key: cord-0885778-qqemspha authors: Baik, Kyung Hwan; Lee, Jong Hwa; Lee, Seokho title: Endogenous timing in three-player Tullock contests date: 2022-03-28 journal: Soc Choice Welfare DOI: 10.1007/s00355-022-01396-5 sha: 60ad4df0c96dd17471e3ee3614a14118c31afcf9 doc_id: 885778 cord_uid: qqemspha We study a three-player Tullock contest in an endogenous-timing framework, focusing on the players’ decisions on timing of effort exertion. In this model, there are two points in time at which the players may choose their effort levels. The players decide independently and announce simultaneously when they each will expend their effort, and then each player chooses her effort level at the point in time which she announced. We find that, given moderate asymmetries among the players, each of the players announces the first point in time, and thus they all choose their effort levels simultaneously at the first point in time. This finding is in sharp contrast to a well-known result obtained from two-player asymmetric contests with endogenous timing. A situation in which individuals or groups of individuals or organizations compete by expending effort or resources to win a prize, which is referred to as a contest, is common in the real world. An example is an election in which candidates compete to be the president of a country. Another example is a rent-seeking contest in which firms compete to win rents created by government protection or those generated We are grateful to Chris Baik, Amy Baik Lee, Wooyoung Lim, David A. Malueg, three anonymous referees, and the associate editor in charge of the paper for their helpful comments and suggestions. by governmental trade policies. Yet another example is a patent-seeking contest in which firms or researchers compete to obtain a patent. Other examples of a contest include litigation, various sporting contests, competition for college admission, and competition for a job or promotion to a higher rank. A strand of the literature on contests deals with endogenous timing of effort exertion in contests. In this strand of the literature, a well-known result is that the contestants choose their effort levels sequentially. Specifically, the seminal papers of Baik and Shogren (1992) and Leininger (1993) consider two-player asymmetric contests in which there are two points in time at which the players may choose their effort levels; the players decide independently and announce simultaneously when they each will expend their effort, and then each player chooses her effort level at the point in time which she announced. They show that the weak player-in terms of the players' composite strength determined by their valuations for the prize and their relative abilities-announces the first point in time while the strong player announces the second point in time; accordingly, the weak player chooses her effort level before the strong player. 1 The intuition behind this result is as follows. Note first the following fact obtained in the effort-expending stage: Around the intersection of the players' reaction functions, the weak player's reaction function is decreasing in the strong player's effort level (measured along the horizontal axis) while the strong player's reaction function is increasing in the weak player's effort level. To put this differently, around the intersection, the weak player regards her effort as a strategic substitute to the strong player's while the strong player regards her effort as a strategic complement to the weak player's. 2 Given this fact, the weak player wants to take the leadership role in the effort-expending stage because she, as the leader, can show the strong player her commitment-in the form of exerting low effort-to avoid a big costly fight. On the other hand, the strong player wants to concede the leadership role because she, as the follower, can compete efficiently against the weak player by responding with an appropriate level of effort to the weak player's challenge. Surprisingly, what the players want to do is perfectly compatible, and is actually carried out. Now, a natural question that arises is: What happens if another player is present in such contests? Do the players in three-player contests choose their effort levels in some sequential manner? In particular, is there any player that wants to concede the leadership role and actually chooses her effort level after some other player? To address these questions, we study a three-player Tullock contest in an endogenous-timing framework, focusing on the players' decisions on timing of 1 This result can also be stated as follows: The underdog chooses her effort level before the favorite. Here the underdog (the favorite) is defined as the player who has a probability of winning less (greater) than one-half at the Nash equilibrium of a two-player asymmetric contest in which the players choose their effort levels simultaneously (see Dixit 1987) . This result is empirically supported by Boyd and Boyd (1995) , who use data from the track and field events held at the 1992 Summer Olympics in Barcelona, Spain. Also, it is experimentally supported by Baik et al. (1999) , who examine subjects' behavior in a laboratory environment in which subjects are given enough time to think about their strategies. 2 The terms strategic substitute and strategic complement are defined in Bulow et al. (1985) . effort exertion. In this model, as in those of Baik and Shogren (1992) and Leininger (1993) , each player's valuation for the prize is exogenously fixed and publicly known, and the players' relative abilities to convert effort into probability of winning are also publicly known. There are two points in time at which the players may choose their effort levels. Each player chooses her effort level at either of the two points, but not at both points. The players play the following game. First, the players decide independently and announce simultaneously whether they each will expend their effort at the first point in time or at the second point in time. Then, knowing when the players choose their effort levels, each player independently chooses her effort level at the point in time which she announced. A player who chooses her effort level at the second point in time knows exactly what happened at the first point in time. Three-player contests in which the players' order of moves is endogenously determined are easily observed in the real world. One example may arise in three-candidate competition for presidential office. Given two time periods, the early period and the late period, in which the candidates may hold their election campaigns, the candidates first decide and announce when they will hold their (main) campaigns, and then actually run their campaigns according to their announced campaign schedules. 3 Another example may arise in three-firm patent competition with two time periods, the early period and the late period. The firms first announce (and commit to) when they will undertake their (main) research activities, and then carry out their research activities according to their announced research plans. Indeed, recently, we observed that vaccine makers first announced their development plans for vaccines for COVID-19 and then actually expended their effort according to their announced plans. We find that, given moderate asymmetries among the players, the game has a unique subgame-perfect equilibrium, where each of the players announces the first point in time, and thus they all choose their effort levels simultaneously at the first point in time. This finding is in sharp contrast to the aforementioned well-known result obtained from two-player asymmetric contests with endogenous timing. Indeed, given moderate asymmetries among the players, the presence of an additional player makes a big difference in the equilibrium timing of effort exertion. More detailed explanations for the main result will be given later in Sects. 