we miss in all empirical series, tha the condition of a successive series of events, can Itself be empirically unconditioned. Without under- going change in itself, it is the cause of the sensuous condition by which a series of actions is brought on the scage. Now without denying the possibility of this causation we have only to remark that there is no field left open lor It If as Kant has shown, all actions are/.% and completely determined by their antP.edento in tf- Oniy when our inquiry into the causes of an action stoj.." I »Sfc [Bp ,?* " ^i^3^ ™Vi " ■'mu%vi!^mm''> 18 Kantian Ethics and the with its conditions, and does not press back into their causes, can such a view gain any plausibility. On extending our investigation it would be seen that the ''sensuous condition," which is supposed to mediate between the empirical events and the transcendental ^ causality, is the product of certain events that precede it in time, — the product, that is, of the empirical character, and no more connected with the intelligible sphere than the action it was excogitated to explain. And if we are not too slothful to follow back the course of our lives, we find, from the present time to the first beginnings of action, a like causal relation between our conduct and our empirical character. Freedom was to be saved by the union of the intelli- gible and empirical character in every action, and yet we find it impossible to conceive such a combination ! Nevertheless, Kant clings to his notion of freedom. But it is after all only a barren abstraction. A will that begins from itself a series of events, without motives, does not difier from caprice, and it is scarcely conceivable that anyone should attach much worth to it. But Kant's age was an age of Blumination, of one-sidod abstractions. It was an epoch of transition, and Kant's philosophy has not escaped the contradictions immanent to all Becoming. As it attempted to cancel the Idealism that emerged from the Critique of Knowledge by bindino- the phenomenal world we know to a noumenal worl of which we know nothing, not even that it exists, so it endeavours to save human freedom, which it had hunted out of the actual world, by sheltering it behind an iutelligible character, which has no other foundation for its being than that fiction of a noumenal world. An object can be analvzed into a manifold nf ppiise -"dcred Ethics of Evolutlnn. 19 A human acfon is shown to be the determined result of Kant .s that the end of the matter. Yon must reld the object as produced by something behind it,-fs a man.festat.on or effect of a thing-in-itself. A;d ho «ct.on, wh,ch the empirical character determined, you must regard as freely caused by an unconditioned reas'on Now without denying that Realism and Idealism BVeedom and Necessity, are as amattor of fact ca t rf hat Kant has faded to accomplish this. His world is an deal world, and his attempted passage to Realism is a leap and net a necessary or even natural t™nsition. S.:n,larly ,s Determmism the logical consequence of his Metaphysics, and Indeterminism is introduced only a the sacnace of unity and consistency. Doubtless our na ural behef m the reality of the objective world, and our not less firm conviction of our own freedom, are facts that eq-e e.p anaMon , but that is not given by a system ha elegates both reality and freeaem to a transcen- dental sphere, which has no conceivable connexion with W..S actual world in which we believe they both exist, and which can enter into no connexion with it, without mvdying the whole system in hopeless contradiction. This leads US to the last objection we have to make to Kant s doctrine of the intelligible and empirical character -an objection that applies to each and all the interpre- tations that may be given it. In every case freedom is supposed to be saved by attributing a causality to the mtelbgible character or pure reason. But the centml point of Kant's philosophy is that the Categories ha" t «d.d„y beyond the sphere of phenomena. It is therefore 2 * i^bs, 44 '-■^J''*S^f^*r^-7'r' 20 Kantian Ethics and the nieiuiiiij,'losH to raaintaiu tliat the intclH^iblo character has any causality, wliother in relation to the empirical character in general, or to the specific acts that are deter- mined by it. Kant here falls into the same contradiction as when he postulati'S a noumenal world as canso of our sensations, though the category of causality has no appli- cation till the sensations have been constituted by thought into the phenomenal world of our knowledge. In both cases the quest of an Absolute, — of an uncon- ditioned first cause is fruitless. The distinction between the iutelligible and empirical character fails of the end for which it was made. It is, however, the natural issue of the Critique of Pure Reason, —but the issue of its weakness and not of its strength. Its source is the dualism of phenomenon and noumenon ; its dynamic impulse the theory of causation. It is these that doomed Kant's Critique to Determinism; — these, and not the immanent principles of the Critical Philosophy. To them we must attribute the result at which we have now arrived. That result is, that for Kant no transition was possible from the theoretical to the practical philo- sophy. Necessity is the outcome of the one, freedom the burden of the other. And it is impossible to effect a reconciliation between them. 2. Freedom of the Will. When the bond of connexion between the theoretical and the practical philosophy has been broken, two courses are open to speculation. It may fasten on one part of the system to the exclusion of the other, or it may hold by both, though seeking beyond Kant the principle of their union. In the last case the contradiction subsisting between causality and freedom would be set aside by a *»*«»*(«-■ Mhics of Evolution. 21 juster conception of these categories themselves. It would be seen tliat the ego, which legislates for nature IS Itself above the reach oi' natural laws. Thought cannot be caught in the diaraond-net it has thrown for things A sound theory of knowledge will show that the laws of Kature are not the laws of Spirit. And if Kant failed us hero, wo shall nevertheless find that Kant's principles when duly developed, free us from the contradictions nito which Kant himself fell. But this course has not always been followed; and there have not been wanting thinkers who, staying them- Belves on the Critique of Knowledge, entirely reject the Critique of Morality and Religion. This is the general attitude of the so-called Neo-Kantians, of whom Lano-o may be taken as the representative. Professing to huM on the theoretical philosophy of Kant (though, as we think, without its foundation), Lange asserts that - the entire practical philosophy is the changeable and perish- able part of the system.* Between the Critique of Pure Reason and the Critique of Practical Reason he sees nothing but contradiction. The one moves in a world of appearances, the other in a world of realities • the one binds phenomena in the changeless bonds of necessity, the other sets noumena under a self-given law of freedom. In that our scientific knowledge is placed on a firm foundation; in this it is exposed to the caprices of the will. Here the limits which were there set to knowledge are overstepped; the death-warrant signed against metaphysics is countermanded. The existence of contradiction we do not deny. We have already hinted how it may be avoided. But grantinc^ everything for which Lange contends (though much * Gcschir/itc des Matcrialismus, ii. 61 (.3rd edition). ^2 22 Kantian Ethics and the might be refuted from Kant himself), does it therefore follow that the ethical philosophy must be rejected ? Does the truth lie exclusively in one Critique ? Or may there not be truths in both parts of the system, which, if well understood, are perfectly accordant ? But even though we are unable to detect this inner harmony, we are not on that account released from the claims of either on our reason. Lange makes this possible for himself by relegating the facts of the moral and religious con- sciousnesss to a " world oi fiction," which, as we are told to our surprise, constitutes at once their "worth and dignity."* But this is no philosophy, it is sheer despair of philosophy. Kant attempted to explain all the facts of our consciousness, while Lange has contented himself with a partial survey, which leaves unexplored one large sphere, that, on his own shov/ing, is " the source of all that is high and holy" in humanity.f He may, if he choose, call that world a fairyland of fiction and find it strange that Kant had not fallen on so happy a name ; but the world itself will still need a philosophical ex- planation, just as much as that other world of nature, than which perhaps it is rather more than less real. And Kant's explanation cannot be affected by the dogmatism of the new school. Indeed we believe the Neo-Kantians to be grossly inconsistent. For does not the philosophy which leads to causality lead as inevitably to freedom ? Both notions stand on precisely the same level; the deduction of the one is as valid as the deduction of the other. The method of the practical philosophy is the method of the theoretical philosophy. In the first place, each sets out with an accepted fact, — here the fact of * Geschichte des Matcrialismus, ii. 61 (3rd edition). t Ihid. Ethics of Evolution.. 28 duty, there the fact of knowledge. Secondly, each eeeks a general formula for the concise expression of the fact. Thirdly, each proposes to explain the possibility of the fact as contained in the formula. Fourthly, each finds that the universality and necessity of the fact are inex- plicable from experience. Fifthly, each is accordingly obliged to posit an a priori element, which, not preceding experience in order of time, is yet not given in experience. Sixthly, each having shown this a priori factor is the only possible hypothesis, delivers a result that we cannot refuse to accept, without showing a fallacy either in the premises or in the argument. Accordingly, to accept the notion of causality and to reject that of freedom is only possible to a one-sided system, such as that which Lange gives. Instead of closing the path to the practical philosophy, he simply passes by it, and offers certainly no resistance to our entrance. Here we are to seek the freedom which the theoretical philosophy necessarily excluded, but which it nevertheless discerned as the " substance of things hoped for, the evidence of things not seen." For the thorough understanding of Kant's treatment of the question a brief sketch of his ethical philosophy is necessary. We must of course confine ourselves to the merest outline. In the analysis of morality as of knowledge he sets out with a truth of universal and necessary validity. In the one case it is the body of mathematical proofs, in the other ^'t is the moral law. In both the inquiry turns on the possibility of such propositions, which are at once synthetic and a priori. Confining attention to the moral law, it is evident that it cannot be constituted by practical principles which prescribe action for the attaininent of an y till t .1 ■^•mmmmr 24 Kantian Ethics and the 111 III end. For the maxim of conduct would then be merely the desire of an object, or the pleasure in the existence of it. But since this pleasure in an object, which must be presupposed as a condition preceding our volition, cannot be known a priori, it would follow that the maxims of our conduct were always ci posteriori, and therefore in- capable of becoming law for all reasonable beings. Op, in Kant's words, " a material principle can never yield a practical law."* Such material principles, however different in other respects, agree in this, that they belong to one general system of Eudaemonism and rest on self- love. But a system, the principles of which turn on one's own happiness, no matter how intellectually soever the understanding may be employed on it, can nev^er furnish any further motives to moral conduct than such as excite and stimulate the inferior powers of desire. Either then a superior power of desire is to bo abandoned, or else reason must itself be a practical or active faculty, i.e.i such a one as can by the bare form of its rule determine a volition, and that abstracted from all f eelin'^s of the agreeable or disagreeable which may follow or compose the matter of choice. But to deny man this higher power of reason is to degrade him to the level of the brutes, which are guided by the light of instinct alone. The only question, therefore, is, how we can conceive of reason as determinator of the will. Only one way is possible. "If a rational being cogitate his maxim of it, and therefore as certain aii the existence of the universe itself. By a law of reason, however, men think themselves free with regard t'^ Iheir volitions, which, as part of the pheno- menal sphere, must nevertheless be subject to the causal nexus. In such a collision, as the notion of necessity stands secure, the objective validitv of the idea of reason — that is, of freedom — becomes extremely doubtful. In 9 •J a IS y •to. 38 Kantian Ethics and the any case it is entirely incomprehensible how freedom is possible. To explain that would be equivalent to solving the insoluble mystery of pure reason becoming practical. One thing, however, is certain,— its impossibility cannot be demonstrated. If the moral law requires that free- dom be postulated, though neither its possibility nor impossibility be susceptible of proof, philosophy has no other task than that of showing its true relation to the causal nexus, with which it seems to stand in direct opposition. And this is what Kant attempts. " Every rational being reckons himself, on the one hand, as intel- ligent in a world of reason, and only as efficient in this system does he call his causality a will. On the other hand, he is conscious of being a part of the physical system in which his actions can only be appearances or phenomena of that causality. As, however, the possi- bility of deriving them from it cannot be understood, we must regard them as determined not by it, but by other phenomena, namely, appetites and desires, which belong to the physical system.^'* But this explanation, far from throwing any light on the difficulty, only brings it into greater prominence. As efficient in the supersensible system man has a cau- sality of will, but as it cannot be seen how this produces his actions, they are simply ascribed to the causality of sensible phenomena. What need then of that pure will, on the activity of which freedom has been staked ? Or how is it a causality at all ? It may be granted with Kant that, were we merely members of the intelligible world, all our actions would tally with the autonomy of the pure will; or that, were we but pieces of the sensible world, all our actions would take place according to the * Werke, iv. 301. Ethics of Evolution. 39 physical law of appetites and desires. It is further con- ceivable that the difference between these two spheres might give ground for an " ought " — for the legislation of the higher over the lower. But how that " ought," and the freedom it implies, can have any practical meaning, we are unable, on this theory, even to imagine. If every human action and volition is necessarily determined by other phenomena, as Kant uniformly asserts, is it not futile to maintain a freedom of the will that can express itself only in a protest against the necessity by which it is encompassed ? But Kant argues that this freedom ia in reality an active factor, on the ground that the intelli- gible world, to which it belongs, is the ultimate ground and condition of the sensible world, in which the volition occurs. What happens in the phenomenal self, under the condition of time, is necessary ; but the noumenal self, on which that other depends, is above the conditions of time, so that nothing precedes its voluntary act, and the entire series of the causally-related sensible existences is in the consciousness of its intelligible being nothing but the sequent of its free causality as noumenon. In cr? rela- tion, therefore, the action may be fixed by meonanical necessity, but in another it is the direct product of reason, or it is free. This hypothesis, which in another form we have already met in the doctrine of intelligible and empirical character, will be found, on closer examination, to offer no safe- guard for human freedom. Because the noumenal world contains the last grounds of the phenomenal world as well as of its laws, it is argued that man, though con- ditioned in this, is in that free. Now, as already observed, the only noumenon which Kant, in accordance with his Copernican notion, was entitled to maintain, was the mm ;3 40 Kantian Ethics and tlu w ilM transcendental unity of apperception, the permanent "I think/' which through the categories laid the foundations of our known world. And this is not peculiar to me or to any other individual; it is universal thought itself. But the foregoing argument only shows that this uni- versal, smce it cannot in reality be conditioned by the laws It has established, is above the reach of the causal nexus, and so unconditionally free. And this is the irference which Schopenhauer drew. Of the individual ego, nothing whatever is asserted. With its content of feeling, volition and knowledge, it is, on the one hand no mere empty thought, nor, on the other hand, is it Bimply a concrete thing in the physical system. And it IS the recognition of this that is wanting in Kant's prac tical philosophy. His system would suffice were wo either pure matter or pure thought; but, since we are neither It never touches our case, and only seems to do so by swinging alternately from the one extreme to the other without ever reaching a firm halting-place between them! If constitutive thought have set motives and volitions in the same category as force and motion, then the freedom of the will does not differ from the freedom of an im- pelled ball. And Kant does not in truth distinguish them m the phenomenal sphere. But as the causal relation is given by thought, he claims for man, along with sub- mission to It, at the same time an exemption from it. In such case Kant always conceives individual ego as constitutive, each for itself, of ... .,ws of the known world. Such a system of subjective Idealism, however, ,s not tenable; for it is impossible that indi- viduals, with their manifold idiosyncrasies, should have created, each for itself, the world it knows in comuon with every other. And thus it was that the first develop- Ethicii of Evolution. 