key: cord-0604659-ks1vq185 authors: Kroy, Klaus title: Superspreading and Heterogeneity in Epidemics date: 2022-02-27 journal: nan DOI: nan sha: d4b05bdcabd141e2f7027939845898a888700749 doc_id: 604659 cord_uid: ks1vq185 Epidemic disease spreading is conventionally often modelled and analyzed by means of rate and diffusion equations, following the paradigms of well-controlled chemical reactions and diffusive dynamics in a test tube. Yet, serious worries that this suggestive and appealing similarity might be a false friend were already voiced by the pioneers of mathematical epidemiology. A century later, we can draw on cross-fertilizations from network and game theory and the emerging field of eco-evolutionary dynamics to substantiate them. Epidemiological spreading is thereby revealed as a fundamentally heterogeneous and erratic process that shares certain properties with more unwieldy phenomena, such as earthquakes, hurricanes, traffic jams, and stock crashes. They are all characterised by high tail risks that materialize very rarely but fatally. That they arise from bursts of unlikely chains of localized random"superspreader"events, by which micro-scale fluctuations and uncertainties may get heftily magnified, makes their accurate prediction and control intrinsically and notoriously hard. That epidemic disease spreading is moreover closely intertwined with equally heterogeneous genetic drift and information feedback adds new challenges -- and chances. many similarities with the other spreading processes mentioned above. One is that researchers feel tempted to model it by diffusion. Indeed, classical epidemiological theories routinely describe disease spreading in the spirit of chemical reactions in a test tube. And, as reviewed by Dirk Brockmann in Chapter 20, they can even schematically account for non-trivial human mobility patterns if formulated on a warped space. But there are also some more erratic elements of epidemic disease spreading, reminiscent of more unwieldy phenomena such as earthquakes, hurricanes, traffic jams, and stock-market crashes. They are characterized by extreme heterogeneities, coupled across diverse scales. Rare chains of micro-scale fluctuations may occasionally get heftily magnified into large erratic outbreaks. One then speaks of a "high tail risks" due to an uncomfortable combination of the large size and impact of an expected event with its estimated small likelihood. Such traits are in sharp contrast to what ordinary diffusion and classical epidemiological models would predict and make the forecasting and control of epidemics intrinsically and notoriously hard. Therefore, the aim of the present chapter is to provide a (non-expert 1 ) synopsis of the crucial role of spatial, probabilistic, and genetic heterogeneity in real-world epidemics. Their importance for the failure of conventional epidemiological models was already anticipated by some of the pioneers in the field [2] . The "false analogy between infection in disease and the mechanism understood under the name of chemical mass action" (H. E. Soper, 1929) was criticized, and first steps were taken (notably by A. G. McKendrick) to resolve the issue. Today, we can draw on cross-fertilizations from network and game theory and the emerging field of eco-evolutionary dynamics to substantiate such worries. The notion of superspreading can serve as a guiding theme. In a narrow sense, it refers to the strong variability in the number of secondary infections or "offspring" of a contagious pathogen carrier [3] . This probabilistic heterogeneity or so-called overdispersion (compared to an idealized test-tube reaction) means that the majority of all infections is not caused by typical encounters but by a small number of exceptional superspreading events. These are intuitively expected to be caused by "supercarriers" and "supershedders" of pathogens. 2 But, as further elucidated below, one should not rashly jump to such conclusions. I want to use the term in a wider sense, also comprising a heterogeneous susceptibility as well as the heterogeneity of the pathogen carriers' social contact networks and spatio-temporal dynamics. Furthermore, it makes sense to also implicate an extended hierarchy of superimposed levels of spreading, similar to the discussion in Chapter 19 of this volume. Namely, beyond the mentioned multi-layered "spreading squared" of pathogens hitchhiking with their mobile hosts (and possibly intermediate "vectors", such as mosquitoes or other transmitting animals), there are further, less palpable, but similarly heterogeneous spreading processes involved. Think of mutation patterns spreading along a pathogen's genealogical or phylogenetic tree, for example. Thereby, epidemic dynamics is always confounded by population genetics [5] . And, as discussed below, one may even ask, whether "genetic drift" (i.e., diffusion in sequence space) may explain "superspreading events without superspreaders" [6, 7] ? Finally, there is the overlaid spreading of information about the course of an unfolding epidemic, which may itself "go viral" and thereby induce highly nonlinear feedback effects [8] . Altogether, epidemics thus have to be regarded as a manifestation of a (quite fickle) complex dynamical system 3 . While this may seem obvious to some experts, it is not always widely appreciated. Speaking of pathogen and disease spreading, a few facts about bacteria and viruses seem in place. First of all, it is important to realize that they are integral parts of any ecosystem. And that the whole biosphere relies on (and is dominated by) microorganisms that have for the largest part not yet been scientifically investigated. Even within our own bodies, bacteria and viruses by far outnumber "our own" cells. In particular, viruses are the most abundant and fastest mutating genetic elements on Earth -their number of offspring in a single infection event easily exceeds the size of the whole host population. And, although not counted among the proper lifeforms, they play a decisive role in shaping the tree of life, as "agents of evolutionary invention" [9] . By infecting us, or more often the broad array of microorganisms inhabiting us, they mould our genetic and transcriptional identity. Even the small minority among them identified as pathogenic usually does little or no harm in their natural reservoir species. But it may occasionally cause significant disease outbreaks at overpopulated gatherings of hosts, or when jumping between cohabiting species. This has become a serious issue with the onset of urbanisation and intensive farming in the wake of the neolithic revolution (see Chapters 16 and 17 of this volume), which has culminated in industrial poultry farms [10] , care and nursing homes [11] , and crowded sickbays, prisons [12] , and warships [13] . Indeed, all types of herding and crowding are closely interwoven with infectious diseases. This applies particularly to warfare, where disease has often trumped combat by its death toll [14, 15] : from the epidemic "killing the warriors in droves" evoked by Homer to spark the story of his Iliad, to the plague of Athens in 430 BC that extinguished about a quarter of those entrenched in the besieged overcrowded city, and the Spanish flu pandemic, with (far) more than 20 million victims, during the First World War. Unsurprisingly, military forces have therefore become leading proponents of germ and vaccine research. George Washington's order to variolate the entire American Army against smallpox is sometimes cited as decisive for the American civil war [16] . The success story could however not be repeated by the enthusiastically advocated vaccination campaigns, targeting epidemiologically irrelevant bacteria such as Pfeiffer's "bacillus influenzae", against the Spanish flu [17] . From the ensuing controversies emerged an early set of criteria for valid vaccine trials, while the types of viruses now held responsible for transmitting the flu, as well as their immune and vaccine escape capabilities, remain mysterious and challenging, another century later [18] [19] [20] . Albeit, till today, the military remains a central player and an incubator for vaccinologists and epidemiologists, many of which later move on to industry and academia, contributing to notable discoveries, e.g., of vector-borne diseases and transmissions, the oral polio vaccine, etc. Together with increased prosperity and improved sanitation, they are widely credited for taming the hazardous impact of contagious diseases on our highly interconnected modern societies ( Fig. 23 .1) 4 . On a less optimistic note, such activity has unavoidably been entangled with bioweapon development 5 , (at least) ever since "variolated" sundries, blankets, and handkerchieves were distributed around Fort Pitt in Pennsylvania to decimate the Native Americans, in the 1760's [16] . And although the ensuing "gain-of-function" 6 research has become increasingly unpopular and repeatedly officially banned [21] , it has ar-guably never ceased [15] . The late Steven Hawking's worries 7 about disasters more imminent than those predicted by his cosmological theories thus do not seem to have arisen out of thin air, but rather underscore a commonly underestimated eminent political dimension of epidemiology that has resurfaced in recent debates [22] [23] [24] . The classical "test-tube" models of epidemiology [25] , based on seminal work by Kermack and McKendrick [26] , were briefly introduced in Chapters 20 and 21 of this volume and, more thoroughly, by the applied mathematician Stephan Luckhaus in his Leipzig lectures. 8 They are better known as compartmental models, since they describe the mutual "chemical reactions" of idealized homogeneous fractions or compartments of a given population, such as the Susceptible, Infected, Recovered, etc. In their simplest form, these models completely disregard the spatial, social, and biological heterogeneity of the population, emphasized in the present contribution. Although one therefore cannot trust their numerical results, they make a number of qualitatively robust predictions that are worthwhile recalling. A major phenomenological observation that is captured well by the standard SIR-type models is the characteristic time course of epidemics. They proceed via overshooting infection waves toward i) extinction due to herd immunity or ii) an endemic state, respectively. The first scenario i) applies to a "static" host population and pathogen, for which the (nominal) herd-immunity threshold follows from the fraction of remaining susceptible individuals at peak infection. The second, more complex, scenario ii) takes into account the gradual emergence of new susceptible individuals, e.g., due to pathogen mutations, (reverse) zoonosis 9 , waning immunity, and/or the host population's turnover (e.g. by births and migration). These processes slowly and inconspicuously shift the balance in favor of new outbreaks, thus leading to repeated infection waves. Irrespective of the precise scenario, a robust conclusion of the standard models is that only a fraction of the population ever becomes infected during an infection wave. 10 Conceptually, the models are furthermore helpful for sorting the reaction rates into two classes: those setting the speed of spreading and the late-time 7 S. Hawking: "we face a number of threats to our survival, from nuclear war, catastrophic global warming, and genetically-engineered viruses" in his Reith Lecture 2016: "Black holes ain't as black as they are painted", http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ljvVPAZHnD4 8 S. Luckhaus, 2020 recordings: