key: cord-0893260-bj3bmu2c authors: Nganmeni, Zéphirin; Pongou, Roland; Tchantcho, Bertrand; Tondji, Jean‐Baptiste title: Vaccine and inclusion date: 2022-04-27 journal: J Public Econ Theory DOI: 10.1111/jpet.12590 sha: 467d703222f871ab14d504de17fb01c75f0f2c4f doc_id: 893260 cord_uid: bj3bmu2c In majoritarian democracies, popular policies may not be inclusive, and inclusive policies may not be popular. This dilemma raises the crucial question of when it is possible to design a policy that is both inclusive and popular. We address this question in the context of vaccine allocation in a polarized economy facing a pandemic. In such an economy, individuals are organized around distinct networks and groups and have in‐group preferences. We provide a complete characterization of the set of inclusive and popular vaccine allocations. The findings imply that the number of vaccine doses necessary to generate an inclusive and popular vaccine allocation is greater than the one necessary to obtain an allocation that is only popular. The analysis further reveals that it is always possible to design the decision‐making rule of the economy to implement an inclusive and popular vaccine allocation. Under such a rule, the composition of any group endowed with the veto power should necessarily reflect the diversity of the society. In majoritarian democracies, the allocation of scarce resources tends to favor the interests of the majority group at the expense of those in minority groups. John Stuart Mill (1860) argued that the tyranny of the majority results in the oppression of minority factions, and he compared the power wielded by the majority to that of a despot. Painful memories of such coercion recently resulted in widespread protests in several western democratic countries around the world, forcing the leaders of these countries to consider the need for their policies to be both just and inclusive. For example, on June 25, 2021, the American President, Joseph R. Biden, issued an executive order strengthening the implementation of diversity, equity, inclusion, and accessibility in the federal workforce (The White House, 2021) . In 2019, the Conservative Party in the United Kingdom (U.K.) won the most seats in parliament, offering a landslide victory to Prime Minister Boris Johnson. He responded by selecting the most diverse cabinet in U.K. political history, aiming to address some of the most pressing challenges facing the country's polarized communities (Bokhari, 2019) . Recently, in response to the COVID-19 pandemic, organizations worldwide participated in the COVAX program-a global initiative coled by GAVI, the World Health Organization (WHO), and the Coalition for Epidemic Preparedness Innovations (CEPI)-to push for a fair and inclusive allocation of COVID-19 vaccines globally. Motivated by these real-world examples, the natural question that arises is whether democratic political leaders who, in general, focus on short-term re-election strategies have enough incentives to implement inclusive policies. These policies are likely to be unpopular, especially if they are perceived as taking away scarce resources from the majority group and allocating them to minority groups. The unpopularity of inclusive policies may be more pronounced in societies organized around distinct networks and groups. However, if closer contacts receive priority in resource allocation, individuals may be less agitated in such communities. Hence, there exists a tradeoff between the popularity and the inclusiveness of policies in fragmented societies. This observation raises the following question: under what conditions can a political leader implement an allocation policy that is both popular and inclusive? We address this question in the context of the allocation of vaccine doses during a pandemic. We propose a vaccine allocation model described as follows. A society consisting of a finite set of individuals or agents, N n = {1, 2, …, }, with n 3 ≥ , is facing the spread of a deadly virus. A safe and effective vaccine against this virus is approved for emergency use. However, the number of available doses, μ, is limited: μ n < , where μ is a non-zero integer. Given N and μ, an allocation of the μ vaccine doses to individuals is any S N ⊆ such that S μ =   , where S   denotes the cardinality of S. We denote by N μ ( ) the set of allocations of μ vaccine doses. Each agent i N ∈ assigns to agent j N ∈ , a real number denoted by δ j i . The set defines the order of priority desired by the agent i for access to vaccination. Given δ i , the weighted utility provided to agent i by a given vaccine allocation X in N μ ( ) is defined by u X δ ( ) i j X j i ≔ ∈  . Each agent i's weighted utility u i induces a weighted preference relation (weak ordering), which we denote by i ≾ , over N μ ( ). For a given society, the influence structure  describes the set of influential coalitions-groups of agents that have the power or ability to rule out any proposed allocation in N μ ( ) regardless of the preferences of agents outside of these coalitions. We refer to the pair E N = ( , )  as a political economy and the couple E μ ( , ) as a vaccine allocation problem. For any preference profile ( ) i general framework, we first derive some conditions under which a stable vaccine allocation exists in a homogeneous society (i.e., either a society that does not contain multiple distinct groups, or a society in which no individuals express in-group preferences). Then, to account for inclusion, we consider a polarized society organized around distinct groups where individuals have in-group preferences. We say that a vaccine allocation is inclusive when it contains agents from each group in the society. Then, we ask the following questions: under what conditions can a political leader consistently implement vaccine allocation policies that are both popular and inclusive? How does their ability to enforce inclusive vaccine allocation policies depend on factors such as the supply of vaccines and the distribution of power among influential groups in a polarized society? We investigate these questions using the core (Gillies, 1959; Shapley, 1955 ) as a solution concept. In a political context, the core is a measure of both policy stability and popularity. When a policy X does not belong to the core, another policy Y is preferred to X by an influential coalition, meaning that X is unstable and unpopular. In our general vaccine allocation problem, Theorem 1, Proposition 1, and Theorem 2 show that both the number of vaccine doses and the society's influence structure are critical for a stable vaccine allocation. Using these results, we determine the existence of stable vaccine allocations in any vaccine allocation game. Theorem 2, our characterization result, shows that the core of a vaccination allocation game G is the intersection of a nonempty set N ( , )   and the set of feasible vaccine allocations, N μ ( ). Therefore, given the limited supply of vaccine doses, Corollary 1 derives the minimum number of doses that guarantees a stable vaccine allocation in a political economy. We extend the analysis to polarized societies organized around two distinct groups, where individuals have in-group preferences. In-group preferences and weighted preferences all belong to the domain of other-regarding preferences. 