key: cord-0902107-iddugo01 authors: Schou, Alexandra; Mølgaard, Jesper; Andersen, Lars Willy; Holm, Søren; Sørensen, Marc title: Ethics in extracorporeal life support: a narrative review date: 2021-07-21 journal: Crit Care DOI: 10.1186/s13054-021-03689-0 sha: fab35d4d932b6926fab9cf20507d822f03d3cfc4 doc_id: 902107 cord_uid: iddugo01 During 50 years of extracorporeal life support (ECLS), this highly invasive technology has left a considerable imprint on modern medicine, and it still confronts researchers, clinicians and policymakers with multifarious ethical challenges. After half a century of academic discussion about the ethics of ECLS, it seems appropriate to review the state of the argument and the trends in it. Through a comprehensive literature search on PubMed, we identified three ethical discourses: (1) trials and evidence accompanying the use of ECLS, (2) ECLS allocation, decision-making and limiting care, and (3) death on ECLS and ECLS in organ donation. All included articles were carefully reviewed, arguments extracted and grouped into the three discourses. This article provides a narrative synthesis of these arguments, evaluates the opportunities for mediation and substantiates the necessity of a shared decision-making approach at the limits of medical care. [Image: see text] SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION: The online version contains supplementary material available at 10.1186/s13054-021-03689-0. Since the beginning of extracorporeal life support (ECLS) 1 in the early 1970s the treatment has changed significantly [1, 2] . The technique 2 has been miniaturised and made more durable and biocompatible. Most importantly, ECLS has evolved from a risky experiment to a standard treatment option for critical respiratory or cardiac failure. Expanding knowledge, centralised care and, not least, the support of a well-established international consortium entrusted with data registry and the development of clinical standards have made ECLS a feasible procedure, serving a growing number of increasingly complex and diverse patients. Nonetheless, as the social costs of ECLS remain high its appropriateness is frequently questioned. However, the ethical concerns mainly focus on specific aspects. To date, none of the numerous, exponentially proliferating publications on the ethics of ECLS, have covered the whole spectrum of moral implications. For the purpose of a broad orienting overview on the existing ethical debate, a comprehensive search was carried out in PubMed on 31 October 2020 under the search terms: "ECLS" OR "extracorporeal life support" OR "ECMO" OR "extracorporeal membrane oxygenation" AND "ethics". This returned 380 titles of which 236 articles were excluded upon inspection of title and abstract. One Open Access *Correspondence: marc.soerensen@regionh.dk 3 Heart Centre, Rigshospitalet, Copenhagen University Hospital, Blegdamsvej 9, 2100 Copenhagen Ø, Denmark Full list of author information is available at the end of the article 1 ECLS refers to all forms of extracorporeal membrane oxygenation (ECMO) through veno-venous (V-V) or veno-arterial (V-A) cannulation and to extracorporeal CO 2 -removal (ECCO 2 R), through either veno-venous or arteriovenous (A-V) cannulation. Where "ECLS" is not explicitly distinguished from "ECMO", the terms are understood as synonymous. ECLS does not cover circulatory support without artificial oxygenation, as in ventricular assist devices (VAD), intra-aortic balloon pumps (IABP) or total artificial hearts (TAH), nor does it include the cardiopulmonary bypass (CPB) in cardiac surgery. hundred and ninety-seven articles were not dealing with an ethical subject; 27 were not electronically accessible; nine were written in a language other than English; and three were re-publications. All of the remaining 144 articles were thoroughly categorised according to their format and provenance, classed with an ethical discourse and summarised with regard to their ethical content (see the interactive Additional file 1 online). Based on this research we identified three ethical discourses, each covering several closely connected issues: (1) the research-ethical discourse on trials and evidence of ECLS (a summary of contributions on the ethical impact of the knowledge about ECLS and its collection); (2) the clinical and public policy ethical discourse on ECLS allocation, decision-making and limiting care (a summary of contributions on the ethical impact of ECLS on the omission and withdrawal of therapy); and (3) the clinical and public policy ethical discourse concerning death on ECLS and extracorporeal interval support for organ retrieval (EISOR) 3 (a summary of contributions on the ethical impact of ECLS on the definition of death and organ donation). The following text was written in three chapters as a narrative synthesis of the most prominent arguments. More recent articles were selectively included. Although ECLS covers different types of support, different indications and goals as well as patients of very different