http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=SZ4dIEb2ttM (English), http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=FJYjqltJn9E (German); see also: http://www.mis.mpg. de/preprints/2020/preprint2020 105.pdf 9 For example, SARS-CoV-2 has remarkably rapidly established so-called "animal reservoirs", e.g., in cat, dog, tiger, lion, puma, mink, and white-tailed deer [27, 28] , which was answered by mass cullings of tens of millions of minks "to protect the vaccines" [29] 10 In the first COVID-19 infection wave, about 0.2% of the German population tested PCRpositive. Almost two years (and several waves and mutants) later, everybody had statistically been PCR-tested at least once, yet only about 6.5% positive. Such low infection rates hint at substantial population heterogeneities and cross-immunities (epidemiological "dark matter") endemic state or herd immunity, respectively. The distinction mirrors that between Arrhenius-and Boltzmann-factors in physical chemistry: the former only modulate the speed of a chemical reaction, while the latter alone determine its outcome via the mass-action law. 11 The fundamental insight for pathogens that cannot be eradicated is that mitigation measures, including non-sterilizing vaccines and pharmaceuticals, are mere (anti-)catalysts. They can at best affect the time course but not the long-term fate of an epidemic, which is determined by the pathogen-host chemistry, alone. For example, rapid border closures may help to gain some time during the early stage of an epidemic. Yet, even the draconian travel quarantine imposed in Wuhan during the onset of the COVID epidemic in early 2020 was estimated to delay the further progression in Mainland China by no more than 3 to 5 days [30] . And even in island countries such as Australia, New Zealand, and Iceland, where the infection numbers were kept extremely low for about two years, they eventually rocketed -thus "vindicating Boltzmann over Arrhenius". Such sobering insights can temper expectations about what pharmaceutical and non-pharmaceutical interventions can generally achieve for the control of epidemics. As the examples suggest, social interventions are notorious for their hard to assess [31] and hard to justify cost-benefit ratios among the experts [32] [33] [34] [35] . Despite some initial empirical [36] , but more often lopsidedly model-based 12 , propositions to the contrary, also the latest epidemic does not seem to provide a plausible exception to this rule [37] [38] [39] [40] [41] [42] . The perplexingly unimpressive effect of global "bulk" interventions on epidemic spreading clearly begs for further explanation. A first clue can be gained if the compartmental models are extended to account for some population heterogeneity by dividing the population up into cohorts with distinct properties. They then admit richer solutions, with some variability how the overall infection rate is distributed among the cohorts. It is then intuitively clear that mitigation measures can be more effective and more economic if they target specific cohorts rather than the whole population [5, 43] . Epidemiologists have long known how to exploit the effect to protect particularly vulnerable groups. 8 COVID-19 again provides a good example. Only a small percentage of the elderly population with comorbidities is at serious risk and accounts for almost all deaths [44, 45] , initially about half of them in long-term care-homes [46] . According to the extended compartmental models with multiple cohorts, the conventional mitigation strategy is then to let the disease spread quickly 13 among the non-vulnerable (the young and healthy [47] [48] [49] ), while the vulnerable group 11 This equilibrium-type constraint confers a crucial element of predictability to epidemics, if their population-wide pathogen-host chemistry is known and remains fixed over time 12 P. W. Magness, AIER 2021: http://www.aier.org/article/the-failure-of-impe rial-college-modeling-is-far-worse-than-we-knew; G. A. Quinn et al., 2021: http: //doi.org/10.31219/osf.io/s9z2p 13 At which point a long-term investment in the healthcare sector appears to pay its way [34] temporarily self-isolates. Altogether, the extent of the infection wave in the vulnerable group -in a well mixed population even their herd immunity threshold -can thereby be reduced, resulting in a much lower overall cumulative death toll. The important take-home message is that it is crucial to account for the population heterogeneity, with respect to both vulnerability and social contacts. Well-intentioned indiscriminate or even misaligned interventions (e.g., off-season for a seasonal disease or targeting the less instead of the more vulnerable cohorts) may be counter-productive, delaying the necessary immunization and resulting in an overall increased death toll, at the end of the line. Curiously, experts who voiced such textbook wisdom during the early days of the recent COVID epidemic encountered fierce political opposition 14 . A number of recent studies (see Ref. [50] and therein) have investigated extensions of the cohort approach to broad distributions of the susceptibility, in order to account for the substantial diversity in the transmission probabilities. Jülicher and coworkers considered a power-law distribution of (natural) susceptibilities, with its exponent α being the only new parameter added to the standard SIR model [50] . Key properties of the epidemic wave dynamics, including the infection curve, the herd immunity level, and the final size of the epidemic, can then still be calculated exactly, while avoiding the proliferation of poorly defined model parameters that generally plagues the modeling of heterogeneities in terms of several discrete cohorts. An important finding is that the average dynamics is naturally sub-exponential, α-dependent, and allows for herd-immunity thresholds as low as a few per cent of the total population. The model also predicts how the transmission probability distribution itself evolves dynamically throughout an epidemic, as the numbers in the susceptible cohorts change and eventually converge to an invariant distribution ∝ x α−1 e −αx . While this is certainly an important step towards reality, further modifications of the test-tube caricature of epidemic spreading become necessary if one wants to account more thoroughly for the whole spectrum of relevant heterogeneities [51] and include, for example, an uneven spatial or social mixing within or between the cohorts, as outlined in the following. Heterogeneous populations should of course not be expected to be well mixed. Their contacts are unevenly distributed with respect to their number as well as to other parameters such as age group and profession. Referring back to the schematic example of the two cohorts, one will only reap the full benefit of a targeted protection strategy if the population is well mixed. If the vulnerable remain permanently segregated, instead, in close mutual contact rather than dispersed within an already largely immunized population, the risk of devastating outbreaks among them is not diminished as much as it could be ("dry-tinder effect") 15 . Generally speaking, beyond a population's susceptibility distribution, one also needs to address its heterogeneous contact networks, if one wants to fully understand the spreading of an epidemic. In clustered networks, the connections are skewed to favor members of the same clique. Cliques are densely intra-connected but only weakly inter-connected. Accordingly, in such networks, infections initially spread very well but then slow down and remain more confined than naively expected. In other words, the fire of infection burns fast but extinguishes easily. To reach the next clique or cluster, the epidemic has to pass via narrow population bottlenecks, where only a few pathogens can pass, so that details matter and chance rules [52] . (This "reign of small numbers" [1] plays a prominent role in virus evolution, as discussed further below.) The topological feature of contact clustering may thus considerably impede the global spread of a disease compared to tree-like contact networks, while it facilitates contact tracing [53, 54] . Besides nursing homes, typical real-world examples for clusters could be households and school classes, say, but also an infected organism itself or its individual organs. While a pathogen may find it easy to spread within a single organ, it may turn out very difficult to invade the next, and similarly for social groups. As a consequence, real-world epidemics only reach a smaller part of the population than predicted by the test-tube models, but most of that relatively easily. This conclusion resonates well with the above-mentioned findings by Jülicher and coworkers. And indeed, their approach can also be interpreted as an attempt to effectively incorporate some contact heterogeneity into the simple SIR model. In practice, however, clustering and distributed susceptibility or transmissibility are distinct features that interfere with each other. To make things worse, they interfere with yet another non-trivial but common topological trait of natural contact networks, namely their heterogeneity with respect to the number of contacts emanating from a network node (its "degree"). In his book "Linked -The New Science of Networks" [55] , A.-L. Barabasi emphasizes this other crucial aspect of real-world contact networks, known as their broad degree distribution. He vividly recounts the story of one of the first known superspreaders, often called Patient Zero of the AIDS epidemic. Who turned out to be a central hub (a particularly highly connected, i.e. highdegree, network node), with an estimated number of 2500 links or more, in a large network of sexual contacts. At least some 40 early patients could explicitly be traced back to him. This is a manifestation of the empirical observation that social and sexual contact networks are very heterogeneous [56] . The weakly connected nodes (with zero or one sex partner, say) are most frequent, but the number of more highly connected hubs decays only slowly, typically like a power-law, as a function of their connectivity (their degree). This means that individuals will not spread a disease simply proportionally to their pathogen load. Indeed, most do not spread a pathogen at all, but a few a lot 16 . Yet, neither do all hubs in a network contribute simply proportionally to their degree, not even if one artificially assumes homogeneous pathogen load and transmission. And it would not be easy to localize them all, anyway, or even to define and select the structurally most relevant ones [57, 58] . Unsurprisingly, the best search tool known to solve this complex task is actually an epidemic, which may in this context be thought of as a "swarm algorithm". Similarly as for the broadly distributed transmissibilities, discussed further above, an important and robust epidemiological consequence of broadly distributed contact numbers is the lowering of the epidemic threshold [59] . In the standard SIR models, which describe relations between population averages, the fate of an epidemic is determined by its effective reproduction number R of secondary infections caused, on average, by an infected individual. The epidemic is predicted to spread exponentially for R > 1 and to decay exponentially for R < 1. However, for the important class of scale-free networks (with power-law degree distributions), the epidemic threshold is formally found to vanish in an infinite network: in strongly heterogeneous networks, pathogens (no matter how weakly contagious) will always spread to a certain macroscopic scale. And they do so in a rather heterogeneous fashion, as illustrated in Fig. 23 .2. With increasing broadening of the degree distribution, occasional disease extinction becomes more likely and outbreaks rarer but more explosive -and all this even without invoking the non-trivial effects due to distributed transmissibilities, clustering, and bottlenecks. In other words, real-world epidemic spreading is, for more than one reason, prone to generating considerable tail risks. To gain some intuition for the tail-risk effects associated with power-law distributions, consider the following gamble. A banker tosses a fair coin for you until tail comes up. What is the fair price for a round, if you earn 2 n+1 (in your favorite currency) for n heads in a row before tail comes up? The problem with this game, and similar real-word processes in finance and epidemics, is that the chance 2 −n−1 for the row of n heads is the reciprocal of the profit 2 n+1 . So the probability distribution for earning x n = 2 n+1 is given by the power law x −1 n . The most striking consequence of this is that your most likely payoff is 2 while its average n x n /x n = n 1 diverges. Accordingly, your likely gain in a single round is fairly small, but the "fair" price is infinity. Notice the so-called Petersburg paradox associated with this result. Namely, that a banker charging a better-than-fair (any finite) price per round, say 1000, can play the game for a long time, and accumulate impressive wealth, before he eventually goes bankrupt and needs to be bailed out by the tax payers. 