IMAGE EVALUATION 
 TEST TARGET (MT-3) 
 
 1.0 
 
 I.I 
 
 Jf IB IIM 
 
 ij m 112.2 
 
 1^ 
 
 12.0 
 
 1.8 
 
 
 1.25 1.4 1.6 
 
 
 ■« 6" 
 
 ► 
 
 V 
 
 a 
 
 <% 
 
 
 Photographic 
 
 Sciences 
 
 Corporation 
 
 23 WEST MAIN STREET 
 
 WEBSTER, N.Y. 14580 
 
 (716) 872-4503 
 
 #> 
 
 V 
 
 v 
 
 ^^ 
 
 
 o 
 
 ^9) 
 
 V 
 
 
 ci^ 
 
 '<^ 
 
 -%"■ 
 
^y^- 
 
 ^4?^ 
 
 t 
 
 § 
 
 /i 
 
 CIHM/ICMH 
 
 Microfiche 
 
 Series. 
 
 CIHIVI/ICMH 
 Collection de 
 microfiches. 
 
 Canadian Institute for Historical Microreproductions / Institut Canadian de microreproductions historiques 
 
 \ 
 
 % 
 
Technical and Bibliographic Notes/Notes techniques et bibliographiques 
 
 The Institute has attemp'<:ed to obtain the best 
 original copy available for filming. Features of this 
 copy which may be bibliographically unique, 
 which may alter any of the images in the 
 reproduction, or which may significantly change 
 the usual method of filming, are checked below. 
 
 Coloured covers/ 
 Couverture de couleur 
 
 Covers damaged/ 
 Couverture endommag^e 
 
 D 
 
 D 
 D 
 D 
 D 
 D 
 
 n 
 
 D 
 
 Covers restored and/or laminated/ 
 Couverture res;itaur6e et/ou pellicul^e 
 
 I I Cover title missing/ 
 
 Le titre de couverture manque 
 
 Coloured maps/ 
 
 Cartes g6ographiques en couleur 
 
 Coloured ink (i.e. other than blue or black)/ 
 Encre de couleur (i.e. autre que bleue ou noire) 
 
 Coloured plates and/or illustrations/ 
 Planches et/ou illustrations en couleur 
 
 Bound with other matei^al/ 
 Reli6 avec d'autres documents 
 
 Tight binding may cause shadows or distortion 
 along interior margin/ 
 
 La re liure serr^e peut causer de I'ombre ou de la 
 distortion le long de la marge intdrieure 
 
 Blank leaves added during restoration may 
 appear within the text. Whenever possible, these 
 have been omitted from filming/ 
 II se peut que certaines pages blanches ajout6es 
 lors d'une restauration apparaissent dans le texte. 
 mair., lorsque cela dtait possible, ces pages n'ont 
 oas 6t6 filmdes. 
 
 Additional comments:/ 
 Commentaires suppldmentaires; 
 
 L'Institut a microfilm^ le meilleur exemplaire 
 qu'il lui a M possible de se procurer. Les details 
 de cet exemplaire qui sont peut-dtre uniques du 
 point de vue bibliographique, qui peuvent modifier 
 une image reproduite, ou qui peuvent exiger une 
 modification dans la m^thode normale de filmage 
 sont indiqu6s ci-dessous. 
 
 □ Coloured pages/ 
 Pages de couleur 
 
 □ Pages damaged/ 
 Pages endommagdes 
 
 □ Pages restored and/or laminated/ 
 Pages restaurdes et/ou pellicul^es 
 
 I I Pages discoloured, stained or foxed/ 
 
 s/ 
 
 n 
 
 This item is filmed at the reduction ratio checked below/ 
 
 Ce document est film6 au taux de reduction indiqui ci-dessous. 
 
 Pages d6color6es. tachetdes ou piqu6es 
 
 Pages detached/ 
 Pages d^tachdes 
 
 Showthrough/ 
 Transparence 
 
 I I Quality of print varies/ 
 
 Qualitd inigale de {'impression 
 
 Includes s>.'pplementary material/ 
 Comprend du materiel suppldmentaire 
 
 Only edition available/ 
 Seule Edition disponible 
 
 Pages wholly or partially obscured by errata 
 slips, tissues, etc., have been refitmed to 
 ensure the best possible image/ 
 Les pages totalement ou partiellement 
 obscurcies par un feuillet d'errata, une pelure, 
 etc., ont 6t4 film^es d nouveau de fapon d 
 obtenir la meilleure image possible. 
 
 10X 
 
 
 
 
 l^X 
 
 
 
 
 18X 
 
 
 
 
 22X 
 
 
 
 
 26X 
 
 
 
 
 30X 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 V 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 12X 
 
 
 
 
 16X 
 
 
 
 
 20X 
 
 
 
 
 24X 
 
 
 
 
 28X 
 
 
 
 
 32X 
 
 
The copy filmed here has been reproduced thanks 
 to the generosity of: 
 
 Metropolitan Toronto Library 
 Social Sciences Department 
 
 L'exemplaire film6 fut reproduit grdce d la 
 g6n6rosit6 de: 
 
 Metropolitan Toronto Library 
 Social Sciences Department 
 
 The images appearing here are the best quality 
 possible considering the condition and legibility 
 of the original copy and in keeping with the 
 filming contract specifications. 
 