41 ment of Kant's system began with the transcendental ego, which, after being universalized by Fichte, passed finally into the Absolute of Schelling and Hegel. If now the noumenal world, as thus understood, contains the grounds and conditions of the phenomenal world, it is not easy to see how the individual man, any more than the individual thing, can escape the grasp of necessity. It is true that, in so far as his will is rational, it would be in harmony with the laws of absolute reason, but that does not distinguish in any way cases of ordinary volition from causation. In short, no individual can break the causal bond in which, according to Kant, he as well as nature is bound. To say with Hegel that freedom con- sists not in liberty of choice but in willing the rational, may be a right enough usage of terms, but it throws no light on the problem before us. We want to know if the man who, incited by a greed of gain, steals his neigh- hour's purse, was as much impelled to that action by that motive as a ball, when struck, to move. The answer of critical philosophy must be considered an affirmative; although it adds, by way of solace, that man is free when he wills according to the universal laws of morality. It might, perhaps, be more correct to say that the man who wills the universal law, which reason gives, is one with reason, and that no higher goal can be set for humanity. But that offti-s not the slightest explanation of how man could come to that stage, how he could advance fvom what Kant would call the ty]-anny of motives to the free- dom of perfect obedience. It is in this process that we suppose freedom to be operative, it is this that we cannot explain without freedom. The goal is worthy for its own sake, but not because we are then first free. Rather to usL Schelling's phrase, are we then sweetly bound by a 9 ill 42 Kantian Ethics and the im.:, f ft ■ 'holy necessity," from which we would not willingly be free to fall away. Meantime the goal has not been reached, and wo are still striving towards it. The notions of guilt and desert, merit and demerit, responsibility and accountability, bear w..aess at once to our feebleness and our strength. That the theory we hare examined can explam them, we are unable to see. It does indeed attempt to explain our conception of duty. But in re- garding it as the voice of creative reason to the creature it has set among the things of the phenomenal world, dictating that something "ought" to be done, where already, in virtue of the laws it has established, some- thing else must inevitably take place, it presents an hypothesis which, however meritorious in other respects, certainly does not show that freedom of the will is possible along with an all-embracing application of the law of causality. Doubtless the "ought" implies the " can," and our only objection to Kant's ethical philosophy is that it makes this implication impossible of realization. Even when Kant's metaphysic be taken in the unde- veloped form in which he left it, the result is practically the same. Suppose that I, the individual, have estab- lished the causal relation in the.world I know, in particular that between motive and volition and that between force and motion. Does, e.g., theft now follow necessarily a certain complex of motives, as the theory requires, then It 18 argued that this connexion, however necessary, is at the same time, since it has been made by me, really free and unconditioned. But this freedom, unless it implied a constant creation on the part of the subject-which in a completed Cosmos is impossible-has already been daposited with the groundwork of the existent world, by tiie forces of which nr, - conduct is now alone determined. Ethics oj Evolution. 43 At *;he dawn of consciousness, when the mind began to perceive, that is, to lay its categories in things, freedom may have been one of its attributes, but after tha iage every act r^ust be originated by the relations then estab- lished. Hence Schelling, with strict consistency, banishes freedom to a timeless creation, and delivers this life wholly over to necessity. As practical reason the ego issues an "ought,'' but as pure reason it . is already grounded an * ." which no "ought" can alter or destroy. The j!.). (rsensible world has already legislated us into the causa^ nexus, it cannot by a moral law legis- late us out again. On this theory freedom must be held as a mere idea of reason, which, however valuable for the speculative thinker, has no worth or validity for the moral agent, and can have no bearing on our life and conduct, which follow necessarily the laws of the natural world. And in some striking illustrations Kant decidedly indi- cates this standpoint. Thus he says that the hardened ruffian, who, moved by some shining example of virtue desires to become a good and honest man, finds he cannot, in consequence of the appetites and desires by which he is slavishly impelled. It is only, therefore, in idea that he wafts himself into another order of things, where motives have lost their sway, and the good will is all in all. Thither his fancy may soar, but he remains what natural causes have made him I It is, as Kant elsewhere tersely observes, only "as t/ through our will a system of things was to come into being.''* II. Along with the foregoing elucidation, which may be called metaphysical, Kant has a practical explanation of freedom, in accordance with which it consists in sub- mission to the moral law= Or since the moral la™ "s * Werke, v. 47. W\ i S) ¥ lit; 44 Kantian Ethics and the given by the ego itself, freedom may be conceived to consist rather in the autonomy than in the subjection. Each aspect alternately comes to the foreground in Kant. At one time he says that " a free will is just the same thing as a will that is subject to moral laws/' and defines practical freedom as "independence of the will from everything else except the moral law."* At another he maintains that "with the idea of freedom that of autonomy is indissolubly attached/' and that the positive constituent in freedom is "the self-legislation of the pure and, as such, practical reason.^f These different statements, however, are only two sides of the one fact. For true freedom, the theory requires both the self-given law and the obedience' to the law ; and if, at times, only one of these conditions is expressly stated, the other must be considered as tacitly as'^umed. There would be no freedom if the self-given .u,w did not determine the will, none, if the law determining the will were not self-given. Kant'f, theory is impregnable so long as both these positions are secure ; it falls when either has been sur- rendered. Eegarding the autonomy of the will, some- thing may be said when we come to treat of the moral principle; meantime, it may guffice, assuming the law, to inquire into its determination of the will. The theory requires that the bare form of the law, its adaptability to a system of universal legislation, shall be the only deter- minator of the moral will. But it will not need much consideration, as we think, to show that this condition is never fulfilled. " The essence of all determination of will by the moral law lies," says Kant, " in this, that it as free will, be determined, not only without any co-operation from * Werkc, iy. 29£i ; v. dP. f iv. ;300 ; v. 3a. Ethics of Evolution. .45 sensitive excitements, but that it even cast all such behind-back and discard them, in so far as they may infringe upon the law, and be determined by it alone."* But how tliis is at all possible, Kant confesses we aro for ever unable to understand. If, however, it be possible, Kant can describe, a priori, the process by which the law humbles self-love and casts out self-conceit, till it win for itself absolute possession of the field as sole determinator of the will. But can we, however, grant the antecedent possibility ? Kant of course would maintain we must, because on his theory morality is not otherwise explicable. Still, if the admission involves an absurdity, as we venture to think it does, it cannot be made ; and the validity of a theory of morals requiring it must, to say the least, become suspicious. Now, is it not absurd to suppose that the rich and varied content of our moral life can be identified with the effect supposed to be produced upon us by the Categorical Imperative, since that effect could never, by any possibility, rise above the level of a mono- tonous uniformity ? The law of duty as interpreted by Kant makes no provision for difference of any kind, and yet the substance of our moral conceptions is far from identical. The variety of their hues and colours is to be accounted for, not by mere matter, which in itself is colourless, and not by mere form, which alone is invisible, but by the reflexion of the one in and through the other. Kant too admits as undeniable, that "all vohtion has an object, that is, a matter;" but he straightway cancels the import of this admission by affirming that the object is not therefore " the ground of the detfsrmination of the will.^f Now this addition is simply unintelligible: for wpi mean by an object of IS »!* fc * Werl-e, v. 77. t V. 37. 46 Kantian Ethics and the volition that which in some way, directly or indirectly, supplies a motive to the will, that is, in Kant's language, determines the will. It would, therefore, be more correct to say that the object in every case determines the will, and that the morality of the action is tested by its form, or its adaptability to universal law. Kant himself, in a notable passage, concedes all that we require for the rejection of his view of freedom. It is, he says, "absolutely impossible to make out with certainty a single case in experience, in which the maxims of an otherwise dutiful action have rested solely on moral grounds and on the idea of duty.''* That is to say, it is absolutely impossible to find a single instance in which occurs that transcendental determination by the moral law, without which freedom, on Kant^s theory, is impossible ! The theory, further, is at variance with the moral notions and beliefs it was designed to explain. We are free, it is said, in obeying, solely for its own sake, a self- given law of reason; but since, confessedly, no human being ever does satisfy such condition, the freedom which it would secure him is never attained, and man must be regarded, like any material object, as the necessitated product of nature. A being that is pure reason alone is the only free being, according to the theory. The least intermixture of sense and imagination, as in man, is at once the mark and the cause of necessitation. But for the explanation of such moral notions as responsibility and punishment, merit and demerit, it was above all things essential to show that the agent is free in the very act for which he is blamed or approved. Were he deter- mined, the good or bad act might have been admired or * Werkc, iv. 254. Ethics of Evolution. 47 disliked, but never rewarded or punished. Of moral conduct and moral principles Kant's practical philosophy gives, and can give, no explanation. His ethical system has two sides, one of which is applicable to pure reason, which is above duty, and the other to material things, which are beneath it. But for man, the only moral being we ^^now, and for whom alone we need a philo- sophy of othics, Kant's system has neither application nor validity. After this somewhat lengthy examination of Kant's account of freedom, it cannot be difficult to appreciate its value. In so far as it is constructive, it fails in the attempt to reconcile ethics with a view of causality, which, to say the least, cannot be shown correct or even well-founded. Doubtless if the category of causaHty is valid for mind, it must be admitted that volitions and actions are inexorably determined. But v/hat ground is there for applying to persons what we know only as true for things ? There is in fact none whatsoever, except the unifying impulse we follow in our scientific research. That everything should stand under one category is doubtless an ideal for knowing, but it is not on that account a condition of being. The universe is under no obligation to adapt itself to a mere postulate of our cognitive method, even though it be, as it well may be, a system of rational relations. What is, even though its sole essence be reason, may nevertheless be richer and more varied than what we actually know. And from our ignorance of how freedom can be possible, it cannot be interred that it is impossible. Indeed, in the present case, it is nothing less than a violation of the logical method of procedure, to deny that freedom, is existent, when it is nevertheless the presupposition of the moral mm IS' 48 Kantian Ethics and the law, of which we are immediately conscious. The masterly- exposition of this relation between *' ought" nnd "can" is perhaps the only permanent contribution which the critical philosophy has made to the problem of freedom. Man ''judges he can do something because he is con- scious he ought, and so recognizes in himself freedom, which, without the moral law, would have remained unknown to him." * Beyond this it will perhaps now be clear that Kant did not get in the solution of the problem ; and, as we may venture to add, beyond this no one has yet advanced. But even this position, it must be openly con- fessed, is not irrefragable. If duty, which according to Kant is the* ratio cognoscendi of freedom, be denied or explained away, there is absolutely no other ground for asserting that the will is free. If anyone can believe, with Professor Bain, that our morality is merely a system of police regulations, or, with Schopenhauer, that duty is " a notion for children and for nations in their infancy, but not for those who have made their own the culture of a maturely developed epoch,"— and experience shows that even this is not incredible to some acute thinkers, then there is no ground for setting a limit to the unifying tendency of our cognitive method, seeing that spirit has renounced the characteristics by which we had supposed it exalted above the categories of nature. But to those who rejrudiate the unscientific procedure of Schopenhauer, and reject the hypothesis by which the Empirical School, after emptying morality of its contents, easily deprives the will of its freedom, the implication of duty, as de- veloped by Kant, will remain the ground for belief in a freedom, which, if not further explicable, is not therefore * Wcr^e, v. 32. Ethics of Evolution. 49 of doubtful existence, inasmuch as explanation is possible only through causal connexions, which by the hypothesis are here excluded. Freedom may be maintained, as wo think, on this old and solid, but certainly unpretentious foundation ;— assuredly on no other whatsoever. If it is said that " the will only as thinking intelligence is free will,"* we have nothing to object, except that it in no way concerns the freedom of our popular con- sciousness or of our ethical systems— the freedom re- quired for the explanation of duty and responsibility, of merit and demerit, of guilt and punishment. It is not a conception explanatory of morality— and it is that which we require— but a more or less probable view of the nature and dignity of man, "-hom it figures as fully adequate to his idea, when volition has been permeated with thought and the potential reason of the individual has been actualized into unity with the divine reason that develops itself in the world. But such a theory, whether advanced by Hegel or by the ancient Stoics, can gain nothing by slurring over the question of the freedom of the will, which remains untouched by the dictum, in regno sumus, Deo parere libertas est. 3. The Moral Principle. Though the freedom of the will is the ratio essendi of our morality, and as such constitutes the supreme question of ethical speculation, morality, as Kani so emphatically reiterates, is the ratio cognoscendi of freedom. "Without a consciousness of the former there would never have been a belief in the latter. Our next inquiry must accordingly be into the nature of the moral conception, for the realization of which freedom has been postulated * Hegel's Werke, viii. 55. J* le: mm 50 Kantian Ethics and the ''1^" m as an indispensable condition. What is duty ? What ia the moral law? Is it rightly formulated in Kant's Categorical Imperative ? These questions lead us from the conditions of morality to its inmost essence and content. iKant's interpretation of the moral law has already been given. To the dogmatic Eudaemonism of his con- temporaries he opposed with overpowering energy a critical conception as clear and simple as it was new and startling. He maintained that the good will was the only absolute good, and that such a will was that, which had for its content and its spring an unconditioned law of universal validity. Put such a law, it was argued, must be one from which all reference to the obiect or matter 4l of our volitioii has been excluded, — one, that is, which by its bare form alone c^n determine the will. It is ex- pressed as a Categorical Imperative : act from a maxim at all times fit for a universal lawl] This conception of the mop^Twill is closely related to the system of theoretic philosophy. As the pure forms of Intuition and of Understanding were discovered by abstracting from the content of our knowledge, so is the pure will reached by abstraction from the matter of our volition. And as through i^n spontaneity the under- standing is distinguished from sense, so through its autonomy is the pure will lifted above desire or appetite. In the sphere of knowledge as of will, it is the self- activity of reason that raises us above the mere appear- ance and unreality, inherent in affections of sense, to the truth and reality of things as they are in themselves. Hence Kant's philosophy is in the main a determination of the functions of self-active reason, and is thus grounded in the question. How are synthetic judgments d 'priori possible ? The answer, it is true, shows there is no a Ethics of Evolution. 