4 and 5, but here it is desirable to give a brief explanation for it. In the three-player contest, if a player were to announce the second point in time, then she would suffer seriously from the second-mover disadvantage in the effort-expending stage because the leaders, if any, would not restrain themselves due to intense competition between themselves. On the other hand, if the player announces the first point in time, then she may exercise strategic leadership and enjoy a first-mover advantage in the effortexpending stage or, at least, she will compete with the other players on equal footing in the effort-expending stage. Consequently, the player is better off by announcing the first point in time rather than the second point in time. Other papers which study endogenous timing in contests include Nitzan (1994) , Morgan (2003 ), Fu (2006 , Konrad and Leininger (2007) , Hoffmann and Rota-Graziosi (2012) , and Baik and Lee (2013) . All these papers, except Konrad and Leininger (2007) , study contests in which just two contestants compete for a prize. Konrad and Leininger (2007) use an all-pay-auction contest success function, Hoffmann and Rota-Graziosi (2012) use a general contest success function, and the rest use logit-form contest success functions. In Nitzan (1994) , Konrad and Leininger (2007) , and Baik and Lee (2013) , each player's valuation for the prize is exogenously fixed and publicly known at the start of the game. In Morgan (2003) and Fu (2006) , however, it is drawn from a probability distribution-which is publicly known at the start of the game-after the players announce when they will expend their effort. The realized valuations are revealed to both players, in Morgan (2003) , while the realized common valuation is revealed to only one of the two players, in Fu (2006) . By contrast, in Hoffmann and Rota-Graziosi (2012), the players' common valuation for the prize is endogenously determined, depending only on their effort levels, and the "valuation function" is known to the players at the start of the game. These papers all show that the contestants choose their effort levels sequentially. Specifically, Fu (2006) shows that the uninformed player chooses her effort level before the informed player. Considering a contest, or an all-pay auction, in which each player's cost function is a general convex function of effort, Konrad and Leininger (2007) show that the player with the lowest cost of effort typically chooses her effort level late while the other players each choose their effort levels either early or late. Hoffmann and Rota-Graziosi (2012) show that in some cases the players choose their effort levels sequentially while in others they do so simultaneously. Baik and Lee (2013) consider a two-player contest in which the players hire delegates and announce simultaneously their contracts, then the delegates decide independently and announce simultaneously whether they each will expend their effort at the first point in time or at the second point in time, and finally each delegate chooses his effort level at the point in time which he announced. They show that the weak delegate, or the delegate with less contingent compensation, announces the first point in time while the strong delegate announces the second point in time, and thus the weak delegate chooses his effort level before the strong delegate. This paper is related also to the literature on endogenous timing in an oligopoly (model). Reinganum (1985) , Gal-Or (1985) , Dowrick (1986) , Boyer and Moreaux (1987) , and Robson (1990) study endogenous role selection in a duopoly. Hamilton and Slutsky (1990) study endogenous timing in two duopoly games, the extended game with observable delay and the extended game with action commitment. Deneckere et al. (1992) examine the incentives to lead and follow in a price-setting game in which two firms have loyal consumer segments, and then examine two games of timing of price announcements. Matsumura (1999) studies endogenous sequencing in a quantitysetting oligopoly model with n firms. In his model, there are m periods in which the firms may choose their output levels. He shows that, in every pure-strategy equilibrium, at least n − 1 firms choose their output levels simultaneously in the first period. Hoffmann and Rota-Graziosi (2020) generalize "the extended game with observable delay" in Hamilton and Slutsky (1990) , and study endogenous timing when the payoff or the marginal payoff of a player becomes non-monotonic with respect to the opponent's strategy. The paper proceeds as follows. In Sect. 2, we present the model of a three-player contest and set up a two-stage game. In Sect. 3, we analyze the proper subgames starting at the second stage, and obtain each player's equilibrium effort levels and expected payoffs in these subgames. Section 4 looks at the first stage in which the players decide independently and announce simultaneously when they each will expend their effort, and obtains the subgame-perfect equilibrium of the full game. In Sect. 5, we first study a two-player contest in an endogenous-timing framework, and then compare the equilibrium timing of effort exertion in this two-player contest with that in the three-player contest. Section 6 considers variations of the main model presented in Sect 2, and discusses restrictions on the parameters imposed by Assumption 2. Finally, Sect. 7 offers our conclusions. Consider a contest in which three risk-neutral players, 1 through 3, compete with each other by expending irreversible effort to win a prize. The players' valuations for the prize may differ. Their abilities to convert effort into probability of winning also may differ. There are two points in time, points 1 and 2, at which the players may choose their effort levels. Each player chooses her effort level at either of the two points, but not at both points. The players play the following game. First, the players decide independently and announce simultaneously whether they each will expend their effort at point 1 or at point 2. Then, knowing when the players choose their effort levels, each player independently chooses her effort level at the point in time which she announced. A player, if any, who chooses her effort level at point 2 observes the effort levels, if any, chosen at point 1 before she does. Let N ≡ {1, 2, 3} denote the set of the players. Let v i , for i ∈ N , denote player i's valuation for the prize. We assume that each player's valuation for the prize is positive and publicly known at the start of the game. Without loss of generality, . Let x denote a 3-tuple vector of effort levels, one for each player: x ≡ (x 1 , x 2 , x 3 ). Then we assume the following contest success function for player i: where i > 0, 3 = 1 , and X = 1 x 1 + 2 x 2 + x 3 . 