 Original copies in printed paper covers are filmed 
 beginning with the front cover and ending on 
 the last page with a printed or illustrated impres- 
 sion, or the back cover when appropriate. All 
 other original copies are filmed beginning on the 
 first page with a printed or illustrated impres- 
 sion, and ending on the last page with a printed 
 or illustrated impression. 
 
 The last recorded frame on each microfiche 
 shall contain the symbol — ► (meaning "CON- 
 TINUED"), or the symbol V (meaning "END"), 
 whichever applies. 
 
 Les images suivantes ont 6t6 reproduites avec le 
 plus grand soin, compte tenu de la condition at 
 de la nettetd de l'exemplaire filmd, et en 
 conformity avec les conditions du contrat de 
 filmage. 
 
 Les exemplaires originaux dont la couverture ei> 
 papier est imprim6e sont fiimds en commenga.it 
 par le premier plat et en terminant soit par la 
 dernidre page qui comporte una empreirte 
 d'impression ou d'illustration, soit par ie second 
 plat, salon le cas. Tous les autres exemplaires 
 originaux sont fiimds en commengant par la 
 premidre page qui comporte une empreir^te 
 d'impressicn ou d'illustration et en terminant par 
 la dernidre page qui comporte une telle 
 empreinte. 
 
 Un des symboles suivants apparaitra sur la 
 dernidre image de cheque microfiche, selon le 
 cas: le symbole -^ signifie "A SUIVRE ", le 
 symbole V signifie "FIN ". 
 
 IVIaps, plates, charts, etc., may be filmed at 
 different reduction ratios. Those too large to be 
 entirely included in one exposure are filmed 
 beginning in the upper left hand corner, left to 
 right and top to bottom, as many frames as 
 required. The following diagrams illustrate the 
 method: 
 
 Les cartes, planches, tableaux, etc., peuvent dtre 
 film6s d des taux de reduction diff^rents. 
 Lorsque le document est trop grand pour dtre 
 reproduit en un seul clich§, il est filmd d partir 
 de Tangle supdrieur gauche, de gauche d droite, 
 et de haut en bas, en prenant le nombre 
 d'images ndcessaire. Les diagrammes suivants 
 iliustrent la mdthode. 
 
 1 2 3 
 
 1 
 
 2 
 
 3 
 
 4 
 
 5 
 
 6 
 
.- ,.r-.. i»-« 
 
 McGILL UNIVERSITY 
 
 PAPERS FROM THE DEPARTMENT 
 
 OP 
 
 Philosophy. 
 
 No. 4. — Rousseau : His Position in the History 
 OF Philosophy. 
 
 BY 
 
 J. CLARK MURRAY, LL.D. 
 
 [Reprinted from the Philosophical Review, Vol. viii. No. 4, July, 1899.] 
 
 Montreal, 1899 
 
/ 
 
 
 
 \^^^' 
 
 ROUSSEAU : HIS POSITION IN THE HISTORY 
 OF PHILOSOPHY. 
 
 By J. CtARK Murray, 
 McGill University. 
 
 [Reprinted from the Philosophical Review, Vol. VIII, No. 4. J«'y. ^Sgg.] 
 
 If^ 
 
<^^tf^ ' 
 
 'I'h^* 
 
 M 
 
 f 
 
'4 
 
 ROUSSEAU: HIS POSITION IN THE HISTORY 
 OF PHILOSOPHY. 
 
 THE past few months have enriched English literature with 
 two new books on Jean Jacques Rousseau. One is en- 
 titled Rousseau, and Education according to Nature. It forms a 
 volume in the series of The Great Educators, and its author, 
 Mr. Thomas Davidson, is already well known to the readers of 
 that series by his admirable volume on Aristotle and the Ancient 
 Educational Ideals. The other book is translated from -^ French 
 work by M. Texte, Professor of Comparative Literature in the 
 University of Lyon. It is an interesting fruit of the professional 
 labor of the author. It takes Rousseau as the first French rep- 
 resentative of the cosmopolitan spirit in literature. Its " whole 
 object," as the Introduction explains, " is to exhibit Rousseau as 
 the man who has done the most to create in the French nation 
 both the taste and the need for the literature of the North." 
 These works, dealing each with a somewhat limited aspect of 
 Rousseau's influence, form thus a striking proof of the manifold 
 interest which continues to be felt in the teaching of the great 
 French writer. The secret of this interest is not difficult to find, 
 though it may be variously interpreted. It is needless to say, that 
 the interest does not arise from any peculiar attractiveness in the 
 personality of Rousseau. Indeed, among the great writers of the 
 world, there are few, the records of whose private lives one would 
 more willingly see obliterated ; and in Rousseau's case, fortu- 
 nately for our purpose, they can be left out of view. Rousseau 
 commands interest still as chief literary representative of one of 
 the greatest movements in the history of the world. That move- 
 ment offers many phases for study. Here we shall look mainly 
 at its philosophical aspect, noticing the others merely as they 
 throw light upon it. 
 