ages and clinical conditions, all conceivable scenarios of ECLS seem to be fraught with high economic and personal costs, more or less limited evidence and, most often, a lack of promising alternatives. None of the most central of the ethical issues mentioned (What evidence should we demand for treatment? When should the treatment be withheld or withdrawn? When should it be allowed to harvest organs from donors?) are necessarily different from the ethical issues in the use of life support systems in general. Rather, the uniqueness of ECLS lies in the simultaneity of these issues, their complexity and their acuteness and aggravation due to a rapidly growing clinical demand. The aim of this review is to unfold the current state of the discourses, to integrate and evaluate them. ECLS in the Coronavirus disease 2019 (COVID-19) pandemic and in paediatrics are included in the sections, as their ethical issues are to a great extent subordinated to the aforementioned discourses. For example, the rationing of ECLS under COVID-19 may be subordinated to the allocation of ECLS in general, while the deliberative role of parents of infants on ECLS may be subordinated to the ethical discourse of (subsidiary) decision-making. Where relevant, however, the sections will deal explicitly with the normative differences between children and adults, and the exceptional role of the pandemic. Gaining knowledge about the impact of ECLS on mortality has always faced researchers with complex ethical dilemmas. The development of evidence underlying ECLS is irrevocably intertwined with the design of the trials that generate that evidence, which therefore remains limited and largely retrospective. There are currently eight randomised controlled trials on the subject, six of which deal with respiratory failure [3, 4] . The two trials on neonates show significant advantage from ECLS, whereas only one out of four trials on respiratory failure in adults corroborates this outcome. Regarding cardiac failure, a minor prospective single-centre study from 2019 does not indicate any significant benefit from V-A ECMO in cardiogenic shock [5] . In extracorporeal cardiopulmonary resuscitation (ECPR), in contrast, a recent randomised controlled trial displays improved survival from out-of-hospital cardiac arrest (OHCA) with favourable neurological performance in the ECLS-group [6] . As the only overlap of all of these studies, ECLS was applied as an immediate, life-saving bridge to spontaneous recovery or restoration. The underlying patient pool is therefore extremely heterogeneous, and the favourable outcomes for children, especially neonates, are commonly attributed to their particular stage of maturation or effective surgery. Prospective research indicates that the benefits of ECLS for adult patients are far more questionable. Correspondingly, the evidence for ECLS and its ethical value have been discussed from the beginning. Even before publication of the first randomised controlled trial in 1979, the evidence-related lack of alternatives to randomisation was both proclaimed and contested in the same journal issue [7] . Chalmers and Miké et al. consider randomisation the gold standard for clinical research, and as such represent a distinctive standpoint among early studies [8, 9] . Conversely, Lantos et al. highlight the reductionism associated with well-designed randomised trials, which were necessarily preceded by a certain degree of practical knowledge and expectation, ethical values and inherent uncertainty. Randomising extremely vulnerable patients to a given trial's control treatment, which the investigator believes to be inferior, seemed unacceptable [10] . Twenty-five years later, the investigators of the EOLIA trial on the use of ECLS in the acute respiratory distress syndrome (ARDS) would be confronted with the same dilemma, and opted to terminate the study [4] . Following the initial discussion, Bartlett et al. and O'Rourke et al. applied different adaptive study designs in their neonatal trials in the 1980s [11] . These approaches were later criticised for only minimising rather than solving the major ethical problem of randomisation [3] . In his influential article from 1992, Truog identified some ECLS-specific features that limit the role and feasibility of randomisation: the rapid and ongoing development of clinical standards and the unacknowledged need for large-scale demographic data and long-term follow-up [12] . Recently, Bartlett and Gattinoni et al. have revisited this viewpoint [3, 13] . In a later editorial, Truog outlines the limitations of obtaining the intensive care patient's informed consent to inclusion in clinical trials [14] . For this reason, in the adaptive studies, consent was only sought from parents whose children had already been randomised to the intervention group. Worrall argues that the ethics of randomisation in ECLS research are conflated with the underlying concept of evidence. Indeed, he shows that the clear and robust concept of evidence is anything but a