4 The parameter i indicates player i's ability in the contest relative to the other players. For example, j > k , for j, k ∈ N , means that player j has more ability than player k in that, ceteris paribus, if x j = x k > 0 , then player j's probability of winning is greater than player k's. We assume that the parameter i , for i ∈ N , is publicly known at the start of the game. Function (1) implies that, ceteris paribus, player i's probability of winning is increasing in her effort level at a decreasing rate; however, it is decreasing in a rival's effort level at a decreasing rate. Then w i is the product of player i's valuation for the prize and her ability parameter, and thus it indicates her "composite strength" in the contest relative to the other players. Assumption 1 We assume, without loss of generality, that w 1 ≥ w 2 ≥ w 3 = 1. We will make further assumptions on the parameters later, during the analysis, which may be considered as defining a three-player contest narrowly (see Assumption 2). Let i denote the expected payoff for player i. Then the payoff function for player i is: 5 We formally consider the following game. In the first stage, each player chooses independently between Point 1 and Point 2. The players announce (and commit to) their choices simultaneously (or, equivalently, without knowing their rivals' choices). In the second stage, after knowing when the players choose their effort levels, each player independently chooses her effort level at the point in time which she announced in the first stage. 6 A player, if any, who chooses her effort level at point 2 observes the effort levels, if any, chosen at point 1 before she does. At the end of this stage, the winner is determined. We assume that the structure of the game is common knowledge among the players. We employ subgame-perfect equilibrium as the solution concept. ( To obtain a subgame-perfect equilibrium of the game, we work backward. In this section, we analyze the proper subgames starting at the second stage, and obtain each player's equilibrium effort levels and expected payoffs in these subgames. Then, in Section 4, we look at the players' decisions, in the first stage, on when to expend their effort. 7 There are eight proper subgames which start at the second stage, but we need to analyze the following seven subgames: a simultaneous-move subgame and six sequential-move subgames. 8 A simultaneous-move subgame arises when the three players choose and announce the same point in time, either Point 1 or Point 2, in the first stage. If player i, for i ∈ N , announces Point 1 but the rest announce Point 2, then the iL sequential-move subgame arises. 9 Finally, the jkL sequential-move subgame, for j = 1 , 2 and k = 2 , 3 with j ≠ k , arises when players j and k announce Point 1 but the remaining player announces Point 2. 10 In this subgame, the players choose their effort levels simultaneously and independently. Accordingly, player i, for i ∈ N , seeks to maximize i in (2) over her effort level x i , given her belief about the other players' effort levels. From the first-order condition for maximizing i , we first derive player i's reaction function (see Appendix A). 11 Then, using the players' reaction functions, we obtain a unique Nash equilibrium, which is denoted by the vector x S ≡ (x S 1 , x S 2 , x S 3 ). Next, substituting into (2) the players' equilibrium effort levels, we obtain player i's expected payoff S i at the Nash equilibrium. We report them in Lemma A in Appendix A. It is straightforward to check that, under Assumption 1, all the players are active-that is, they expend positive effort-at the Nash equilibrium if and only if w 1 + w 2 > w 1 w 2 . Fix player i, for i ∈ N . In this subgame, player i first chooses her effort level at point 1. Then, after observing player i's effort level, the rest choose their effort levels simultaneously and independently at point 2. Let x iL h , for h ∈ N , denote player h's effort level specified in an equilibrium of the iL sequential-move subgame. Let iL h denote player h's expected payoff in the equilibrium. We obtain and report them in Appendix B. It is straightforward to check that, under Assumption 1, all the players are active in the equilibrium of the iL sequential-move subgame if and only if w 1 (w 2 + 1) < w 2 + 2 for i = 1, w 1 w 2 < 2 for i = 2 , and w 1 + w 2 > w 1 w 2 for i = 3. Fix players j and k, for j = 1 , 2 and k = 2 , 3 with j ≠ k . In this subgame, players j and k first choose their effort levels simultaneously and independently at point 1. Then, after observing their effort levels, the remaining player chooses her effort level at point 2. Let x jkL h , for h ∈ N , denote player h's effort level specified in an equilibrium of the jkL sequential-move subgame. Let jkL h denote player h's expected payoff in the equilibrium. We obtain and report them in Appendix C. It is straightforward to check that, under Assumption 1, all the players are active in the equilibrium of the jkL sequential-move subgame if and only if w 1 + w 2 > 1.5w 1 w 2 for jk = 12, w 1 < 2 for jk = 13 , and w 2 < 2 for jk = 23. We consider the first stage of the full game in which the players each announce when to expend their effort. Which point in time does each player choose and announce in a subgame-perfect equilibrium of the full game? In the first stage, each player has perfect foresight about the equilibrium of every second-stage subgame, and thus about the players' second-stage equilibrium expected payoffs reported in Lemmas A through C. Figure 1 illustrates the strategic interaction among the players in the first stage. Panel A of Fig. 1 illustrates it when player 3 announces Point 1 in the first stage, while panel B illustrates it when player 3 announces Point 2. For example, if player 3 announces Point 1 but the rest announce Point 2, then the 3L sequential-move subgame will arise, which will lead to the payoff vector ( 3L 1 , 3L 2 , 3L 3 ) in panel A. We restrict our analysis to cases where all three players are active in the equilibrium of every second-stage subgame (see Sect. 6.2). It follows from the assumptions stated in Lemmas A through C that, under Assumption 1, these cases occur if and only if Assumption 2 holds. Assumption 2 We assume that w 1 (w 2 + 1) < w 2 + 2 and w 1 + w 2 > 1.5w 1 w 2 . Note that these two inequalities in Assumption 2 come from the assumptions stated in part (i) of Lemmas B and that of Lemma C, respectively. Figure 2 illustrates the values of w 1 and w 2 (or, equivalently, 1 1 and 2 2 ), which satisfy both Assumption 1 and Assumption 2. In other words, at the values of w 1 and w 2 located in the shaded area of Fig. 2 , all three players are active in the equilibrium of every second-stage subgame. Note that the northeast part of the shaded area is bounded by the "active-players-in-equilibrium condition" for the 1L sequential-move subgame, w 1 (w 2 + 1) < w 2 + 2 , and that for the 12L sequential-move subgame, w 1 + w 2 > 1.5w 1 w 2 . Now, we compare, for each player, the second-stage equilibrium expected payoffs reported in Lemmas A through C. Under Assumptions 1 and 2, it is straightforward to obtain Lemma 1. Lemma 1 Under Assumptions 1 and 2, we obtain: Suppose, for example, that players 2 and 3 each announce Point 1. In this case, if player 1 also announces Point 1, then a simultaneous-move subgame will arise, which will lead to S 1 for her. If instead player 1 announces Point 2, then the 23L sequential-move subgame will arise, which will lead to 23L 1 for her. Part (a) says that S 1 > 23L 1 . Suppose, for another example, that players j and k each, for j = 1 , 2 and k = 2 , 3 with j ≠ k , announce Point 2. In this case, if the remaining player, player i, also announces Point 2, then a simultaneous-move subgame will arise, which will lead to S i for her. If instead player i announces Point 1, then the iL sequential-move subgame will arise, which will lead to x iL i for her. Lemma 1 says that iL i > S i , for i ∈ N . This comparison result can be easily understood because, in the iL sequentialmove subgame, player i is the first mover, and thus one of her options is to receive the payoff S i by choosing her effort level at the Nash equilibrium of a simultaneousmove subgame. Note that Lemma 1 holds even for the case where the three players have equal composite strength: w 1 = w 2 = w 3 = 1. 