 It is an old criticism of the eighteenth century that its life had 
 become encrusted in extremely artificial forms. At all times, 
 indeed, human life tends to outgrow the modes of thought, of 
 
-■*—*. 
 
 B iiW ■iti 
 
 358 
 
 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [Vol. VIII. 
 
 language, of social action, in which it has to find concrete em- 
 bodiment ; and if they do not yield before the requirements of a 
 new order, they come to 
 
 "lie with a weight 
 Heavy as frost, and deep almost as life " 
 
 At no period, and in no country, perhaps in the whole history of 
 the world, did the higher life of man chafe so impatic itly under 
 the restraint of an effete order, as in the France of last century. 
 This antiquated order imposed its irksome regulations upon every 
 sphere of human activity, spiritual and external alike. But 
 social authority especially had extended itself into an infinitude 
 of conventional rules, which narrowed the legitimate sphere of 
 free action, of origination, in the individual, and thereby fettered 
 the evolution of society, of the race. Thus, social regulation in 
 general came to appear, for many thoughtful men of the time, as 
 an artificial restriction, originating in human invention, and having 
 no foundation in any laws which nature herself has imposed upon 
 human life. Aspiration, therefore, took the form of a call to 
 emancipate men from the tyrannous complications, the oppres- 
 sive inequalities, of this artificial state by returning to the primi- 
 tive simplicity and freedom, to the fraternal equality, which must 
 have characterized the state of nature.- Now, it is evident that 
 the whole significance of this call hinges upon the conception of 
 nature by which it is interpreted — a conception which must in- 
 terpret the nature of things in general, but the nature of man in 
 particular. It is not necessary here to discuss the various mean- 
 ings of the word nature. A predominant use of the word is to 
 denote that which is essential — that which makes a thing what 
 it is, and without which it would no longer be the same thing. 
 This meaning appears very early in the Greek fuai^, which came 
 to be commonly rendered in Latin by natura. Even in the 
 
 ' The wide spread of this aspiration among the reading people of the world could 
 not be more significantly indicated than by the extraordinary popularity of Robinson 
 Crusoe. Not only was the novel translated into all the languages of Europe, but, be- 
 fore the century was old, imitations of it in these languages were to be counted by the 
 score. M. Texte has given some account of this f>opularity (pp. 124-128). It is a 
 fact of further significance in this connection, as readers of Entile will remember, 
 that Defoe's story is the only book which Rousseau allows his^pupil to read. 
 
 ifc 
 
 
3S8 
 
 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [Vol. VIII. 
 
 language, of social action, in which it has to find concrete em- 
 bodiment ; and if thoy do not yield before the requirements of a 
 new order, they come to 
 
 " lie with a weight 
 Heavy as frost, and deep almost as life " 
 
 At no period, and in no country, perhaps in the whole history of 
 the world, did the higher life of man chafe so impatic itly under 
 the restraint of an effete order, as in the France of last century. 
 This antiquated order imposed its irksome regulations upon every 
 sphere of human activity, spiritual and external alike. But 
 social authority especially had extended itself into an infinitude 
 of conventional rules, which narrowed the legitimate sphere of 
 free action, of origination, in the individual, and thereby fettered 
 the evolution of society, of the race. Thus, social regulation in 
 general came to appear, for many thoughtful men of the time, as 
 an artificial restriction, originating in human invention, and having 
 no foundation in any laws which nature herself has imposed upon 
 human life. Aspiration, therefore, took the form of a call to 
 emancipate men from the tyrannous complications, the oppres- 
 sive inequalities, of this artificial state by returning to the primi- 
 tive simplicity and freedom, to the fraternal equality, which must 
 have characterized the state of nature.- Now, it is evident that 
 the whole significance of this call Iiinges upon the conception of 
 nature by which it is interpreted — a conception which must in- 
 terpret the nature of things in general, but the nature of man in 
 particular. It is not necessary here to discuss the various mean- 
 ings of the word nature. A predominant use of the word is to 
 denote that which is essential — that which makes a thing what 
 it is, and without which it would no longer be the same thing. 
 This meaning appears very early in the Greek <p6ffi;, which came 
 to be commonly rendered in Latin by tiatura. Even in the 
 
 1 The wide spread of this aspiration among the reading people of the world could 
 not be more significantly indicated than by the extraordinary popularity of Robimon 
 Crttsoe. Not only was the novel translated into all the languages of Europe, but, be- 
 fore the century was old, imitations of it in these languages were to be counted by the 
 score. M. Texte has given some account of this popularity (pp. 124-128). It is a 
 fact of further significance in this connection, as readers of Emile will remember, 
 that Defoe's story is the only book which Rousseau allows his^pupil to read. 
 
No. 4.] 
 