given. Different interpretations yielded different ethical conclusions [15] . In a response to Lantos et al. from 1993 Miké et al. introduced what they call the concept of ethics of evidence, which brings together the professionals' moral duty to contribute to the best statistical evidence about ECLS and to a deliberative assessment of the remaining uncertainty in a multilateral process involving both patients and society [9] . On this reading, it should be fairly uncontroversial. However, Miké et al. overlook that evidence is not the starting point of deliberation, rather its product, at a specific point of time during a reflective communication process. Formal, prospective research, as Lantos et al. put it, is always preceded by some sort of more or less informal historical experience, as the design of trials presupposes expectation and deselection [10] . Both the use of an unproven treatment with clinical equipoise and randomisation without equipoise can be equally unethical. Ultimately, the review and publication process is not merely follow-up, but an essential, integral element of research itself. Miké et al. would therefore benefit from incorporating Lantos' moral scruples, since ethics apply from the beginning of an inquiry, not only at the end [16] . Both clinical and scientific evolution entail collective learning. This is a unidirectional movement, in which the agents involved irrevocably adopt a new mental state-the time after ECLS can never again be the time before ECLS. In this process, randomised trials are superior to other studies when it comes to detecting the impact of an unproven treatment, but are inferior to other study designs at answering the question of how this impact is working-let alone what these findings mean in their clinical context. Appropriate ECLS-utilisation is extensively discussed due to its heavy staffing and logistical requirements. While several historical cost-effectiveness analyses have shown it to be cost-efficient for some patient populations and indications in certain national health systems, at least compared to other highly cost-intensive interventions, this is not universally the case [1] . Initiating or continuing ECLS indiscriminately conflicts at a minimum with physicians' duty to allocate resources responsibly [17, 18] . However, the lack of clear evidence limits the use of prospective economic calculations. Allocation decisions surrounding the use of ECLS are already made urgently with a lack of time, information and therapeutic alternatives. The introduction of ECPR in cardiac arrest has made these decisions even more time sensitive. Brauner et al. hold that similar economic forces that led to CPR being indicated in any event of cardiac arrest were currently driving the expansion of indications for ECLS [19] . Understanding these forces would be essential for establishing a more appropriate practice. As more evidence regarding the impact of ECLS emerges, the calculation of cost per life-year saved [1, 20] and regular cost-benefit analyses [18] might assist decision-making. Quality-adjusted life-years might be part of this evaluation, yet they would contain the patient's subjective judgements [20] and would not consider the decision's societal impact [21] . In healthcare systems based on private health insurance, resource allocation might depend on the payer's willingness to cover the costs, which could result in unequal access to ECLS [1] . To ensure that the most vulnerable patients are protected, in times of scarcity ECLS resources should be prioritised at a national health policy level, guided by pre-existing rationing plans [20, [22] [23] [24] . The COVID-19 pandemic has further focused attention on prioritisation [25, 26] . Rather than adding novel ethical conflicts, ECLS ultimately changed state from being relatively limited to absolutely scarce. Tyrrell et al. provide a systematic overview of different national recommendations referring to the traditional concepts of utilitarianism and egalitarianism [27] . Those might be still reconcilable if utility is reframed as beneficence and equality as equity [28] . DeLaney et al. argue for frequently reviewing disaster-protocols aimed at assessing ECLS-prioritisation that takes into account the individual's societal and instrumental value, as well as the primacy of the youngest patients and those with the longest life expectancy [29] . However, while few authors would disagree that those in the greatest need should be prioritised during an ECLS-shortage, they may dissent on what constitutes "the greatest need": the prospect of survival, when the alternative is death? Survival for a full life cycle? How to weight the likely survival of one individual against the less likely survival of many? Should an older patient with good recovery prospects but a short remaining lifespan give way to two children with unpredictable or poorer outcomes [30] ? Most authors emphasise that the key to a successful ECLS course would be clear and timely communication, ensuring that the individual's