12 Using Lemma 1, we obtain the following result regarding the players' decisions on timing of effort exertion. Under Assumptions 1 and 2 , for every player, Point 1 leads to a higher second-stage equilibrium expected payoff than does Point 2, no matter what the other players announce in the first stage. Consequently, under Assumptions 1 and 2, the game has a unique subgame-perfect equilibrium in which every player announces Point 1 in the first stage. The result that player i, for i ∈ N , announces Point 1 in the first stage, no matter what the other players announce, can be explained as follows. Consider first the case where the other players both announce Point 1. Player i has two options: either to announce Point 1 or to announce Point 2. If she announces Point 1, then she will compete with the other players on equal footing in the effort-expending stage: The three players will choose their effort levels simultaneously and independently at point 1. On the other hand, if player i announces Point 2, then she, as the only follower, will suffer seriously from the second-mover disadvantage in the effortexpending stage: She will face the aggressive leaders because the leaders themselves will compete and choose high effort levels at point 1. 13 Accordingly, given that the other players both announce Point 1, player i also announces Point 1. Next, consider the case where the other players announce different points in time: Player j announces Point 1, while player k announces Point 2, for j, k ∈ N ⧵ {i} with j ≠ k . In this case, if player i announces Point 1, then she will be one of the two leaders in the effort-expending stage; however, if she announces Point 2, then she will be one of the two followers. Since a first-mover advantage exists in the effortexpending stage, player i is better off by announcing Point 1 rather than Point 2. Finally, consider the case where the other players both announce Point 2. In this case, too, player i is better off by announcing Point 1 rather than Point 2. The intuition is obvious. Given that the other players both announce Point 2, if player i announces Point 1, then she will exercise strategic leadership and enjoy a firstmover advantage in the effort-expending stage. However, if player i announces Point 2, then she will play a simultaneous-move game with the other players in the effortexpending stage, which will result in a smaller expected payoff to player i as compared to player i's announcing Point 1. 14 In this section, we first study briefly a two-player contest in an endogenous-timing framework. Then we compare the equilibrium timing of effort exertion in this two-player contest with that in the three-player contest analyzed in the preceding sections. 13 In this context, we mean that x jkL j > x S j and x jkL k > x S k , for j, k ∈ N ⧵ {i} with j ≠ k . It is straightforward to check that these inequalities hold in the case where w 1 = w 2 = 1. 14 Note that, if player i announces Point 1, one of her options in the effort-expending stage is to choose her effort level at the Nash equilibrium of the simultaneous-move subgame. Consider a contest which is the same as the one in Sect. 2 with the exception that now only player h, for h = 1 or 2, and player 3 compete to win a prize. Specifically, consider the following game. In the first stage, each player chooses independently between Point 1 and Point 2. The players announce (and commit to) their choices simultaneously. In the second stage, after knowing when the players choose their effort levels, each player independently chooses her effort level at the point in time which she announced in the first stage. A player who chooses her effort level at point 2 observes the effort levels chosen at point 1 before she does. Now that the analysis is similar to that in Sects. 3 and 4, it is relegated to Appendix D. As shown in Appendix D, under the assumption that 1 < w h < 2 , we obtain the following result on the players' decisions on timing of effort exertion. 15 Remark 1 Under Assumption 1 and the assumption that 1 < w h < 2 , in equilibrium, player 3 announces Point 1, while player h announces Point 2. Remark 1 implies that the weak player (in terms of composite strength) chooses her effort level before the strong player. The intuition behind this well-known result has been explained in Sect. 1 (see also Baik and Lee 2013) , and therefore is omitted. What happens if another player is present in the contest? According to Proposition 1, in the three-player contest with the restrictions on the parameters by Assumption 2, each of the players announces Point 1, and thus they all choose their effort levels simultaneously at point 1. Since we have provided, below Proposition 1, the detailed intuition behind this result, here we briefly explain why we do not obtain a result similar to Remark 1. Suppose, similarly to Remark 1, that the weakest player announces Point 1-that is, she chooses to be the leader in the effort-expending stage-while the remaining players announce Point 2. Given the restrictions on the parameters by Assumption 2, unlike in the two-player contest, each of the followers could not compete efficiently against the weakest player (or the leader)-in other words, the weakest player would not trigger a softened response from each of the followers-because the followers themselves engage in intense competition. This would make each of the followers not gain such advantage that the follower in the two-player contest can obtain. Further, this would lead to each of the followers deviating from Point 2 to Point 1. 16 Indeed, in the three-player contest with the restrictions on the parameters by Assumption 2, none of the players announce that they will be (possible) followers. A follower, if any, would compete with either two leaders or one leader and another follower. In both cases, she would suffer seriously from the second-mover disadvantage, facing the opponents who would not restrain themselves due to more intense competition, compared to the two-player contest. We consider a model (modified from the main model presented in Sect. 2) in which there are n players, where n > 3 . Let N + ≡ {1, ..., n} denote the set of the players. Without loss of generality, let v i = i v n for i ∈ N + , where i > 0 and n = 1 , and let v n = 1 . We assume the following contest success function for player i: where i > 0, n = 1 , and X = ∑ n z=1 z x z . Let w i ≡ i i v n . Assumption 1 in Sect. 2 is now replaced with Assumption 3 below. We assume, without loss of generality, that w 1 ≥ w 2 ≥ . . . ≥ w n = 1. As in Sect. 2, we consider the following game. In the first stage, the players each choose independently between Point 1 and Point 2, and