16 Not unexpectedly, staff members feature prominently in the timeline of the well documented nursing-home outbreak referenced in footnote 15. < l a t e x i t s h a 1 _ b a s e 6 4 = " z y y q 3 x a j 9 a z 9 W a 9 z 0 c L V r 6 z D 3 7 B + v g G 9 p S a y w = = < / l a t e x i t > P (n) / hni n /n! < l a t e x i t s h a 1 _ b a s e 6 4 = " 0 4 c o t h 6 f S / n U b c 8 j X 9 d r n e e L J T w = " Homogeneous versus heterogeneous spreading. Transmission trees grown from a single seed with offspring numbers from a Poisson distribution (left) or a truncated powerlaw (right, α ≈ 2.35) with gray × indicating P (0). In the Poisson or test-tube setting, most infected nodes pass on a spreading disease: average behavior matters. The powerlaw case (aka overdispersed, fat-tailed, scale-free) is more realistic for human contact networks [51, 56] . Its (identical) average hardly matters, as most nodes infect no others, and the epidemic is driven by rare, explosive but unstable bursts [60] or superspreading events. The more fat-tailed P (n), "the more the tail wags the dog" [61] . Beyond illustrating the key problem with power-law risks, which indeed seem to arise ubiquitously in non-equilibrium real-world processes from plate tectonics to financial markets [62] , the toy model is also instructive in another sense. It shows that high tail risks do not always require very heterogeneous conditions as a necessary prerequisite. They can even result from statistically independent random events, like coin tosses, if the process is capable of producing exponential growth. Which leads back to epidemiology, where the gambler's profit amounts to pathogen proliferation, of course, and the banker's allegedly 100% safe business model is the analog of the epidemiologist's confident prediction of the next infection wave. Since, according to the standard models, epidemics are of course the textbook paradigm for exponential growth. Or are they? So far, the discussion of heterogeneities has focussed on topological features. However, unlike fads or idioms, contagious diseases do not spread via phone calls and emails but require physical encounters. Which means that the mentioned heterogeneous social networks need to be considered together with their embedding into real space. And the physical geometry of the latter, as encoded in a city map or by regions of inhabitable land on the globe, brings new heterogeneities into the equation that can potentially override the mentioned topological features or even change them [63] . For example, the topological feature of clustering, discussed above, may to some extent be thought to arise as consequence of spatial embedding (to households, work places, . . . ). Also, so-called superspreading events, with an explosive growth of infections, clearly seem to be tied to specific patterns of spatial crowding and mobility: besides the mentioned nursing homes and warships also large conferences [64] , cold slaughter houses [65] , and hot parties [66, 67] (with poor air conditioning) -but not public trains [68] , the exchange of bank notes [69] , or outdoor events [70] . Once more, a small fraction of (in this case spatial 17 ) interaction patterns appears to produce almost all spreading [71] . A crucial role of the spatial geometry has also been established for the process of gene spreading, which is closely related to pathogen spreading. Genomes can remain confined with their phenotypes to certain habitats for a long time, before the latter embark on larger excursions, leading to so-called founder effects. As elaborated in Johannes Krause's popular book [72] , the co-evolution of largely isolated social groups with specific pathogens is moreover suspected to have caused major historic epidemics upon invasion of new, already inhabited territories. This is also a main topic in the history of colonialism and imperialism [73, 74] . In return, one may speculate that the rapid growth in human mobility and globalization throughout the last 150 years 18 , could plausibly partly explain the decaying impact of epidemics, as apparent from Fig. 23.1 ; namely, chiefly via the global distribution of pathogens and cross-immunities it has brought about [75] . Counter-intuitively as it may sound to some, it would mean that, in the long run, the severity of epidemics is best tamed by frequent traveling and cross-country social gatherings, and that christmas [66] , carnival [67] , and après-ski [76] parties may inadvertently serve some noble purpose. Not only to address such intriguing open questions, the embedding of epidemic spreading into real-space geometry is of major interest. Two key elements to consider are then the spatial heterogeneity of the population density and its heterogeneous mobility patterns [51] . A scaling approach, pioneered and popularized by Geoffrey West [63] covers both in one stroke, without necessitating the underlying mechanistic details to be resolved. It is consistent with the empirical finding that socioeconomic metrics of urban life, such as the average wages or the number of restaurants, theaters, lawyers, crimes, and cases of AIDS and flu, all scale in a more or less universal, superlinear manner with city size. This approach has also tentatively been applied to the early attack of the COVID-19 pandemic [77] , and a suggestive correlation between mortality and the so-called population weighted density 19 seems to hint in a similar direction. Chapter 20 of this volume follows a more explicit route for the example of air traffic, along similar lines as pursued in invasion biology [78] : if you can take a plane, this may substantially affect what you (as well as the species you carry along) perceive as the metric of the globe. One can capture such heterogeneous mobility by means of a warped metric, i.e., very much in the same spirit as for diffusion in curved spacetime [79] or for the case of non-isothermal Brownian motion [80] , described in Chapter 8 of this volume. One can also try to take the full spectrum of means of transport into account -allowing travellers to jump the line with the help of planes, trains, busses and cabs, say. A tractable approach to do so has already been explored in the closely related context of eco-evolutionary dynamics [81] . Translated to the spread of an epidemic, its predictions imply that the textbook wisdom of exponential epidemic growth requires substantial revision, as they suggest a very different (even logarithmic) intermediate asymptotic dynamics of disease spreading, under such circumstances. Recent epidemiological studies arrive at similar conclusions, albeit on entirely different grounds [82, 83] . Also the contribution by Armin Bunde and coauthors in Chapter 21 points out that the transport dynamics on a spatial network will inevitably become algebraic rather than exponential, when the network is poised towards breakup (i.e., near to its percolation threshold). Summarizing the above discussion, the main problem with the epidemic standard models is that the infectiousness of the infected, the susceptibility of the susceptible and recovered, and the social and spatial contact networks connecting them are in reality all far from homogeneous. This entails a substantial quantitative renormalization of the standard epidemiological model predictions -chiefly, a drastically reduced overall herd immunity threshold and endemic pathogen concentration. But, conjointly with the propensity to (locally) exponential growth dynamics, the heterogeneities furthermore create substantial tail risks that threaten to severely undermine the mechanistic logic of the widely employed test-tube models, altogether. This problem is addressed next. The forgoing discussion has highlighted the similar and dissimilar roles of clustering, broad degree distributions, as well as biological, spatial, and mobility heterogeneities. But how all of them interfere in real-world epidemics is so far still poorly understood. And even if some effects might be hoped to compensate (rather than amplify) each other, the detailed mechanisms are far from clear, a century after such concerns were first raised and tentatively addressed [2] . If taken literally, all of them involve problematic limiting procedures that do not peacefully coexist. For example, as mentioned above, taking a powerlaw degree distribution seriously for an infinite network would predict a vanishing epidemiological threshold. Which means that even an extremely weakly contagious pathogen could trigger a massive infection wave. However, neither are real-world networks infinite nor are their degree distributions true powerlaws, so that such predictions cannot be taken at face value but have to be reinterpreted cautiously. The statistician and popular author Nassim N. Taleb has recently analyzed records of historical epidemics from this perspective to find that, indeed, the distribution of fatalities is strongly fat-tailed, "suggesting a tail risk that is unfortunately largely ignored in common epidemiological models" [61] . This goes against most people's common sense, derived from experience with near-equilibrium processes, to which the law of large numbers and the central limit theorem apply. But their intuition is a poor guide far from equilibrium. In particularly, for (locally) exponential growth processes and processes with considerable tail risks, the coarse-grained variables used to formulate rate-equation models may themselves become scale-dependent, fuzzy concepts, if not mechanistically meaningless. This applies, in particular, to the standard estimators of epidemiological or financial risks derived from these variables, such as the average reproduction number R [53, 59] or the infamous "value at risk" (VAR) [84] . For example, rather than controlling the global increase of infections in an epidemic, as assumed by the standard models, R acquires a vague meaning, such as a "probability for certain large but localized outbreaks", in heterogeneous networks. And the naive trust of financial-risk