perspective is included in the decision to initiate or (dis-)continue therapy [31] . In elective cases of expected (post-procedural) ECLS, an informed consent should be obtained in advance [32] . Shared decision-making may enhance patient autonomy in awake patients, but it also presupposes the patient's cognitive capacity to process the information, and the patient or surrogates may find the burden of weighty decisions overwhelming. Misunderstanding, emotional distortion, patients' trust in expertise, urgency and lack of prognostic certainty make true informed consent difficult to achieve and basic ethical principles hard to apply [20, 31, 33] . Consent would often be implied, but rarely explicitly sought before initiating ECLS [32] . Moreover, true consent for decannulation could not be properly achieved before cannulation, as consent might be given under duress [18] . Perhaps for these reasons, the majority of physicians counter-intuitively advocated for their discretion in limiting V-A ECMO in a notable survey conducted by Meltzer et al. in 2016 [35] . Three years later, Abrams et al. confirmed this trend with regard to V-V ECMO [36] . Whitman and Bein et al. congruently focus on the limits of patient and surrogate responsibility and the professionals' obligation for counselling and guidance [31, 37, 38] . Given a lack of cognitive capacity, those acting on behalf of patients should always act in the patient's best interest [21] . As the objective of ECLS is to help patients survive until recovery or restitution, initiating or continuing ECLS is generally considered inappropriate if there are no such prospects [39] . This applies both to pre-ECLS patients and to those already undergoing it, as most authors suggest that withholding and withdrawing ECLS are ethically equivalent [17, 38, 40, 41] . However, some highlight the cruelty of withdrawing ECLS from objecting patients [17, 18] . For patients trapped on this metaphorical bridge to nowhere, a no-escalation-strategy might provide a way out [42] . DeMartino et al. claim that ECLS should not be withheld because withdrawal seems unethical. To do so would deny patients an opportunity while their prognosis is clarified [34] . Paris et al. state that the concept of professional responsibility should be understood in a principlistic way [43] . The quality of life principle should be integrated with the sanctity of life principle of personalism [21, 23, 44] . Meanwhile, the concept of futility is generally regarded as flawed if the deliberation does not take account of the patient's wishes and expectations [45] . The pivotal point of the ethical debate is the extent of this deliberation-i.e. whether professional integrity and responsibility on the one hand or patient autonomy on the other hand should be the decisive factor in the event of disagreement. Preemptive ethics consultation, daily interdisciplinary rounds, and early advance care planning that addresses values, appropriate goals and fears, as well as support from spiritual and palliative care providers, are widely recommended [20, 35, 38, 46] . It is difficult to find an operational definition of human life, and the same is true of death. As circulation is halted, and organs are deprived of oxygen, they start dying off at different speeds. Further, the invention of the ventilator and extracorporeal circulation has forced a new thinking, inasmuch as the loss of respiration and heart function no longer mean death and brain function was made central in the concept of human life [47] . According to Baker et al. consciousness and self-awareness were the only emergent phenomena whose loss would be at once necessary and sufficient to define the death of a person [48] . As advancements in intensive care and organ transplantation necessitated a more reproducible diagnostic tool for the determination of death, in 1968 the brain death criteria were established, which defined the clinical signs of the irreversible loss of vital brain function [49] . In order to maximise the organ yield, in 1981 Bernat adopted a prospective death criterion based on the concept of permanence, where "irreversible" denoted a condition that, like in brain death, could not be reverted by any known technologies, "permanent" denoted a condition that would not be reverted, and therefore become irreversible [48] . Bernat's concept of the permanence of death implies that death is technologically dependent, because the exact moment at which the cessation of brain activity changes from permanent to irreversible can be modified with ECLS-and, in the absence of international standards, it might also differ from place to place [50] . In an early contribution on EISOR, Shemie holds that critics of this dependence typically fail to recognise that the concept of death would have inevitably and always (independently from ECLS) been definitional rather than clearly descriptive [47] . Verhejde et al. argue that not even permanence could be empirically determined, since there were no reliable tests to confirm