1 Generally, factors such as ethnic, cultural, or gender proximity account for the establishment of groups in society. We can justify in-group preferences for two reasons. First, agents may display altruism toward their group members. Second, an agent's vulnerability to infection decreases with an increase in vaccination rate among closer contacts. We derive a necessary and sufficient condition for an inclusive vaccine allocation in a polarized political economy with two groups. Our first set of analyses covers one-dimensional polarized societies. Assuming that the influence structure is such that each of the two groups is influential, Theorem 3 shows that any stable vaccine allocation should provide one vaccine dose to each agent. Theorem 4 stipulates that if only one group is influential, then any stable allocation should provide a vaccine dose to each agent in that group. The latter finding implies that not being influential negatively affects the wellbeing of a group's members. Theorem 5, on the other hand, states that when no group constitutes an influential coalition, then the planner should supply at least two vaccine doses to ensure vaccine allocation stability in society. Finally, Proposition 2 offers a characterization of the stable and inclusive (balanced or perfect inclusion, respectively) vaccine allocations for multidimensional polarized societies. Proposition 2 implies that the number of doses necessary to generate a stable and balanced vaccine allocation is greater than the one necessary to obtain a vaccine allocation that is both stable and inclusive, as the latter case requires a larger number of doses to ensure that the vaccine allocation is stable. Therefore, it is challenging to ensure vaccine inclusiveness in a fragmented society that does not have the means to produce or acquire a sufficiently high number of doses. When inclusiveness fails, any stable vaccine allocation favors the majority group or group with the decisive (or veto) power. This latter finding is consistent with studies showing that when voting rights are unequally distributed, individuals with greater voting power have a greater ability to induce social outcomes that maximize their preferences. 2 The problem of the allocation of scarce resources during health crises is classical. 3 Following the global shortage of essential medical resources as a direct consequence of the COVID-19 pandemic, governments worldwide had to enforce nonpharmaceutical control policies-lockdowns, targeted quarantines, mask-wearing, and social distancing-to contain the contagion until the approval of possible vaccines and treatments. Under such situations, scientists and policymakers suggested priority measures based on different ethical considerations. Since those allocation mechanisms involve tradeoffs, finding optimal, and peaceful solutions are the primary concern for elected officials. The vaccine case is unique given its externality effect and its health dimension. Although almost all countries generally face a scarcity of doses upon vaccine discovery, the problem is exacerbated in developing countries given their lack of economic, medical, and advanced technological resources (Gori et al., 2021a) . For this reason, our framework could probably apply better to a developing country. However, our allocation approach can also inform political leaders in Western countries. Indeed, during a pandemic, policymakers in developed nations must calibrate vaccination policies that will not affect their popularity. Strikes due to either mandatory vaccination campaigns (Austen, 2021) or vaccine priority mechanisms perceived as unfair by some groups of the society (Lori et al., 2021) , among others, can significantly reduce their chances of survival in the government. In this study, we assume that individuals have a positive attitude toward vaccines and want to receive a vaccine dose. 4 This assumption is still very general in contexts where vaccine production is costly, with the cost being supported by taxpayers or international donors as in developing countries (Gori et al., 2021a) . When governments use fiscal policy returns to support vaccine doses, we can show that all our results will remain valid if we assume that certain individuals are vaccine-hesitant. Vaccinehesitant individuals will not receive any dose in stable vaccine allocations. The issue of inclusion and global coordination in allocating scarce resources such as vaccines is timely. Studies show that fragmented and segregated communities have been hit hardest by the COVID-19 pandemic (DebnamGuzman et al., 2022) , and restrictive policies-policies that favor population health over economic gains-benefited minority groups less in the United States (see, e.g., Pongou et al., 2022a) . As such, the issue of inclusion has received the attention of several academics and policymakers during the current COVID-19 pandemic. Our study joins the ongoing wealth of contributions pushing for inclusive actions in the fight against COVID-19. We can cite, among others, So and Woo (2020) , Emanuel et al. (2020) , Lancet (2020), Zard et al. (2021) , Shete et al. (2021) , and Norheim et al. (2021) . Our findings show that implementing vaccine allocations representing a society's structure does not hurt the popularity of either a selfless or selfish political leader. Indeed, during times of crisis voters generally appreciate leaders with humanitarian principles and good leadership (Bechtel & Hainmueller, 2011; Bol et al., 2021; Healy & Malhotra, 2009) . For instance, the recent landslide re-election victory of the Jacinda Ardern-led Labour government in New Zealand is 2 See, for example, Pongou and Tchantcho (2021) and Nganmeni et al. (2021) . 3 For the case of vaccines, see, for example, a survey by . 4 In reality, individuals may have different attitudes towards vaccination. Not everyone in the population wishes to be vaccinated. Indeed, the issue of vaccine hesitancy or the reluctance of people to receive safe and recommended available vaccines (MacDonald, 2015) is prevalent. Troiano and Nardi (2021) and Machingaidze and Wiysonge (2021) document several drivers of vaccine hesitancy in the era of COVID-19. For instance, the recent protests in Canada are evidence of some antivaccination campaigns against a compulsory mandate of the COVID-19 vaccines (Austen, 2021) . evidence of the rewards political leaders can reap from good leadership during pandemics and other global crises (Goldfinch et al., 2021; Paull, 2021) . Our work contributes to the growing literature, which recommends considering economic, social, and demographic dimensions when allocating vaccines during pandemics. Along this line, some studies suggest using vaccine effectiveness (Kirwin et al., 2021; Matrajt et al., 2021) , cost-benefit analyses by mixing epidemiological and economic models (Duijzer, van Jaarsveld, Wallinga, & Dekker, 2018; Matrajt et al., 2013; Medlock and Galvani, 2009; Mylius et al., 2008; Rao & Brandeau, 2021) , mechanism design approach (Akbarpour et al., 2021; Castillo et al., 2021; Kremer et al., 2022; Pathak et al., 2021; Westerink-Duijzer et al., 2020; Xue & Ouellette, 2020) , and ethics (Emanuel et al., 2020; Nichol & Mermin-Bunnell, 2021; Pathak et al., 2021; Wu et al., 2020; Yi & Marathe, 2015) . 