51 priori knowledge, except with reference to objects of an at least possible experience, and that metaphysic there- fore is impossible, seeing that our knowledge is confined to appearances, as constituted by the forms and con- ditions under which we know, and can never reach to reality,— to things as they are in themselves. If these cannot appear to us in any other way than through the forms of our perception, whereby they are eo ipso dis- torted, the sublation of the limit to our knowledge is only conceivable on the hypothesis, that beside the pure forms, the mind also supplied the matter of our know- ledge, that is, that the mind possessed the faculty of intellectual perception. And though Kant rejects this supposition, yet not only the problem of his Critique but the whole tenor of the work itself show that his highest ideal of a science was r^e constructed from pure notions by the activity of thought, to the exclusion of every element of sense. It is because the theoretical reason does not escape its sensuous limitation that he denies to it a true knowledge of the really existent, and subor- dinates it to the practical reason, which through the moral law brings us into connexion with the world of reality. The supersensible, which cannot be known as an object, is to be realized in the moral life of the subject himself. As Socrates in despair of natural philosophy concentrates the force of his genius on the problems of moral speculation and practice, so Kant, become sceptical of a metaphysic that was incapable of explaining reahty, takes refuge in an ethic in which it was at least to be experienced. Fichte following out the same line of thought arrived at the conclusion that the theoretical ego had no other niison d'etre than the need felt by the practical ego for some opposition or resistance, by con- 4 * 52 Kantian Ethics and tho tact with which it might carry on its infinite process of self-realization supposed to bo demanded by the moral law. And tho young titanic Schelling, kindled into enthusiasm by tho fire of Fichto's genius, proposes to refute the dogmatism of tho theoretical consciousness by " realizing in oneself a system which is tho direct contrary of it." But the realization of the supersensible by volition seems not less impossible than the comprehension of it in knowledge. For, since we never will without willing something, which as object of a possible experience does not lie on a plane different from that of our knowledge, no distinction like that supposed can be made between the two faculties. And least of all for Kant was any such admissible. What he urged against Leibnitz with such monotonous repetition in the theoretical philosophy must be brought against himself in the practical. That knowledge is impossible v hout a sensuous content, as he so cogently demonstrated, is not more obvious than that volition is inconceivable without desires or appetites as motives. Thought whether in knowing or willing is empty till filled by experience, though in both cases experience is blind till illumipated by thought. A true ethic as a true psychology must reconcile Rationalism and Empiricism, and it can only be considered as a defect that Kant did not carry into his ethical system the method by which, in the theoretical, he mediated so successfully between Locke and Leibnitz. The inference from his principle cannot, however, be difficult to draw. If reason as theoretical produces only the forms of our perception, so must reason as practical be limited to the forms of our volition. Defining the matter of volition as the definite objects in view or the ends to EtMca of Evolution. 58 bo attained, and the form as tho universal rule we follow in the determination of ends, it is manifest that the material element in every volition can be given only in experience. Fro.n this source, however, cannot bo derived a principle which is universal and necessary, and which raises us above tho sensible, into communion with the Huporsensible world. The moral law can, therefore, have regard neither to the ends nor to the consequences of our actions, but only to tho rules which precede them, to the form of the will from which they have issued. But as it is no empirical principle it cannot have a content ; it is formal, and, as such, empty as tho Categories or the Intuitions. Whatever is moral must conform to the Categorical Imperative; whatever is known to the cate- gory of causality; but that does not tell us what things are actually moral, or what causally related. Or the moral law might be compared with the laws of logic, which supply indeed a test of consistency, but not of truth. If A is true, not-A must be false ; and if B is the maxim of your conduct, not-B cannot be willed to be a universal law. But in neither case is the condition established on which the consequence rests; and it is equally conceivable that not-A is true, and therefore A false, or that not-B is the maxim of your conduct, and B therefore unfit for universal law. But the point of supreme importance is to determine what is and what should be the principle of moral conduct. Here, however, the practical reason can give no information, since its very essence consists in being formal. But if this be the ethical outcome of Kant's principles, he himself did not consistently abide by it. From the law, which, in virtue of its source, we have seen to be formal and empty, he attempts to deduce the system of •41 64 Kantiini F.lhu-n and fho f: I our ri^rlits and tluticH. 'I'ho impossibility of rucU n dorivfttion iiiuy bo uliown by consiiloring tlio clmnictDr of tho law itsolf. Tho Cutt>gorical Imporativo begins with {]w notion of action. Wo aro so to art Miat tho maxims of our oi.mluct may adapt thomsolvps to universal law. Now an act is tho translation by volition of a thonjrht into reality, as, convoraoly, knowUnlgo is tlu» tranNlution of reality into tlu)nj^ht. Tho idea on tho ono hand is n nu>ro state of our consciousness, the chanf^e in the world on the other hand is a !ni>ro event of nature. For action there is ro.pnird a union of both through tho will. A volition actualizes tho idea. Ihit this is imjwssiblo tndess tho idea to bo reali»;od is sonietliinfr di,r,„ito, some particular 0!ul and no mere abstract i)rineiplo. There can bo no vohtion in genend, no realization of a thought, whoso universality sta.ids directly opposed to tho j)articularity of Qxktout things. Now tlu) Imperative is such an abstmction. It requires you to realize something, and yet gives you nothing that you can realize. And tho will to which this lmi)erative a(hlresses itself is likewise an abstraction. It is its essence to bo formal, but tho law requires you to materialize it, to give it a content, to contradict its essence. O.dy as fornud is it good, and yet as good it ordains an activity which it cannot under- tako without c(vising to bo formal. Its object is the nmstory of tho sensuous nature^, and yet it is defiled by any contact with sense. Such a pure will is, in short, a contradiction: as will it must have a delinito content or matter for its activity, but as pure will it nuist bo merely formal, that is, it can have no content. The other clement in tho Categorical Imperative is that of conformabiliiy to universal law. The maxim on I'Jfhicti of Evolution. 55 which you net tnuHt luhipl- it.Hc^lf to u principlo for othorH. Jhit RH nnythinj^ you chooHo fur your own uiuxiia ia HUHr(.ptil)lo of thiH univormil iipph'ivition, so fur uh tho law Jiloiio is to (l.Mri.h), wo iiuiHt Hiiy witli llogol tliat "thoro iH nothinj^ whutHoovor whicli iu thiw way could not bucorno II moral law." * 'J'jio law forbids you niakinj^ any prin- ciplo and tho contradictory of it, ut tho Hanio timo, niaxinm of your conduct ; but it dooH not jirovcnt you chooHiuf^ cither ono or tho otluT of thoHo two. Which it shall bo, ii) loft ontiroly unih^tcTtnincd. Jf doccption bo tho maxitn of your conduct, you inuHt not w il truth- fuhu\sH for univorHal law; or if truthl'ulmwH bo your maxitn, deception cannot bo willed uh priiunplo for others ; but thero is no way of dotormining from tho law >vlono whether truthfulness or decoption should bo tukon as starting-point. Sui)poHo tho (jueHtion bo put, "if, when h\ dillicidty, I may not make a promiHo with tho inten- tion of not observing it;" then, says Kant, "I soon perceive, it is true, that I can will tho lio, but not a universal law to lio, for thon thoro couhl bo no such thing us promising." f Hut what contradiction is thoro in tho supposition that mon have ceased to make and give promises ? Wo set out to prove that promise- breaking is immoral, and wo show that if cuiversally miopted it would K-ad to tho abrogation of promise- making. JJut why should there be promiso-making ? Though tho nbsenco of it might conflict with other conditions, it is certainly not forbidden by tho formal law. Whatever of cogency tho argument seems to carry with it, it derives from an illicit appeal to tho consequoncos of actions in tho real world, — by descending, that is, from the a priori sphere of thought to the a. posteriori of cxperiouco. Only if promise-keeping bo * llogcl's Wcrkc, i. \io2. f Wcric, iv. 250-251, M >^ 56 Knnlian FAhirtt and ihv moral, doos tho lu,v pronoiinoo pmmiHo.l)n>nkln^ immorft!. And tho Iftw itHclf ia inmpftbh, of dole nniiiinK wli(«t,lior Miomlity it8i>(f conHiHt ill promiso-koopijijf or in prorniHo- broakin^. Hut tho point of intoroHt is prorisoly to Hhow that tho ono i8 moral and should bo, tho other imniural and Miiould not bo. Tho contradictions imnmnont in tho Categorical Tm- ponitivo havo now boon dovolopcnl ; and it will porliapH bo mhnittod that thoy coimtitntc^ a Huflicic-nt rofntation of any nior,«ly formal principle of morality. If this bo Kfaniod, it follows that an ethical systom can bo coiiHtructod only on ft fi>undntion which is not formal, that is, only on tho basis of a law wl.ich has a material content. Hut Kant, in H proposition a,-* closely reasoned as any of its protofypos in Goometry, claims to havo dcmoiiHtratod that "all nuiterial practical jirinciples are, as such, of one and the eairo ki.ul, and belong to a general systoin of self-love or individual happiness." * Now, if there is any fact of which our moral consciousness is indubitably certain, it is that duty does not consist in tho i)ursuit of individual happiness, and it is on this account that egoistic hedonism fails as a philosophy of ethics. If, then, all material principles are of this nature, as tho proposition asserts, then obviously they afford no explanation of tho facts of our moral life j and, since tho samo has been shown of all formal principles, it would follow that an ethical philosophy was for over impossible. But before assenting to this conclusion, tho proof must be examined by which Kant professes to have established the premise on which it rests. What is v.iiid, what not valid, in his demon- stration of the ogoipm of all material principles? First of all it must bo granted, with Kant, that the pleasure arising from the idea of the existence of an * Wet'kc, y. 22. J'UhicH of h'voluUon. 67 ohjoot roBtH oti tho roocptivity of tho mibjoct, .H.d boloPK* th(!rofor(3 to sonso a.ul not to undorstandin^. Tt must furtJuT 1,0 granted that thi« c^xpoctod plooH„ro .lotor- nnnoH tho doHJro towardH tho realization of tho object Nor oaT. it bo doniod that a prir.cipio whieh makes Hi.ch' pleaHuro tho higheHt detertninator of tho will in ouo of Bolf-lovo. Hut it (..tnnot bo granted that all material princ.pIeH are of tins nature. And we must, therefore, alllrm that Kant has not proved what he set out to prove! Indeed, this becomes obvious by a mero comparison of the enunciation and tho conch.Hion of the proposition. The proof only warrants what the conclusion expresses,' namely, that "all material in'\ncip\c», whirk jmt tho deter- minatnr of choicv in plmsuro or pain, roHuUing from the e.U8toncn of an object, are, so far, all of the same Vind that they belong to a system of self-love or individual happiness." JJut fV enunciation affirms that all material prmciplos as meh belong to a system of self-love. And between this universal and that particular judgment there lies an area which, it requires littlo logic to terich us, is wholly untouched by tho demonstration. If only the class of material principles specified is egoistic, it does not follow that tho same can bo predicatod oi' all material principles as such. The result, accordingly, is that morality, w) ich wo have found inexplicable from tho mero form of a universal law, is not incompatible with a principle that differs t>om the formal law, in that it has a content, but agrees with ;t, in that it is of universal extension. Such a principh cannot be the product of reason alone, which is onl^- form-giving, nor yet of sense a?one, which is only the source of matter. It is to bo a principle for men, aari differs therefore on the one band from'a law for m'ereiy ■ *y4 68 Kaniian EJiics and the Q. rational beings like the angels, as on the other, from a maxim for merely sensuous beings like the brutes. It must express the end for us as men, Tavep(;>invov ayadiv. It can be found only in the characteristics of human nature— in the idea of man as such. Any other derivation of it misses the mark, either by aiming too high, or not liigh enough. We believe that the conception of Aristotle must form the starting-point of any scientific ethic, though, as may hereafter rppear, Aristotle .iid not apprehend, as Kant did, the significance of an a priori element in morality. But a rightly-developed Aristotel- lanism 'n ethics must mediate between Formalism and Empiricism, just as Criticism, in the theoretical sphere, brought together the truth of Sensationalism and Rationalism. Against such a derivation of morality from the essential nature of man, no one has, however, protested more vigorously than Kant himself. " It is,'^ he says (to quote only one of scores of passages), « of the last moment to be on our guard ag-nst supposing for an instant that the reality of this principle can be deduced from the peculiar character of human nature. For duty is to be the unconditicnate necessity qf an action, and must accordingly be valid for all rational beings (to whom an Imperative is at all applicable) and only on this account binding on the human will. Whatever is derived, on the contrary, from the particular constitution of human nature, from certain feelings or tendencies, or even if possible from a special bias peculiar to human reason but not necessary for the will of every rational being, may, it is true, be a maxim for us, but never a universal llw, may, that is, be a subjective principle we like to follow! but can rover be an objective law, ordaining how to act^ Ethics of Evolution. 59 even though the bent, inclination, and constitution of our nature were opposed to it. Indeed, the sublimity and internal dignity of the law show themselves the more conspicuously, according as the subjective motives are in opposition to it, without however weakening its deter- minative force or derogating from its validity."* In this passage Kant very emphatically rejects the deduction of the ethical princ^ le from the peculiar nature of man. He wdl have it binuing on man, soleli/ because it is valid for all rational beings. But since we know of no other rational beings than man, it does seem a work of super- erogation to excogitate for them a system of morality, and a hopeless undertaking to reach in this way the definite rights and duties incident to human life.' If the law which it is Kant's merit to have shown must be universal^ be yet elevated above the universal o^ human nature, so as to include within itself every ratioaal being, then by leaving the actual world we know for an imaginary world of which we know nothing, we make it incapable of sustaining any content, without which, however, wo have found morality wholly inexplicable. Why, then, did Kant here aim so high— Kant, who had formerly meted out the domains and bounds of knowledge and cautioned us against those stormy and perilous seas of the Unknowable, which encompass on every side the tiny island of our knowable world ? He sought, in fact, to rid his morality of the empirical element, which could not be avoided if the idea of humanity were taken as its foundation. For Kant the empirical was always associated with the idea of the accidental; and he felt that its admission into morality would sully the purity of +he good will and endanger the dignity of a law that was * Wei-lc, iv. 273. •*« 'm ! II •'•1 60 Kantian Ethics and the pit. I to be valid even though opposed by the appetites, the tendencies, or even by the constitution of our nature. But Kant here fails to distinguish what is essentially different. His grounds are vahd against a system that makes pleasure the end and aim of action, but they do not touch a principle like that of Aristotle, which lays a foundation for morality in the essential and permanently, abiding nature of man. It makes all the difference in the world whether the principle be ^Sov^ or eiSatfiov la, hnt it is just this that Kant failed to see. Vers.d as he was in the moral speculations of the French and English, it is more than probable that he knew only at second-hand the great masterpieces of antiquity; and so failed to profit by a distinction which Aristotle had so clearly developed. The ancient moralist, recognizing that the good after which all strive was universally named eiSaifiovid, pro- ceeds to notice the variety of meaning covered by that term, and rejects r/Bovv a^ an equivalent for it. The absolute good must L ' in itself sufficient and cannot, like pleasure, be dependent on anything else. What this self- sufficient good, which is desired only for its own sake, may be, will appear from a consideration of the work peculiar to man (r^ iavrov ^pr-pv, rh X^oov, rh oiKetov). For as the flute-player and the sculptor and the artist find the good and the perfoct in their respective works, Ro must the absolute good be found in the peculiar work of man, if such indeed there be. That, however, cannot be doubted; for nature that has assigned special functions to the flute-player and the sculptor would not have left man, as such, without an end. It is incredible that eye and hand and foot, and in general every member, have manifestly each a function of their own, but man as a totality, man apart from these individual members has Ethics of Evolution. 