regulators in VAR and other average numbers has even been denounced a key ingredient of the financial meltdown they were expected to mitigate! Contrary to formal predictions by idealized models, originally devised as "illuminating caricatures" [5] to broadly outline some general principles, local details (like those triggering a traffic jam out of the blue), finite-size effects (how big it gets), and pure chance (when or where it happens) will thus matter a lot, under practical circumstances. Certain realworld epidemics may then quickly go extinct, while others blow up without a clear logical explanation -no matter how much the fallible human mind clings to reassuring and self-complacent narratives of simple (linear) cause and effect. The Petersburg gamble may again be invoked to illustrate the main point behind this perplexing risk management paradox -and our innate incompetence to appropriately deal with small fatal risks. It explicitly shows how common intuitive measures employed to quantify and manage the course of epidemics or financial markets, such as averages and variances, may become uninformative and unreliable, if not outright deceptive, in the presence of powerlaw risks. You could say that, as always in statistics, knowing that the average chance for a disaster is low will do little to console you if you are the one who happens to be hurt. But, as the example illustrates, for systems with substantial tail risk, this effect is grotesquely exaggerated far beyond the scale of individual cases (recall that the fair price, namely the average payoff, is infinite, but how incredibly rich the banker may get by charging only a finite price). For epidemic disease spreading, this tendency is aggravated by the propensity to produce locally exponential growth. The latter entails a sensitive dependence on initial conditions and rate coefficients, familiar from chaotic systems, where it is often referred to as the butterfly effect. Its consequence in conjunction with the outlined heterogeneity effects is the de facto breakdown of determinism on global length and time scales. The bottom line is, that the spread of real-world epidemics is far more sensitive to finite-size effects and accidental details, down to the scale of individuals [85] if not within any single organism [4, [86] [87] [88] , than admitted by the widely adopted theoretical models. Any two outbreaks, even in what appears to be the same setting, may thus have very different epidemiological outcomes [61, 82, 89] . How far these heterogeneities can judiciously be averaged out [43, 83, 90] and subsumed into effective parametrizations [91] , to be dealt with deterministically on large enough scales, thus allowing for "typically" (yet not necessarily always) reliable predictions, is an intriguing open question. As an immediate practical consequence, a highly erratic and somewhat counterintuitive response to mitigation measures can emerge [89, 92] . In particular, while processes with a narrow-tailed distribution respond favorably to measures acting on bulk behavior (such as a speed limit for all drivers), those with fat-tailed risks respond poorly and instead require more specifically targeted interventions, which, in return, will incur substantially lower economic costs. For example, convincing sex workers to use condoms is vastly more effective in reducing the spread of AIDS than announcing an overall sex ban. 20 Analog conclusions apply to other diseases with fat-tailed offspring distributions, such as COVID-19 [93] or Ebola [94] , which was found to be contracted by health-care workers in Sierra Leone with a 100 times increased risk. Ironically, in epidemics, many of the networks on which our modern societies so heavily rely, may fall prey to their very strength. It is exactly their strongly heterogeneous contact distributions, leading to transmission graphs as the one shown in the right panel of Fig. 23 .2, that are responsible for the much-praised resilience of scale-free networks against failure. (Deleting a node is inconsequential unless you have very accidentally hit a hub.) But in the context of epidemiology, this translates into a vexing insensitivity of the spreading process against all types of pharmaceutical and non-pharmaceutical "bulk" mitigation measures that are indiscriminately applied to a population as a whole rather than to targeted individuals, specific locations, or critical events [71] . Which in turn helps to explain why the effectiveness of such measures is so hard to accurately evaluate [31] . And why it regularly turns out disappointing in terms of the cost-benefit ratio [33] , even under highly controlled laboratory settings [95] . That each generation of epidemiologists apparently needs to learn this lesson anew [32, 42] , underscores the immensely unintuitive character of the heterogeneous epidemic dynamics. As in the Petersburg paradox, one cannot assume heterogeneities to average out smoothly in epidemiology, as tacitly done when one writes down coupled rate equations for average variables, claiming simple causal relations between them. Even if such models may nicely capture certain aspects of the observed dynamics on a descriptive level, this should not be mistaken as proof of a causal relation. To use a hackneyed analogy: a correlation between the numbers of babies born in a house and storks on its roofs may have a causal origin (e.g., a healthy rural ecosystem may be favorable for both), but this does not imply that more births will mechanistically attract more storks, or vice versa. If stated so bluntly, this may seem an obvious pitfall that is easily avoided. But a cursory survey of the literature suggests it to be a rather common trap. Encouraged by the ease with which one can come up with phenomenological fits to the stereotype patterns of infection waves, many authors have apparently failed to realize that the mathematically toxic mix of heterogeneities with locally exponential growth dynamics may render forecasting and forecasting-based risk management and disease control rather subtle tasks, even retrospectively! 21 Associated common 20 To the referee who swears by the latter: for how many generations should it be maintained? 21 For introductions see e.g. T.Wiethölter, 2022: http://coronakriseblog.wordpress.com; fallacies of data analysis are widely documented and supported by empirical surveys, which underscores the "need to shift study design toward prioritizing the handling of data sources rather than refining models" [31, 38, 41, 96, 97] . Physicists, as well as meteorologists working on weather forecasts [98] , should actually not need to be reminded of this. Weather forecasts can at least rely on real-time data gathered from thousands of automated weather stations all over the land, sea, and sky to rapidly feed back into the models, as well as on a broad consensus on the underlying physical equations. And, importantly, the public reactions they trigger (e.g., leaving the house with or without an umbrella) do not react back onto the weather itself to cause what epidemiologists call the "prediction paradox". From this distinction, an increased responsibility of the epidemic relative to the meteorological modeller ensues, as pointed out in Ref. [41] . Based on an in-depth study of a real-world example, it exemplifies how self-fulfilling prophecies can be a particularly harmful type of predictions. In summary, since deterministic modeling and forecasting is a mine field, responsible risk assessment in epidemiology hinges most crucially on precise and unambiguous empirical data, which are then readily condensed into easy-to-use empirical risk calculators for medical doctors and the general public. 22 While a pathogen is invading a host population, mutations, insertions, and deletions are accumulating in its genome, which gives rise to genetic drift (the technical term for diffusion in gene space). The ensuing coupled spreading dynamics has been a central topic in population genetics and immunology for almost a century [99] . Genome sequencing allows to harness it for a new form of spatiotemporal genomic epidemiology. In this context, genetic changes play the role of a molecular barcode and a molecular clock. Pathogen spreading can thereby be backtracked and displayed in the form of phylogenetic trees. This provides modern epidemiology with entirely new tools, equivalent to C-14 dating in archeology and fingerprints in forensic analysis. The molecular clock rate decides what time scales can be resolved [100] . In the case of highly conserved DNA viruses, such as the smallpox 23 virus variola, the approach is suitable to study historic time scales [101] . Intriguingly, the phylogenetic analysis reveals that the little diversification of major variola lineages that has occurred at all, can be traced back to the 18th and 19th centuries, concomitant with the development of modern vaccination. At the other end of the spectrum, if genetic change is many orders of magnitude faster and, as in the case of HIV and various RNA viruses, say, occurs on a weekly to monthly basis, with error rates per nucleotide and replication cycle up to the ‰-range, phylogenetic analysis C. Kuhbandner, Telepolis 2020: http://www.heise.de/tp/features/Warum-die-Wirksamke it-des-Lockdowns-wissenschaftlich-nicht-bewiesen-ist-4992909.html 22 See, e.g., the QCovid risk calculator: http://qcovid.org; its current risk estimate for catching COVID and dying from it is 0.003% for the author and 0.0001% for his kids of age. 23 Smallpox holds a unique position in the history of medicine, as it was the first disease for which a vaccine was developed and remains the only human disease eradicated by vaccination can resolve much finer epidemiological details. It can then help to track the formation of genetic variants leading to the emergence of repeated infection waves [102] and to validate global spreading pathways and local superspreading events [103] (which show up in the phylogeny in a similar way as in the infection trees in Fig. 23.2 ). It has lately even provided hot trails for contact tracing [104] . Phylogenetic analysis has furthermore backed up estimates for transmission properties such as the bottleneck size (the number of virions required for an infection), supporting the notion of substantial transmission heterogeneity, as even a few virions appear to suffice for a successful infection [104] . Another interesting recent finding was the low genetic variability within superspreading clusters. During the early stage of spreading of COVID-19 in the United States, a superspreading study analyzing 118 infection cases in a skilled nursing facility essentially found a monoclonal genealogical fingerprint (59 of the genomes were found to be identical) and a somewhat larger, though still relatively low, genetic variability in a larger superspreading event at a conference [64] . These results underscore that superspreading events may exhibit rather little (if any) immune escape. It is indeed plausible that new genetic variants are not bred through superspreading, if it is understood to mean that many individuals are infected by a single person. Genetic variation is more likely to increase by sequential passage through many immunologically diverse individuals. (This is exactly how gain-offunction experiments are conducted, after all [21, 22] , which makes one wonder whether it is really always a good idea to follow the intuitive impulse to "flatten the curve". 