announce their choices simultaneously. In the second stage, after knowing when the players choose their effort levels, each player independently chooses her effort level at the point in time which she announced in the first stage. A player who chooses her effort level at point 2 observes the effort levels chosen at point 1 before she does. We relegate the analysis to Appendix E. As shown in Appendix E, we obtain the following result on the players' decisions on timing of effort exertion. Assumption 3 and the assumption that n − 0.5 < ∑ n z=1 (1∕w z ) ≤ 2(n − 1)∕w 1 , a subgame-perfect equilibrium occurs in which each of the n players announces Point 1. Note that the second assumption in Remark 2 reflects the "active-players-inequilibrium condition" in (E14) and the condition (E15) under which no player has an incentive to deviate from her first-stage action, Point 1. Note also that, due to computational intractability, we merely find a subgame-perfect equilibrium, without checking its possible uniqueness, in which each of the n players announces Point 1. for X = 0 , In Sect. 4, we have assumed (Assumption 2) that all three players are active in the equilibrium of every second-stage subgame. Several explanations for this assumption are in order since it appears restrictive. First, a three-player contest may be defined as one in which all three players are active at the Nash equilibrium of a simultaneous-move game (or, in this paper, a simultaneous-move subgame). If so, the values of w 1 and w 2 that are relevant to our analysis are constrained by Assumption 1 and the "active-players-in-equilibrium condition" for a simultaneous-move subgame, w 1 + w 2 > w 1 w 2 (see Lemma A). Then, in Fig. 2 , these values are located in the area "bounded" by the horizontal line at w 2 = 1 , the 45 o line, and curve S that represents the equation w 1 + w 2 = w 1 w 2 . Second, Assumption 2, which may be considered as defining a three-player contest narrowly, enables us to complete the analysis of the first stage (see Lemma 1). Indeed, due to Assumption 2, we are able to compare, for each player, the secondstage equilibrium expected payoffs, and thereby to show explicitly that the game has a unique subgame-perfect equilibrium in which each of the three players announces Point 1 in the first stage. Third, it is straightforward to check that Remark 2 holds true for n = 3 . That is, it is straightforward to see that, under Assumption 1 and the assumption that 2.5 < ∑ 3 z=1 (1∕w z ) ≤ 4∕w 1 or, equivalently, 1.5w 1 w 2 < w 1 + w 2 ≤ (4 − w 1 )w 2 , a subgame-perfect equilibrium occurs in which each of the three players announces Point 1 in the first stage. In Fig. 2 , the values of w 1 and w 2 that satisfy these two assumptions are located in the shaded area and in area T. (The solid border line of area T represents the equation w 1 + w 2 = (4 − w 1 )w 2 .) Note that, unlike Assumption 2, the second assumption ensures only that all three players are active at the Nash equilibrium of a simultaneous-move subgame and in the equilibrium of the jkL sequentialmove subgame, for j = 1 , 2 and k = 2 , 3 with j ≠ k (see (E14) in Appendix E). Fourth, the values of w 1 and w 2 located in area K of Fig. 2 satisfy the following strict inequalities: 1.5w 1 w 2 < w 1 + w 2 and w 1 + w 2 > (4 − w 1 )w 2 . The first inequality ensures that all three players are active at the Nash equilibrium of a simultaneous-move subgame and in the equilibrium of the jkL sequential-move subgame, for j = 1 , 2 and k = 2 , 3 with j ≠ k . Satisfying the second inequality implies that there is at least one player who does not announce Point 1 in the first stage (see (E15) in Appendix E). Hence, at the values of w 1 and w 2 located in area K, the game has no subgame-perfect equilibrium in which each player announces Point 1 in the first stage. We have shown in Sect. 4 that, in the endogenous-timing framework, the three players all choose their effort levels simultaneously at point 1. An interesting question that arises is: If a contest organizer or the government could decide and enforce when the players will each expend their effort, what would the optimal timing of effort exertion be? We consider a variation of the main model in which the contest organizer chooses and enforces the timing of effort exertion which maximizes (or, alternatively, minimizes) the total effort expended by the players (see Baik 2013; Hinnosaar 2019) . 17 Formally, we consider the following game. In the first stage, the contest organizer decides and announces when the players will each choose their effort levels. In the second stage, after knowing who moves when, each player independently chooses her effort level at the point in time which the contest organizer assigned to her in the first stage. A player who chooses her effort level at point 2 observes the effort levels chosen at point 1 before she does. It seems to be computationally intractable to analyze this game with general values of the parameters, 1 , 2 , 1 , and 2 . Accordingly, we assume that 1 1 = 2 2 = 1 or, equivalently, w 1 = w 2 = 1. Table 1 shows, in this case, under which timing assumptions the total effort level is maximized and minimized, respectively. We obtain it from Lemmas A through C. In Table 1 , X S denotes the total effort level resulting when the players choose their effort levels simultaneously. In the table, X iL , for i ∈ N , denotes the total effort level resulting when player i chooses her effort level at point 1 and the rest choose their effort levels simultaneously at point 2. Finally, X jkL , for j = 1, 2 Table 1 Comparison of the total effort levels obtained under different timing assumptions when 1 1 = 2 2 = 1 Notes: Let i, j = 1 , 2 with i ≠j. Let G ≡ 22 j − 5 i − 5 1 2 , and let H ≡ −5 2 − 5 1 + 22 1 2 . Recall that 3 = 1 Lowest effort level and k = 2, 3 with j ≠ k , denotes the total effort level resulting when players j and k choose their effort levels simultaneously at point 1 and the remaining player chooses her effort level at point 2. Suppose, for example, that 1 > 2 > 3 . Table 1 shows, in this case, that the total effort level is maximized when player 3 chooses her effort level at point 1 and the rest choose their effort levels simultaneously at point 2. Therefore, if the contest organizer desires to maximize the total effort level, then she would announce this timing of effort exertion in the first stage. Suppose, for another example, that 1 = 2 = 3 . Table 1 shows, in this case, that the total effort level is minimized if the players choose their effort levels simultaneously. Therefore, if the contest organizer desires to minimize the total effort level, then she would announce this timing of effort exertion in the first stage. Hinnosaar (2019) studies sequential contests with identical players in which, at each point in time, the sum of the effort levels expended by the earlier movers is publicly disclosed. He shows that the total effort level is minimized in the simultaneous contest, and is maximized in the fully sequential contest. However, Table 1 indicates that the total effort level may not be minimized in the simultaneous contest if players are asymmetric. We have so far assumed that there are only two points in time at which the players may choose their effort levels. This two-point-in-time model has a limitation in that it excludes the possibility that each player announces a point in time which is different from the