 ROUSSEAU, 
 
 359 
 
 Odyssey, tfoatz is used to denote the peculiar power (xftdro^) of 
 the mythical herb wo/y, by which Ulysses was instructed to 
 neutralize the enchantment of Circe. This early use determined ' 
 its later meaning as a philosophical term. Philosophy in fact be- 
 came an endeavor to find out the essential element which makes 
 things what they are, and therefore ancient critics commonly 
 described early philosophical treatises by the conventional title 
 
 But this . jrm of philosophical inquiry soon became ambiguous. 
 The ambiguity appeared in the word (i-px^jt which is said to have 
 been applied first by Anaxagoras to denote the primitive sub- 
 stance which forms the essential nature of all things. This word, 
 like its Latin equivalent principium, and in general all words de- 
 noting priority or primacy, may be applied to what is first in 
 rank, as well as to what is first in time. Generally and logically, 
 empiricism considers merely the order in time. On its interpre- 
 tation, all inquiry into the nature of things becomes simply an at- 
 tempt to discover their primitive form. In the sciences of human 
 life, the direction of such an inquiry is obvious. Reason, not 
 being, obtrusively at least, a primitive factor of human action, 
 cannot be regarded as an essential constituent of human nature. 
 Even sensibility must be described, from its appearance in the 
 embryo, as being naturally and essentially of a very rudimentary 
 type. In short, the tendency in mental life will be to eliminate 
 all that differentiates the intelligence of man from that of the 
 higher animals, in bodily life, to eliminate all that differentiates his 
 organism from the lowest forms of organic matter. , 
 
 But philosophical interest gathers specially about the spheres 
 of mental, moral, and social life, both separately and in their 
 relation to one another. This interest is connected with the di- 
 vergence of views represented by the twofold meaning of d.pfnij. 
 The divergence has received '< familiar expression in the great 
 conflict which has divided the history of religious speculation in 
 the Christian church, the conflict between the Pelagian and the 
 Augustinian theories of human nature. But, though accentuated 
 in Christian thought, the divergence seems almost to represent 
 an inevitable antinomy of reflection on the subject, and hadi 
 
3^ 
 
 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIFAV. [Vol. VIII. 
 
 therefore made its appearance in Pagan thought long before. 
 Among Pagan thinkers, probably the Pelagian view predominated, 
 especially after the rise of Stoicism. ICven the Flpicurcins are 
 not unfamiliar with this view ; and a mind like Cicero's, with no 
 great power of origination, but with great receptivity for the 
 thoughts of others, seems to vacillate between the two views, 
 drawn alternately, to both. Like a true Pelagian, he contends 
 that, though external prosperity is a matter which God alone can 
 regulate, " virtutcm autem nemo unquam acceptam adco retulit.'" 
 Yet in the very same treatise he had before fallen into the Au- 
 gustinian view, that "nemo vir magitus sine aliquo afflatu divino 
 unquam fuit."* 
 
 The problem involved in this antinomy is the relation of mind^ 
 morals, religion, society, to man's nature. The first clear sight 
 of this problem dates from the great intellectual ferment in 
 Athens during the fifty years that followed the victory of Salamis. 
 One of the first results of reflection at that peri'^d was the scep- 
 tical conclusion of the Sophists with regard religion and 
 morality. Their attitude on religion denied the power of man to 
 discover anything about the gods ; their ethics maintained that 
 the moral law has its source, not in nature, but merely in the 
 customs and enactments of society. On the other hand, the in- 
 fluence of Socrates seems to have been decidedly opposed to this 
 view, and that is the interpretation put upon his teaching by his 
 greatest disciples, Xenophon and Plato. But he did not carry 
 all his followers with him in this direction. The teaching of 
 Aristippus and the Cyrenaics often outdid that of the Sophists in 
 undermining all natural foundation for the moral and religious 
 life of the world ; and even the Cynics, notwithstanding their 
 exaltation of self-denial, took at times such a narrow view of na- 
 ture as to degrade into meaningless artificialities even those regu- 
 lations of animal need, which are most indispensable in the in- 
 terests of moral refinement. 
 
 Socratic teaching, however, had been anticipated in the great 
 
 ^ De Nat. Dear., Ill, 36. Harnack, 1 see, remarks that these words might serve 
 for a motto to Pelagianism [Lehrbuch der Dogmengcschichle, Vol. Ill, p. 156, note 2). 
 
 s Ibid., II, 66. Seneca, with all his Stoicism, is thoroughly Augustinian. " Bonus- 
 ▼ir sine deo nemo est " i^Epist., IV, 12, 2), is a thought to which he often recurs. 
 
No. 4.] 
 
 ROUSSEAL. 
 