this state [51] . However, Bernat's concept was recently supported by Shapey et al.: in a systematic review on EISOR they did not show any return of spontaneous cerebral or cardiac activity after 5 min of stand-off time [52] . Since the 1960s, vital organ donation has been undertaken in implicit accordance with the dead donor rule (DDR). This stipulates that vital organs must only be removed from deceased donors, and therefore that death must not be caused by the removal of a vital organ. Ever since the introduction of the brain death criteria, the majority of vital organ procurements have been performed on donors who had been declared dead based on these criteria (donation after brain death, DBD). In 1966, the French National Council of the Order of Physicians suggested that organ procurement from donors who were not yet declared dead could be legitimate under certain circumstances. The 2000s saw the introduction of organ donation after circulatory determination of death (DCDD), which was split into two broad categories: controlled (cDCDD), typically preceded by a period of time of critical illness; and uncontrolled (uDCDD), typically succeeding a refractory cardiac arrest [53] . In both cases, the question of when the patient is to be declared dead hinges on the cessation of cerebral perfusion. In the case of organ procurement from ECLS, death would be declared in the limbo between permanent and irreversible [54] . To give an example of a setting in which DCDD may be relevant, a donor would usually present serious cardiovascular and eventually also neurological deficiencies, without fulfilling the brain death criteria. If that individual is neither likely to recover nor eligible for transplantation or VAD, organ procurement for donation would be precluded following DBD and DDR, but not under DCDD, as per Bernat's concept of the permanence of death. Several protocols for cDCDD and uDCDD have been developed and successfully adopted in Europe and Canada, all of which include a varying no-touch interval of asystole, where all medical support ceases and the organ donor is observed for circulatory auto-resuscitation. However, as Halpern et al. object, the confidence of time needed is based on anecdotal reports or small cohorts [55] . For the same reason, Dalle Ave and Bernat argue that post-mortem interventions like ECLS that could restart circulation to the brain should not be deployed, as this would retrospectively negate the diagnosis. Simultaneous occlusion of the aorta or brain vessels would raise questions about physicians' complicity in the donor's death [53, 54, 56] . Halpern et al., as well as Glannon, suggest that DDR should be abandoned [55, 57] . They base this point of view on the fact that the precise transition from permanence to irreversibility in dying is unknown and argue that DDR would invalidate the wish of the donor who has consented to organ donation, as it can jeopardise transplantation. They suggest that the donors' wish, the absence of suffering and a poor and irreversible prognosis constitute ethically satisfying grounds for the donation of vital organs. By contrast, Wall et al. and Molina et al. hold that uDCDD, performed within the framework of DDR, would be ethically feasible, provided that irreversible death is declared after failed resuscitation attempts [58, 59] . A fascinating prospect for ECLS is the possibility of saving more lives due to a larger population of possible organ donors. However, this can be a double-edged sword, as ECLS could be seen as both an advanced resuscitation tool and an advanced organ-procurement tool [60] . Care should be taken to underline the limitations of ECLS therapy, so that it is not seen as a way of "harvesting" organs from patients who could be resuscitated [61] . The professional roles in transplantation should be strictly separated [53, [62] [63] [64] . In this article, we explored the current state of the debate regarding the ethics of ECLS. In a literature review from the beginning of ECLS to the present, we assessed an extensive corpus of scientific contributions. The complexity of the subject is partly due to rather distinct discourses, dealing with different but interconnected ethical issues over several decades. ECLS itself is complex, however, the discourses seem to be universal. We therefore suggest that the ethics of ECLS should be recognised as an epistemic concept, in which descriptive facts and ethical norms do not merely supplement but inevitably affect each other. Thus, whether the effectiveness of ECLS is sufficiently supported by evidence, where decision-making authority regarding the limits of ECLS should lie, and whether ECLS should be used in DCDD are all a matter of balancing reasons, rather than deriving norms from facts. Neither dealing with prognostic uncertainty or multilateral communication nor pushing the boundaries of death is novel to the medical profession, but these issues have been particularly aggravated by the evolving technology of ECLS, not least in relation to