61 none. Granting, then, that man must have some work or activity peculiar to him as man, we must next determine Its character. It cannot be merely to live, to nourish himself, and to grow, for that is common to him with the plants ; nor yet to live a life of feeling, for that he shares with the animals. What distinguishes man from these is reason, and the end of his being must therefore consist in an activity of reason. Is now the motive from which Kant forbids the deduction of morality from the peculiar nature of man justified by this view of the typical system of Aristotle ? Does it endanger either the purity of the will or the un- conditionality of the law ? The answer of courod depends upon what we mean by our terms. If the will is good and the law is absolute only because they are both empty abstractions, then assuredly they are robbed of their dignity in a system like that of Aristotle, which requires that each should have a definite content. But a dignity that consists in barren formality and that cannot come in contact with reahty without losing its essential character, it is at once absurd and impossible to maintain in a philosophy of our concrete morality. It is not necessary to repeat our criticism of the practical philosophy; it will suffice to recall that the one great- truth we found in its principles was that the moral law and the good will are possible only by merging the paifcicularity of sense in the universality of reason. But for this, which was excluded by the system of Kant, ample provision is made in the system of An;.+-itle. It provides for the law a form that is univers-;!, and a matter that is concrete. The character of generality cannot be wanting to a principle which formulates, not the empirical and accidental nature of the individual, but 1 '31 in i 62 Kantian Ethics and the **«»> '«^. the inner necessary and unconditioned idea of the species itself. Nor yet can it lack a content, for it is not an abstract universal of reason, but the concrete universal of humanity. And the union of form and matter in actual living practice is guaranteed by an Imperative ordaining that reason, by which alone man is made what he is, shall permeate all the activity of his life and gain the mastery over his bhndly self-seeking appetites and desires. In this way the individual while concretely realizing the idea of his own being follows laws that are unconditioned, because given in the idea, and that are universal, because the idea is not peculiar to him, but valid for every human being. The principle of Aristotle accordingly satisfies the requirements of the moral law as explicated by Kant. The same may be said of the good will, which is how- ever not explicitly discussed by Aristotle. With the correlate question of freedom and necessity it came first with Christianity into the living consciousness of modern Europe. But it is not only in harmony with, it is really supplementary to, a principle that places the absolute good in the realization of the essential nature of man. The good will is, as Kant explains, one that wills the universal; and since, as we have seen, the universal canrot be abstract, the good will can be no other than that which wills the concrete universal. When man no longer follows blindly his selfish appetites and desires, but acts rationally in accordance with the idea he has of his own worth and dignity as man, then the will is good, for it is in the unhampered service of reason. Instead, therefore, of arguing with Kant that the moral law is not grounded in the peculiarity of human nature and is binding on man only because valid for all Ethics of Evolution. 63 rational beings, we must, in the spirit of Aristotolianism, maintain "that no other task can be given to man than the reab-zation of the idea of his own worth, and that no other than this can be comprehended, no other recognized by him."* Had Kant really understood this principle, it may be doubted whether he would have cast it so lightly aside. But there is ample evidence that he had no right comproben-ion of it whatsoever. And his table of ethical principles, a table professedly exhaustive, does not even contain the name of Aristotle, for whose principle there is in fact no representative. It omits the name of the greatest of morahsts and passes over in silence the only principle Kant had been at pains specifically to refute ! It may now be considered as established that the moral law, which Kant rightly argued must be unconditional, can be no other than a material principle whose form and content are given in the idea of man as man. Kant'a opposition to this view, if it be not a mere misunder- standing, must be held ungrounded and untenable. We have now to add that Kant himself by a very instructive inconsequence more than once assumes the principle he had so vigorously combated. Thus when he speaks of " the idea of humanity man carries in his soul as archetype of his actions," he concedes everything for which we here contend.f And this agreement is no accidental occurrence, but a result rendered inevitable by the logic of the moral consciousness. Hence Kant is obliged to carry this conception into the development of the practical philosophy, though, it is true, with a sacrifice of its unity and consistency. Without supposing ilf i # T iFendelcaburg's NaturreoU, p. 41 (2nd ed. 1861) iii. 260. 64 Kantian Ethics and the that the last grounds of morality were contained in the idea of man as such, he could never have reached the second formulf. for the Categorical Imperative, the formula ordaining : so to act as to use the humanity in thine own person and in the person of every other always as an end, never merely as a. means.* And only on the same assumption is it possible to classify duties as tending to the perfection of self or to the happiness of otherp f Had Kant only meditated on the principle here un- consciously and illogically assumed he would have found in it the key to the solution of that unnatural antinomy between goodness and happiness, which was not to be avoided on his own conception of morality. True to the noble thought with which his ethical writings begin, that a good will is the only absolute good, he rightly refuses to identify the moral with the pleasurable, and, as a consequence, regards the pleasurable as an impure motive to the good will. The children of the kingdom take not the hireling's wages, nor give the hireling's service. Duty is the necessity of an act out of reverence for the law. On this side there is no compromise between virtue and happiness. But on another, the case is different. For, as we have already seen, in the highest good, which the moral law enjoins us to realize, happiness is an element not less than virtue. And, as is well known, the antinomy supplies grounds for postulating the existence of God. Without inquiring into the nature of the new eudae- monistic God that Kant thus sets up on the ruins of Deism, we may merely observe that He has no other function than the mediation of a contradiction which is due solely to the one-sidedness of Kant's ethical philo- * Werke, iv. 277. f vii. 189. Ethics of Evolution. ed in the iched the tive, the manity in er always ly on the 8 tending therp f here un- ive found antinomy LOt to be ue to the )gin, that Y refuses ud, as a I impure kingdom lireling's everence between case is highest appiness is well itulating 65 :: ir Th'°^ '^^ - -ompaniment of, morarX: naf ,r« """"^^ ^""' ^^^^ ^° «^-d of a super- 11 ■, . ^ '" "' ' '^"^ '^° ^^^^<^ incliuation to good seemed to detract from the worth of goodness, which as he concexved, only the moral law ootid produce And o sharply does he exclude inclination from mollL fhat to an end winch is unwillingly adopted."* Thus Schiller ecu d say that the Draco of his age' expounded tL 1 But? Sir/'^^ir '''^'''' ^-^^ --y ^^- ev 1 . r "f ^ -^--tained, duty cannot be for at last an abidmg disposition which has its delight onlv m the good. The ideal of a moral man ,•« ^ ..^ which t,e ^.awof the mind" has t^.:;; ^r^.^ the service of the good. But Kant regarded as end IZ was only beginning, and placed, accordingly, duty il al eternal warfare between ^^flesh" and '^spiHt'^^ S^rJ! from a aw valid for rational beings alone' he was owj when he reached the specifically human nature to suppress entirely the claims of sense. But the enemy not completely conquered until reconciled ; and Kantl mistake consists in attempting to quench thj fire of sens instead of turning it to account for the quickening oh" moral life and the glow of moral feeling. Had he t^^kl for his principle, instead of that formal universal of reason the idea of human nature as such, he would Lf seen ^at morality consisting as it does in' the real" at Ln of the end to which we arc destined. mu«t necessarily * Wirle, vii. 189. 5 GO Kaniian Etlilcn nml fh,> h ■ bo accompntiiod by plonauro in tlio nttainTnont. (if tlini. pvul. Tho idea is Mio OHsoniial mid tlio otiixiiinl, tlio ])lonHuro tlid nccidtMilal and tli(> Hccdudary. 'V\w oikIh in which tho i(h'a of luitnanity cxpivHscs itself must bo tho otdy niotivoH of tlio jrood will ; but whon thoso nro honestly fuKiUcd, Mumi i)l(>asnr(> spriiijrs np at onco as conso(]u»mco and as si^ni of tho nvoral m.'ido for the sak(> of comparison between tho two principles. It has been seen alri>ii(ly that tlio Catojjforical lm})(>rativo is formal and empty, but wo must now add that it is essentially sid)jectivo. Tho individuMl is supposed to bo t'lo source and the standard of all moral f^ood, and no account is taken of tho morality already existent in tho world. l?ut this wliolly ignores the development of tho individual consciousness, which is made np for tho most ])art of the moral and intellectual substance it has assimilated from its environment. Unus homo, nuUm homo. Tho individual has not to create from his own innate emptiness some new morality; in the main, ho has only to make his own the morality of his people and his country. And his moral notions aro accordingly conditioned by the history and circumstances of tho * Troiiclcloiil)uru;'H Hisfovisrhc Ihitrage, iii. 212 (od. 1867). Elhirn of Kvoluh'on. q; nd. I.O 0...-I, „nlHlM.,s, u,..I Uy (,,.,3 ,u.cun...lut,.a ol,- vv.tl.on Ins cdncuUon ih li„i,sl.,.,| . „.,, <,,„. ,.f ^.^,.^ •norul man ks never UM,sin.ilativc, I,..,, alwnyH c.vafciv. or Holf.or,gn.ut.nf.. The fornm,! uuW.vhuI in an idea of his mun not tlu, oLje-Cively ,.,.ali..,l ..nivernal of State, of tln.rc-h of lanuly, nud of Soeioly. And as Kant's prac t.cul plnlosophy i^n.onvs tl.o derivation of tho individual con.sc.ouHnc.H,s fro,„ the objctivo consciouHncss as -'-or.ov -rroXtrcK^v, can be no other than tho 6 * Wi-^v i-JSJ 08 Kantian Ethics and the \^ K I civil commiinify or tho Stato. In other lanjjrnaf^'o, our Bocinl institutions are tho objoctivo oxprossion of tlio idea of humanity as it embodies itself in the course of history. The view of tho moral principle for which wo havo been contending rests on a meta])liysical assumption that must now bo indicated. If the account given bo correct, duty consists in tho realization of an end or idea, for tho sake of which alone man exists as moral agent. Hero wo are in accord with Kant, who conceived tho perfecting of the will through reason as tho final cause of our existence. Kthics is inevitably driven to a teloological conception of tho universe. Wo find morality explicablo only if thought be assumed as prins, and force or matter as the sub- ordniato condition for tho fulfilment of tho ends which thought establishes. This organic conception of tho world we are not now called upon metaphysically to justify. Wo havo only to observe that it is forced upon us by tho interpretation of tho facts of tho moral con- sciousnjss. By implication, therefore, wo have already rejected an ethical philosophy built on a system of meta- physics directly opposed to tho teloological. Where matter is taken as the primary and original, and thought as the secondary and derivative, there emerges such a system,— which may, by way of contrast, bo called tho mechanical. A science of physics is possible, but a science of ethics is impossible under this conception of tho universe. If man is nothing but a congeries of feelings and ideas, which a blindly working nature has set up, without purpose and without aim, if his actions are the necessary consequences of feelings which are neither caused by him nor subject to his control, does it not seem evident that moral responsibility is meaningless Fdhics of Eoolatiun. 69 f\ui)fV!, our on of tlio course of 1 wo Imvo iption that )e correct, ea, for the Hero wo rfecting of • existence, coption of if thought 3 the sub- )nds which )n of the y^sically to rccd upon noral con- ve ah'oady 1 of raeta- l. Where id thouglit ^cs such a called the )le, but a tion of the Df feelings as set up, 18 are the ro neither oes it not loaninglcss and duty a vain mocking word? If wo are merely tho arena m which events happen, and not tho self-centred personalities from whom actions take their source, then morality consists in a simple lalssoz-falre, and ethics is not distinguishable from physics. 4. Evolution idle TIedonism. But thougli our final result is that the mechanical con- ception of the universe cannot bo reconciled with the do!iveranc(^s of tho moral consciiuisness, it ia notorious that evolution, as thus interpreted, has been applied— and, as is widely supposed, with success— to the problems of moral philosophy. Of this philosophizing Mr. Herbert {Spencer's Data of Ethics may be taken as a typical exat-plo. And it now remains to examine the philosophy of ethics which that work contaiii s.* Mr. Spencer makes no reference to the will in his work * It may bo well to note that with Darwinism as a biological hypothesis wo have in this casay really no concern. Certain metaphysical assumptiona often associated with it we are liowcver forced to rtyect. There aro two apheres-the sphere of nature and the sphere of spirit. And if Darwinism has shed light on that it has left this as it found it. Lange— no biass- ' authority— says • " The evolution of man from lower forms of life is from the point of view of natural science perfectly self-evident ; while, on the contrary, his conscious life (Gcistesleben) remains still a problem when all 'Jie consequences of Darwinism have been granted" (Gcschk-hte des Maleralismus, ii. 313 (3rd ed.) ). It is our eUbrt to show what this conscious life, on its moral side, really imi)lies. And we enter our humble protest against the illogical method of importing into the sphere of morality a hypothesis taken from other phenomena. We demand that the facts of morality shall be studied, as Darwin studied the facta of life, and then, but Lot till then, a theory of them given-a theory deduced LUC ...1 ,!,.., ,^itu xcitrfcnt-c to them, and not with reference to a « holly different class of facts. I, 70 Kantian Ethics and the h*4'' ^ ** on ethics, but olsowhoro ho rejects tho conception o^ freedom as an ilhisiou. Not that ho proves it such, ...»♦, that ho examines its validity at all ; but, simply sotti, .; out with tho asHumptioi;, ho shows how tho "illus-'on' has been Konerated. It arose, ho informs us, from the belief "that at e.ich moment tho r(/() present as such i consciousness (I exclude the implied, but unknown sub- stratiim which can never be present) id somothing moro than tho i\}r,rvvgnto of foeliijgs and ideas which then exists."* But tho fact is, it seems, that tho c(jo is nothing else than this "aggregate,'' and in no other sense can it be said that " I '' determine this or that action or volition. As the influence of Hume is traceable in Mr. Spencer'b Lockean theory of knowledge, here it meets us at tho very threshold of tJio ethics. But the hypothesis is not on that account any the loss mysterious. Why should all mankind have fallen into this strange error of supposing themselves something more than their "feelings and ideas" ? This supposition, so marvellous in itself, needs some justification before being used as an axiom to account for real or imaginary illusions. And the next stage is equally wondei-ful. For even though we concede tliat men, under a strange infatuation, have come to believe in a "mental self'" present to conscious- ness, apart fro-n tho aggregate of ideas and emotions, how can there ariso from this tho notion of freedom ? Because, says Mr. Spencer, wo attribute the action to it and not to the causality of a feeling or idua. But why we should do this, there is no reason given ; and none perhaps could be given except the exigencies of a fore- gone conclusion. Without a previous belief that we were free, there would be no ground for assigning the * P^ili-holofiy, 1. 50). »iicoption o^ it Hiich, liot nply sotti. .; "illus-"on' s, iroin tho i aa audi ) known aub- jthiiig" nioro which then tho C(j() ia II no other ilia or that ia traceable (\go, here it d. But tho myaterioua. hia atransro ! than their marvclloua used aa an iona. And '■en thougli ation, have conscious- emotiona, freedom ? action to it But why and none s of a fore- f that we ii^niing the Eihics of Evolution. 71 volition to tho causality of tho ryo and not of tho feeling that preceded it. Indeed, wore inference at all posaible for Hueh a consciousnesa-and that cannot bo adoiitted— would it not argue from the connexion between feelings and actions that the will waa neceaaitated ? Even, then, though wo grant tho absurd supposition of tnat ghostly presence in consciousneaa-that ego apart from ideaa and emotiona-wo must deny that it could throw such a deceptive halo about tho myateriea of tho human will. But how it ever got its s-at there in consciouanesa ; how wo, who are merely bundlea of conscious states, could appear to tho " aggregaies^' that we are more than " aggre- gates," is a mystery without parallel, or paralleled only by tho belief in freedom which this buatard ego imposes upon our credulity. The genesis of tho notion of freedom here given, ia, we think, absurd ; but the fact romaina that for Mr. Speucer the notion is an illusion. And holding with K nt that freedom ia the ratio es.mdi of morality, it ia not eaay for ua to see how ethio.- is possible on the denial of it. Mr. Spencer was, perhaps, dimly conacious of the aume diffi* culty ; for it ia only by changing the problem of ethics that his system ia at all conceivable. With a naivete that is really surprising, he saya in hia well-known letter to Mr. Mill : '< The view for which I contend ia, that morality properly ao-called— the acience of right conduct —has for its object to determine how and why certain modea of conduct aro detrimental and certain other modes beneficial. These good and bad results cannot be accidental, but must bo necessary consequencea of the constitution of things; and I coaceive it to be the business of Moral Science to deduce, from tlie laws of life and the conditions of existence, what kinds of action %\ 11' 72 Kantian Ethics and the J ^4 1^. % ■ necessarily tend to produce happi.iess, and what kinds to produce unhappiness."