24 ) After a series of infections, subsequent superspreading events may however play a key role in selecting and amplifying some of rare genetic variants, and in distributing them widely through the population, while others erratically die out [103, 105] , similarly as discussed above for whole epidemics. In summary, much as the spreading of pathogens in real space, also their genetic dynamics is highly nonlinear and governed by substantial heterogeneity. It is dominated by the combined effects of repeated passages through narrow population bottlenecks that can produce mutational bursts, followed by proliferation bursts within the infected organisms and superspreading among them. The spread and amplification of emerging variants effected by this repeated chain of events goes under the name of "founder effect" in genetics [105] . As an important consequence of the population-genetic heterogeneity, the mitigation of epidemics of fast mutating pathogens (such as RNA viruses) by pharmaceuticals or vaccination is a very subtle task. Modeling suggests that a widespread distribution of vaccines that afford imperfect immunization and sterilization during an ongoing epidemic may result in a wide range of potential epidemiological and evolutionary outcomes [106] . In particular, attempts to suppress pathogen spreading in a population by vaccination can promote spreading in gene space. Similar as with antibiotic resistances, infections after waning immunity would be key potential contributors to viral immune escapes via so-called antigenic drift, which may possibly already set in at relatively low vaccination rates [107] . This is currently also a concern in the context of COVID-19 [108] [109] [110] . It is therefore imperative to determine the strength and duration of clinical protection and sterile immunity in order to avoid negative impacts. And, similarly as with other mitigation strategies, it is crucial to address the population heterogeneity and selectively target pertinent cohorts to avoid compromising the potential benefits, e.g., by incubating escape mutants in non-vulnerable cohorts [47] [48] [49] . While pathogen superspreading is commonly ascribed to individual supershedders or socially highly connected hubs, there appears to exist another, more subtle and more worrisome type of superspreading events for rapidly mutating germs. It is characterized by close encounters of many infectious and susceptible individuals under incubator-like conditions, say, at overcrowded parties or similar "3C" 17 events. In terms of network theory, one thus deals with (temporarily) strongly interconnected host clusters, which favor co-infections [88] , so that one may also speak of "cluster infections". Under such conditions, which do not rely on individual superspreaders [6, 103] , both the overall pathogen concentration and its genetic diversity may peak simultaneously, thus likely resulting in burstlike outbreaks both on the population and genetic level. This has important epidemiological and genetic consequences. Namely, on the one hand, it means that a state that would be classified as epidemiologically stable by the conventional test-tube models (that replace heterogeneous distributions by averages) gets a great chance to conspicuously reveal its actual metastability 8 . On the other hand, it implies that the larger genetic diversity of the invading pathogen ensemble provides it with exceptional opportunities to cope with the immunological diversity of the host population and, moreover, with a unique platform for genetic competition and cooperation. There is then a greatly increased chance for synergistic mutations, reassortments, and recombinations to bring together independent mutations, akin to what happens inside immunocompromised patients [111] . Pathogen evolution is thereby considerably accelerated, and viable new variants may emerge via so-called antigenic shift [20] , which would otherwise be quite unlikely. To distinguish such incubator-type infections from superspreader transmissions involving supershedders and hubs, alone, one could characterize them as cooperative superspreading (or "superbreeding") events [7] . Instead of a monoclonal pathogen meeting a single host organism, such superbreeding involves the encounter of a genetically diverse pathogen population with a similarly diverse population of immune systems. It is an intriguing speculation, whether the associated population-genetic heterogeneities and nonlinearities could possibly give rise to so-called explosive growth regimes (e.g., during the carnival week), similar to what is predicted for certain contagious social spreading processes [112] . Could this then possibly also help to explain a sudden burst-like emergence of pathogen subtypes and variants that can largely evade the pre-existing and vaccine-induced immunity in their host population [7, 105, 110] ? On a more conceptual note, in such situations, where (back-and-forth) mutations are frequent, the fitness of an individual genotype becomes meaningless and the target of natural selection is no longer the fastest growing replicator but rather a whole cloud of mutants (of continuously changing prevalence). Of which the catalogued subtypes and variants represent merely the tip of the iceberg [19] . This cloud is the so-called quasispecies, which can collectively outperform single competing genotypes, even fitter ones, via the "quasispecies effect" or "survival of the flattest" [113] . Put simply, having too many mutations in a genome, most of which will be deleterious or at best neutral, can drive a population to extinction ("Muller's ratchet"). But also too few mutations can cause extinction, namely by rendering a population unable to survive changes in the environment, and to recover its genetic diversity after drastic population reductions in bottlenecks [52] . Quasispecies evolution thus allows fast mutating microbes to strike an optimum balance between evolvability and structural preservation [19] . Importantly, the quasispecies cloud should not be imagined as simple collections of mutants but rather as groups of interactive variants, which reappear after each bottleneck, via a stupendous replication burst that may boost their numbers from a handful of virions to many billions. This allows for an effective sampling of large parts of the available sequence space, and concomitant phenotypic expansions, so that each quasispecies genome swarm in an infected individual is unique and new [114] . Each genetic and phenotypic pattern then contributes collectively to the characteristics of the microbial population, helping its resilience and colonization of complex ecosystems [7] . Many consequences of quasispecies dynamics run counter to traditional views of microbial behavior and evolution and have profound implications for the understanding of viral disease. An example is the apparent paradox that attenuated RNA viruses from vaccines can occasionally revert to more virulent forms, thereby revealing their "quasispecies memory". A plausible case is polio [7] , for which the World Health Organization has over the last few years consistently reported more deaths through vaccination than from wild-type infections. Another example of quasispecies dynamics at work should be the above mentioned cooperative superspreading events [105] . They may be suspected to play a major role in the spread of various viral diseases [6, 19, 103] , including the seasonal flu, which infects between 5 and 15% of the world's human population every year, causing several million cases of severe illness, and hundred thousands of respiratory deaths. As previously for SARS and MERS, sequencing indicates that the quasispecies concept also applies to SARS-CoV-2. A considerable intrahost genetic heterogeneity was detected [87] , and quasispecies were seen to differ from one day to the next, as well as between anatomical sites [115] . In vivo, these viruses thus all appear as complex and dynamic variant distributions (not properly resolved by oral or nasal swabs alone). So they are potentially capable of producing staggering cooperative mutational bursts. It remains an open question whether these can account for the mystifying assembly of omicron [110] . It should not come as a surprise, then, that the development of effective sterilising vaccines to halt quasispecies epidemics is notoriously difficult, as testified by empirical studies under well-controlled settings for both human popula- tions [13] and their livestock [10] . Even if vaccination reduces the number of influenza infections by a particular strand, meta-analysis cannot detect a systematic reduction of the overall number of influenza-like illness episodes [116, 117] . Other pathogens or variants seem to happily fill the gap [118, 119] . Enthusiastic claims that "real-time practical forecasts" of the seasonal flu can be achieved "by leveraging historical and modern experimental assays and gene sequences" [120] to improve vaccination and disease control have to be gauged against this bleak empirical evidence, as well as against Fig. 23 .3 25 . It exemplifies (for Europe) that the worldwide seasonal flu has seemingly just been extinguished. The effect appears to be insensitive to a countries' "stringency index" or "containment and health index", and neither vaccination nor forecasting can claim credit for it. One can conclude that, with fast mutating RNA viruses, vaccinologists face similar heterogeneities and nonlinear effects (yielding unexpected and counterintuitive outcomes), on the level of a virus population, as epidemiologists experience with measures targeting cohorts of its host population [18] . They are recently particularly worried by a possible negative impact of repeated influenza vaccination on vaccine responsiveness and vaccine effectiveness (protection from infection) [121] . And they warn that with improved vaccine efficacy and wider application comes a heightened risk for immune escape, thus likely creating the right conditions for a significant zoonotic transfer leading to a pandemic [20] . To reduce such risks, current flu-vaccine developments aim at highly conserved parts of viruses, and, on the same grounds, researchers advise against antiviral monotherapy (use of a single antiviral agent) [19, 122] . Other major examples of the stunning ability of biological systems to defeat our attempts at mitigation in similar ways include the worldwide spread of antibiotic resistance genes across distantly related bacteria, crossing species, and phylum boundaries and physical locations; the rapid evolution of cancers in the face of chemical attack; and the ability of HIV to out-adapt treatment. Which prompted the authors of Ref. [123] to draw a bold analogy between the fundamental limitations to current medical practice and attempts to design integrated circuits without a fundamental knowledge of quantum electronics and semiconductor physics. The foregoing paragraphs have provided a glimpse as to why there has recently been increasing mutual interest and synergies between the fields of epidemiology and eco-evolutionary dynamics. Thanks to the rapid recent development of micro-manipulation techniques, sequencing, and synthetic biology, epidemiologists can now increasingly resolve and harness the crucial dynamics in the "genomic sector" of the complex, multi-layered process of disease spreading. In return, the traditional, descriptive approach to evolution has increasingly given way to a bona-fide experimental science. The modern perspective on evolution has thereby naturally become more microbe-centric, and better aligned with the fact that most of life is microbial, and all life primarily relies on microbial processes. And it has embraced the notion that ecological and