 361 
 
 thought of Anaxagoras, that the real dft-jn^ of all things is reason 
 or intelligence. It has been, among ancient as v^ell as among 
 modern critics, a common objection urged against Anaxagoras, 
 that he failed to carry his own theory to its logical issue — that, 
 while in his general conception of nature, things were referred to 
 a rational purpose, yet many particular things were explained by 
 purely mechanical action. Hut it may be questioned how far 
 this criticism is just. The attitude of Anaxagoras may have 
 been merely that of philosophical science. For, while philoso- 
 phy must connect the whole of nature with the purpose of cre- 
 ative intelligence, yet this connection can be indicated only in its 
 general outlines at best, and science would be sure to be led 
 astray, if its prime object were to hunt after the universal thought 
 of the Creator, instead of the particular laws in which that 
 thought is evolved. But, to whatever extent the criticisms of 
 Anaxagoras may be justified, he rendered it impossible to leave 
 reason out of account in the explanation of the universe ; and 
 e\'er since his time the most atheistic materialism has been 
 haunted by the query, whether the processes of nature can find 
 any complete explanation until they are traced to rational pur- 
 posive action. It was this fact, that seemed to Aristotle to im- 
 part such significance to Anaxagoras in the history of speculative 
 thought In fact, the influence of Anaxagoras is strikingly indi- 
 cated in the teaching of Aristotle himself. In his well-known 
 theory of causality, Aristotle makes the end to which things 
 are adapted an essential principle of their explanation ; so that 
 the nature of a thing, according to him, must be sought, not in 
 the rudimentary state out of which it has grown, but rather in 
 the form which it ultimately assumes, the end which that form 
 subserves. 
 
 But the Anaxagorean doctrine found its clearest expression 
 and its fullest application in the philosophy of the Stoics. That 
 doctrine, indeed, may be said to be the central and germinative 
 idea of their whole system. With them, nature and reason came 
 to be identified, and this identi'" .tion held in macrocosm and 
 microcosm alike. They did not shrink, as Anaxagoras was 
 charged with doing, from the attempt to trace rational a^ itation 
 
*). 
 
 362 
 
 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [Vol. VIII. 
 
 in the minutest, as well as in the vastest, productions of nature ; 
 and the courage of their convictions is shown in many an alleged 
 purpose of natural products, which, to modern thought seems a 
 very superficial conceit. As they found reason embodied all 
 through the universe at large, they could not but find it particu- 
 larly in the nature of man. Reason is, in fact, for them the pri- 
 mary and dominant factor of man's nature. On it our very self- 
 hood depends. 7*0 iyio Xkyonzv xuto. tooto, is a statement of 
 Chr^'sippus which has been preserved. 
 
 The divergence of views in reference to human nature, which 
 had thus arisen in Pagan speculation, took a more earnest phase 
 in Christian thought, when it came to be connected with the 
 problems of the religious life. The natural state of man assumed 
 a new interpretation. It came to mean the state into which man 
 falls when he is completely divorced from the divine life. Such 
 a concept of man's nature, it may be urged, is one against which 
 religious thought must always be apt to revolt ; for any devout 
 interpretation of nature obliges us to believe that every creature 
 lives and moves and has being only in God. The concept there- 
 fore of man absolutely severed from the life of God must be a 
 mere fiction of abstract speculation, like the later fiction of a state 
 of nature in which man is conceived as absolutely isolated from 
 society. But in the elaboration of such a fictitious abstraction 
 man is necessarily conceived as by nature wholly void of good- 
 ness, if not even positively averse to it. All genuine goodness comes 
 to be viewed as an unmerited grace of God to man, and a grace 
 to b' won only through the society which He institutes for the 
 purpose. Extra ecclcsiam non esse lioininibus salutem, was a 
 logical conclusion of this dogmatic reasoning ; and we shall see 
 immediately that the later conception of the state of nature led to 
 the denial of the possibility of moral life outside of civil society. 
 The cognate theories fotm thus a speculative foundation for the 
 most appalling absolutism in church and state. 
 
 The Augustinian conception of man's natural state underwent 
 an energetic revival with the rise of modern speculation, cs ncially 
 in the spheres of Christian tliought represented in French liter- 
 ature. In the Calvinism of the Huguenots, equally with the 
 
No. 4.] 
 
 ROUSSEAU. 
 
 363 
 
 i 
 
 Jansenism of the Catholic Church, the teaching of Augustine 
 remained the dominant influence ; and it is importarc to bear in 
 mind, that it was among the Jansenists of Port Royal, that the 
 philosophy of Descartes found its most powerful expositors. 
 
 But u new impulse and a new direction were given to the idea 
 of a state of nature oy Hobbes. This great thinker is indeed oftei. 
 misunderstood. His theory 01 .human nature is represented as if 
 it were an extravagant Augustirianism, interpreted in the light 
 of political science rather than in that of dogmatic theology. It 
 is not a pure negation of the Stoical theory, or a rehabilitation of 
 the theory which had been represented by the Sophists and the 
 Cyrenaics. On the contrary, it is rather a remarkable combi- 
 nation of the two views which had been previously opposed to 
 one another. Instead of regarding social institutions and rational 
 laws for the government of human life as purely artificial creations 
 of human convention, he finds a foundation for them in nature. 
 That foundation, moreover, i? laid both in the reason and in the 
 sensibility of man. The sufficiency of the foundation may, 
 indeed, be questioned, but it is not without a certain solidity of 
 its kind. Its insufficiency is perhaps peculiarly evident in the 
 enumeration of the emotional impulses upon which social life de- 
 pends. " The passions that incline men to peace," he says, " are 
 fear of death ; desire of such things as are necessary for com- 
 modious living ; and a hope by their industry to obtain them." 
 This, so far as I have observed, is all that Hobbes has to say on 
 the subject. But it is perhaps significant, that he finds the chief 
 foundation of social union in the intelligent requirements c Treason, 
 rather than in the blind instincts of sensibility. Those require- 
 ments, demanding social harmony among men, constitute, ac- 
 cording to Hobbes, laws of nature ; and natural law, at least in 
 his earlier work Dc Civc^ is identified wi^-h divine law, and indeed 
 with divine law as expounded in the Scnnon on the Mount. 
 ^ The preceding sketch will enable us to understand more clearly 
 the place of Rousseau in the development of speculation on the 
 problems upon which his influence was most powerful. That influ- 
 
 ' Leviathan, ]). I16 (Molesworth's ed.). 
 