* That the science thus sketched in outline would, when realized, be useful, there can be no doubt whatever. And any one who has in the slightest dej?ree observed how much needless suffenng is entailed, through ignorance of the conditions under which we live, would welcome a hygienic almanac in which human actions were tabulated according to their "beneficiar^ or "detrimental' results, specific effects being set over against specific causes with explanation of their necessary connexions. The possi- bility of such a science may be doubted; and the induc- tions it would bring together from al uost all th-.; other sciences, especially from Biology, Psychology, and Sociology, certainly imply an almost superhuman effort and grasp to adapt them to the infinite variety of human activities. In outline, however, the science is at least conceivable. But though its possibility be granted, and the benefits to be derived from it be emphasized, we must note that it -- aid be the science of hedonistic action not of ri(jU conduct. It would have shown the causes nnd the conditions of pleasure, but it .^ould not have touched the question of goodaess. From the tables it could in any case be seen what it was prudent to do, but in no case what it was duty to do. To identify moral action with beneficial results, is to obliterate distinctions that are as important as they are manifestly obvious. If any one asserted that the science of sound properly so-called had for its object to detormine how and why certain relations existed among the phenomena of colour it might be difl^cult to refute him, although you were certain he used wjrds in a meaning entirely foreign to * /)(rA7 of Rfhirs, p. 57. »r I Ethics of Evolution. 73 it kinds to 'uld, whea ver. And 3rved how norance of i^elcome a tabulated i " results, luses with ^he possi- the induc- th'.) other :>gy, and nan effort of human ! at least nted, and , we must ction not i.uses nnd 3 touched could in but in no "al action ions that . If any so-called /■ certain olour, it ou were >reign to the popular usage. The case is precisely the same with Mr. Spencer. He asserts that ethics or the science of right conduct aims at determining how and why actions are beneficial or detrimental. But the voice of humanity, as caught alike in language rnd in thought, has pro- clanned the incommensurability of right with the bene- ficial and of wrong with the detrimental. It is sure that pleasure is not morality nor misery immorality; and that the moral life aces not consist in the pursuit of the one or the avoidance of the other. A -moral science- that proposes to deduce the laws and conditions of happiness is as much opposed to the facts of the moral conscious- ness as an acoustics of colours to the facts of extern-d perception. A - moral science" must be a philosophy of our morality, not of our pleasures or our advantages, or anything else that is gratuitously identified with our morality. This false equation between the good and the beneficial has led Mr. Spencer to assign to the law of causality an important place in his evolutionistic theory of ethics. Ke blames moral philosophers for not erecting "into 'a method the ascertaining of necessary relations between causes and effects, and deducing rules of conduct from formulated statements of them.-* And in "studying the various ethical theories," he has been "struck with the fact that they are all characterized either by entire absence of the idea of causation or by inadequa+e presence of it."t And the fact is not essentially different from Mr. Spencer's representation. Moralists have never attempted to show the causal connexion between specific modes of action and the feelings of pleasure or pain accompanying them, much less to construct on such a * DataofEthtcs,x>.(S\. ^ Ibid. -p. ii). 1% 74 Kantian Ethics and the \l If?'- foundation a system of rules valid for all human conduct. Already in possession of a moral estate, becjuoatlied by the spirit of past generations, they did not foolishly attempt to create it do novo by their own individual efforts. They found existing in the world a system of morality, which had formed the fibre of their spiritual being before as yet they had awakened to reflection and become "ethical philosophers.'^ And this universal ethos, at whose breasts thc^y had been suckled, naturally seemed bett' ■- than any jjoor empty i)hantom of their own indi- vidual brain. It never occurred to them that the world had waited for '' rules of conduct'' till they appeared, like gift-bringing (lods from Heaven, to supply the universal want. Nor did they deem it any part of their task to construct from their own private minds a set of laws to which hutnanity must conform. Recognizing the superior wisdom of universal reason, as it exists not merely ideally in the moral notions of individuals, but actually intlie objective realization of these into State and Society and Family, they proposed to themselves no other problem than the understanding of what actually exists —the comprehension of the dicf^seit)^, not the creation of an imnginnvy jenscit.'<. And the solution of this problem took them far beyond the "idea of 'causation," which, if not entirely absent from their systems, is introduced only to bo excluded on the ground that morality is impossiolo, if spirit be in any way subject to the categories, wl'.'lx spirit itself has imposed upon nature. The etliics of evolution, however, has hitliorto univer- versally, though, as wo venture to think, not aecc 'sarily, followed a wholly different method. And it is t-u.. which Mr. Spencer adopts. Instead of setting out from tbe totality of facts to be explained^ he begins wicii an ' f Ethics of Evolution. 75 I conduct, ed by tlio y attempt II efforts, morality, iig before 1 become jtlios, at f seemed )wn indi- ihe world ppoiirod, [)ply tlio of their } a set of izing the ists not lals, but tato and no other !y exists 'ation of [)roblem vhich, if 3od ouly )oss7Uia, univer- :)y3Rrily, o whii'ii om fie nch an assumption borrowed from elsewhere, gratuitously im- porting into the realm of thought a category, which we know only as valid for nature. The law of causality which the knowing subject finds, because he has put, in the objective world, is, without any grounds except the needs of a mechunicul hypothesis of the universe, pro- claimed a law for self-consciousness itself. If the facts cannot bo explained on this dogmatic assumpt-on, so much the worse for the facts. The hypothesis is not perhaps consonant with " morality as it is," but it i the source of - morality as it should be l" Without appu- rently observing the infinite presumption implied in the impugning by any one man of the morality oi humanity, or the ludicrousness of a " philosopher " creating from his own individual prejudices and prepossessions a "morality as it should be," our Evolutionists dilate upon more than one " defect in the current system of morality," develop points hitherto hidden from " men at large an'd moralists as exponents of their view," and, as if pos'Iessed of an insight at once poelic and prophetic, celebrate the coming triumph of " Industrialism," when man, who "as at present constituted," is net in h rrmony with the requirements of the theory, shall have adapted himself " to the conditions of social life,- or to the -guidance by proximate pleasures and pains," which all other animals have already accepted as Categorical Imperative in their " system of morality."* We ask fo^ .->■ juiilosophy of our existent morality, and we are pre .-id.ed Tnth a dogmatic non-existent morality. This surely is to receive a stone, * See Data of .Ethic- pp. v., 70, 87, 132. " Hence iLere is a supi)o«able formula for th.. udivities wf eacli sp,.cie8, which could It be drawn out, would constitute a s>,stem of morality i'or that species (p. 132j. 76 Kantian Ethics and the St V 'V. when wo have aslorl for bread. But that is not the worst. A philosophy of morality we may dispense with, — not, however, with morality itself. Yet the Evolutionist requires that it be suppressed when it conflicts with his " Moral Science," whose '' deductions are to be recog- nized as laws of conduct, and are to be conformed to,'' irrespective of the dictates of duty or the unmistakable voice of conscience. The facts, it would seem, exist for the sake of the theory, not the theory for the explanation of the facts. We have already advanced far enough to see that the Evolution-hypothesis does not really affect, because it never reaches, the problems of ethical philosophy. These lie in the moral consciousness of humanity, to which it simply gives the go-by. The conceptions of duty and responsibility may be taken as fundamental. Mankind, if we except a few philosophers, is certain that the con- ditio sine qua non of the first is the freedom of the will, and of o second, the self-sameness or identity of the perse these be denied, it can see neither meaning nor c • ; in the moral conceptions. The Evolutionist, however, enters the ethical sphere with a ready-made theory framed, irrespective of morality, from a wholly different class of phenomena. His premises are that the self is merely a collection of disconnected ideas, feelings, and volitions, and that will is only the name for a deter- mination towards action by any of these ideas, feelings, or emotions. An ego to which the " states of consciousness" belong, and by which they are held together, he ro^^ards as a fiction and an illusion. Not less illusory Le i Pro- claims that belief of the uiiphilosophical mind, which holds to a will that ivills something, and not to the will of the "philosophers," which is only another nao^e for Ethics of EvohLtion. ! not the ie with, — olutionist i with his >e recog- med to/' istakable exist for jlauation that the cause it . These which it luty and [ankind, the con- the will, '" of the neauing utionist, ly-made wholly :hat the eelings, I deter- ings.. or usness^' reofards :i.e ';>ro- which the will LTie for the " niovement" produced by the " composition" of the "forces" called motives, as they act and re-act in the chaotic region called self. But, as we have just said, the denial of freedom and of personal identity, and the extension of causality to mind — which is only the other side of that denial — lead inevitably to the annihilation of all morality. The problem of the ethical philosopher has therefore no existence for the Evolutionist, who has already excluded it by the one-sidtdness of his mecha- nical hypothesis. But he proposes a new problem to himself. Emptying morality of its content and iden- tifying the good with the pleasurable, he sets out "to deduce from the laws of life and the conditions of exist- ence, what kinds of action necessarily tend to produce happiness, and what kinds to produce unhappiness." And these he enjoins upon men as laws of their conduct. Here, however, he falls into an inconsequence. For if man is necessitated like any material object, as the theory asserts, then you cannot enjoin anything upon him any more than you can command the sun to stand still, or the stars to change their courses. And though such a " Moral Science " may interest the theorist, it is of no use for practice, just because there would be no practice, when the life of man was reduced to a series of events causally happening within the arena he has somel^ow mis- taken for a personal self. If on the other hanu man is not necessitated, as the theory has assumed, then it is evident that the "iaws of his conduct" wiil be very diiferent from those deduced from a hypothesis borrowed from the mechanical world. In any case, therefore, the " moral " speculations of the Evolutionist can have no interest for us as Moralists. If a consideration of the scope of the eihics of evolurlon I 78 Kantian Ethics and the i^hii '^y end in doubts as to the wo.th of such a science, an examination of its subject-matter will only confirm them. It has to deduce from the laws of life and the conditions of existence what kinds of action necessarily tend to produce happiness, and what kinds to produce unhappiness. It is at the outset assumed, in connexion with a hypothesis framed to fit a wholly different class of phenomena, thai^. the pursuit of pleasure and the avoidance of pams are the ultimate aims of all human conduct. Thus the inquiry into morality bc-ins with the assertion that morality is not an end in itself, but merely a means to something else. -The ultimate moral aim" is "a desirable state of feeling" (p. 4G). You arc to be virtuous, either ,that you yourself or that others naay be happy. The ethics of evolution, though certain that "the good is universally the pleasurable ■' (p. 30), wavers as to whether it is the pleasurable for you or the pleasurable for Society. The incon- gruities that emerge from its fusion of egoistic and universahstio Hedonism will meet us later. Meantime we wish to dwell on the first assumption that pleasure is the end, "pleasure somewhere, at some time, to some bemg^' (p. 4G). Meeting one assertion with another why shall we not maintain that moraliiy is an end in Itself? This can be impugned only on the supposition that there is no absolute end, or, if there be, that it is not morality. The ethics of evolution rests on the latter assumption. It asserts that morality is only a means to an ulterior end, which is pleasure. But nothing could be more gratuitous than this dogmatic assumption ^.ith which Mr. Spencer begins. As he denies that morality IS an end m itself, so is it open to anyone else to deny that pleasure is an end in itself. For the question lence^ an ' confirm and the 3cessarily produce onnexion t class of voidance conduct, assertion a means " is "a ! to be others though urable "' usurable ! incon- tic and eantime asure is 'O some mother, end in position at it is latter Bans to ;• could n \/ith lorality deny lestion. Ethics of Evolution. 79 Why should I be happy? is just as little, or just as much justifiable as the question. Why must I be moral ? The end can never be reached by simply asking Why. And it is no argument in favour of Hedonism that it gives a reason for viitue, so long as it gives no reason for that reason. Granted that you are to be moral that you may be happy, why then are you to be happy ? And the same may be asked of each and every end. . If therefore we are to have a philosophy of our morality at all, it can only be by facing the facts of the moral world and observing with what end alone they arc compatible or possible. That pleasure is the ultimate end Empiricism has generally taken for granted. Evolution, however, adduces a reason for it. It maintains that pleasure is the condition under which life has developed and the condition under which alone it can continue. If pleasure be not the end of conduct, then life would disappear. But just because you have given a reason for pleasure as end, it is not an ultimate end. You are moral that you may be happy, for without pleasure you could not live. Life is, therefore, taken as the ulterior end— that for which you rre at once moral and happy. But the old spectre again starts up in the question, Why shall I live ? And if, as we venture to think, no other answer can be given than that of Kant, which asserts that morality alone is that which makes life worth living, then with all our questionings w^e have merely described a circle and returned to the starting-point, that we are moral because morality itself is the end. Or if so much be nob granted, it must at least be conceded that pleasure has no more claim to be the ultimate end than virtue itself. 80 Kantian Ethics and the But if dc jure it cannot be shown tliat pleasure is the ulterior end and virtue only a means to it, there are de facto grounds for inverting that relation. For what- ever be the opinion of the speculator as to what, accordinfr to his theory, should be moans, and what ends, the moral consciousness, whence alone the data of ethics can be taken, is indubitably certain that virtue must be an end in itself, and never a mere n.'on-nt to anything else. It is sure that the moral man, neither directly nor indi- rectly, aims at wages or perquisites in the performance of his duties. And it suspects of immorality the man who practises virtue only as a convenient way of attaining something beyond it. All this is too well known to call for further illustration. And yet, universally recognized as it is by the consciousness of mankind, it is habitually ignored by our Evolutionists. Their Ethics, as we have seen, sets out from a hypothesis which is the direct contrary of it— from the assumption that pleasure is the only good and virtue merely a means to its attainment. Thus, instead of explaining the phenomena of the moral world, the ethics of evolution passes them over, or, at best, explains them away. The facts, however, abide; and none is more certain than the fact that pleasure can never be the end of moral volition and action. Besides these objections to the fundamental assumption of the ethics of evolution — objections which we venture to call insuperable— there is another which leaves that science without any raison d'etre whatever. To put this position beyond doubt will occupy us in the remainder of this essay. Meantime the essence of the matter may be stated in a few words. The subject-matter of "moral science " is the content of the moral world. This con- sists, on its inner side, of certain conceptions, emotions, Ethics of EcoJution. 81 ure is the there are ?