evolutionary time scales may often mutually interfere much more than admitted by some core postulates of the traditional theories of evolution (and epidemiology, for that matter) in terms of the "Central Dogma" or "Modern Synthesis" [124] . Microbial species have a number of unique characteristics that are not captured by conventional ecological and evolutionary theory, chiefly their rapid evolution, horizontal gene transfer, their ability to produce public goods, toxins and antibiotics, and their complex feedback with hosts [125] . This complexity may partly be attributed to genetic variability, but recent research has moreover underscored a remarkable ability for phenotypic diversification [126] . Progress in the field is now boosted by real-time laboratory studies of the ecoevolutionary dynamics of bacteria and viruses, which are ideal models for that purpose. Physicists (in particular statistical mechanicians) have become major contributors, eager to exploit interdisciplinary synergies between the converging fields of mathematical and evolutionary biology, ecology, epidemiology, gametheory, and non-equilibrium statistical physics [123] . Their ambitious long-term aim is to create a fundamental understanding of how the unique self-referential dynamics of evolution (in which the conventional distinction between the physical data and its governing laws is largely abolished) arises as a universality class from the molecular processes, via an extreme version of non-equilibrium statistical physics. This development nurtures hopes for future progress in epidemiology and vaccinology that could lead to a much deeper level of understanding and possibly to smarter, scientifically better grounded mitigation strategies. Apart from being confounded with gene spreading, epidemic spreading is also closely intertwined with information spreading. As more extensively discussed in the contribution by Platteau and coworkers in Chapter 22 of this volume, game theory can help to address many of the difficult, multi-layered problems resulting from this additional complication. Here, I want to focus on a particularly interesting aspect, namely information feedback with frustration. First, to briefly clarify the relevance of information feedback, let me note the obvious: while pathogens spread through a population, its members may acquire and evaluate knowledge about the spreading process and adjust their behavior accordingly [8] . That animals can discriminate infectious individuals by their scent [127] suggests that this feedback effect is not limited to human populations. It allows individuals to act according to their own judicious risk assessment. Such information flow between agents and/or feedback about the state of the community can generate very complex dynamics, where small causes can have disproportionately large effects [128] . Mathematically speaking, one deals with a layered process of (piggyback) disease spreading plus superimposed information spreading. The latter acts very similarly to a competing infectious strain in a multilayered ("multiplex") network, as discussed in Chapter 19 of this volume. And there is indeed new evidence from mobility surveys to support the notion that it is actually information about the spreading process (rather than centrally imposed mitigation orders, say), which arguably has the strongest impact on pertinent behavioral change in an epidemic -see, e.g., Fig. 23 .4 26 and Refs. [40, 68, 71, 129] . In this respect, the infected population may be viewed as an agent-based algorithm, employing swarm-intelligence in order to collectively outsmart the spreading pathogen, in a self-organized way [40, 130] . This distinctive feature of epidemiological dynamics has various profound practical, social, and political implications, further elaborated in Sec. 23.14. Frustration is a special characteristic feature deeply ingrained in epidemiological information feedback, though maybe not quite so obviously. Game theoretic tournaments have proven follow-the-crowd or herding strategies of social copying to be surprisingly successful [131] . In particular, they may drive swarms or flocks towards a so-called non-equilibrium critical state, with a large susceptibility to external stimuli. The latter may help swarms to defy predators by generating large-scale coherent response patterns [132] . However, in the case of disease spreading, such herding, which "aligns" individuals, usually with some time delay [133] , is not at all a smart reaction. In this context, swarm formation essentially either describes the epidemic spreading of the pathogen itself, or some equally unfavorable panic reaction in the host population. Indeed, epidemic diseases are known to trigger psychological and sociological patterns in human societies that can themselves be analyzed in epidemic terms [134, 135] . Helped by the dominant fear culture in the media [136] 27 , such psychic epidemics can seize whole societies, undermine and disrupt their social fabric, and make them slip into primitive collectivism and so-called mass formation [137, 138] . How would a smart reaction instead look like? From the perspective of an infected population, quantifying the "best" counter-strategy and the "cost" of an epidemic can become exceedingly difficult, due to the high dimensionality of the notion of cost and its heterogeneity across the population. As discussed above, the specific threats due to the spreading of the disease may be very unevenly distributed throughout a population. Furthermore, they need to be gauged in a context of other diseases [139] and the economic and social costs of mitigation measures [32, 33] , which may be distributed quite differently but also very unevenly. Therefore, it is highly unlikely that a globally applicable one-fits all optimum solution exists. This introduces the crucial element of frustration, as one would say in physics, suggesting that the host population might try out a reciprocal strategy of decoherence. Frustrated systems stand out in that the desired optimum can not be reached by any uniform rule but instead requires a broad diversity of strategies. In this respect, they are reminiscent of glasses and spin glasses in physics, which have challenged condensed-matter physicists for decades and still remain enigmatic (despite all theoretical progress honored by the 2021 Nobel prize in physics 28 ). Briefly, if an ensemble of magnetic moments suddenly and spontaneously undergoes a phase transition to a state of collective alignment upon cooling, one speaks of a ferromagnet. This is the physical analog to the mentioned groupthink strategy of social copying, and the outcome is mass formation [138] . However, in strongly disordered magnets (as in realworld epidemics), global alignment is not a favorable option. One then speaks of a frustrated system. The magnetic moments start to search and compete for very complex, disordered low-energy configurations in a highly degenerate, rugged free-energy landscape, which entices them into exceptionally slow, nonstationary dynamics. And this description comes much closer to the problem faced by a population invaded by a pathogen than a ferromagnet. To break down the essence of frustration to a comparatively simple example, consider the so-called minority game [140] , which was originally devised to elucidate the workings of market economies. It can, with some qualification, indeed formally be mapped onto a spin-glass problem and has been studied analytically by the replica method [141] . In this game, each participating agent has only two options to choose from, which may naturally be named "go" (i.e., go out to get work done, food organised, etc.) and "stay" (i.e., stay at home to avoid overly crowded situations), in an epidemiological context. The spreading pathogen would clearly "prefer" its host agent to join the majority or best follow a globally coherent rule, in order to optimize its spreading. The agent, instead, tries to anticipate the future moves of everybody else in the game, in order to decide how to best end up among the minority (going out when streets are empty, staying home when they are crowded). To this end, each agent is endowed with a set of (random) strategies or predictors that guide its decision to stay or go. A strategy rises or falls in esteem, based on whether it gets the individual into the minority or not. In this way, each agent builds a personal decision matrix, which may evolve over time, according to its experience. Intriguingly, if the game is played on a computer or with human players, it turns out that the population soon self-organizes so that attendance fluctuates near an optimum value, without external guiding. The fact that the agents use different strategies to predict what the majority will do, is however essential for the spontaneous emergence of a smart solution. There is no "representative agent", and what matters is the interaction between all the agents' individual decision making processes. The best solution arises from the interplay of many diverse individual strategies. In fact, the quality of the solution deteriorates if too many agents align their strategies, which may give rise to so-called pork cycles (everybody staying home today because the streets where crowded yesterday). Even worse, if the population gets dominated by trend-followers rather than minority seekers, the subtle optimal mode of decoherent cooperativity may catastrophically collapse [142] . Besides, to a lesser degree, it also deteriorates if the predictors become more sophisticated than required by the actual behavioral complexity of the population as a whole (or, alternatively, if the latter is artifi-cially too much suppressed). In economical terms, the latter limit corresponds to the paradigm of a perfectly efficient market, where smart strategies cannot beat random strategies, and there is nothing to gain by adaptive behavior. Translated into the epidemiological context, the take-home message from the minority game is thus very much what was already emphasized above: for a population to cope well with an epidemic, it is crucial that all individuals have access to accurate and unambiguous empirical data about the course of the epidemic, and that they can make up and freely follow their best individual risk assessments and optimization strategies [130] . A counter argument that is sometimes raised (in discord with empirical findings, as it seems [40] ) against such highly individualized optimization strategies is that they might fail to protect some particularly vulnerable minorities. However, given their low cost compared to certain excessively expensive, intrusive, and potentially harmful alternative strategies that have recently been tried (lockdowns, emergency mass vaccination programs), they leave ample resources for that purpose. According to the above conclusions, a central task of epidemiologists should be to supply the public with reliable pertinent real-time data about an unfolding epidemic, in the spirit of weather reports. For several reasons, this is not an easy task, however. First, data are often poorly standardized, marred by reporting delays, and scarce and statistically unreliable when most urgently needed, namely during the early stage of a new epidemic. Secondly, the very diverse ways raw data for various parameters are acquired, evaluated, and graphically presented may impede their appropriate interpretation by the public. Figure 23 .5 may serve to illustrate the point: initially the widely reported case numbers, which were not normalized to test frequency (if to anything at all) suggested