 'Chap. IV. His later translation of the work into English retains this statement. 
 
3^4 
 
 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [Vol. VIII. 
 
 ence ran mainly along the lines of three ideas : The state of nature ; 
 the state of civil society ; and education. 
 
 I. In regard to the state of nature, his hostile critique of 
 Hobbes and Mandeville is apt to create the impression that his 
 view of human nature represents a strong reaction against theirs, 
 and in the direction of the nobler view of the Stoics. But, on 
 more careful examination, his view is seen to be far more com- 
 pletely opposed to the Stoical, and to form in fact a curiously 
 illogical syncretism of irreconcilable doctrines. While his whole 
 philosophy proceeds on the assumption that man is by nature 
 virtuous, and his antagonism to Hobbes and Mandeville arises 
 from the fact that they seem to proceed on an opposite view, he 
 yet describes the natural state of man by characteristics which 
 are incompatible with any intelligent conception of virtue. He 
 recognizes indeed the difficulty of defining this state, as it is one 
 which not only exists no longer, bu.: may never have existed in 
 the past, and may never exist in the future.^ Still he be- 
 lieves it possible, by analytical sti'dy of human nature as it is, to 
 strip off the artificial covering by which its original form is con- 
 cealed ; and though the rhetoric, which gave him his power, does 
 not always contribute to exactness, yet we can detect two features 
 by which he characterizes the original nature of man. 
 
 (l) The first is that man's natural sl^ate must be prior to the 
 evolution of reason. This, it nc d not be said, is the explicit 
 theme of the Discourse on the corruption of men by science ^.nd 
 art ; it underlies also the reasoning of the Discourse on the origin 
 of inequality among me:i. It may not be difficult to show that 
 this conception of man's natural state is modified, if not even 
 contradicted, in later writings of Rousseau ; yet it remained to 
 the last a dominant idea in his teachin-. All that teachincf re- 
 ceives a certain unity of aim, when we bear in mind that Rous- 
 seau looked for the well-being of man, not from the expansion of 
 man's intelligence, not from the growth of science and art, but by 
 getting rid of all that had been won for life by scientific or ar- 
 tistic intelligence, and by returning to th : primitive instincts of an 
 untutored sensibility. 
 
 ' See preface and opening paragraphs of the Discours mr ronj;iite, etc. 
 
 \ 
 
No. 4.] 
 
 ROUSSEAU. 
 
 365 
 
 It is but fair to Rousseau to plead that all paradox may be 
 viewed as but an exaggeration and misinterpretation of a truth. 
 The truth in this case is a protest, partly against the overestimation 
 of a culture that is purely intellectual, partly against the frequent 
 perversion of intelligence to corrupt the moral life in general, but 
 especially in its uncutored innocence. Rousseau's teaching, in all 
 his leading works, perhaps also in the more deliberate actions of 
 his life, may be interpreted as a protest against both of these errors. 
 His protest, indeed, often runs into an extravagance more paradox- 
 ical than the errors against which it was directed. But it is difficult 
 for a fervid writer, like Rousseau, to avoid hyperbole ; and the 
 palpable extravagance of an hyperbole often takes from it its 
 misleading influence. Rousseau himself, in fact, seems at times 
 quite aware of his paradoxical exaggeration. " It would be 
 frightful," he says in the second Discourse, "to be obliged to 
 praise as a beneficent being the man who first suggested to the 
 dweller on the banks of the Orinoco the use of the boards \\ hich 
 he applies to the temples of his children, and which assures to 
 them at least a part of their original imbecility and happiness."^ 
 
 (2) A second feature of man's natural state is, that it is abso- 
 lutely non-social. There is no aspect of this conception of man's 
 nature which brings out so clearly its fictitious character — none 
 which does such rude violence to the most evident facts of obser- 
 vation and experience. The attempt to picture man as by nature 
 a solitary being, simply eliminates all the attributes by which he is 
 most distinctively characterized, and leaves an animal essentially 
 different from man as we know him, not only in mental faculties, 
 but even in bodily organization. Not to dwell on the curious hints 
 about primitive man's physical life, that are scattered throughout 
 the notes to the second Discourse, Rosseau is, of course, obliged 
 to wipe out from man's original nature all his social instincts. He 
 does indeed of necessity, recognize the sexual instinct ; and, in 
 
 ' M. Saint-Marc Girardin gives point to his own critique, but is scarcely fair to 
 Rousseau, when he introduces this quotation not with the author's own words, " II 
 serait aftreux d'etre oblig6 de louer coinme un §tre bienfaisant," etc., but substitutes 
 for them " Eh bien ! quand vous ne pensereiz pas, oil serait le mal ? L' imb6cillit6 
 n'est pas un si grand malheur, et ce fut un Stre bienfaisant," etc. {^Rousseau: Sa 
 vie et ses ottvrages. Vol. I, p. 103). 
 