^or what- iccording mds, the )thic3 can st be an ing else, nor indi- formance the man attaining n to call cognized abitually we have le direct re is the ainment. he moral r, or, at ', abide ; sure can lumption venture ves that put this linder of may be " moral 'his con- motions. and beliefs ; on the outer, of a realization of these in the State, the Family, and Society. Ethics has to explain these moral phenomena, just as astronomy has to explain the phenomena of the heavens. A science which fails to do that, whatever else it may be, is no " moral science," and has from tlie point of view of morality no justification whatsoever. Now it is precisely this we maintain, this we hope to demonstrate, of the ethics of evolution. For that purpose we might proceed at once to an examination of the relative parts of Mr. Spencer's Da fa of Ethics, which may be considered the classical, as it is the latest, exposition of " moral science " from the stand- point of mechanical evolution. But before doing so, wo shall attempt to establish our position by a few general considerations of a more abstract character. Our thesis is that the ethics of evolution can give no explanation of the facts of morality. The moral law, as Kant correctly interpreting the moral consciousness affirms, is universal and necessary. It prescribes some- thing to be done, not by any particular individual, but by all human beings, and not under certain conditions, but absolutely or unconditionally. The popular con- sciousness is clear on both these points; and even Mr. Spencer may hero be in harmony with it, for he ordains that the laws to be deduced by his " moral science" shall be observed by all men, irrespective of their own personal desires and estimates. But how now are these characteristics to be explained from the principle of Hedonism i' If the moral worth of actions be estimated by the feelings of pleasure and pain which accompany them, then it is obvious that the standard of morality cannot be objective and universally valid. For the agreeable and the dis!igreeal/le depend upon tlio relation I 82 Kantian Ethics and thn h^; of the object to the subject nnd manifestly vary with different ) ersons and even with the snnio person at different •; mes. Now, according to tho theory, it must follow that A, who finds his pleasure in excessive sensual gratification, or in violating the rights of others, is equally moral with B, who pursues a conduct the direct contrary of this. Or how are you to prove to the former that his life is immoral, when by hypothesis pleasure is the only standard of what is right, and pleasure can be estimated only by each individual for himself ? Thus Hedonism knows nothing of the notion of duty — of a something that is obligatory upon me whether I like it or not, and upon all others equally under the same circumstances. But this is ono of the most prominent factors in the moral consciousness, which an ethical philosophy is bound to explain. It is not, however, necessaiy that momentary pleasure be taken as the end; and the theory next aims at freeing itself from its palpable defects by placing the end in the greatest possible happiness of the individual during the entire period of his life. It assumes that from the experience of the race a series of rules might be collected to show v/hat activities were conducive to the highest and most enduring pleasures, and what brought the greatest quantum of enjoyment with the least alloy of pain. This is tho " Nautical Almanack " of Mill's UtHitarianism, which Mr. Spencer endeavours to supersede by substituting for its empirical inductions a system of rational deductions from the laws of life and the conditions of existence. Tho Almanack is certainly open to the gravest objections. The rules of experience are at best only the expression of an average and probable calculation, and the individual Ethics of Euulation. 8;{ mry with )tTson at ', it must ^e sensual others, is he direct he former pleasure isure can himself ? I of duty ) whether andcr the the most ss, which Y pleasure 1 aims at acing the individual imes that les might ducive to md what with the Imanack " ndeavours inductions ws of life lanack is The rules ion of an individual can never be sure they have an application to his particuhir case. Even were that found to bo so, they may be in conflict with the maturest judgments he himself has formed on the line of conduct to be pursued; and since his pleasure is the end, he must, it might bo supposed, be left free to follow the moans he deems best. And this brink's us to an objection which neither the Hedonism of Mr. Mill nor that of Mr. Spencer is able to overcome. Popular morality is aware of an obligation on the part of the agent to submit himself to laws, which it conceives as binding upon him. But what binding force have the rules of experience, what the deductions of the ethics of evolution? I may follow them or I may not. The end is pleasure, and with that end no rules, no deductions are necessarily given. They come to it from without; and, as their connection is external and artificial, it may be recognized or it may be ignored. Even though the rules are the surest way to the greatest sum-total of happiness, you can only call the individual who declines to follow them a fool, but you cannot compel or oblige him to act against his own views and wishes. What shall he care for the "groans of an abstraction V Hedonism endeavours to escape this objection, by placing the end, no longer in the happiness of the individual, but in the well-being of the community c even of the " entire sentient creation." It defines good as that which tends to promote the happiness of all sentient beings, bad as that which is detrimental to their welfare. And in the relation between the individual and society, it thinks it has found a basis for the notions of duty, responsibility, and accountability. This is, however, an illusion. If pleasure is the only good, G* A: IMAGE EVALUATION T^ST TARGET (MT-S) / Zt ^ 1.0 I.I 1^12.8 ^ 136 ^ 1^ 12.0 2.2 1:25 i 1.4 18 1.6 .^ V]

>^ -(^ '^ (9/1 Photographic Sciences Corporation 23 WEST MAIN STREET WEBSTER, N.r. HS80 (716) 872-4503 •1>' iV # ^3 \ , 'c^" ,. ^^ <^.* ri.^ 4^ ^^o Ux 84 Kantian Ethics and the neither the origin nor the validity of the moral notions admits of explanation. Not their origin : for though the end assumed is nominally a universal, it is incapable, because it is sensuous and not rational, of ever being in practice more than a particular. Grant that pleasure is the summum honum, and it follows, not that the individual will seek to promote it in others, but only that he will pursue it for himself. And that he should ever have passed from the particularity inherent in the principle to the universality which it is framed to explain, is only then conceivable, if at the dawn of self-consciousness he possess, not merely a sensuous but also a rational nature, which makes it possible for him to compare himself with others and to give himself universal laws of conduct, and in which is already contained a pnori the form of duty or moral obligation that furnishes at once the groundwork and the possibility of all personal morality. Utilitarianism, however, Avill not accept this position. It perseveres in the attempt to derive the universal from the particular, as though by a natural dialectic selfishness inevitably passed over into morality. Men, it is argued, soon perceive that their stock of pleasures is likely in the end to be increased if tliey abstain from those acts which excite the enmity and opposition of their fellow-men. And to a certain extent this is no doubt true. But even such a fact cannot explain the genesis of the moral character of the notions under consideration. On the contrary, it is inconsistent with the unconditionedness of all moral precepts, and its logical outcome is, not a system of morality, but a series of pliable rules of prudence and of cunning. And this brings us to the second point, which regards the validitij of the moral conceptions. '« Ethics of EooJ ition. 85 •al notions tliougli the incapable, ever being it pleasure t that the , but only he should srent in the framed to dawn of 1 sensuous )0ssible for ;ire himself is already obligation ! possibility wever, will he attempt as thoug'li )assed over rccive that end to be hich excite a. And to even such xl character e contrary, of all moral I system of udence and cond point, conceptions. i Were they grounded only on prudential considerations, one would be free to do evil provided no bad con- sequences were to be feared. If I am to aim at the universal good only as a means of reaching my own individual pleasure, then there is no reason why I should not, e.g. violate the rights of others, provided I were cunniiig enough to avoid, or powerful enough to avert, the consequences which such an act would bring upon me. This conclusion can be invalidated only by the assertion of a harmony, whether accidental or pre- established, between the pleasures of each and tb . pleasures of all. What is disagreeable to a community is disagreeable to the individuals who compose it ; and similarly of the agreeable. And this argument has found favour with some who have been at pains to refute in Political Economy the fallacy of protection. Yet it is essentially the same logic in both cases. It is detrimental to the State as a wJiole to protect any industry for which its resources have uo adaptation ; but the class protected may prosper, and that just because the State is the loser. So in the moral sphere, it may also happen, that what is detrimental to society as a whole brings the greatest advantage to some particular individual. New grounds must, therefore, be sought for his obligation to sacrifice himself to the community. And these are, ^ist of all, found in the force exercised by the State and by the social institutions and conventions. The ultimate ground of morality is the fear of punishment. But such a bald statement makes very apparent the insufficiency of the theory. For though it may explain subjection, it can give no account of moral ohUgation. Its consequences are the suppression of all that is most characteristic in the phenomena of the moral consciousness; and, in ■•■■ila i oo Kantian Ethics and the 1 pi'actice, disregard for rights and duties, so long as they may be neglected without present or future disadvantage. Besides, if, as the wisest philosophers assure us, the State and Society are themselves only morality on the objection side, then the hypothesis, besides its other defects, is chargeable with explaining a notion by itself- with deriving morality from that whose sole content is moi'ality. Thus all forms of Hedonism seem worthless as theorief. of morality. Has then the hedonistic ethics of evolution escaped this destiny ? Or, is it, aa Mr. Spencer sup- poses, a rational philosophy of the moral world ? To answer these questions is the only problem that remains. Evolutionists, as already pointed out, enter the moral sphere with a ready-made conception of the universe, framed for the explanation or physical, or at most of biological phenomena. If the entire visible universe has been evolved under a process of necessary causation, mind and conscience, it is assumed, must also be subject to the same laws and governed by the same necessities. Hence the great ethical problem is to trace the genesis of our moral notions. If they are the accidental products of a blindly-moving fate, called the "Unknown and Unknowable,'' the Evolutionist has only to examine into their origin without in any way testing their validity. And the general result of the ethics of evolution is that ''experiences of utility organized and consolidated through all past generations of the human race have been producing corresponding nervous modifications, which, by continued transmission and accumulation have become in us certain faculties of moral intuition — certain emotions responding to right and wrong conduct."* This surely * Data nf E! hies, p. 123. Ethics of Evolution. 87 ig as they advantage. !j the State 3 objection defects, is IS elf- with jontent is IS theorier, ' evolution mcer sup- irld ? To it remains, the moral universe, 1 most of iverse has causation, be subject ecessities. le genesis 1 products lown and examine r validity, on is that isoiidated lave been s, which, '6 become emotions his surely is a wonderful attempt at graphic illustration. You see, ' as it were, with the eye of fancy, utilities adhering to the nervous system, gathering themselves about it as about a central germ, till they undergo ultimately a new birth and look out upon you as faculties of moral intuition ! But in the light of reason this whole process reveals itself as illusory. The experiences of utility can only mean experiences of pleasure, and these can neither be organized nor consolidated. A pleasurable feehng has only a transient existence : it is, it is not. It is perish- able, and in the moment of being ceases to be. If experi- ence of pleasures can in any way affect the nervous system, it is only by producing changes in its structure, as the reaction of function on organism. There is no " consolidated and organized " bundle of utilities which is handed from one g aeration to another, till it turns up at last as a system of morality. At most there is but a momentary nervous modification accompanying each experience of pleasure. These modifications may be repeated, but they cannot, properly speaking, be accu- mulated or tra'asmitted. The nervous system, however, may be transmitted, and along with it the effects which have been registered on it by the experiences of pleasur - able feeling. And this is no hypercritical distinction. For Mr. Spencer's language implies that there is some- thing else transmitted than a nervous system, something which is "accumulated" into a faculty of "moral intui- tion." But though the pleasures experienced have produced never so many nervouo modifications, though these, or rather the nervous system to which they belong, have been transmitted through never so many generations, they remain at last simply modifications of a nervous system— nothii;g more. And to identify them with a 88 Kantian Ethics and th %e Is.. r faculty of moral intuition is to leap at a bound from the outer wo/lcl of matter to tho inmost centre of self-con- scious thouglit. Tlie transformation here sketched in outline, however, Mr. Spencer attempts to make clear bj; a four-fold view o£ ethics. The science, he says, has a physical, a biological, a psychological, and a sociological aspect. Is the metamorphosis as thus mediated conceivable? Or, passing from the origin to the validltij of our moral notions, is the science thus established a satisfactory philosophy of our morality ? Making causahty the foundation of his system, Mr. Spencer first of all finds a "basis for morality in the physical order" (p. 59). Snppose, he proceeds, by tying a mam artery we stop m, st of the blood going to a hmb, there follows waste exceeding the repair and, in the end, disablement. This, he assures us, is " part of the physical order," and results "apart from any divine com- mand, or political enactment, or moral intuition." And that is so evident that we are only surprised it should I^ave been thought to need specific mention. But the fact that has not been observed is that the moral judg- ment passed on the act is not based on the physical order. If the limb wer tied by a surgeon for some beneficent end, then ev.n though the present conse- quences-the efeds of the act-are painful, we do not call the act wrong. Contrariwise, if a murderer has adopted this method of taking life he is condemned not because death as effect followed tying the artery as cause, but because he has violated the supreme impera- tive of morality-the law of reverence for mankind Whenever a moral judgment is passed on an act, it will be found to have its ground, elstwhcre than in the causal d from the of self-con- 3, however, old view of biological, Is the )le ? Or, our moral atisfactory 5tem, Mr. ity in the »ceeds, by- going to a md, in the art of the vine com- n." And it should But the oral judg- 5 physical for some nt conse- ve do not derer has uned, not irtery as 3 impera- mankind. ct, it will ihe causal Ethics of Evolution. 89 connexion of the events to which it refers. ^U'. Spencer, however, has another illustration of his thesis. The c^eath consequent on a " cancer of the oesophagus '* that pre- vents swallowing, is as " independent of any theological or political autliority^' as that caused by a want of food brought about by the robbery or the fraud of others.. But this merely amounts to saying that, if a man does not take food, he will certainly die, whether starvation be due to a " cancer of the oesophagus " that prevents swallowing, or to an unmerited poverty that can supply nothing to swallow. So far both cases are alike ; but so far also there is no ethical judgment, and therefore no possibility of a " basis for morality in the physical order.'' When the moral sphere is entered the analogy ceases. In the first case no one is blamed, in the second we condemn the robbers who brought poverty and death on their victim. And were their action as necessary a product of nature as the cancer of the oesophagus, why do we hold them responsible for the effects they have wrought and yet leave the cancer uncensured ? We contend that on Mr. Spencer's theory of a " basis for morality in the phj'sical order," the cancer deserves the same moral reprobation as the robbers ! In other words, the theory by reducing human actions to the dead level of physical causation is utterly incapable of explaining the facts of the moral consciousness. Duty, responsi- bility, and remorse imply a freedom of the will, which is wholly unknown and unjustifiable in the physical order. But Mr. Spencer does not in reality so much attempt to find a basis for morality in the physical system, as to discover analogies between the moral phenomena and tha mechanical conceptions with which he approaches them. Be the foundation of morality what it may, he maintains 90 Kantian 7'Jfhics and the it |«*» IS9l<^ \^*\ r that since tlio process of evolution has been from an "indcHaito, incoherent homogeneity to a definite co- herent hetoroc^'enoity/' moral actions must differ from the actions of the lower animals in general, and from immoral actions in particular, by these characteristics. " Moral principles," he elsewhere observes, " must con- form to physical necessities " (p. 62.). And his affiliation of moral conduct with highly evolved conduct is unintel- ligible without this presupposition. The facts, hotvover, do not bear out the requisites of the hypothesis. For it is obvious that many kinds of immoral conduct are characterized by definitcness and coherence, which Mr. Spencer predicates of moral conduct alone. The mechan- ical hypothesis of evolution may require that all immoral conduct should be indefinite and incoherent, but that is plainly not the case. The thief, acting on his principles, may lead just as coherent and definite a life as the hedon- istic moralist. For example, Mr. Spencer says : " The conscientious man is exact in all his transactions. He supplies a precise weight for a specific sum ; he gives a definite quality in fulfilment of understanding ; he pays the full amount he bargained to do. In times as well as in quantities, his acts answer completely to anticipation, &c." Now all this may be asserted -with equal propriety of certain classes of immoral men. Thus the