that Iceland and somewhat later also Sweden were hit very hard compared to the UK and particularly Germany. Considering instead the cumulative mortality after the first infection wave, one could have concluded instead that Iceland had had no epidemic, while Sweden and the UK had been similarly severely hit. Moreover, by the end of 2021, the daily German death rates turned out to be roughly an order of magnitude above Iceland's and Sweden's, with an all-time case fatality rate (CFR) 30% above Sweden's. Sweden had taken by far the most relaxed attitude, almost exclusively relying on the voluntary action of its citizens 19 , a policy eventually adopted by Iceland 24 when its so-called 7-day incidence was close to 4× Germany's ( Fig. 23.6 ) and 25× Sweden's. So, what should the man in the street make of all this? Also, whether a country's outcome of the epidemic depends on its government and media leaning more toward the threat-denial or the fear-mongering side, seems a matter of debate [143] . For example, the Russian government was accused to have contributed to the country's comparatively high number of COVID-related excess mortality (possibly as high as 20% in 2020 [144] ) by downplaying the COVID threat. But such accusations would probably not be raised against the Spanish government, although Spain's excess mortality (about 14% [145] ) was not so far off. In any case, the communication between governments and the public could be prone to considerable nonlinear effects. As a case study plausibly suggests, unconvincing or inadequately communicated government rigour, however well-intentioned, risks to trigger adverse reactions of their citizens that can exacerbate the impact of an epidemic [146] . In this light, the lockdowns of a whole country (New Zealand) and parts of one of the world's largest container ports (China), each in response to a single positive case in August 2021, may have been counterproductive, as they conveyed an unrealistically exaggerated threat to the public; especially, if gauged against the low or even insignificant excess mortalities in countries that coped with a range of far less drastic, mostly voluntary interventions, such as Japan [40] and Sweden 19 (or also Germany, for which a government-commissioned investigation found that the health system was at no time in danger of being overwhelmed 29 ) [145] . On top of all these perplexing and seemingly inconsistent observations, there are other, less fateful problems, mainly related to poor data handling and presentation, against which politicians, the media, and even health-care officials 30 are apparently not immune. To pick an illustrative example, during the early COVID-19 pandemic, the Süddeutsche Zeitung, a widely read German newspaper, regularly reported the time series of the cumulative PCR-positive cases 29 by plotting them in a fixed square-shaped frame. By the necessary rescaling of the daily expanding time axis, the sub-exponential and eventually saturating growth process ended up being displayed as a progressively steepening curve. This malpractice (which would certainly deserve to be included in one of Edward R. Tufte's fabulous books on data visualization) only stopped in late April 2020, not too long before the curve would have degenerated into a meaningless step function. And a systematic empirical study of the mainstream-media's coverage of the first year of the pandemic detected a serious lack of contextualization and awareness of scientific uncertainties and debate, plus a significant bias in favor of politicians of the ruling parties and hard authoritarian interventionsprompting the authors to raise the question whether fighting a pandemic can be such an obvious priority as to override the standards of diverse and balanced reporting 31 . As a rule, journalists, politicians, and the wider public tend to underestimate the substantial uncertainties inherent in scientific modeling and debate, and are prone to trust individual favorable model predictions beyond their range of validity [147] . Moreover, in a retrospective study of the British BSE crisis, scholars did not attest politicians who claimed to "follow the science" much credibility. Instead, they concluded that "secrecy allowed ministers and senior officials to maintain the public pretence that [. . . ] policies were based on secure scientific foundations, while privately acknowledging that regulations were being decided entirely on political rather than scientific grounds" [148] . In the more recent COVID-19 context, although the World Health Organization recommends that, to be able to successfully fight an epidemic, policy makers should "inform, empower and listen to communities" 32 , a report by Amnesty International 33 finds that, "governments have curtailed freedom of expression instead of encouraging it". Convinced that tightening surveillance and influencing behaviour are "central to public policy, and government (sic) can draw on a potentially powerful new set of tools" 34 , some politicians have actively sought psychological 34 and technical 35 expert advice how to spy on and to nudge (rather than better inform) the public in a crisis. And a growing research community is now studying the spreading and artificial-intelligence aided [149] collection, analysis, and blocking of misinformation diffusing through the world wide web, in order to fight "the first global infodemic 36 " [150] and to further develop the art of censorship, in general [151] . Advancing internet censorship 37 31 36 which is associated with exponential growth and overabundance of information and can seriously impact on the course of an epidemic, according to the World Health Organization 37 . . . and stowing away statistical data, because it is prone to misinterpretation; see, e.g., L. Brownlie, The National 2022: http://www.thenational.scot/news/19931745.covid-dat a-will-not-published-concerns-misrepresented-anti-vaxxers; A. Mandavilli, The New can be understood as a type of information-layer equivalent of what lockdowns attempt in real space. The declared aim is to mitigate an epidemic indirectly, via central control of the superimposed information spreading. A telling example is provided by two blogs published by Tomas Pueyo and Aaron Ginn on March 10 and 20, respectively, on the web-platform Medium. Both blogs quickly went viral, acquiring millions of views within days, thereby spreading awareness of the pandemic. Pueyo advocated lockdowns (to restrain an otherwise allegedly 12 unrestricted exponential growth of infections), whereas Ginn's blog questioned their adequacy, warning of hysteria -and was deleted within 24 hours 38 . While it is quite unlikely (if only due the language barrier) that these two blogs have decisively affected the almost perfectly concurrent sharp turning points in the mobility pattern observed in Germany (Fig. 23.4) , censors seem to act as if they did. A common argument is that the public needs likewise to be protected from hazardous misinformation as from biological pathogens. However, an alternative solution, more in line with democratic principles 39 , could be to offer filters such as News Guard's browser extension Internet Trust Tool for safe, supervised news consumption to those particularly scared of misinformation, and let the others read, think, and decide for themselves. Above all, this raises the question: who decides what is right or wrong, trustworthy information, and mis-, mal-and disinformation 40 [152] ? Should it be the administrators of LinkedIn, who temporarily suspended and then reinstated the account of Robert Malone, who is widely respected for his seminal contributions to mRNA-vaccine development 41 ? Or those of Twitter who recently suspended his account, to the dismay of half a million followers? Or better YouTube's, who censored the epidemiologist Knut Wittkowski 14 ? Or is it Facebook's certified 42 third-party fact checkers, who first banned the so-called lab-leak theory, together with millions of other contents (including the accounts of New York University researchers who investigated such practices 43 ), but later changed their minds 44 [153] ? What if the editors in chief of one of the world's top most cited general medical journals have a point, who, in an open letter to Mark Zuckerberg, complain about a fact check as "inaccurate, incompetent and irresponsible" [154] ? Can it be that "Facebook is trying to control how people think under the guise of 'fact checking' ?" [155] and that such fact checking activity has "enforced falsehoods about the pandemic's origins, never evaluated the evidence, never apologized, and was never held accountable" 45 ? Maybe not all too surprisingly, two years into the ongoing pandemic, facing a series of scandals with fishy data handling and communication by corporate and official sources, legacy media write about a "pandemic of ignorance" 46 and reveal that the US Centers of Disease Control and Prevention (CDC) have withheld critical data on the COVID pandemic for up to a year over fear that the information might be misinterpreted and "because basically, at the end of the day, it's not yet ready for prime time" 37 . Again, whether "mistrust in the authorities" is indeed "a complex problem that needs a holistic approach [. . . ] of journalists, fact-checkers, policymakers, government entities, social media platforms" and demands a "call to arms" [150] , or whether it is rather indicative of their failure to properly "inform, empower and listen to communities" 32 , seems debatable. Finally, also the scientific debate itself does not take place in an ivory tower. Due to a widespread feeling of urgency, the scientific publishing process has often been accelerated during the latest pandemic [156, 157] , and the exploitation of this trend by scientists "surfing the COVID-19 scientific wave" [158] has become a concern. Worse, there is circumstancial, formal, and judicial possible evidence that science is becoming increasingly politicized [159] as well as manipulated by governments and corporations, and that "legitimate tools of regulation within science have become weaponized" [160, 161] . 47 According to the assessment of two renowned experts on business ethics and philosophy of science, these are not merely isolated cases, accidental mistakes, and coincidences. The authors rather see a pattern of systematic political abuse of science [162] . In this context, the well documented historical malpractices of the tobacco industry may provide an instructive cautionary paradigm. The release of millions of internal documents as a result of the Master Settlement Agreement in 1998 revealed a systematic manipulation of research on health risks associated with smoking; e.g., by launching a public relations campaign about "junk science" and "good epidemiological practices" and creating fake controversy under the motto "doubt is our product" [163] , heavily exploiting the penchant of the press for controversy and its often naive notion of balance [164] . Similarly aggressive or "disruptive" covert marketing patterns have more recently been documented for the health industry, e.g., during the (arguably mislabelled) swine flu pandemic and elsewhere [165] [166] [167] [168] . Most recently, documents obtained through a freedom-of-information-act request have prompted accusations that leading virologists colluded to mislead the world with regard to the plausible scenarios for the origin of SARS-CoV-2. 