■^ 
 
 366 
 
 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [Vol. VIII. 
 
 the Contrat aocial at least, he admits the family to be a society 
 formed by nature. But such concessions only bring out more 
 clearly the repulsively individualistic character of his theory of 
 human nature, for the only natural bond he can see in family 
 life is the dependence of child upon parent. With the cessation 
 of that dependence the bond between them is snapped.* The 
 family is thus a purely animal connection ; it implies nothing of 
 the distinctive nature of a human society. In like manner, Rous- 
 seau ignores, even explicitly denies, any spiritual element in the 
 natural attraction of the sexes for each other ; for him, it is simply 
 an animal instinct, not binding to any union beyond the moment 
 of gratification. Was not Nietzsche justified in describing Rous- 
 seau's return to nature as a restoration of man " in /wpuris natu- 
 ralibus"? 
 
 II. From this conception of man's natural state, it is a neces- 
 sary inference that the social state is wholly artificial. The origin 
 o^^ch an artificial condition becomes very difficult for Rous- 
 seau to explain. Hobbes, as we have seen, recognized three 
 "passions that incline men to peace," and therefore to social 
 union ; and such union, he maintained, is also suggested by the 
 natural dictates of reason. But Rousseau was apparently unable 
 to find any such basis for society in man's nature. He does in- 
 deed recognize two human instincts " anterior to reason." ^ One 
 of these is simply the instinct of self-conser\'ation ; but the other,, 
 namely, sympathy or pity, is essentially social. It is worth not- 
 ing, moreover, that Rousseau does not follow Hobbes in his 
 purely egoistic theory of natural feelings. In his view, pity is 
 not merely " grief for the calamity of another, arising from the 
 imagination that the like calamity may befall oneself" ' It is a 
 bit of genuine altruism in human nature. But none the less does 
 it fail to afford any ground for the formation of society. Accord- 
 ingly, he is driven to that a priori method, so common among 
 the social philosophers of last century — the method of ' spinning 
 out of their own consciousness ' the history of the origin of so- 
 
 ' Control social, Liv. I, chap. 2. 
 '^ Preface to the second Discourse. 
 " Hobbes' s Leviathan, p. 47. 
 
.No. 4,] 
 
 ROUSSEAL. 
 
 1^7 
 
 ciety. Rousseau's writings contain typical illustrations of this 
 method. There is, in fact, something delicious in the ndivctc with 
 which, in the second Discourse, he sums up an hypothetical 
 sketch : " Tel fut ou diit ctrc I'origine de la societe." 
 
 It has often been pointed out that the Contrat social mitigates 
 to some extent the harshness of the two discourses, by tracing the 
 corruptions of natural innocence to the artificial influence of life 
 in society. But the later work makes no mitigation of the earlier 
 theory, which holds man to be by nature non-social. Indeed, this 
 theory is obtruded, perhaps more bluntly than ever before, in 
 some parts of the Contrat social. Take, for example, the chap- 
 ter on the function of legislators in the second book. There, it 
 is said, that " he, who ventures to undertake the establishment of 
 a nation, ought to feel himself in the condition of changing, so to 
 speak, human nature, of transforming each individual, who is by 
 himself a perfect and isolated whole, into a part of a larger whole, 
 from which the individual receives in some sort his life and be- 
 ing ;" and so on in the same line of thought. 
 
 With this view of human nature, Rousseau had no alternative 
 but to trace the foundation of society to an arbitrary convention. 
 In this conclusion, we may recognize specially the influence of 
 Hobbes. The idea of a pact or covenant, indeed, was, in the 
 seventeenth century, a prominent category of thought in the ex- 
 position of moral and religious obligations. The celebrated work 
 of Witsius, Dc Occonojuia Foedcrum Dei cum Hominibiis (1677), 
 not only went through numerous editions and translations, but 
 created a vast literature, representing a peculiar system of religious 
 ideas, which has come to be known by the name of Federal Theol- 
 ogy. This system seems to have found wide acceptance, especially 
 in the Calvinistic sections of the Protestant church ; ' and it is 
 not impossible that Rousseau in his youth may have been 
 familiar with its exposition by the Swiss preachers. But proba- 
 bly Hobbes was the most potent influence in giving this direction 
 to Rousseau's speculations. Yet it must be remembered that 
 there is an important difference between the two theories. For, 
 
 ' May not the national covenants in England and Scotland have been due partly 
 to the familiarity of the Calvinistic mind with this system of thought ? 
 
^i 
 
 368 
 
 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. [Vol. VIII. 
 
 as we have seen, Hobbes finds a basis for social union both in 
 the natural impulses of passion, and in the natural dictates of rea- 
 son. The social contract is, therefore, for him simply the formal 
 enactment of natural law — the enactment necessary to give that 
 law practical force. For Rousseau, on the other hand, society is 
 based on a pure convention, which involves a more or less vio- 
 lent transformation of man's original nature. 
 