other players' choices. Hence, the model is vulnerable to criticism on the grounds that it examines sequentiality versus simultaneity without actually allowing full sequentiality. Here we briefly consider a model (modified from the main model presented in Sect. 2) in which there are three points in time (points 1, 2, and 3) at which the three players may choose their effort levels. Formally, we consider the following game. In the first stage, each of the three players chooses independently among Point 1, Point 2, and Point 3 . The players announce (and commit to) their choices simultaneously. In the second stage, after knowing when the players choose their effort levels, each player independently chooses her effort level at the point in time which she announced in the first stage. A player who chooses her effort level at point 2 or point 3 observes the effort levels previously chosen. At the end of this stage, the winner is determined. It is immediate from Remark 2 that, under Assumption 1 and the assumption that 1.5w 1 w 2 < w 1 + w 2 ≤ (4 − w 1 )w 2 or, equivalently, 2.5w 1 < 1 + w 1 + w 1 ∕w 2 ≤ 4 , there exists a subgame-perfect equilibrium in which each of the three players announces Point 1 in the first stage-that is, no player has an incentive to deviate from Point 1 to Point 2 or Point 3. 18 Due to computational intractability, we are unable to complete the full analysis. However, on the basis of the results obtained in Sect. 4 and those described in the following paragraph, we believe that, under Assumption 1 and the assumption that all three players are active in the equilibrium of every subgame starting at the second stage, the subgame-perfect equilibrium in which each of the three players announces Point 1 in the first stage is the only one. Assuming that 1 = 2 = 1 , we find the following (see also Lee 2007) . First, there exists no subgame-perfect equilibrium in which every player announces Point 3. Second, there exists no subgame-perfect equilibrium in which each player announces a point in time which is different from the other players' choices. We have studied a three-player Tullock contest in an endogenous-timing framework, focusing on the players' decisions on timing of effort exertion. In this model, there are two points in time, 1 and 2, at which the players may choose their effort levels. The players decide independently and announce simultaneously when they each will expend their effort, and then each player chooses her effort level at the point in time which she announced. Restricting our analysis to cases where all three players are active in the equilibrium of every second-stage subgame, we have shown that, in equilibrium, each of the players announces Point 1, and thus they all choose their effort levels simultaneously at point 1. This is in sharp contrast to a well-known result from two-player asymmetric contests studied in an endogenous-timing framework: In equilibrium, the weak player announces Point 1 and chooses her effort level at point 1 while the strong player announces Point 2 and chooses her effort level at point 2. We have elaborated on this contrast in Sect. 5. In Sect. 6, we have considered variations of the main model presented in Sect. 2: a model in which there are more than three players, a model in which a contest organizer decides and enforces when the three players will each expend their effort, and a model in which there are three points in time at which the three players may choose their effort levels. We have focused on the players' equilibrium decisions on timing of effort exertion. However, it would be interesting to examine how the players' effort levels in the subgame-perfect equilibrium respond when player k's valuation parameter k or her ability parameter k or her composite strength k k , for k = 1 , 2, changes, ceteris paribus (see Baik 1994) . One could, no doubt, perform these comparative statics using Lemma A. We have assumed that player i's valuation parameter i and her ability parameter i , for i ∈ N + , are publicly known. It would be interesting to study a model in which the players have incomplete information about these parameters. Perhaps more importantly, it would be interesting to experimentally investigate the main qualitative predictions of the three-player contest-specifically, the equilibrium timing of effort exertion and the equilibrium effort levels of the players. Further, it would be interesting to compare these experimental results with existing experimental studies of two-player asymmetric contests (see, for example, Baik et al. 1999) . We leave them for future research. Player 1 seeks to maximize 1 in (2) over her effort level x 1 , taking the other players' effort levels as given. From the first-order condition for maximizing 1 , we derive player 1's reaction function: It is straightforward to see that 1 in (2) is strictly concave in x 1 , which implies that the second-order condition for maximizing 1 is satisfied and player 1's best response to the other players' effort levels is unique. Similarly, we derive the reaction functions for players 2 and 3: and Using these three reaction functions, we obtain a unique Nash equilibrium. Next, substituting into (2) the players' effort levels at the Nash equilibrium, we obtain their equilibrium expected payoffs. Lemma A Assume that Assumption 1 holds and that w 1 + w 2 > w 1 w 2 . (a) The players' (positive) effort levels at a unique Nash equilibrium are: The players' expected payoffs at the Nash equilibrium are: S It is immediate from part (a) that, under Assumption 1, players 1 and 2 are always active at the Nash equilibrium, but player 3 is active at the Nash equilibrium if and only if w 1 + w 2 > w 1 w 2 . It is also immediate from part (a) that all the players are � . Similarly, we obtain the players' equilibrium effort levels and their equilibrium expected payoffs in the 2L and the 3L sequential-move subgame. Lemma B Assume that Assumption 1 holds. (i) Assuming that w 1 (w 2 + 1) < w 2 + 2 , we obtain the following in a unique equilibrium of the 1L sequential-move subgame. (a) The players' (positive) effort levels are: x 1L 1 = {w 2 1 (w 2 + 1) 2 − w 2 2 }∕4 1 w 2 (w 2 + 1), x 1L 2 = {2w 3 2 + w 2 2 − w 2 1 (w 2 + 1) 2 + 2w 1 w 2 2 (w 2 + 1)}∕4 2 w 2 (w 2 + 1) 2 , and x 1L 3 = {w 2 2 + 2w 2 − w 2 1 (w 2 + 1) 2 + 2w 1 (w 2 + 1)}∕4(w 2 + 1) 2 . (b) The players' expected payoffs are: 1L 1 = {w 1 (w 2 + 1) − w 2 } 2 ∕4 1 w 2 (w 2 + 1), 1L 2 = {2w 2 2 + w 2 − w 1 (w 2 + 1)} 2 ∕4 2 w 2 (w 2 + 1) 2 , and 1L 3 = {w 2 + 2 − w 1 (w 2 + 1)} 2 ∕4(w 2 + 1) 2 . (ii) Assuming that w 1 w 2 < 2 , we obtain the following in a unique equilibrium of the 2L sequential-move subgame. (a) The players' (positive) effort levels are: , and The players' expected payoffs are: 2L (iii) Assuming that w 1 + w 2 > w 1 w 2 , we obtain the following in a unique equilibrium of the 3L sequential-move subgame. (a) The players' (positive) effort levels are: The players' expected payoffs are: 3L 1 = {2w 2 1 + w 1 w 2 − (w 1 + w 2 )} 2 ∕4 1 w 1 (w 1 + w 2 ) 2 , 3L 2 = {2w 2 2 + w 1 w 2 − (w 1 + w 2 )} 2 ∕4 2 w 2 (w 1 + w 2 ) 2 , and 3L 3 = (w 1 + w 2 − w 1 w 2 ) 2 ∕4w 1 w 2 (w 1 + w 2 ). Fix players j and k, for j = 1 , 2 and k = 2 , 3 with j ≠ k . In this subgame, players j and k first choose their effort levels simultaneously and independently at point 1. Then, after observing their effort levels, the remaining player chooses her effort level at point 