COVID-19, leaving a great need for careful technology assessment but also individualised practice and openmindedness from all sides. Few authors may fully subscribe to this, but some are thinking along similar lines. Early works by Bartlett [3] and Lantos et al. [10] describe how ECLS research is linked to its ethical prerequisites and consequences; Jaramillo et al. [17] point out the rationality of deliberation in limiting ECLS; Carlisle et al. [65] oppose the clear-cut understanding of futility; and in the face of the common utilitarian ECLSprioritisation model advocated by Abrams et al. [66] , Supady et al. [26] prefer the egalitarian approach of Norman Daniels, which is based on the right to participate in a fair and transparent allocation process. Finally, Ross [67] and Halpern et al. [55] depict the notion of death as pragmatic and therefore alterable. All of these authors contribute in one way or another to the conceptualisation of ECLS as a matter of dialogue. This dialogue, the exchange of arguments and their mutual scrutiny should be seen as the origin of the ethical and factual significance of ECLS and appeal to both legal and healthcare professionals and administrators, patients, surrogates, politicians and the public. It may be justified to represent agents through law, algorithms and expertise, not least when faced with mass critical care needs during a pandemic, but it also signifies avoidance of the argument and could mean that relevant objections remain unheard. Both historical arguments and arguments from deviant discourses can be of great value. For example, the discourse surrounding early neonatal trials may help to improve the future research design in adult critical illness, while the discourse on the ontology and measurability of death may provide valuable knowledge about futility. The present article's broad overview may help to inform those in charge and those seeking substantiation in the ethics of ECLS. Abbreviations ECLS: Extracorporeal life support; COVID-19: Coronavirus disease 2019; ECMO: Extracorporeal membrane oxygenation; V-V: Veno-venous; V-A: Veno-arterial; A-V: Arterio-venous; ECCO 2 R: Extracorporeal carbon dioxide removal; VAD: Ventricular assist device; IABP: Intra-aortic balloon pump; TAH: Total artificial heart; CPB: Cardiopulmonary bypass; EISOR: Extracorporeal interval support for organ retrieval; (E)CPR: (Extracorporeal) cardiopulmonary resuscitation; OHCA: Out-of-hospital cardiac arrest; ARDS: Acute respiratory distress syndrome; DDR: Dead donor rule; DBD: Donation after brain death; (c/u)DCDD: (Controlled/ uncontrolled) Donation after circulatory determination of death. Extracorporeal life support: utilization, cost, controversy, and ethics of trying to save lives Ethical considerations for post-cardiotomy extracorporeal membrane oxygenation Clinical research in acute fatal illness: lessons from extracorporeal membrane oxygenation Extracorporeal membrane oxygenation for severe acute respiratory distress syndrome Temporary circulatory support for cardiogenic shock Advanced reperfusion strategies for patients with out-of-hospital cardiac arrest and refractory ventricular fibrillation (ARREST): a phase 2, single center, open-label, randomised controlled trial Ethics of randomization: use of extracorporeal membrane oxygenation A belated randomized control trial Neonatal extracorporeal membrane oxygenation (ECMO): clinical trials and the ethics of evidence Extracorporeal membrane oxygenation and the ethics of clinical research in pediatrics The use of response-adaptive designs in clinical trials The epistemology and ethics of chronic disease research: further lessons from ECMO Use of ECMO in ARDS: does the EOLIA trial really help? Informed consent and research design in critical care medicine Evidence and ethics in medicine Extracorporeal membrane oxygenation after stem cell transplant: clinical decision-making in the absence of evidence How should ECMO initiation and withdrawal decisions be shared? What's new in extracorporeal membrane oxygenation for cardiac failure and cardiac arrest in adults? Will we code for default ECMO? Ethical and end of life considerations for neonates requiring ECMO support Principlism and personalism. Comparing two ethical models applied clinically in neonates undergoing extracorporeal membrane oxygenation support. Front Pediatr Gender and age disparity in the initiation of life-supporting treatments: a populationbased cohort study End-of-life care in advanced kidney disease: ethical and legal issues and key challenges for black and minority ethnic groups Use of extracorporeal technology during pandemics: ethical and staffing considerations Cardiopulmonary resuscitation in intensive care unit patients with coronavirus disease 2019 Procedural justice and egalitarian principles for rationing decisions in the COVID-19 crisis Managing intensive care admissions when there are not enough beds during the COVID-19 pandemic: a systematic review Allocating scarce intensive care resources during the COVID-19pandemic: practical challenges to theoretical frameworks Extracorporeal life support for pandemic influenza: the role of extracorporeal membrane oxygenation in pandemic management Shakhsheer B. Extracorporeal membrane oxygenation for pediatric patients with coronavirus disease 2019-related illness Understanding ethical decisions for patients on extracorporeal life support Do-(not-)mechanical-circulatorysupport orders: should we ask all cardiac surgery patients for informed consent for post-cardiotomy extracorporeal life circulatory support? Is informed consent for extracorporeal life support even possible? Decisions to withdraw extracorporeal membrane oxygenation support: patient characteristics and ethical considerations A survey of physicians' attitudes toward decision-making authority for initiating and withdrawing VA-ECMO: results and ethical implications for shared decision making Practice patterns and ethical considerations in the management of venovenous extracorporeal membrane oxygenation patients: an international survey Extracorporeal membrane oxygenation for the treatment of postcardiotomy shock Ethical dilemmas encountered with the use of extracorporeal membrane oxygenation in adults Extracorporeal membrane oxygenation bridge to no recovery American Heart Association guidelines update for cardiopulmonary resuscitation and emergency cardiovascular care ICU care Before and after lung transplantation Ethical dilemmas with the use of ECMO as a bridge to transplantation Physicians' refusal to provide life-prolonging medical interventions Ethical uncertainty: an approach to decisions involving extracorporeal membrane oxygenation Termination of extracorporeal membrane oxygenation for cardiac support Ethics committee consultation and extracorporeal membrane oxygenation Clarifying the paradigm for the ethics of donation and transplantation: was 'dead' really so clear before organ donation? Biophilosophical basis for identifying the death of a person Donation after brain circulation determination of death Extracorporeal membrane oxygenation in pediatric organ donation Presumed consent for organ preservation in uncontrolled donation after cardiac death in the united states: a public policy with serious consequences Systematic review to assess the possibility of return of cerebral and cardiac activity after normothermic regional perfusion for donors after circulatory death Uncontrolled donation after circulatory determination of death: a systematic ethical analysis convenient online submission • thorough peer review by experienced researchers in your field • rapid publication on acceptance • support for research data, including large and complex data types • gold Open Access which fosters wider collaboration and increased citations maximum visibility for your research: over 100M website views per year • At BMC, research is always in progress. Learn more biomedcentral.com/submissions Ready to submit your research Ready to submit your research ? Choose BMC The circulatory-respiratory determination of death in organ donation Organ donors after circulatory determination of death: not necessarily dead, and it does not necessarily matter Ethical issues in the use of extracorporeal membrane oxygenation in controlled donation after circulatory determination of death The moral insignificance of death in organ donation Uncontrolled organ donation after circulatory determination of death: US policy failures and call to action Uncontrolled donation after circulatory death: ethics of implementation Extracorporeal life support and multiorgan donation in a severe polytrauma patient: a case report Extracorporeal membrane oxygenation (ECMO) assisted cardiopulmonary resuscitation or uncontrolled donation after the circulatory determination of death following out-of-hospital refractory cardiac arrest-An ethical analysis of an unresolved clinical dilemma The ethics of extracorporeal membrane oxygenation in brain-dead potential organ donors Protocols for uncontrolled donation after circulatory death: a systematic review of international guidelines, practices and transplant outcomes The boundaries of organ donation after circulatory death Emerging issues in the ethical utilization of pediatric extracorporeal membrane oxygenation ECMO during the COVID-19 pandemic: when is it justified? Respecting choice in definitions of death Publisher's Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations Not applicable.Authors' contributions AS, JM and MS have all contributed equally in terms of planning, composing and writing the drafts, searching for literature and editing the final manuscript, LWA and SH have contributed equally in terms of composing and editing the final manuscript. The online version contains supplementary material available at https:// doi. org/ 10. 1186/ s13054-021-03689-0.Additional file 1. List of PubMed-cited articles dealing with the ethics of ECLS, categorised by provenance (country), their excerpted ethical content, their corresponding ethical discourse and biographical data.