5 In a recent study, Forman et al. (2021) highlight 11 COVID-19 vaccine challenges and potential solutions that may help decision-makers develop sound, safe, and effective vaccination campaigns against current and future disease outbreaks. Although most of these contributions cover the issue of vaccine inclusiveness, we differ in scope and analysis. We propose a framework in which political leaders could benefit from good leadership during pandemics by exploiting the society's influence structure and vaccine technology to implement popular and inclusive vaccine allocations. Our paper also complements other studies that have proposed interacting economics and epidemiology models on designing optimal nonpharmaceutical interventions during a pandemic like COVID-19. For recent contributions, see Acemoglu et al. (2021) , Gollier (2020) , Gori et al. (2021a Gori et al. ( , 2021b , Hritonenko et al. (2021) , Gallic et al. (2021) , and Rothert (2021), Pongou et al. (2022b) ; see also Boucekkine et al. (2021) on the economics of epidemics and contagious diseases. Finally, we also contribute to the literature that uses tools from voting environments to solve allocation problems. Examples include, but are not limited to, the apportionment and proportional representation problems (Balinski & Laraki, 2007; Brill et al., 2018; Florek, 2012; Johnston, 1983; Jones et al., 2020) , and the claim problems (Flores-Szwagrzak, 2015; Ju et al., 2007) . Our study is closely related to the coalition structure model introduced by Aumann and Dreze (1974) , and a recent modeling approach by Martin et al. (2021) . In line with these studies, our conceptual framework uses weighted preferences to consider the patterns of relationships between agents. We identify necessary and sufficient conditions under which it is possible to design a vaccine allocation policy that is popular and inclusive in a fragmented political economy. The rest of the article is organized as follows. Section 2 describes the vaccine allocation problem. Section 3 provides general results on the existence and determination of stable vaccine allocations. Section 4 examines the issue of inclusive vaccine allocation problems in a polarized society, and Section 5 concludes. In our theoretical model of vaccine allocation, N n = {1, …, } is a set of n agents indexed from 1 to n, where n is a nonzero integer, and μ is the number of vaccine doses available to these agents. We denote by 2 N the set of coalitions or nonempty subsets of N . Each agent requests a vaccine dose, but the supply of vaccines cannot satisfy total demand as μ n < . A vaccine allocation is a possible way to choose from N , the μ agents who can receive the vaccines. If for any subset E 2 N ∈ , E   refers to the cardinality of E, then we denote the set of possible (or Note that the available number of vaccine doses depends both on a society's economic purchasing power and its technological production capacity. For example, in less developed societies which lack the technology required to produce the vaccine, the parameter μ may be relatively low in comparison to its value in more developed countries. Each agent obtains some utility from any feasible vaccine allocation. We consider an ordinal approach in the formalization of agents' utility. We assume that agents have ordinal preferences over the set of feasible vaccine allocations. In our model, we distinguish two preference domains. In this domain, agent i N ∈ assigns to each agent j N ∈ a real number denoted by δ j i , which measures how much utility accrues to i if j is vaccinated. 6 Given The relation i ≺ denotes the strict part of i ≾ , and the relation~i denotes the indifference part of i ≾ . Euclidean preferences constitute a specific class of weighted preferences. We use elements of the usual Euclidean affine geometry to define Euclidean preferences. For this purpose, let m be a nonzero integer. Each agent i is represented in the m-dimensional Euclidean space m by a position q i , also called the ideal point; see, for example, Owen (1971) , Shapley (1977) , and Frank & Shapley (1981) . A given set of positions corresponds to a configuration of the agents' ideal points. Let d be the usual Euclidean distance. We need to choose the weights δ such that for all i j N , ∈ , δ j i decreases when the distance between the ideal points of i and j increases. One can choose, for instance, δ d q q = − ( , ) . Remark that d N : × 2 N → is not necessarily a metric in the mathematical sense. Generally, coalitions that decide upon which group of μ agents should receive the available vaccine doses in society have some decisive (or veto) power under a given preapproved set of rules. An influential coalition (or a winning coalition) is any group S of agents endowed with the ability to challenge any proposed allocation X N μ ( ) ∈ .  denotes the set of influential coalitions, and it is fixed a priori. An influential structure can therefore be interpreted as a power-sharing agreement and can be designed to account for health, political, social, and economic factors. We assume that  satisfies the following two conditions: (1)  ∅ ∉ and  ≠ ∅; and (2) for all coalitions S and T , if S  ∈ and S T ⊆ , then T  ∈ . According to assumption (1), an empty coalition cannot influence the allocation of vaccines. Assumption (1) also states that at least one influential coalition exists. Assumption (2) is a classical monotonicity condition which stipulates that the addition of new agents to an influential coalition yields another influential coalition. The two assumptions together imply that the entire community, N , is an influential coalition. We consider an influence structure,  , to be weighted if there exists a real number α called a quota, with α n 0 < < , and for each i N ∈ , there exists a nonnegative weight, . In this case, we , and we call  a α-weighted influence structure. When α α = i j , for all agents i and j,  is called a α-weighted symmetric influence structure. , and we refer to the couple E μ ( , ) as a vaccine allocation problem. A vaccine allocation game, which we denote G, is any Sometimes, we will also denote a vaccine allocation game as represents the agents' utility profile over N μ ( ). We denote by the set of all vaccine allocation games. . Given preference heterogeneity, implementing a vaccine allocation that satisfies all agents' societal expectations can be impossible with a limited supply of doses. Therefore, the goal of the political leader (or social planner) is to choose among N μ ( ), vaccine allocations that will get some degree of approval in society. for all i S ∈ . 