2. To solve for an equilibrium of the 12L sequential-move subgame, we work backward. At point 2, player 3 knows player 1's effort level, x 1 , and player 2's effort level, x 2 . Player 3 seeks to maximize 3 in (2) over her effort level x 3 . From the first-order condition for maximizing 3 , we derive player 3's strategy in any equilibrium: Next, consider point 1 at which players 1 and 2 choose their effort levels simultaneously and independently. Let j (x 1 , x 2 ) , for j = 1 , 2, be player j's expected (C1) Solving equation (C3) for x 1 , we obtain player 1's best response to player 2's effort level x 2 , which is denoted by x 1 (x 2 ). Player 1's reaction function is then x 1 = x 1 (x 2 ), the implicit form of which is given in equation (C3). Similarly, the implicit form of player 2's reaction function, x 2 = x 2 (x 1 ), is Using the reaction functions for players 1 and 2, or rather equations (C3) and (C4), we obtain the equilibrium effort levels of players 1 and 2, x 12L 1 and x 12L 2 , in the 12L sequential-move subgame. Substituting x 12L 1 and x 12L 2 into x 3 (x 1 , x 2 ) in (C1), we obtain player 3's equilibrium effort level x 12L 3 . Substituting into (2) the players' equilibrium effort levels, we obtain player h's equilibrium expected payoff 12L h , for h ∈ N. Similarly, we obtain the players' equilibrium effort levels and their equilibrium expected payoffs in the 13L and the 23L sequential-move subgame. Lemma C Assume that Assumption 1 holds. (i) Assuming that w 1 + w 2 > 1.5w 1 w 2 , we obtain the following in a unique equilibrium of the 12L sequential-move subgame. (a) The players' (positive) effort levels are: x 12L 1 = 9w 2 1 w 2 2 (2w 1 − w 2 )∕4 1 (w 1 + w 2 ) 3 , x 12L 2 = 9w 2 1 w 2 2 (2w 2 − w 1 )∕4 2 (w 1 + w 2 ) 3 , and x 12L 3 = 3w 1 w 2 (2w 1 + 2w 2 − 3w 1 w 2 )∕4(w 1 + w 2 ) 2 . (b) The players' expected payoffs are: 12L 1 = 3w 2 1 w 2 (2w 1 − w 2 ) 2 ∕4 1 (w 1 + w 2 ) 3 , 12L 2 = 3w 1 w 2 2 (2w 2 − w 1 ) 2 ∕4 2 (w 1 + w 2 ) 3 , and 12L 3 = (2w 1 + 2w 2 − 3w 1 w 2 ) 2 ∕4(w 1 + w 2 ) 2 . (ii) Assuming that w 1 < 2 , we obtain the following in a unique equilibrium of the 13L sequential-move subgame. (a) The players' (positive) effort levels are: x 13L 1 = 9w 2 1 (2w 1 − 1)∕4 1 w 2 (w 1 + 1) 3 , x 13L 2 = 3w 1 (2w 1 w 2 + 2w 2 − 3w 1 )∕4 2 w 2 (w 1 + 1) 2 , and x 13L 3 = 9w 2 1 (2 − w 1 )∕4w 2 (w 1 + 1) 3 . (b) The players' expected payoffs are: 13L 1 = 3w 2 1 (2w 1 − 1) 2 ∕4 1 w 2 (w 1 + 1) 3 , 13L 2 = (2w 1 w 2 + 2w 2 − 3w 1 ) 2 ∕4 2 w 2 (w 1 + 1) 2 , and 13L 3 = 3w 1 (2 − w 1 ) 2 ∕4w 2 (w 1 + 1) 3 . 1 (x 1 , x 2 ) = w 1 x 1 ∕ ( 1 x 1 + 2 x 2 ) − x 1 (C2) 2 (x 1 , x 2 ) = w 2 x 2 ∕ ( 1 x 1 + 2 x 2 ) − x 2 . (C3) 4( 1 x 1 + 2 x 2 ) 3 − w 2 1 ( 1 x 1 + 2 2 x 2 ) 2 = 0. (C4) 4( 1 x 1 + 2 x 2 ) 3 − w 2 2 (2 1 x 1 + 2 x 2 ) 2 = 0. (iii) Assuming that w 2 < 2 , we obtain the following in a unique equilibrium of the 23L sequential-move subgame. (a) The players' (positive) effort levels are: x 23L 1 = 3w 2 (2w 1 w 2 + 2w 1 − 3w 2 )∕4 1 w 1 (w 2 + 1) 2 , x 23L 2 = 9w 2 2 (2w 2 − 1)∕4 2 w 1 (w 2 + 1) 3 , and x 23L 3 = 9w 2 2 (2 − w 2 )∕4w 1 (w 2 + 1) 3 . (b) The players' expected payoffs are: 23L 1 = (2w 1 w 2 + 2w 1 − 3w 2 ) 2 ∕4 1 w 1 (w 2 + 1) 2 , 23L 2 = 3w 2 2 (2w 2 − 1) 2 ∕4 2 w 1 (w 2 + 1) 3 , and 23L 3 = 3w 2 (2 − w 2 ) 2 ∕4w 1 (w 2 + 1) 3 . In this appendix, we consider endogenous timing of effort exertion in a two-player contest in which player h, for h = 1 or 2, and player 3 compete to win a prize. Specifically, we consider the following game. In the first stage, each player chooses independently between Point 1 and Point 2. The players announce (and commit to) their choices simultaneously. In the second stage, after knowing when the players choose their effort levels, each player independently chooses her effort level at the point in time which she announced in the first stage. A player who chooses her effort level at point 2 observes the effort levels chosen at point 1 before she does. At the end of this stage, the winner is determined. Let y j , for j = h , 3, denote player j's effort level. We assume the following contest success function for player j: Let j denote the expected payoff for player j. Then the payoff function for player j is given by To obtain a subgame-perfect equilibrium of the game, we work backward. We first analyze the subgames starting at the second stage, and then consider the players' first-stage decisions on timing of effort exertion. There are four subgames starting at the second stage, but we need to analyze the following three subgames: a simultaneous-move subgame, the hL sequential-move subgame, and the 3L sequential-move subgame (see footnote 9). Conducting an analysis similar to the one in Sect. 3, we obtain the players' equilibrium expected payoffs in the three subgames. Let S j represent player j's equilibrium expected payoff in a simultaneous-move subgame. Let hL j represent player j's equilibrium expected payoff in the hL sequential-move subgame, and let 3L j represent her equilibrium expected payoff in the 3L sequential-move subgame. Lemma D below p j = j y j ∕( h y h + y 3 ) for y h + y 3 > 0 1∕2 for y h + y 3 = 0 . j = v j p j − y j = w j y j ∕( h y h + y 3 ) − y j for y h + y 3 > 0 v j ∕2 for y h + y 3 = 0 . Effort levels in contests with two asymmetric players Two-player lopsided contests under different timing assumptions Endogenous timing in a gaming experiment Endogenous timing in contests with delegation Strategic behavior in contests: comment Strategic choice of sharing rules in collective contests Strategic behaviour in contests: evidence from the 1992 Barcelona Olympic Games Being a leader or a follower: reflections on the distribution of roles in duopoly Multimarket oligopoly: strategic substitutes and complements A model of price leadership based on consumer loyalty Strategic behavior in contests Stackelberg and Cournot duopoly: choosing roles Endogenous timing of contest with asymmetric information First mover and second mover advantages Endogenous timing in duopoly games: Stackelberg or Cournot equilibria Politically contestable rents and transfers Mimeo Hoffmann M, Rota-Graziosi G (2012) Endogenous timing in general rent-seeking and conflict models Endogenous timing in the presence of non-monotonicities The generalized Stackelberg equilibrium of the all-pay auction with complete information More efficient rent-seeking-A Münchhausen solution Quantity-setting oligopoly with endogenous sequencing Sequential contests More on more efficient rent seeking and strategic behavior in contests: comment A two-stage model of research and development with endogenous second-mover advantages Duopoly with endogenous strategic timing: Stackelberg regained Toward a theory of the rent-seeking society Contest theory: incentive mechanisms and ranking methods We now end this appendix by stating the result we have obtained: If we assume Assumption 3, (E14) and (E15), then a subgame-perfect equilibrium occurs in which each of the n players announces Point 1. Note that (E14) and (E15) can be combined and rewritten as active at the Nash equilibrium if players 2 and 3 have the same composite strength: w 2 = w 3 = 1. Fix player i, for i ∈ N . In this subgame, player i first chooses her effort level at point 1. Then, after observing player i's effort level, the rest choose their effort levels simultaneously and independently at point 2.To solve for an equilibrium of the 1L sequential-move