burglar is exact in all his transactions ; he supplies a precise key for a definite door; ho gives a fixed share to his comrades according to agreement ; he keeps his appointment to the day, to the minute ; and as father — shall he not train his children to this definite and coherent mode of livino- ? In short, the difference between morality and immorality lies much deeper than these superficial and accidental marks. Evil is not made good by becoming definite and coherent Ethics of Evulntl.nn. 91 I from an efiuito co- litfor from and from acteristics. must con- 3 affiliation is uniiitel- , liotvever, is. For it nduct are svliich Mr. e mechan- II immoral but that is principles, :he bedon- a: "The ions. He e gives a ; he pays as well as ticipation, propriety- burglar is •ecise key comrades ent to the i train his ving ? In )rality lies al marks. I coherent nor is right made wrong by the mcrofiat of a mechanical metaphysic, because at times it may be indefinite and incohercmt. It is, however, in the biological view that the peculiarity of Mr. Spencer's ethical system comes more distinctly into prominence. His treatment of pleasures and pains, and of their relation to morality, constitutes the essential moment of this aspect of ethics. Pleasure-giving acts, he argues, are those which increase life ; pain-giving, those which decrease it. This is shown by two consider- ations : first, that originally the act which an animal tends to perform is the pleasure-giving, and, secondly, that each developed creature is kept alive by pursuing the pleasurable and avoiding the painful. This connexion between pleasure-giving acts and life-sustaining acts is sup- posed to supply to morality an ultimate basis. For if the pleasurable be the condition of existence, then morality, which is impossible without life, must be based on that which makes life possible, i.e., on pleasure. Ingenious as the argument must be admitted to be, it is never- theless exposed to serious objections. In the first place, by assigning a reason for the ultimateness of pleasure as an end, it really makes iL only a means to something else, that is, to life. And the question. Why should I live ? requires that a reason be assigned for this end, which also becomes thus a means, and so on ad infinitum. But, secondly, even if this bo passed over, the argument is still untenable. For granting that morality is based on the conditions of sentient existence, it must follow that my morality is based on the laws of my sentient existence. The lowest sentient beings seek their own pleasures and avoid their own pains ; and as " this which holds with the lowest consciousness must hold throughout," it is obvious Isf^iS- 92 Kantian Ethics and the that I am what I am in virtue of having pursued a similar line of conduct. Now as moral conduct is merely "highly evolved conduct," morality must consist alone in seeking by the safest and best and most numerous means my own pleasures and avoiding my own pains. It might be granted that each individual did not seek, and ought not to seek, merely the momentary pleasui'es. As somehow endowed with higher faculties than those of sense, he might compare present pleasures with one another and choo&e the highest of them, or he might even postpone them all for the sake of a future enjoyment. But Mr. Spencer requires no such concession. The theory of pleasures and pains on which the evolution of life has been dependent refers to present pleasures and pains. " Does the action tend to maintenance of complete life for the time being ? And does it tend to prolongation of life to its full extent ? To answer yes or no to either of these questions, is implicitly to class the action as right or wrong in respect of its immediate bearings, whatever it may be in respect of its remote bearings " (p. 77). From these words of Mr. Spencer's it is clear that every- thing must be right which gives either momentary pleasure or the possibility of increased future pleasure. But facts must be our tests for theories ; and -they certainly are not in h rmony with this dictum. The moral consciousness emphatically asserts that adultery is wrong, even though it " tend to maintenance of complete life for the time being," and that forgery is not right even though it " tend to prolongation of life to its full extent." What- ever be the merit of Mr, Spencer's hypothesis as such, it is assuredly no theory of the moral world. He himself has recognized its inadequacy to the facts of the moral consciousness^ but he traces this to anomalies which, in EthicH of EcnliUion. 08 a similar y"hi " tnilitimt " life, niiiii .■^till camos with him noiiih ol' iho old iKljiiHtmcntH, which do not nii»wor tho rociuirumoiitH of Mio "iiuhi.striiil " h'lb into which lio hay como. lint it is apparently for<,'ottcn that this r.n(>r^'cnco is man's own act, (hat ho has created for liimseir a'ik( his past and his present social environment, and that heforo lie is adjiistt>d to lh(> " indnHlrial" lifo (us tho theory reqnires) ho may already have enveloped l-imseU" in a more highly-deV(>ioped tissne of social re- lations. For the soc'al ori^jinism is not, as Mr. Spencer BO inconsistently seoms to anpposo, a lifeless stationary mechanism, hnt a livinj^ and proji^ressivo or^mniam. Were man merely sentient he wcnid bo i.' bject to no otlu>r inflnenco than that of the physical environment, which wonld in timo brini^' him wholly into harmony with ^[r. Spencer's hypothesis, lint )i.s rational and moral ho is not merely law-obeyini*- but also law-giving. It is f/ti's fact that explains tho misadjustments of man's higher natmv to the recpiirements of a hypothesis which is at best valid only for brut(>a. At thin point wo nuist expect remonstrances from tho Evolutionists, lias not M\\ Darwin, they might ask, tmced tho descent of man from the lower animals ? Who dare in this generation speak irrovennitly of the brutes, or even of the matter from which tlu>y have been generated ? If you distinguish man ao antithetically from tho other animals, then "the implication is that tho system of guiilance by pli'asures and pains, which has answered with all types of creatures below the human, fails with tho human" (p. 84). Now this implication I am certainly ready to accept. Nay, apart from it, 1 find tho whole moral world an inexplicable riddle, upor which even the ethics of evolution has not thrown a ray of light. Brute- ■ Filhli'H n( l']i'ttl.ilflon. 05 itill civrrios 'h do not * Hfo into nttt'ii tliiifc 'jvatod for nroniin>nfc, Iriiil" litb onvolo{)(Ml social ro- *. Spoiicor stiitioiinry 111. Wore no otlior mt, which ony with moral ho It is f/iis I's higher lich is at from tlio ight ask, Is? Who brutes, or :>ncrated ? bho other ystem of cred with with tho certainly lio whole even the Bruto- giiidanct* l)y pli'Msur(!s am' pains is prol)a])ly n<«t .sufHc'ont for man, ju.st Ixoause he in mort; than a brute. JJut it is no probli'm of ours to det(»rmim; what *' .ui-iwors " or what "sullices" for human or for other beinj^s. Takiuj^ oiM' stand on imlnbitablo facts, wo have only to ask what are the conditions of their possil)ility. Ami the facta of tho moral world we iind inexplicable if pleasure bo tho end for human b('in<>;s. Mr. Spencer endeavours to strenf^then his position by thrustiu<^ on his opponents a wholly irrelevant problem. " The admission beiiifjf," ho says, "that with nuinkind it [j^uiihince by pler.sures and pains] 8ucce(>ds in so far as fullilment of certain impera- tive wants goes, ,i; fails in respect of wants th'it are not imperative!.* TIioho who think this arc recpiired, in the first place, to show ua how tho limit is to be draw?i between the two ; and then fco show ns why the system which succeeds in tho lov/or will not succeed in tho hiijfher'* (p. 85). Now that we are not obliged to show anything of tho kind will be mjiuifest by a slight survey of the situaticm. The fact is the moi'al world ; the ethics of evolution is the proposed oxphination. It sets out with a biological theory of pleasures and pains in accord- ance with which man does and should seek tho one and avoid the othvr. JJut on examining the actual facts, it perceives that man does not make this the end of his conduct, and that it could bo at most valid only for his sentient nature. Does 'he Evolutionist now recede from tho position he has taken np and confess himself van- quished by tho logic of facts ? Quite the reverse. I grant, he says, that man's higher nature cannot bo brought under my hypothesis, but I believe that in the course of development this disharmony will disappear. * These "wanes tlvat are not imperative" arc, however, accordinf]; to p. 87, those of " tlie higher parts of our nature !"' N- i r 1 ^ 96 Kantian Ethics and the Have you not faith equal to that ? Then you shall explain why a system f guida,nce which " succeeds " in the lower nature will not " succeed " in the higher. But the obvious rejoinder to our Evolutionist is, that you are neither the Creator nor the critic of the Creator's ways ; and have, therefore, nothing- to do with what "succeeds'' and what does not " succeed." You have only to explain what actually exists. Whether guidance by pleasure and pain would succeed or not is a question in which you have not the slightest interest ; you are only certain that it does not " explain " — does not, even on Mr. Spencer's own admission, explain the facts to which he has applied it. Nay, it is because he is obliged to make this con- fession of the inadequacy of his theory that he throws out that other vain problem to his opponents. His theory does not explain the facts, so he turns upon you with the question, Why do not the facts adapt themselves to my theory ? But the biological standpoint, from which everything must be judged right that brings a surplus of present enjoyment, is after all surrendered by Mr. Spencer with the admission ■ iat " in mankind as at present constituted, guidance by proximate pleasures and pains fails thr ugh- out a wide range of cases " (p. 85).' It is important to observe that biology has not made the slightest contribu- tion towards the solution of moral phenomena. We leave it, with Mr. Spencer, in asserting that "special and proximate pleasures and pains must be disregarded out of consideration for remote and diffused pleasures and pains" (p. 85). And with this transition the Ethics of Biology becomes the ordinary egoistic Hedonism, which wo have already found grounds for rejecting as a philosophy of our morality. Ethics of Evolution. 97 lall explain i" in the '. But the it you are or's ways ; succeeds" to explain easure and h. you have dn that it Spencer's las applied this con- throws out lis theory u with the Tea to my verything )f present ncer with instituted, . thr ugh- portant to contribu- We leave )ccial and arded out 3ures and Ethics of ira, which ug as a But the guidance by present pleasures and pains for which Biology so pathetically pleaded as the basis of ethics (how vainly wo have already seen) is excluded by Psychology, which demands " the subjection of immediate sensations to the idea of sensations to come*' (p, 108), and which claims that the fei^lings shall " have authorities pro- portional to the degrees in which they are removed by their complexity and their ideality from simple sensations and appetites " (p. 109). What then, we ask astonished, was the need of listening vo the vain story of Biology at all? Why assert there what is denied here? Mf. Spencer is not insensible to this objection, and forthwith adduces a new ground for his biological treatment of ethics. "The current conception," he says, "is, not that the lower must yield to the higher when the two conflict, but that the lower must be disregarded even when there is no conflict" (p. 111). Without inquiring into the truth of this surprising assertion, we may merely remark that it supplies no raison d'etre for assigning a biological aspect to ethics, from which was deduced the Tightness of what gave momentary pleasure, and the Vfongness of what caused momentary pain, irrespective of "higher" and "lower," of greater and less degree of " ideality" and " complexity," or of any other limitation or qualification whatsoever it be. Passing however at once to the psychological view, we are told that " the essential trait in the moral conscious- ness is the control of some feeling or feelings by some other feeling or feelings" (p. 113). How one feeling controls another is not however explained. That we determine our acts iu relation to feelings and desires, that we compare our motives, and, if we would be moral, act according to the higher, is no doubt quite true. And this might be taken as 7 98 Kantian Ethics and the ■ '•W'l fei the meaning of the above passage, had not Mr. Spencer elsewhere said, the "conscious relinquishment of imme- diate and special good to gain distant and general good • ... is a cardinal trait of the self-restraint called moral" (p. 114). But that this is no part of the self- restraint called moral, Mr. Spencer has been able to hide from himself and others only by using words that suggest a meaning to which he has no right. If we remember that by good he means the pleasurable, and if we make this substitution in the foregoing extract, it will be palpably manifest that it does not furnish any trait, much less the car linal trait, of the self-restraint called moral. The traffic in pleasures doubtless involves self-restraint, but assuredly not of the kind called moral. On the con- trary, it may be highly immoral. Thus, if a thief relin- quish stealing £100 to-day, in order that by to-morrow he may have the increased pleasure of stealing £1000, nobody believes he has manifested " a cardinal trait of the self-restraint called moral." But it is only after Mr. Spencer has in this way emptied morality of all its con- tent, that he attempts from the psychological standpoint a theory of its genesis. Thus his first problem is the " postponement of present to future " good or pleasure, which he is pleased to call the problem of "moral control." Among savages, we are informed, the only restraint to the following of every impulse is mutual fear of vengeance. When some advance in government has been made and the strongest has become chief, this restraint consists merely in the fear of his anger. When he dies, the restraint becomes a dread of his ghost. Social opinion strengthens this feeling, for everbody has the same fear. What then would bo thpi issue of this ? Plainly all for which Mr. Spencer contends. Mr. Spencer nt of imme- eneral good ;raint called of the self- able to hide ;hat suggest Q remember if we make it will be trait, much ailed moral. }lf-restraint, On the con- L thief relin- to-morrow Jing £1000, rial trait of y after Mr. all its con- standpoint t of present ised to call savages, we ig of every me advance ■ongest has I the fear of nos a dread feeling, for iijld be thfi >r contends. Ethics of Evolution. 99 namely, that the individual savago gives up a present pleasure from dread of coming pain. The fear of punish- ment is his permanent motive. But this restraint is not yet moral. Mr. Spencer distinguishes it from the moral in this way, that the one is a restraint due to the "extrinsic eflfocts" of actions, the other to their " intrinsic effects." Moral restraint is founded, that is, on an unchanging physical order, while this primitive restraint of the savage has its origin in a form of society that is necessarily changeable. Now arguing with Mr. Spencer on his own promises — on the assumption that moral restraint has no other meaning than ho allogos — we are bound to maintain that his hypothesis does not explain the origin even of such a restraint. For no transition ia possible from the restraint of the savago to the restraint of the Evolutionist, except on assumptions foreign to the theory. AVhy does the savago, whoso self-control is not yet moral, forego the pleasure of sc ".Iping the comrade with whom he is angry ? Because of the " extrinsic effects" of the action, namely, the chief's vengeance, would bo Mr. Spencer's reply. But why does the moral Evohi- tionist refrain from slaying his enemy even under tlie greatest provocation ? Because of the "intrinsic eCfccts" of the action, namely, the destruction of the possibilities of happiness for tho enemy and, in a certain measure, for his relatives and connections. Now these two cases have not the slightest analogy as regards tho ground of resiiraint, which is the notion to be explained. The savago refrains from destroying lif" from fear of future pain to himself, the Evolutionist from concern for the pleasures and pains of others. The first motive is possible to a merely sensuous nature, tho second presupposes the moral nature we are engaged in deriving. And between tliat stage of 100 Kantian Ethics a/nd the Iv (9"^! tho non-moral and this development of the moral, the hypothesis has not offered the slightest mediation. When Mr. Spencer says, "The truly moral deterrent from murder is not constituted by a representation of hanging as a consequence, or by a representation of tortures in hell as a consequence^ or by a representation of the horror and hatred excited in fellow-men ; but by a representa- tion of tho necessary natural results — the infliction of death-agony on the victim, the destruction of all his possibilities of happiness, the entailed sufferings to his belongings " (p. 120)— when he says all that, I repeat, he forgets that his own account of the genesis of morahty can explain only those deterrents which he here rejects as not moral, aud that it cannot by any possibility be brought into connexion with those deterrents which are here pronounced truly moral. In the selfishness which knows no restraint but that rendered prudent by the "extrinsic effects" there is no immanent dialectic that carries it over into a disinterested restraint constituted by an idea of the " intrinsic effects " of action. Mr. Spencer does, however, assert tliat guidance by extrinsic effects is the necessary antecedent to guidance by intrinsic effects. " Only after political, religious, and social restraints have produced a stable community can there be sufficient experience of the pains .... which crimes of aggiession cause, so as to generate that moral aversion to them constituted by consciousness of their intrinsically evil effects " (p. 122). But does Mr. Spencer mean to say that the intrinsic effects of murder are not aa soon perceived as the extrinsic effects ? That the death- agony of the victim is not, while the dread of punishment is, present to the consciousness of the murderer ? The difference lies not in the priority of perception, but in the Ethics of EvohUion. 