key: cord-1044514-cetngehb authors: Evans, Nicholas G. title: Human Infection Challenge Studies: a Test for the Social Value Criterion of Research Ethics date: 2020-07-15 journal: mSphere DOI: 10.1128/msphere.00669-20 sha: e323d51ebe2fb3e4047f2f8ae91421030841c56b doc_id: 1044514 cord_uid: cetngehb Human infection challenge studies involving the intentional infection of research participants with a disease-causing agent have recently been suggested as a means to speed up the search for a vaccine for the ongoing coronavirus disease 2019 (COVID-19) outbreak. Calls for challenge studies, however, rely on the expected social value of these studies. This value represents more than the simple possibility that a successful study will lead to the rapid development and dissemination of vaccines but also some expectation that this will actually occur. I show how this expectation may not be realistic in the current political moment and offer potential ways to make sure that any challenge trials that arise actually achieve their goals. be global (8) . Recent commentary on challenge studies in the context of COVID-19 has assessed the value of a vaccine for this disease as greater than that of a cure for HIV/AIDS (9) . Even in cases where challenge studies might not be directly testing a promising vaccine candidate, but might be performed to clarify the dynamics of infection or viral pathogenesis, among other important issues, the ultimate referent of the value of this research is a vaccine to end the global pandemic (2) . The magnitude of this benefit, however, will likely not be as great as hoped given the current climate into which challenge studies emerge. This is significant: we know that not all benefits justify challenge studies. In the case of Zika virus disease, initial surveys of the ethics of challenge studies in December 2016 led to the conclusion that a lack of (i) a strong argument that a challenge study would accelerate vaccine development or (ii) an indication that field trials of vaccines would be prohibitively difficult to conduct spoke against pursuing a challenge study at the time (10) . What it suggests is that, if not a minimal benefit, a minimal risk-benefit ratio is needed to justify challenge studies. The bigger problem that arises in the context of COVID-19 is that vaccines are not vaccinations. It is doubtful that anyone is interested in merely possessing a COVID-19 vaccine; the aim is to end the pandemic. Moreover, when discussing cures or vaccines for pandemic diseases, it is not simply that we are interested in the possibility of deploying a vaccine or in vaccinating a very small number of people. We want to have some confidence that this would actually come to pass, at scale, and in the world we live in (11) . Recent writing on challenge studies noted that hurdles to realizing the social value requirement described above often come in two forms. First, candidate vaccines resulting from challenge studies need to make it to the people who need vaccination. Second, communities that may be asked to participate in challenge studies, or that may be disproportionately impacted by decisions (including those arising from challenge i) in vaccine design and distribution, must be engaged (2, 3) . What confidence should we have that we are on the right path to surmounting these challenges as we make the assessment of when, if, or how to pursue challenge studies? Concerning the first hurdle, the situation is not rosy. While alliances exist such as the Coalition for Epidemic Preparedness Innovations (CEPI) and Gavi, the Vaccine Alliance, these are not necessarily equipped for the level of mobilization required for a COVID-19 vaccination campaign (12) . The World Health Organization is attempting to take a leading role in ensuring that challenge studies are feasible and socially valuable, but such efforts may be severely undermined by the United States' current plans to withdraw its membership from the agency (13) . Yet even if it were not to do so, instruments such as the Pandemic Influenza Preparedness framework-arguably the benchmark for ensuring access to vaccines during a disease pandemic-have been criticized for lacking the commitment by states necessary to meet demand (14) , throwing into question the possibility of access to and sharing of a COVID-19 vaccine. The actions of state and substate actors give us reason to fear that the political will to distribute an efficacious vaccine is limited. Internationally, assertions of sovereignty by the United Kingdom and the United States in claiming priority over access to a vaccine have been documented in the course of this pandemic (15) . Domestically in the United States, the situation is likewise perilous. Previous work on challenge studies has suggested the U.S. Government might use the "march-in" provisions of the Bayh-Dole Act (2) , where the funding agency asserts rights to expanded licensing (i.e., beyond that reserved for patent holders) for innovations developed with public funds. Yet in the 40 years since Bayh-Dole was passed, those provisions have never been utilized (16) . It is not impossible that march-in rights might be used during COVID-19, but history speaks strongly against it. Highly inequitable, ultimately ineffective vaccination programs may fail to achieve their goals because of political will rather than scientific roadblocks. The second hurdle may be even more daunting. The United States, in particular but not exclusively, is experiencing a resurgence in conspiracy theories and extremist behavior in the context of COVID-19. These conspiracy theories are often directed against actors who are, for better or worse, leaders in developing and deploying vaccines: conspiracy theories concerning The Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation; the United Nations and World Health Organization; and