2. A stable (or popular) vaccine allocation is not challenged in the game G. 3. The core of G, denoted by C G ( ), is the set of stable vaccine allocations for G: A stable vaccine allocation will be adopted in society if it is proposed for approval. With the preference profile u is a political economy, and μ is the number of vaccine doses. Keeping all the other elements in G fixed, we can determine the set of stable vaccine allocations, C E μ ( , ), for different values of μ. The illustrations that we display below provide some intuition behind the characterization of stable vaccine allocations that we will derive in Section 3. Consider two communities A and B, that consist of seven agents numbered from 1 to 7; that is, in each community, N = {1, …, 7}. We analyze the existence of stable vaccine allocations in some vaccine allocation games  based on Euclidean preferences, assuming one-dimensional spatial configurations of agents' ideal points that we describe in Community A (Section 2.6.1) and Community B (Section 2.6.2). In our illustration, agents' ideal points are on the horizontal axis. Therefore, we derive agents' utilities u ( ) i using the usual Euclidean distance. For simplicity, we focus on some symmetric weighted influence structures and remove u ( ) i in the notation of a vaccine allocation game. We represent Community A by a political economy , where agents' ideal points q { } i are evenly spaced and displayed in the horizontal line in Figure 1 . In this illustration, we consider allocation games that differ only with the endowed influence structure  . Case 1A: Assume that = [4; 1, …, 1]  . If μ = 1, then there exists only one stable vaccine allocation that is X = {4}. Note that the influence structure  is equivalent to the simple majority rule, and the stable allocation corresponds to the median agent. If μ = 2, the set of stable allocations is C E ( , 2) = {{3, 4}, {4, 5}} . Indeed, neither of these two allocations in C E ( , 2) can be challenged since any influential coalition must include Agent 4. Still, agents only support peers whose positions are closer to their ideal points. . Unlike Case 1A, we can find two disjointed influential coalitions in  . If the planner can only supply up to two vaccine doses, then there is no stable allocation; that is, C E μ ( , ) = ∅ for μ {1, 2} ∈ . For μ = 3, the only stable vaccine allocation is {3, 4, 5} . For μ = 4, there is also no stable vaccine allocation: C E ( , 4) = ∅. For instance, if X = {2, 3, 4, 5} is proposed for approval, then Y = {3, 4, 5, 6} can challenge X via the influential coalition S = {5, 6, 7}. It follows that sometimes, an increase in the available number of vaccine doses can induce rivalries that make it challenging to obtain a stable allocation. To have a stable vaccine allocation, we must consider the same number of agents on either side of the median agent for this specific illustration. Supplying an odd number of vaccine doses (μ odd, μ 7 > 1 ≥ ) in Community A can enable the planner to solve the vaccine allocation deadlock. For instance, C E Notice that there is only one stable allocation in each case of available doses μ for which C E μ ( , ) is nonempty. We represent Community B by a political economy , and agents' ideal points are represented in Figure 2 . This configuration reflects a polarized society with two distinct and distant groups. In other words, the distance d q q ( , ) 4 5 is large compared to d q q ( , ) 1 4 and d q q ( , ) 5 7 . Case 1B: As in Case 1A, we assume that = [4; 1, …, 1]  . We have an influential group (N 1 ) and a noninfluential group (N 2 ). Following a similar approach as in Section 2.6.1, we show that We note that when the supply of vaccine doses is sufficiently low in Community B, (i.e., μ 4 ≤ ), Agents 5, 6, and 7 are disadvantaged since they do not belong in any of the stable vaccine allocations. The latter shows that a social planner cannot implement an inclusive policy when a society is polarized, and the size of resources is low. We also note that, compared to Case 1A, for each supply of vaccine doses μ, the core C E μ ( , ) in Case 1B only consists of one allocation. We formalize Case 1B in Theorem 4. Case 2B: As in Case 2A, we assume that = [3; 1, …, 1]  . In this case, both groups N 1 and N 2 , are influential. This yields a chaotic situation that requires a large supply of vaccine doses to obtain a stable allocation. Precisely, for μ 6 ≤ , C E μ ( , ) = ∅ and C E N ( , 7) = { }. We provide a formal result in Theorem 3. Case 3B: We assume in this situation that = [5; 1, …, 1]  . We have a polarized society but no group constitutes an influential coalition. This section provides three main results that determine the existence and characterize stable vaccine allocations in a political economy. In a vaccine allocation game G N q μ u = , , { }, , ( ) we need to highlight the characteristic properties of a stable allocation. We deduce the first one directly from the definition of the concept of stable allocation according to which an allocation and influential coalition S  ∈ such that Y challenges X via S. In other words if we consider any allocation Y and any influential coalition S, there is at least one agent of S who does not favor replacing X over Y . We can formally express these statements in the following remark. Remark 1. An allocation X is stable if for any allocation Y and for any influential coalition S, there exists an agent When the agents have Euclidean preferences, recall that for any coalition S and any agent and then, by definition, d i S u S ( , ) = − ( ) i . Hence, from Remark 1, an allocation X is stable under the Euclidean preference assumption, if for any allocation Y 2 N ∈ and for any influential coalition S  ∈ , there is an agent . This property induces a well-known characterization of the elements of the usual core in a spatial voting game. Indeed, a position P is in the core of a spatial voting game if and only if P is on the convex hull of all the winning coalitions, see Saari (2014) or Martin et al. (2021) . In a vaccine allocation game, if μ = 1, then a set reduced to a single point located on the convex envelope of all the winning coalitions is a stable allocation. However, it can be shown that the converse of the latter statement is not true. For an arbitrary value of μ 1 ≥ , the use of Remark 1 in determining the stability of a vaccine allocation requires pairwise comparisons over the set N μ ( ). We need additional notations to provide other alternative characterizations of stable allocations. Let u u = ( ) i be an agents' utility profile. For any coalitions S, T 2 N ∈ , any agent i N ∈ , and any nonzero integer k μ ≤ , we consider the following sets: , ) contains the subsets Λ with the same cardinality as T such that agent i prefers T to Λ. Under Euclidean preferences, we , ) contains coalitions Λ with the same cardinality as T such that any member of S prefers T to Λ. We articulate Theorem 1. is stable if and only if for any influential coalition S  ∈ and any coalition T 2 N ∈ , if there is a coalition Λ 2 N ∈ such that B S T Λ ( , ) ∈ and X Λ ⊆ , then X T ∩ ≠ ∅. Proof. We proceed by double implication. ⇒): Consider a stable allocation X , an influential coalition S, and a coalition T. Assume that there exists B S T Λ ( , ) ∈ such that X Λ ⊆ and let us show that X T ∩ ≠ ∅. If we assume, on the contrary, that X T = ∩ ∅, then Y X T = ( \Λ) ∪ is an allocation such that Y X T \ = and X Y \ = Λ. Recall that B S T Λ ( , ) ∈ implies that T Λ =     and, then, . We must notice that the utility functions are additive on disjoint subsets. Implying that, for all subsets L L N , ′ ⊆ , if L L′ = ∩ ∅ then for any agent i, . Since X can be written as a disjoint union of the subsets X Y \ and X Y ∩ , for any i S ∈ , we have u . We deduce that the allocation Y can challenge X via the influential coalition S, which contradicts the fact that X is stable. Thus, for any influential coalition S and any coalition T, if there is B S T Λ ( , ) ∈ and X Λ ⊆ , then X T ∩ ≠ ∅. ⇐): Conversely, assume that for any influential coalition S and any coalition T , if there exist B S T Λ ( , ) ∈ and X Λ ⊆ , then, X T ∩ ≠ ∅. We need to show that X is a stable vaccine allocation. By definition, if X is not stable, then we can find an allocation Y and an influential coalition S such that Y challenges X via S. This means that for any We get a contradiction of the initial assumption, and we conclude that X is a stable allocation. given any influential coalition S and any allocation T N μ ( ) ∈ to confirm core vaccine allocations that we provided in Section 2.6. For clarity, we show in Example 1 an additional use of Theorem 1 in a simple two-dimensional vaccine allocation problem. More generally, using Theorem 1, it is straightforward to show that a vaccine allocation X N μ ( ) ∈ is not stable. We do not need to compare X with all allocations containing μ elements. Finding coalitions T and Λ containing fewer elements is enough to reach a nonstability result. However, showing the stability of an allocation requires more operations. One observation from Example 1 is that we can apply Theorem 1 by focusing on the coalitions T which do not intersect X . Such a coalition T must therefore be included in N X \ . Moreover, T cannot contain more elements than X , otherwise, we are sure that there does not exist Λ to be used with T in Theorem 1. In what follows, we formalize this alternative procedure of proving whether a vaccine allocation is stable. We need additional notations. Assume that μ is fixed in n {1, …, } and consider an allocation X N μ ( ) ∈ . Let n X be the integer defined by . Proposition 1 follows. is stable if and only if for any coalition X ⊆  and any coalition T N X ∈ , if T =     , T does not challenge . Proof. We proceed by double implication. ⇒): Assume that X is a stable vaccine allocation. Consider two coalitions  and T such that X ⊆  , T N X ∈ , and T =     . We want to show that T does not challenge . Assume on the contrary that T challenges . By Definition 1, there exists an influential coalition S  ∈ such that T challenges  via S. It follows that . Since X is a stable vaccine allocation, Theorem 1 yields that X T ∩ ≠ ∅. The latter is a contradiction, because by assumption, T N X ∈ . We conclude that T does not challenge . ⇐): Assume that for any coalition X ⊆  and any coalition T N X ∈ , if T =     , then T does not challenge . We need to show that X is a stable vaccine allocation. Consider S  ∈ , T 2 N ∈ , and assume that there exists a coalition . We want to show that X T ∩ ≠ ∅. Assume on the contrary that X T = ∩ ∅. . The latter implies that T =      and u T u ( ) > ( ) i i  for all i S ∈ , or T challenges  via S, which contradicts the initial assumption. Thus, T contains more elements than X , and we deduce that there is no coalition , which contradicts our assumption. This completes the proof. □ If there is a fixed number of μ doses of vaccine, Proposition 1 improves in some cases the procedure for checking the stability of a given allocation X N μ ( ) ∈ . Indeed, X is a stable vaccine allocation if no coalition of N X can challenge X . Formally, we must look for a subset     , and an influential coalition S X whose members unanimously prefer T X to X  . Thus, X is stable if we cannot find such coalitions X  , T X , and S X . Next, we provide a formal characterization of the set of stable vaccine allocations in any political economy. Before stating the result, we need the following notations. Let us denote: Given a coalition Λ, the set (Λ)  contains any coalition T such that T = Λ     and there exists an influential coalition S whose members unanimously prefer T to Λ. We refer to the elements of (Λ)  as coalitions of the same size as Λ that challenge Λ. The set Proof. We proceed by double inclusion. ⊆): Let X be a stable vaccine allocation. By definition, . For this purpose, consider a coalition . According to Theorem 1, we have , we must show that Y is a stable allocation. According to Theorem 1, it is sufficient to show that, for any influential coalition S and any coalition T | 13 N ( , )   as the set of coalition L N ⊆ such that for any L Λ ⊆ and any T N L ∈ , if T Λ =    , then T does not challenge Λ. Thus, we can obtain another characterization of core allocations similar to Theorem 2 using Proposition 1. Using Theorem 2, it is straightforward to show that there is no stable vaccine allocation in a game G N q μ u = , , { }, , ( ) question arises: what conditions on μ guarantee that the intersection N N μ ( , ) ( )   ∩ is nonempty? The answer to this question depends on the parameters of the vaccine allocation game. Although we do not provide a comprehensive answer to this question, we do characterize the number of vaccine doses μ* that guarantees the nonemptiness of denote the minimum number of vaccine doses that guarantees the nonemptiness of . Obviously, if Assume that the preference profile u ( ) i is fixed. Corollary 1 shows that μ E *( ) is the smallest number of doses for a stable vaccine allocation. be a political economy. Then, C E μ E ( , *( )) ≠ ∅, and C E μ ( , ) = ∅ for any μ μ E < *( ). The proof of Corollary 1 is straightforward. We illustrate the determination of μ E *( ) in the simple vaccine allocation problem in a political economy E N q = ( , , { }) i  described in Example 1. However, in addition of majority rule, we consider two other influence structures: Dictatorial rule-S  ∈ if and only S 1 ∈ ; and unanimity rule-S  ∈ if and only S = 3   . We check that for the dictatorial rule, as for majority rule, In this section, we assume that a society consisting of N n =   agents is partitioned into two nonempty and disjoint subsets (or subgroups) N 1 and N 2 . In addition, agents have in-group preferences, meaning that an agent derives more utility when a member of their subgroup is vaccinated than when a member of the other subgroup is vaccinated. Formally, N N N = 1 2 ∪ such that for any t {1, 2} ∈ , N t ≠ ∅ and N N = 1 2 ∩ ∅. For any agent i, let t i ( ) be the unique element of {1, 2} such that i N t i ( ) . The example discussed in Section 2.6 shows that a noninfluential group can be completely excluded from all stable vaccine allocations (see, e.g., Case 1B in Section 2.6.2). From a normative and ethical perspective, this situation may not be acceptable in several societies. We aim to examine the conditions under which social planners or political leaders can avoid such undesirable outcomes. In other words, we are interested in identifying conditions under which a vaccine allocation that is both stable and inclusive exists. In the scenario described above, such an inclusive allocation would need to provide opportunities for agents in both subgroups to receive vaccine doses. Below, we formally define two related concepts: inclusive vaccine allocations and balanced vaccine allocations. Definition 2. Let G ∈ be a vaccine allocation game involving a set N of agents partitioned into two nonempty subsets N 1 and N 2 . Consider a stable vaccine allocation X C G ( ) ∈ . 