101 moral, the tion. When !rrent from of hanging tortures in if the horror representa- infliction of of all his rings to his it, I repeat^ of morality- re rejects as be brought li are here hich knows ! "extrinsic t carries it by an idea uidance by to guidance ligious, and imunity can . . . which that moral ?ss of their ^r. Spencer r are not aa : the death- punishment erer ? The , but in the fact which Mr. Spencer attempts to ignore, and on which his hypothesis shipwrecks, namely, that the one series of effects (the extrinsic) concern the agent, while the other (the intrinsic) in no way affect him. Is it not evident to anyone who will see that the extrinsic eflPects, which are by hypothesis dread of coming pain to me, can never generate aversion — moral or otherwise — to anything that threatens another, or causes another pain or even death ? Thus the pyschological view of ethics presents us with nothing which is not fanciful and absurd as a theory of our morality. It may now be added that it presupposes, even for that, a Society, a Religion, and a State. But as these are nothing else than a realized morality, the ethics of evolution must once more be charged with deriving morality from morality itself. Or more correctly, while professing to deduce morality from pleasures and pains it assumes along with these a social, civil, and religious organism, which can only be described in terms of the morality not yet deduced. If Physics, Biology, and Psychology have failed to supply us with a philosophy of ethics, the case would seem nearly hopeless from the standpoint of evolution. There remains, however, the "sociological view;'' and as Mr. Spencer has warned us that any of his conclusions regarding the correlative aspect of conduct becomes untrue if divorced from the other, it is necessary to follow him in this last stage. Were man not a social being, so begins the " sociolo- gical view," his " system of morality " or the " formula for his activities," would be limited to self and offspring, and would offer no contrast to the formula of other animals. And since there are other species which display " considerable degrees of sociality " it might be expected ■mmmt^iif. 102 Kantian Ethics and the l^ii \S. IV. i*» that we should find a striking likeness between their " morality " and our own. But Mr. Spencer tells us that tnau is the only species which has a *' formula for com- plete life.*' How strange that must appear to those who derive morality from adaptation to the environment — physical^ biological, or social — he does not seem to have perceived. The formula, however, is not discordant with previous results, for though asserting that " the life of the social organism must as an end rank above the lives of its units" (p. 133), yet it is only because the individual happiness, which has all along been the ultimate end, can in this way be the better secured. The duties towards my fellowmen have, therefore, their final ground in the aim to secure for myself the greatest quantum of plea3ure and the least of pain. But such a system makes us a mere collection of mutually repellent atoms that have no affinity with the moral agents to be explained. This insuperable diflficulty for all hedonistic systems — the impossibility of reconciling the universal in morality with the particular in feeling — Mr. Spencer quietly passes over with the dictum, that our present condition is one of transition, and the normal state is one in which all acts of aggression have been banished. In that Utopia "the relations at present familiar to us will be inverted; and instead cf each maintaining his own claims, others will maintain his claims for him" (p. 252). With this hypothesis, framed to obviate objections to the fun- damental assumption of the ethics of evolution, we have surely touched the goal of the new " moral science." If it does not furnish any account of the moral world, it at least prophesies that its present form is only transitional. But, alas, the Arcadia which it discerns is not yet within the ken of ordinary mortals, and its dim margin fades iii Ethics of Evolution. 103 veen their for ever and for ever as we move. And as moralists we ills us that have really nothing to do with that untrodden future. k for com- For the fact is that we have certain moral notions and those who beliefs in the present stage of our development, of which [•onment— we ask for a philosophical explanation. Any theory which 5m to have passes these over in favour of some imaginary reality of rdant with the future, may be ingenious enough, but is assuredly life of the worthless as a philosophy of our actual morality. lives of its And thus the ethics of evolution has little to add to the individual hedonistic systems we had already found grounds for e end, can rejecting. It has, however, laid stress on one important 's towards fact, hitherto much ignored in all moral speculations — on nd in the the gradual development of moral notions, feelings, and )f plea3ure beliefs. But neither that fact itself nor the validity of akes us a the moral conceptions has it in any way philosophically it have no explained. Its principle is directly opposed to the empty ed. This abstraction formulated by Kant, but it is impotent as this 5ms — the to account for the concrete facts of the moral world. Be- morality tween them both lies the idea of humanity as foundation 3r quietly for morality. And in the varying degrees of insight with condition which this idea has been comprehended by diflFerent 9 in which peoples and at different epochs, we shall find an explan- In that ation for the divergence of moral belief and practice, as it js will be has existed, or as it still exists at the present day. vn claims. 2). With ) the fun- , , we have nee/' If THE END. orld, it at insitional. ret within gin fades 1 1 -immimmM^^ ■ t ■•^ Ik* CI VU lur (F. lated f 2 vols, - Vide ' lur (F. his Ep Primit Menzi: - Vide ' sard (B Eeligic 8vo. jard (E cloth. ible for book t( KAAS, ^ Eev. P Testan leek (F. Edited - Vide ' rahmo 1 Churcl 1878, bnning a brief 14, Henrietta Street, Covent Garden, London; 20, South Frederick Street, Edinburgh. CATALOGUE OF SOME WOEKS published by \riLLIAM8 & NOEGATE. lur (F. C.) Cliurch History of the Firfct Three Centuries. Trans- lated from the Third German Edition. Edited by the Eev. Allan Menzies. 2 vols, 8vo. 21«. • Vide Theological Translation Fund Library. lur (F. C.) Paul, the Apostle of Jesus Christ, his Life and "Work, his Epistles and his Doctrine. A Contribution to the Critical History of Primitive Christianity. Edited by E. Zeller. Translated by Rev. Allan Menzies. 2 vols. 8vo, cloth. 2I3. — Vide Theological Translation Fund Library. ard (Eev. Chas.) Port Eoyal, a Contribution to the History of Religion and Literature in France. Cheaper Edition. 2 vols. Cro-wn 8vo. 12«. jard (Eev. Dr. J. E.) The Autobiography of Satan. Crown 8vo, cloth. 7s. 6d. ible for Young People. A Critical, Historical, and Moral Hand- book to the Old and New Testaments. By Dr. H. Oort and Dr. J. Hooy- KAAS, with the assistance of Dr. Kuenen. Translated from the Dutch by the Eev. P. H. Wicksteed. Vols. I. to IV., Old Testament, 19s. ; V. VL, New Testament, 12s, Maps. 6 vols. Crown 8vo, cloth. 31s. eek (F.) Lectures on the Apocalypse. Edited by T. Hossbach. Edited by the Eev. Dr. S. Davidson. 8vo, cloth. 10s. 6d. — Vide Theological Translation Fund Library. •ahmo Year-Book, Brief Eecords of Work and Life in the Theistic Churches of India. Edited by S. D. Collett; for 1876, Is.; 1877, Is.; 1878, Is. 6(i. : 1879, 8yo, Is. 6d ; 1880. la. (yd. bnning's Complete Works, including the " Perfect Life," with a brief Memoir. Centenary Edition. 868 pp. Crown 8vo, Is. ; cloth, 2s.. Catalogue of some Works S s, >^ i, ■■>. 51 " i F |»«i Chaniiing and Lucy Aikin. Correspondence of William Eller wald ( Clmnninf,', D.D., and Lucy Aikin, from 1826 to 1842, Edited by Ani of the 2 vols. [— Vide ' Letitia Le Hheton. Crown 8vo, cloth. (pub. at 9».) ; Cliilow (W. B.) Sunshine and Shadows; or. Sketches of Though Philosophic unci Koligious. I?y William Benton Clulow. New Editio revised and enlarged. 8vo, cloth. 7.";. 6 Cobbe (Miss ?. P.) The Hopes of the Iluman Race, Hereafter ar Here. Essays on the liifj after Death. "With a Preface having spcci reference to Mr. Mill's Essay on Religion. Second Edition. Crown 8 cloth. Cobbe (Miss F. P.) Essays. Darwinism in Morals, and (13) oth( E.;s.iy8 (Religion in Childhood, Unconscious Cerebration, Dreams, the Dev Auricular Confesaion. ^c. &c.). 400 pp. 8vo, cloth. (pub. at 10s.) Cobbe (Miss F. P.) Broken Lights. An Inquiry into the Presoi Condition and Future Prospects of Religious Faith. Third JlLdilion. Crov 8vo, cloth. Cobbe (Miss F. P.) Dawning Lights. An Inquiry concerning tl Secular Results of the Now Reformation. 8vo, cloth Cobbe (Miss F. P.) Alone to the Alone. Prayers for Theists, I several Contributors. Third Edition. Crown 8vo, cloth, gilt edges, Cobbe (Miss F. F.) The Duties of Women. A Course of Lecturjigginso delivered in Loudon A Clifton. Crown 8vo, cloth. I ^nd tl Cobbe (Miss F. P.) Eoligious Duty. 8vo, cloth, (pub. at Is. Qd.) 5 Cobbe (Miss F. P.) Studies, New and Old, of Ethical and Soci Subjects. 8vo, cloth. (pub. at 10s. M.) I Cobbe (Miss F. P.) Ee-Echoes. Crown Svo. 7*. 6 Davids (T. W. Rhys) Lectures on the Origin and Growth of Eel gion, as illustrated by Buddhism. Hibbert Lectures, 1881. 8vo, cloth. 10s. 6 Davidson (Eev. Dr.) On a Fresh Ee vision of the English Old Te tament. Crown 8vo, cloth. Echoes of Holy Thoughts : arranged as Private Meditations befoi a First Communion. Second Edition, with a Preface by the Rev. J. Hami TON Thom, of Liverpool. Printed with red lines. Crown 8vo, cloth, 2s, Ewald (Professor H.) Commentary on the Prophets of the Old Tei tament. Translated by the Rev. J. Fred. Smith. Vol. L Yoel, Anic Hozea, and Zakharya ix. — xi. Vol. XL Yesayah, Obadya, Micah. Vol. II Nahum, Sephanya, Habaqquq, Zakharya xil — :av., Yeremya. Vol. I Hezekiel, Y'esaya xl. — Ixvi., with Translation. Vol. V. Haggai, Zakharj Mulaki, Joua, JJaruch, Appendix and Index. Complete in 6 vols. 8v cloth. each 10s. 6 ■■ Vide Theological Translation Fund Library. ould (S, Toledo extant Paulin anson ( Christ! Chief , to and ■ Lettei C. V. ausrath Jesus, with tl C. T. ] — Vide ibbert ] of the cloth. ■orne (. HORNI Andre ones (I pointe — Anth — The ( — A Bo 12 mo, — The i eim's ] with 1 Gernii V. i nappcr Dr. B Published by Williams and Norgate. William EUer wald (Professor 11.) Commentary on the Psalms. (Poetical Books Edited by AnJI of the Old Testament. Part I.) Translated by the liev. E. Johnson, M.A. (pub. at 9».) ^ 2 vols. 8vo, cloth. each 10«. 6t/. ■ Vide Theological Translation Fund Library. ould (S. Baring) Lost and Hostile Gospels. An Accourt of the Toledoth Jesher, two Hebrew Gospels circulating in the Middle Ages, nnd extant Eragiucnts of the (lospols of ths First Three Centuries of Petrine and Pauline Origin. By the Rev. S. Baring Gould, Crown 8vo, cloth. la. 6d. anson (Sir Richard) The Apostle Paul and the Preaching of Christianity in the Primitive Clmrch. By Sir Richard Davis Hanson, Chief Justice of South Australia, Author of "The Jesus of History," " letters to and from Rome," &c. 8vo, cloth. (pub. at I2s.) 7s. Gd. — Letters to and from Rome in the Years A.D. 61, 62 and 63. Translated by C. V. S. Crown 8vo, cloth. 2s. 6d. ausrath. History of the "New Testament Times. The Time of Jesus. By Dr. A. Hauhrath, Professor of Theology, Heidelberg. Translated, with the Author's sanction, from the Second German Edition, by the Revds. C. T. Poynting and P. Quknzeu. 2 vols. 8vo, cloth. 2l3. — Vide Theological Translation Fund Library. ibbert Lectures, vide Davids, Miiller, Eenan, Renouf. igginson (Rev. E.) Ecce Messias ; or, the Hebrew Messianic Hope and the Christian Reality. By Edward Hiqginson, Author of " Tlie Spirit of the Bible," "Astro-Theology," "Six Essays on Inspiration," &c. 8vo, cloth. (pub. at lOi'. 6c?.) 6*. ies of Though ow. New Editi 7s. 3, Hereafter an face having spec ition. Crown 8i , and (13) oth Dreams, the Dev (pub. at 10s.) nto the Prcsoi I'd JSdilion. Ciov r concerning tl for Theists, I gilt edges, urse of Lectur lb. at 7*. Qd.) 5 lical and Soci 75.6 Growth of Eel 8 vo, cloth. 10s. 6 Inglish Old Te f i ^ditations befoi the Rev. J. Hami 8vo, cloth. 2s. 6 . of the Old Te ol. L Yoel, Ani( ,, Micah. Vol. II Bremya. Vol. I Haggai, Zakharj te in 6 vols. 8v each 10s. 6 lub! at 10s. 6d.) I [orne (Rev. W.) Religious Life and Thought. By William ' TT '\r A 1"»,..,,1„,% I/ V n r.-. i V. Q». in "Pill Inci-. nil V 'n tVio TTni v(»rsit.v nf St. HoRNE, M.A., Dundee, Examiner in Pliilosophy in the University of St. Andrews ; Author of " Reason and Revelation." Crown 8vo, cloth. 3s. 6d. ones (Rev. R. Crompton) Psalms and Canticles, selected and pointed for Chanting. 18mo, cloth. Is. 6d — Anthems, with Indexes and References to the Music. 18mo, cloth. Is. 3d. — The Chants and Anthems, together in 1 vol. 2s. Gd. A Book of Prayer in 30 orders of Worship, for Public or Private Devotions. 12mo, cloth. 2s. 6d. — The same with the Chants. 18mo, cloth. 3ft aim's History of Jesus of Nazara, considered in its connection with the National Life of Israel, and Related in detail. Translated from the German by A. Ransom and the Rev. E. M. Geldart, in 6 vols. Vols. I. to V. 8vo, cloth. each 10s. Gd. Vide TheoloOTcal Tr-anslation Fund Library. :napport. The Religion of Israel. Translated from the Dutch of Dr. Knappert, by R. A. Armstrong, B.A. 12mo, cloth. 2*. Gd. ..»*f»i»«if(l¥»*« J "4 r Catalogue of some Works Kuencn (Dr. A.) Tho Religion of Israel to the Fall of the Jewij enan (] State. By Dr. A. Kuknek, ProfesHor of Theology at the University, Leydc Cultui Translated from tho Dutch by A. H. May. 3 vols. 8vo, cloth. ?Aa. 61 '^' Vido Theological Translation Fund Library. Macan (Reg. W.) The Resurrection of Jesus Christ. An Essa «^o^ ( in Thryo Chapters. I'ublishod for tho llibbort Trustees. 8vo, cloth. "'"" Mackay (R. W.) Sketch of the Rise and Progress of Christianit 8vo, cloth. (pub. at 10«. 6rf.) i Martineau (Rev. Dr. James) Religion as Affected by Modern Mut rialism ; and, Modern Materialism : its Attitude towards Theology. A Critici and Defence. 8vo. 2.v. 6 Modern Materialism. Separately. 1a 6 Loss and Gain in Recent Theology. An Address. Svo. Ideal Substitutes for God considered, in an Opening Lecture at Manchest Now College. Svo. "Why Dissent 1 An Address. Svo. Mind : a Quarterly Revie-W- of Psycholog'y and Philosophy. Coi tributions by Mr. Herbert Spencer, Professor Bain, Mr. Henry Sidgwic Mr. Shadworth H. Hodgson, Professor Flint, Mr. James Sully, tho Rev. Jo Venn, tho Editor (Professor Croom Robertson), and others. Vols. I. to \' 1876 to 1881, each 12s. ; cloth, 13s. 6d 12s. per annum, post fri Miiller (Professor Max) Lectures on the Origin and Growth Religion, as illustrated by tho Religions of India. Hibbert Lectures, 187 Svo, cloth. 10s. 6 Peill (Rev. G.) The Three-fold Basis of Universal Restitutio! "^i^^ H Crown Svo, cloth. "* J^ssav The Pentateuch and the Book of Joshua, in the Light of the Scien( pencer gion, 1879. oville ( Song cloth. eville ( dence, muelsc Contr Esq., theQ econd 1 that J Crowi harpe ( being Old! harpe i Text. Jissay DERIC and Moral Sense of our Age. A Complement to all Criticisms of the Tex (By Dr. R. Willis.) 526 pp. Crown Svo, cloth. 6 Pfleiderer (0.) Paulinism. iin Ev^ay towards the History of th Theology of Primitive Christianity. ranslated ly £. Peters, Esq. 2 vol Svo, cloth. 21 Vide Theological Translation Fund Library. Protestant Commentary, A Short, on the New Testament, vit Introductions. From the German of Hilgenfeld, Holtzmann, Lang, Pfleidcre Lir sins, and others. Translated by the Itev. F. II. Jones, of Oldham. 2 vrl Vol. L Svo, cloth. 10s. 6( Vide Theological Translation Fund Library. First Princ Princ Princ Cerci The J pencer the]^ ■ Essa — Essa ;11 of tho 3ev,ii Dnan (E.) On the Influence of the Institutions, Thought and University, Ltjycl , cloth. 31«. I Culture of Rome on Christianity, and the Devolopmont of the Catholic Church. By Ehnkbt Rbnan, Membro do I'lnstituto. Translated by the Rev. Charles Bkard, of Liverpool, llibbort Lectures, 1880. 8vo, cloth. lOi. 6d. rist An Ess J^^io^ (P« ^^ I*ago) Lectures on the Origin and Growth of Eeli 8vo, cloth. ) of Christianit [pub. at 10«. Gd.) « ly Modern Mat heology. A Critiq 2.V. 6 1a 6 cture at Manchoi^ lilosophy. Coi r. Henry Sidgwic 5ully, tho Rev. Jo irs. Vols. I. to \' )er annum, post fri and Growth bert Lectures, 187 10s rsal Eestitutio Published by Williams and Norgate. gion, as illustrated by tho Religion of Ancient Egypt. 1879. 8vo, cloth. ilibbert Lectures, 10». 6(/. oville (Eov. Dr. A.) The Song of Songs, commonly called the Song of Solomon, or the Canticle. Translated from tho French. Crown 8vo, cloth. M. eville (Rev. Dr. A.) The Devil : his Origin, Greatness, and Deca- dence. Translated from the French. Second Eilition. 12mo, cloth. 2». imuelson (Jas.) Views of the Deity, Traditional and Scientific; a Contribution to tho Study of Theological Science. By James Samuelson, Esq., of the Middle Temple, Barrister-at-law, Founder and former Editor of the Quarterly Journal of Science. Crown 8vo, cloth. 4s. 6J. econd Adam, The, the Seed of the Woman. A Thesis maintaining that Jesus, the Only-begotten of the Father, is very Man, a Human Person. Crown 8vo, cloth. "*• harpe (S.) Bible. The Holy Bible, translated by Samuel Sharpe, being a Revision of the Authorized English Version. Fourth Edition of the Old Testament ; Eighth Edition of the New Testament. 8vo, roan. 4s. 6d harpe (S.) The New Testament. Translated from Griesbach's Text. 14th Thousand, fcap. 8vo, cloth. Is. Gd. mith (Eev. J. Fred.) Studies in Eeligion under German Masters. Essays on Herder, Gosthe, Leasing, Franck and Lang. By the Rev. J. Fre- derick Smith, of Chesterfield. Crown 8vo, cloth. 5«. it of the Scien( pencer (Herbert) Works. The Doctrine of Evolution. 8vo, cloth, iticisms of the Te J ^xx^^ Principles, Fourth Edition. 16«. Principles of Biology. 2 vols. Principles of Psychology. Fourth Thousand. 2 vols. Principles of Sociology. Vol. L Ceremonial Institutions. Principles of Sociology. Vol. IL Part i. The Data of Ethics. Principles of Morality. Fourth Thousand. Part i, ipencer (Herbert) The Study of Sociology. Library Edition (being the Ninth), with a Postscript. 8vo, cloth. 10s. Gd. 6 e History of th ETERS, Esq. 2 vol 21 lestament, vit lOs. 6 16