subgame, we work backward. At point 2, players 2 and 3 know player 1's effort level x 1 . Player 2 seeks to maximize 2 in (2) over her effort level x 2 , taking player 3's effort level as given. From the first-order condition for maximizing 2 , we derive player 2's reaction function:Similarly, we derive the reaction function for player 3:Using these two reaction functions, we obtain the Nash equilibrium at point 2: and Next, consider point 1 at which player 1 chooses her effort level. Let 1 (x 1 ) be player 1's expected payoff-computed at point 1 of the subgame-which takes into account the Nash equilibrium at point 2. Substituting x N 2 (x 1 ) and x N 3 (x 1 ) into (2), we obtain At point 1, player 1 has perfect foresight about 1 (x 1 ) for any value of x 1 . She chooses a value of x 1 which maximizes 1 (x 1 ). From the first-order condition for maximizing 1 (x 1 ), we obtain player 1's equilibrium effort level x 1L 1 . Substituting x 1L 1 into x N 2 (x 1 ) and x N 3 (x 1 ) above, we obtain the equilibrium effort levels of players 2 and 3, x 1L 2 and x 1L 3 , respectively. Substituting into (2) the players' equilibrium effort levels, we obtain player h's equilibrium expected payoff 1L h , for h ∈ N.At point 1, players 1 and 2 have perfect foresight about 1 (x 1 , x 2 ) and 2 (x 1 , x 2 ) for any values of x 1 and x 2 . We first derive the reaction function for player 1. Player 1 seeks to maximize reports these expected payoffs, and compares them. Note that, in addition to Assumption 1, we further assume that w h < 2 , which makes both players active in the equilibrium of every second-stage subgame.Lemma D (i) Under Assumption 1 and the assumption that 1 ≤ w h < 2 , we obtain:Now we consider the players' first-stage decisions. We restrict our analysis to cases where 1 < w h < 2 . Part (ii) of Lemma D implies that, in the asymmetric contest, Point 1 leads to a higher second-stage equilibrium expected payoff for player 3 than does Point 2, no matter what player h announces in the first stage. This in turn implies that player 3 announces Point 1 in the first stage. Next, it is immediate from part (ii) that player h announces Point 2 in the first stage, forming her belief that player 3 announces Point 1. In this appendix, we consider endogenous timing of effort exertion in an n-player contest, where n > 3 . Specifically, we consider the following game. In the first stage, the players each choose independently between Point 1 and Point 2, and announce their choices simultaneously. In the second stage, after knowing when the players choose their effort levels, each player independently chooses her effort level at the point in time which she announced in the first stage. A player who chooses her effort level at point 2 observes the effort levels chosen at point 1 before she does.To obtain a subgame-perfect equilibrium of the game, we work backward. We first analyze the proper subgames that start at the second stage, and then look at the players' first-stage decisions on timing of effort exertion.Due to computational intractability, we aim to merely find a subgame-perfect equilibrium, without checking its possible uniqueness, in which each of the n players announces Point 1. Accordingly, we need to analyze only n + 1 subgames among the 2 n ones (starting at the second stage): a simultaneous-move subgame and the (−i)L sequential-move subgame, for each i ∈ N + , where (−i)L is used as a shorthand for "with all players except player i as the leaders."A simultaneous-move subgamePlayer i, for i ∈ N + , seeks to maximize i over her effort level x i , taking the other players' effort levels as given, where i = w i x i ∕X − x i . From the first-order condition for maximizing i , we derive player i's reaction function: Let x S i , for i ∈ N + , represent player i's effort level at the Nash equilibrium, and let X S = n ∑ z=1 z x S z . Then they satisfy player i's reaction function, so that we haveAdding these equations together, we have Substituting this expression for X S into (E1), we obtain the equilibrium effort levels of the n active players:Next, substituting the players' equilibrium effort levels in (E2) into their payoff functions, we obtain their expected payoffs at the Nash equilibrium:The (−i)L sequential-move subgame Fix player i, for i ∈ N + . In this subgame, all the players except player i first choose their effort levels simultaneously and independently at point 1, and then after observing their effort levels, player i chooses her effort level at point 2. To solve for an equilibrium of this subgame, we work backward.At point 2, knowing the list x −i of the other players' effort levels, player i seeks to maximize i over her effort level x i . From the first-order condition for maximizing i , we derive player i's strategy in any equilibrium:Next, consider point 1 at which the n − 1 leaders choose their effort levels simultaneously and independently. Let j (x −i ), for j ∈ N + ⧵ {i} , be player j's expected payoff-computed at point 1 of the subgame-which takes into account player i's equilibrium strategy in (E4). Substituting x i (x −i ) in (E4) into player j's payoff function, we obtain At point 1, player j, for j ∈ N + ⧵ {i} , seeks to maximize j (x −i ) over her effort level x j , taking the other leaders' effort levels as given. The first-order condition for maximizing j (x −i ) reduces to where Q ≡ ∑ z≠i z x z . The leaders' equilibrium effort levels satisfy the n − 1 first-order conditions in (E5) simultaneously. In order to obtain these n − 1 equilibrium effort levels, we take the following four steps.Step 1. Using (E5), we have for any h, k ∈ N + ⧵ {i} : w 2 h (2Q − h x h ) 2 = 4w i Q 3 and w 2 k (2Q − k x k ) 2 = 4w i Q 3 . These two equations yieldStep 2. Fix player k, for k ∈ N + ⧵ {i} . Using (E6), we have for eachThen, adding these n − 1 equations together, we obtainStep 3. Using (E7), we have forSquaring both sides of this equation and rearranging the terms, we obtainNext, substituting this equation into (E5), we obtainwhich yieldsStep 4. Let x (−i)L j , for j ∈ N + ⧵ {i} , represent player j's effort level in the equilibrium. Substituting (E8) into (E5) and doing some algebra, we obtain The active-players-in-equilibrium conditions Using (E2), it is straightforward to check that, under Assumption 3, all the players are active at the Nash equilibrium of a simultaneous-move subgame if and only if the following condition is satisfied:Next, using (E9) and (E10), it is straightforward to check that, under Assumption 3, all the players are active in the equilibrium of the (−i)L sequential-move subgame, for a fixed i ∈ N + , if and only if the following condition is satisfied: We look at the players' decisions, in the first stage, on when to expend their effort. As mentioned above, we aim to merely find a subgame-perfect equilibrium in which each of the n players announces Point 1. To this end, it suffices to show that S i in (E3)≥ (−i)L i in (E11), for all i ∈ N + . Indeed, in such a case, a subgameperfect equilibrium occurs in which no player has an incentive to deviate from her first-stage action, Point 1.Using (E3) and (E11), we obtain under Assumption 3 that S i ≥ (−i)L i for a fixed i ∈ N + if the following condition is satisfied: Accordingly, we obtain under Assumption 3 that S i ≥ (−i)L i for all i ∈ N + if the following condition is satisfied: or, equivalently,Publisher's Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.