1) The allocation X is inclusive if X N 1 ∩ ≠ ∅ and X N 2 ∩ ≠ ∅. 2) The allocation X is balanced if for any allocation Y such that Y X =    , we have: An inclusive allocation is any allocation where a non-zero number of vaccines is provided to both groups of agents, while a balanced allocation is a special type of inclusive allocation, where vaccines are allocated such that the number of agents who receive a vaccine dose is almost the same in both groups. We are interested in the necessary and sufficient conditions which guarantee the existence of a stable and inclusive (resp. balanced) vaccine allocation. Our analysis covers both one-dimensional (Section 4.1) and multidimensional (Section 4.2) polarized societies. This section considers a one-dimensional spatial framework, which generalizes the examples discussed in Section 2.6. Agents have Euclidean preferences based on ideal points located on a line or horizontal axis. Figure 2 in Section 2.6.2 represents an example of the configuration of agents' ideal points in such a polarized society. In what follows, a vaccine allocation game G 1 ∈ is an array G N q μ u = , , { }, , ( ) such that for any t {1, 2} ∈ , N t ≠ ∅, N N = 1 2 ∩ ∅, and u ( ) i is a profile of one-dimensional Euclidean preferences over N μ ( ). Theorem 3 below provides a necessary and sufficient condition for the existence of a stable vaccine allocation when both the two subgroups are influential. Interestingly, there exists a unique stable allocation, and this allocation is inclusive and balanced. Proof. We first show that for any μ n < , there is no stable allocation. Fix μ n < . Any allocation X is such that N X N X . If N X 2 ∩ ≠ ∅, then let j N X 2 ∈ ∩ . Agent i is a member of N 1 , which is not in X , and j is a member of N 2 , which is in X . In the allocation Y X j i = ( \{ }) { } ∪ , a member of N 2 is replaced by a member of N 1 , and any member of N 1 prefers Y to allocation X . By assumption N 1  ∈ ; therefore, X is challenged by Y via N 1 , which proves that X is not a stable allocation. If N X 2 ∩ ≠ ∅, then N X 1 ∩ ≠ ∅. In this case, choose any k N 2 ∈ and set Z X i k = ( \{ }) { } ∪ . Following the same reasoning, any member of N 2 prefers Z to allocation X . By assumption N 2  ∈ . So, X is challenged by Z via N 2 , which implies that X is not a stable allocation. To complete the proof, it is clear that for μ N =  , the allocation X N = { } is stable. □ It is straightforward to show that the stable allocation derived from Theorem 3 is both inclusive and balanced since each agent receives a vaccine dose. Theorem 4 below provides the minimum number of vaccine doses necessary to achieve an inclusive and stable allocation when only one subgroup of the two subgroups in the society is influential. Theorem 4. If N 1  ∈ and N 2  ∉ , then the existence of an inclusive and stable allocation requires N + 1 1   vaccine doses. Under this condition, there is a stable vaccine allocation in which each agent in N 1 receives a dose, and at least one agent in N 2 receives a dose. Proof. Assume that N 1  ∈ and N 2  ∉ . We prove Theorem 4 in two steps. Step 1. Suppose that μ be an inclusive allocation. Then we necessarily have N X and by definition of an inclusive allocation, , and any member of N 1 prefers Y over X . Since N 1  ∈ by assumption, it follows that Y challenges X , and X is not a stable allocation. Step 2. Suppose that μ N + 1 1 ≥   , and show that there exists a stable and inclusive vaccine allocation. In a one-dimensional space, the ideal points of the agents lie on the same line. By assumption, the society is polarized. Therefore, the ideal points of the members of N 1 are grouped on one side and those of the members of N 2 on the other side. Consider the vaccine allocation X , which contains the agents associated with the first μ ideal points which appear when we follow the axis starting from the side containing the ideal points of the members of N 1 . It is straightforward that X N 2 ∩ ≠ ∅, since N X < 1    . The latter means that X is an inclusive vaccine allocation. Moreover, for any coalition X Λ ⊆ and T N X \ ⊆ such that T = Λ    , no agent i in N 1 prefers T to Λ because, according to the polarization hypothesis and the structure of X , the ideal point of an agent i N ∈ is closer to the ideal point of any member of X compared to that of any member of N X \ . It follows that N 2 contains the set of agents who prefer T to Λ. By assumption, N 2 is not an influential coalition. Hence, T does not challenge Λ. Thanks to Proposition 1, X is a stable vaccine allocation. Since X N 1 ∩ ≠ ∅ and X N 2 ∩ ≠ ∅, we can conclude that X is a stable and inclusive vaccine allocation. □ Finally, Theorem 5 below deals with the existence of stable and inclusive vaccine allocations when neither of the two subgroups in the society is influential. Theorem 5. Assume N 1  ∉ and N 2  ∉ . Then, for any μ 1 ≥ , the set of stable vaccine allocations is nonempty. Moreover, the existence of an inclusive and stable allocation requires at least two vaccine doses. Proof. We note that under the assumption of a polarized society in a one-dimensional space, there exist i in N 1 and j in N 2 such that: d q q d q q k N l N ( , ) = min{ ( , ) : and } i j k l 1 2 ∈ ∈ . We prove Theorem 5 in three steps. Step 1. For μ = 1, it is clear that we cannot have an inclusive vaccine allocation. In contrast, several vaccine allocations are stable. For instance, let the allocation X i = { } and consider another allocation . If t N 1 ∈ , then the members of N 2 unanimously prefer i to t, it follows that the agents who prefer t to i is a subset of N 1 , that is, a noninfluential coalition. Likewise, if t N 2 ∈ , then the members of N 1 unanimously prefer i to t, it follows that the agents who prefer t to i is a subset of N 2 , that is, a noninfluential coalition. Thus, no vaccine allocation Y can challenge X , then X is a stable vaccine allocation. Step 2. For μ = 2, we can determine a stable allocation containing two elements. Let us consider the allocation X i j = { , }. We show that X is stable. For instance, consider another allocation Y k l = { , }. If Y N 1 ⊆ , for instance, then any member of N 2 prefers X to Y ; since N N N \ = 2 1  ∉ , no influential coalition prefers Y to X , that is, X cannot be challenged. Likewise, if Y N 2 ⊆ , then X cannot be challenged. For the remaining case, X contains an element of N 1 and an element of N 2 . Without loss of generality, assume that k N 1 ∈ and l N 2 ∈ . No member of N 1 can prefer l to j. Likewise, no member of N 2 prefers k to i, that is, X cannot be challenged. We have proved that X is an inclusive and stable allocation for μ = 2. Step 3. More generally, for μ 2 ≥ , consider any allocation X N μ ( ) ∈ such as i j X { , } ⊆ . Then, X is an inclusive vaccine allocation since X N 1 ∩ ≠ ∅ and X N 2 ∩ ≠ ∅. We can use the same reasoning as above to show that X is a stable allocation. □ Remark that Theorems 3, 4, and 5 imply that the design of the influence structure  significantly affects the existence of a stable and inclusive vaccine allocation for a fixed number of doses μ. Theorem 3 proves that, in the case of perfect inclusion (where the vaccine supply is large enough to ensure all members of a society are able to receive a dose), it is always possible to implement a vaccine allocation which is stable, inclusive, and balanced. Theorem 4 demonstrates that the group which possesses the veto power has vaccine priority over the other group. Theorem 4 also implies that if the number of doses is not large enough to satisfy influential group members' demand for doses, then the vulnerable group receives no vaccine dose. According to Theorem 5, when neither group in society constitutes an influential coalition, the leader can always implement a stable and inclusive vaccine allocation as long as they can supply at least two doses. As we might expect, Theorem 5 does not imply that all stable vaccine allocations are inclusive. Indeed, as we illustrate in Case 3B in Section 2.6.2 when μ = 4, the core consists of four allocations among which only one stable vaccine allocation, N = {1, 2, 3, 4} 1 , is not inclusive since it does not include any agent in N = {5, 6, 7} 2 . An implication of Theorem 4 is that under majority rule, the majority group members have vaccine priority, and members of the minority group either receive nothing or receive the residual supply of doses. We should note that majority rule is just one of many constitutional arrangements covered by Theorem 4. In other constitutional arrangements where the minority group is influential (i.e., is able to veto any proposed vaccine allocation) then the minority group will have priority access to vaccine doses, while the majority group will receive the residual supply. We can also apply Theorems 3 and 5 to constitutional arrangements other than majority rule, as Theorem 3 includes influence structures similar to unanimity rules, and Theorem 5 covers constitutional arrangements in which neither group has decisive power. When constitutional arrangements are such that neither group has decisive power, it requires that any coalition must include members of both groups to be influential. Such constitutional arrangements can be viewed as inclusive and generally have a multicameral representation (Guemmegne & Pongou, 2014; Taylor & Zwicker, 1993) . Under such arrangements, it takes two vaccine doses to achieve an inclusive and stable vaccine allocation. Therefore, our analysis reveals that it is always possible to design the decision-making rule of the political economy to implement a vaccine allocation that is both stable and inclusive. Under such a rule, the composition of any group endowed with the veto power should necessarily reflect the diversity of the society. In a multidimensional polarized society, searching for an inclusive or balanced stable vaccine allocation is cumbersome. Indeed, in a high-dimensional space, the ideal points can have a disparate configuration. A simple approach is to choose among the stable allocations, those that are inclusive. To prove the existence of stable vaccine allocations in multidimensional polarized societies, we define the sets be a political economy. For any μ > 0, denote by C E μ ( , ) in (respectively, C E μ ( , )) ba the set of inclusive (respectively, balanced) and stable vaccine allocations. Also, let μ E L L N *( ) = min{ : . Proposition 2 follows Theorem 2 and Corollary 1. be a political economy. Then, the following assertions hold: (1) C E μ E ( , *( )) One can show that μ E *( ) ba is greater than μ E *( ) in , implying that implementing a stable and balanced allocation is more demanding than enacting a vaccine allocation that is both stable and inclusive. This is not surprising since any balanced vaccine allocation is inclusive, whereas the converse is generally not true. Also, note that the number of vaccine doses necessary to implement a stable vaccine allocation is smaller than the number of doses needed to reach a stable and inclusive allocation or a stable and balanced allocation. These observations imply that fragmented societies which cannot acquire a sufficiently large number of vaccine doses will find it challenging to implement vaccine allocation policies that are both stable and inclusive. In such societies, majority group members will have vaccine priority at the disadvantage of minority factions. One can test the predictions of the model using data on vaccine coverage in fragmented societies which differ in terms of their economic or technological ability to produce or acquire doses. Our primary motivation is to examine stable and inclusive vaccine allocation policies in a political economy. Stable vaccine allocations represent policies that a political leader could implement without losing popularity. Our model assumes that individuals are organized around distinct groups or networks and have weighted other-regarding preferences. These preferences imply that utility derived from vaccinated agents depends on the agent's identity. Given the protective nature of vaccines, we assume that an agent's satisfaction increases as their group's members get vaccinated even if this individual does not receive a dose themselves. A straightforward rationale behind this assumption is that an agent's likelihood of getting infected by the virus decreases as the vaccinated population in their group increases, as agents interact with those within their group more frequently than with those outside their group. First, we characterize stable vaccine allocations in any political economy. Our analysis shows that the existence of a stable vaccine allocation depends on the vaccine supply. In particular, a stable vaccine allocation may not exist if vaccine supply is very low relative to the number of eligible individuals. Our results imply that there exists a minimum number of doses that guarantees the existence of a stable allocation. This number depends on the society's influence structure and the configuration of individual preferences. Second, to study the existence of allocations that are both stable and inclusive, we extend our analysis to polarized societies partitioned into two distinct and disjoint groups, where individuals have in-group preferences. We characterize the set of stable and inclusive vaccine allocations, as well as