the U.S. National Institutes of Health are rampant. Some may verge on the unbelievable, such as the conspiracy theory that gain-of-function research conducted on severe acute respiratory syndrome (SARS)-like coronaviruses in 2015 is connected to the emergence of COVID-19 that made it to British tabloids (17) , or the conspiracy that ongoing measures to increase social distancing represent a prologue to forced vaccination campaigns intended to cause global depopulation popular with conspiracy theorists in the United States (18) . But others, even if false in this moment, are grounded in the dark history of the life sciences. The ongoing concern that developing nations are simply treated as laboratories by developed nations to test dangerous drugs is absolutely grounded in the history of exploitative clinical trials not just abroad but in the United States itself. The latter conspiracy theory has made it as far as prominent right-wing commentators in the United States (19) , which arguably means that it is nearing prime-time dissemination. The capacity of these hurdles to derail vaccine efforts should not be underestimated. The last of these was enough to lead a U.S. official to claim that vaccination in the US could fail to contain the virus following a CNN poll that announced that one-third of Americans surveyed would not try to get vaccinated against COVID-19 (20) . Another poll showed 20% of all participants responding "no" to plans to get a COVID-19 vaccine, rising to 40% for Black respondents (21) . This calls the expected actual social value of a challenge study into question. Many of these issues are part of a broader array of challenges facing vaccine development. But some, particularly community engagement challenges, may become ever more acute as the prospect of intentional infection with COVID-19 is advanced. The narrative of intentionally infecting a participant with a disease for the purpose of giving them a vaccine is homologous to existing and widespread conspiracies, some grounded in the long historical injustices visited on vulnerable communities. Because challenge studies require a particularly favorable risk-benefit ratio or even minimal expected social benefit in virtue of the risk they entail, those studies are left in an ethically fraught position. This does not mean, however, that challenge studies are inherently unethical. Severe doubts about the expected social value of challenge studies exist in this moment. One response is to modify the way that we conduct clinical trials. This modification would see vaccine trials approved in concert with access and benefit sharing mechanisms and with the firm commitment of funds to ensure sustainable distribution prior to commencing challenge studies. There is still time to do this, given that many vaccine candidates are in the early stages of development. It also means conceiving of public engagement in the broadest possible terms and engaging communities early and on their own terms. This would require mobilization of resources to engage the many thousands of local communities that might be affected either by inequities in vaccine distribution or by both real and fantastical fears about challenge studies and vaccines. This engagement is not merely for education but also to determine and respond to the needs of those communities, ideally with their participation. Governments could do this, but given that antivaccination sentiment can often be derived from broader distrust of government and industry (22) , other stakeholders may need to engage communities directly. This is no small challenge-it conceivably represents a bigger challenge than the technical task of finding a vaccine. But in order to justify the demand for resources and the risk of challenge studies, it is necessary. Without it, the social benefit of the rapid search for a COVID-19 vaccine will remain unrealized. Human challenge studies to accelerate coronavirus vaccine licensure Ethics of controlled human infection to address COVID-19 COVID-19 human challenge studies: ethical issues The ethical challenge of infection-inducing challenge experiments A view from the common cold unit The time course of the immune response to experimental coronavirus infection of man Intranasal interferon as protection against experimental respiratory coronavirus infection in volunteers When could human challenge trials be deployed to combat emerging infectious diseases? Lessons from the case of a Zika virus human challenge trial AIDS activism and coronavirus vaccine challenge trials Ethical considerations for Zika virus human challenge trials The social value of candidate HIV cures: actualism versus possibilism Developing Covid-19 vaccines at pandemic speed Trump administration sends letter withdrawing U.S. from World Health Organization over coronavirus response The pandemic influenza preparedness framework: a viable procurement option for developing states? AstraZeneca Covid-19 deal reinforces 'vaccine sovereignty March-in rights under the Bayh-Dole Act 17 Coronavirus study identifies 'gain of function for efficient spread in humans Get ready for the vaccine infowar Experimenting on and incidentally paralyzing and infertilizing poor colored children in Africa and India is as dangerous as it sounds. You and @WHO got around FDA vaccine regulations by traveling to third world countries and offering "philanthropy". You are both absolute scum Fauci says Covid-19 vaccine may not get US to herd immunity if too many people refuse to get it Just 50% of Americans plan to get a COVID-19 vaccine. Here's how to win over the rest Public health law and institutional vaccine skepticism N.G.E. receives funding from the NSF (no. 1734521) and the Greenwall Foundation. Thanks to Anna Muldoon for assistance with some sources and for comments on a previous draft of this paper.