 There is one point, however, in which Rousseau follows 
 Hobbes. For both, the social compact involves a complete surren- 
 der of the individual to society, and the tyranny of social rule is 
 none the less exacting on account of the democracy which Rous- 
 seau advocates. In fact, it is a tyranny all the more insidious 
 that it puts on a show of reasonable self-government. It is the 
 people as a whole who appear simply to constrain the people as 
 individuals. It is forgotten that the people as a whole are, in 
 almost every case, merely a majority — in many cases, merely a 
 majority of the actual voters, overriding not only the minority, 
 but a vaster majority, who either do not care to vote at all, or 
 are disqualified from voting by being women or minors. 
 
 III. The absolutism, thus claimed for the State, cannot but 
 appear in strange conflict with Rousseau's theory of education, 
 through which his influence has been, perhaps, more powerful and 
 more beneficial than through any other part of his teaching. The 
 corruption of human life, as we have seen, he traces to the artificial 
 restraint imposed on its natural freedom by social organization, 
 on the one hand, and by intellectual culture, on the other. His 
 theory of education therefore proceeds on the assumption that, if the 
 artificial fetters of society and of civilization are once broken, and 
 the original nature of man allowed free play, it will develop a life 
 of unsophisticated innocence. The logical issue of such an educa- 
 tional theory would be the abrogation of all restrictive govern- 
 ment of human life. Anarchism rather than despotism is the po- 
 litical doctrine it involves. 
 
 This contradiction points to some defect in the theory of edu- 
 cation, which leaves no ground for governmental control of 
 human life. The defect in educational theory arises from defects, 
 which have been already pointed out, in the theory of man's es- 
 
No. 4.] 
 
 ROUSSEAU. 
 
 369 
 
 sential nature. This theory, it will be remembered, not only 
 degrades intelligence from the rank of ro jj^-s/ww/ov — the power 
 which by nature has the right to rule in man, but treats intelli- 
 gence as if it were an artificial and corrupting growth. As vo- 
 lition is properly intelligent action, will is thus eliminated from 
 man's original nature too. The only element left is, therefore, 
 sensibility, and even this is so narrowed as to exclude all those 
 affections which bind men instinctively to one another, and lead 
 them instinctively to seek their individual good by concerted ac- 
 tion. The ideal end of human life is, by such a theory, lowered 
 to that of the crudest hedonism. To dally with agreeable feel- 
 ing, to avoid everything that might mar such dalliance — that is 
 the Sovereign Good for Rousseau. It is not necessary here to 
 illustrate '\i\ detail the pedagogical methods proposed by Rous- 
 seau for the attainment of this ideal. The monograph of Mr. 
 Davidson gives an elaborate analysis of these, which will be 
 found extremely helpful for the student of educational theory. 
 
 There is one fact which may be noticed in this connection as 
 perhaps likely to brin • into clearer view the distinctive defect of 
 Rousseau's teaching. In referring to his influence on contempo- 
 rary and subsequent speculation, it is common to point to the ex- 
 traordinary fascination which he exercised over Kant.^ I call 
 this extraordinary, because it would be difficult to point to two 
 men who exhibit a more striking contrast in per3onal character, in 
 modes of thought, and in style of literary expression. I shall not 
 attempt to unriddle the mystery of this fascination. But it may be 
 be said that the movement inaugurated by Kant was in a certain 
 sense, like Rousseau's, a return to nature. To penetrate beyond 
 the adventitious accretions of human thought, the conventional 
 customs of human action ; to reach the original facts of human 
 nature out of which these have grown ; — that was the aim of Kant 
 as well as of Rousseau. 
 
 Eut it seems to me simply of infinite significance, that in 
 Kant's mind the vague endeavor to return to nature translated 
 
 ' It seems to have been specially Rousseau's educational theory that interested 
 Kant. It was Entile, not, as Mr. Davidson (p. 224) supposes, La nouvelle HiloUe, 
 that induced Kant to give up his daily walk. See K. Fischer's Geschichte der neuerett 
 Philosophic, Vol. Ill, p. 220. 
 
370 
 
 THE PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW. 
 
 \\ 
 
 itself into a critique of pure reason. It cannot be denied that, in 
 ethical theory at least, this led Kant into an extreme Stoicisni, 
 which hardly allowed fair play to the emotional nature of man ; 
 but in the interpretation of educational problems it implies a 
 radical difference from Rousseau. At the present day, moreover, 
 when science is applying somewhat loosely the lower conception 
 of organization and organic growth to explain the higher phe- 
 nomena of human life, it is well to be re^ .''nded that neither the 
 individual man nor the community of men is merely an organism, 
 and that, therefore, the true evolution of humanity is directed, 
 not by physical force or animal instinct, but by strenuous efforts 
 of free intelligence towards a higher realization of intelligence 
 and freedom. 
 
 J. Clark Murray. 
 McGiLL University. 
 
 .. ' 
 
 i • 
 
 1*1 
 
 ^- 
 
II 
 
 ^• 
 
 y 
 
 / 
 
 hi