the set of stable and balanced allocations, where a balanced allocation is an allocation that achieves perfect inclusion. These characterizations imply that the number of vaccine doses necessary to generate a stable and balanced allocation is greater than the number of doses necessary to obtain a stable and inclusive allocation. Similarly, the number of doses needed to achieve a stable and inclusive allocation is greater than the number of doses needed to achieve a stable allocation. These findings mean that solving the problem of vaccine inclusiveness in a fragmented society which does not have the means to acquire a sufficiently high number of vaccine doses is a challenging task. When inclusiveness fails, any stable vaccine allocation favors the majority group. Our findings also demonstrate the critical role of the economy's influence structure in implementing vaccine inclusiveness. Importantly, these results imply that one can design an influence structure to implement a stable allocation that is inclusive. In this case, the composition of any influential coalition must include members of all groups, thus reflecting the society's diversity. Our findings imply that polarized societies which are unable to obtain a large number of vaccine doses will be less likely to implement vaccine allocation policies that include underrepresented groups or communities without influence. Optimal targeted lockdowns in a multigroup SIR model An economic framework for vaccine prioritization Cooperative games with coalition structures Vaccine passports roll out, and so do unruly anti-vaccine protests. The New York Times A theory of measuring, electing and ranking How lasting is voter gratitude? An analysis of the short-and long-term electoral returns to beneficial policy A diverse cabinet is great, but can Boris Johnson's team actually deliver policies which reflect our diversity? The effect of COVID-19 lockdowns on political support: Some good news for democracy? Optimal age-and sex-based management of the queue to ventilators during the covid-19 crisis Optimal lockdown in altruistic economies The economics of epidemics and contagious diseases: An introduction Multiwinner approval rules as apportionment methods Prosociality predicts health behaviors during the COVID-19 pandemic Market design to accelerate COVID-19 vaccine supply Identity during a crisis: COVID-19 and ethnic divisions in the United States Models of other-regarding preferences, inequality, and redistribution Other-regarding preferences in general equilibrium Literature review: The vaccine supply chain Dose-optimal vaccine allocation over multiple populations Divided we stay home: Social distancing and ethnic diversity An ethical framework for global vaccine allocation A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation A numerical method to determine a degressive proportional distribution of seats in the European Parliament Priority classes and weighted constrained equal awards rules for the claims problem COVID-19 vaccine challenges: What have we learned so far and what remains to be done? The distribution of power in the Optimal lockdowns for COVID-19 pandemics: Analyzing the efficiency of sanitary policies in Europe Solutions to general non-zero-sum games Trust in government increased during the Covid-19 pandemic in Australia and New Zealand Cost-benefit analysis of age-specific deconfinement strategies Economic development with deadly communicable diseases and public prevention COVID-19 epidemic and mitigation policies: Positive and normative analyses in a neoclassical growth model A po2licy-based rationalization of collective rules: Dimensionality, specialized houses, and decentralized authority Myopic voters and natural disaster policy Model with transmission delays for COVID-19 control: Theory and empirical assessment Proportional representation and fair representation in the European Parliament. Area New quota-based apportionment methods: The allocation of delegates in the Republican presidential primary Non-manipulable division rules in claim problems and generalizations The handbook of experimental economics A net benefit approach for the optimal allocation of a covid-19 vaccine Designing advance market commitments for new vaccines Global governance for covid-19 vaccines Vaccine inequity: Inside the cutthroat race to secure doses Vaccine hesitancy: Definition, scope and determinants Understanding COVID-19 vaccine hesitancy Dominance in spatial voting with imprecise ideals Optimizing vaccine allocation for COVID-19 vaccines shows the potential role of single-dose vaccination Optimal vaccine allocation for the early mitigation of pandemic influenza Optimizing influenza vaccine distribution Optimal allocation of pandemic influenza vaccine depends on age, risk and timing Stable allocations of vaccines in a political economy The ethics of COVID-19 vaccine distribution Difficult trade-offs in response to covid-19: The case for open and inclusive decision making Political games. Naval Research Logistics Quarterly Fair allocation of vaccines, ventilators and antiviral treatments: Leaving no ethical value behind in health care rationing Pandemic elections and the Covid-safe effect: Incumbents re-elected in six Covid-19 safe havens Round-robin political tournaments: Abstention, truthful equilibria, and effective power Laissez-faire, social networks, and race in a pandemic Optimal interventions in networks during a pandemic Incorporating fairness into game theory and economics Optimal allocation of limited vaccine to control an infectious disease: Simple analytical conditions Optimal federal transfers during uncoordinated response to a pandemic Unifying voting theory from Nakamura's to Greenberg's theorems A comparison of power indices and a non symmetric generalization Equity metrics: Toward a more effective and inclusive pandemic response Reserving coronavirus disease 2019 vaccines for global access: Cross sectional analysis Weighted voting, multicameral representation, and power Executive order on diversity, equity, inclusion, and accessibility in the federal workforce Vaccine hesitancy in the era of COVID-19 Core allocations for cooperation problems in vaccination Allocating vaccines in a pandemic: the ethical dimension Innovation policy and the market for vaccines Fairness versus efficiency of vaccine allocation strategies Leave no one behind: Ensuring access to COVID-19 vaccines for refugee and displaced populations Vaccine and inclusion We express our gratitude to Editor Rabah Amir, an Associate Editor, and two anonymous referees for insightful and constructive comments and suggestions that have helped improve the paper. We also wish to thank Andrew Dormer for excellent research assistance. Roland Pongou acknowledges generous research support from the Government of Ontario under ERA grant 400201-190299-2001, the SSHRC's Partnership Engage Grants COVID-19 Special Initiative (PEG 231377-190299-2001, and the SSHRC's Insight Grant 231415-190299-2001. The authors declare no conflicts of interest. http://orcid.org/0000-0003-3567-4219