48 Altogether, one may eventually feel drawn to the somewhat paradox conclusion that we are facing an information crisis while virtually drowning in information. And in the face of the heterogeneous character and the sheer complexity of epidemic spreading, this can make one worry as to how much all our scientific and information technological advances can in the end really help us to outsmart a major epidemic. Throughout this chapter, I have emphasized the effects of phenotypical, social, spatial, and genetic heterogeneities on epidemic spreading. It may thus be read as a warning that the deceptively simple conventional epidemiological models, in which most of this complexity is swept under the rug, should not be taken too literally. The bottom line is that, in epidemics, the tail often wags the dog. There is a subtle interplay of eco-evolutionary pathogen dynamics with broadly distributed transmissibility, social connectivity, and spatial mobility patterns. They render epidemics a manifestation of a very complex dynamical system. A breakdown of large-scale determinism, associated with erratic burst dynamics, superspreading events, high tail risks, and a failure of SIR-type forecasting and global disease management practices, was identified as a potential major consequence. Attempts to contain infectious disease spreading by pharmaceutical and non-pharmaceutical interventions need to face its multi-layered character: heterogeneous spatiotemporal spreading is intertwined with heterogeneous genetic spreading, and attempts to suppress the former may promote the latter, creating potentially worrisome immune escape variants. Figure 23 .6 displays normalized German COVID case numbers to wrap up and illustrate some of these points. The dynamics exhibits large irregular fluctuations, featuring substantial upward and downward excursions, as well as considerable spatial scatter. That such non-trivial heterogeneities persist on the spatial scales of larger parts of a densely populated country like Germany, and on time scales of years, is suggestive of poor spatiotemporal self-averaging. There appear to be extended phases of close temporal synchronization, during which the averaged incidences exhibit exponential growth and decay, at diverse rates. Whether and how these patterns emerge from the local case numbers may be contingent on the "art of averaging" [43] , though. One may also perceive an underlying long-term trend of exponentially increasing infection numbers. If real, it could be indicative of a "directed" evolution of the rates and affinities of the pathogen-host chemistry by antigenic drift and selection. We may then be witnessing an evolutionary self-selection of increasingly contagious variants, acting as drivers of the repeated infection waves via repeated mutational bursts. And a linear net increase of effective binding energies would then account for a trend of exponentially increasing infection numbers, across the train of repeated reinfection waves. Other factors, such as seasonal effects, information feedback, and state regulations, should certainly not light-handedly be dismissed. Above, I have stressed particularly the role of spreading information about the course of the epidemic. This feedback effect is intricately intertwined, on yet another superimposed level, with the already complex spatiotemporal and genetic spreading dynamics. Game theory hints at the timely feedback and public sharing of accurately contextualized information as key elements of a potential counter-tactic that harnesses swarm intelligence to mitigate the impact of an epidemic. However, just in the midst of the information era, there appear to be technological, political, economic, and social trends that threaten to cut down on this genuinely human strength. We must fear to forgo the potential benefits that could be reaped by bringing our swarm intelligence to bear against the swarm algorithms executed by invading pathogens. Which prompts me to close this chapter by recalling D. A. Henderson's 49 "overriding principle" of epidemiology, namely that "experience has shown that communities faced with epidemics or other adverse events respond best and with the least anxiety when the normal social functioning of the community is least disrupted" [32] , and C. G. Jung's insistent warnings that there is no adequate protection against psychic epidemics, which are infinitely more devastating than the worst of natural catastrophes. mr na-inventors-account-after-deleting-it-for-spreading-misinformation 42 by the Poynter Institute for Media Studies, whose donors include the Charles Koch Institute, the National Endowment for Democracy, the Omidyar Network, Google, and Facebook [152], and which seems to fiddle even with the Wayback Machine The Verge Brownian motion: a paradigm of soft matter and biological physics The law of mass-action in epidemiology: A historical perspective Superspreading and the effect of individual variation on disease emergence Just 2% of SARS-CoV-2-positive individuals carry 90% of the virus circulating in communities Infectious Diseases of Humans. Dynamics and Control Superspreading events without superspreaders: Using high attack rate events to estimate n0 for airborne transmission of COVID-19. medRxiv Quasispecies diversity determines pathogenesis through cooperative interactions in a viral population Dynamical interplay between awareness and epidemic spreading in multiplex networks Viruses: agents of evolutionary invention Herd immunity to newcastle disease virus in poultry by vaccination For-profit long-term care homes and the risk of COVID-19 outbreaks and resident deaths Association between prison crowding and COVID-19 incidence rates in Massachusetts prisons Outbreak of influenza in highly vaccinated crew of U.S. Navy ship War Epidemics: An Historical Geography of Infectious Diseases in Military Conflict and Civil Strife Next generation bioweapons: the technology of genetic engineering applied to biowarfare and bioterrorism The US military commitment to vaccine development: A REFERENCES century of successes and challenges The state of science, microbiology, and vaccines circa 1918 Natural Selection on the Influenza Virus Genome Viral quasispecies An antigenic thrift-based approach to influenza vaccine design. Vaccines Why do exceptionally dangerous gain-of-function experiments in influenza? Meth Might SARS-CoV-2 have arisen via serial passage through an animal host or cell culture? Opinion: To stop the next pandemic, we need to unravel the origins of COVID-19 Investigate the origins of COVID-19 Mathematical Models in Epidemiology A contribution to the mathematical theory of epidemics Bats, pangolins, minks and other animals -villains or victims of SARS-CoV-2? SARS-CoV-2 exposure in wild white-tailed deer (Odocoileus virginianus) Mass culling of minks to protect the COVID-19 vaccines: is it rational? The effect of travel restrictions on the spread of the 2019 novel coronavirus (COVID-19) outbreak Effect estimates of COVID-19 non-pharmaceutical interventions are non-robust and highly model-dependent Disease mitigation measures in the control of pandemic influenza Covid-19 lockdown cost/benefits: A critical assessment of the literature The relation between length of lockdown, numbers of infected people and deaths of covid-19, and economic growth of countries: Lessons learned to cope with future pandemics similar to covid-19 and to constrain the deterioration of economic system Promises made to be broken: Performance and performativity in digital vaccine and immunity certification Did lockdowns serve their purpose? Government mandated lockdowns do not reduce Covid-19 deaths: implications for evaluating the stringent New Zealand response Assessing mandatory stay-at-home and business closure effects on the spread of COVID-19 COVID-19: Rethinking the lockdown groupthink Japan's voluntary lockdown Was Germany's lockdown in spring 2020 necessary? How bad data quality can turn a simulation into a delusion that shapes the future The Johns Hopkins Institute for Applied Economics, Global Health, and the Study of Business Enterprise Mathematical Epidemiology of Infectious Diseases: Model Building, Analysis, and Interpretation The Age-Related Risk of Severe Outcomes Due to COVID-19 Infection: A Rapid Review Age-specific mortality and immunity patterns of SARS-CoV-2 ECDC Public Health Emergency Team et al. High impact of COVID-19 in long-term care facilities, suggestion for monitoring in the EU/EEA Pre-activated antiviral innate immunity in the upper airways controls early sars-cov-2 infection in children Why are we vaccinating children against covid-19? Long COVID symptoms and duration in sars-cov-2 positive children -a nationwide cohort study Power-law population heterogeneity governs epidemic waves Epidemic processes in complex networks Why are viral genomes so fragile? The bottleneck hypothesis Properties of highly clustered networks Modelling disease spread through random and regular contacts in clustered populations Linked: The New Science of Networks The web of human sexual contacts Identification of influential spreaders in complex networks Unification of theoretical approaches for epidemic spreading on complex networks Infection dynamics on scale-free networks Bursts. The Hidden Patterns Behind Everything We Do Tail risk of contagious diseases Ubiquitous power law scaling in nonlinear self-excited hawkes processes The Universal Laws of Life Phylogenetic analysis of SARS-CoV-2 in Boston highlights the impact of superspreading events SARS-CoV-2 outbreak investigation in a german meat processing plant Outbreak caused by the SARS-CoV-2 Omicron variant in Norway Analysis of the dynamics, outcome, and prerequisites of the first German SARS-CoV-2 superspreading event. medRxiv Update on SARS-CoV-2 infection risks in long-distance trains, 2020. Deutsche Bahn Catch me (if you can): assessing the risk of SARS-CoV-2 transmission via euro cash Outdoor Transmission of SARS-CoV-2 and Other Respiratory Viruses: A Systematic Review Mobility network models of COVID-19 explain inequities and inform reopening Die Reise unserer Gene: Eine Geschichteüber uns und unsere Vorfahren Epidemics and History: Disease, Power and Imperialism Born to Die: Disease and New World Conquest Increased frequency of travel in the presence of crossimmunity may act to decrease the chance of a global pandemic Persistence of immunity to SARS-CoV-2 over time in the ski resort Ischgl Mansueto Institute for Urban Innovation Research Paper No. 19 Patterns of spread in biological invasions dominated by long-distance jump dispersal: Insights from argentine ants Diffusion in curved spacetimes Hot Brownian motion Acceleration of evolutionary spread by longrange dispersal A generalized-growth model to characterize the early ascending phase of infectious disease outbreaks The Gompertz growth of COVID-19 outbreaks is caused by super-spreaders Plight of the fortune tellers When individual behaviour matters: homogeneous and network models in epidemiology Community transmission and viral load kinetics of the SARS-CoV-2 delta (B.1.617.2) variant in vaccinated and unvaccinated individuals in the UK: a prospective, longitudinal, cohort study Mutational signatures and heterogeneous host response revealed via large-scale characterization of SARS-CoV-2 genomic diversity Patterns of within-host genetic diversity in SARS-CoV-2. eLife Network theory and SARS: predicting outbreak diversity Equivalence and its invalidation between non-Markovian and Markovian spreading dynamics on complex networks Effective population size in ecology and evolution Discontinuous epidemic transition due to limited testing Evidence that coronavirus superspreading is fat-tailed Ebola virus disease in health care workers-Sierra Leone SARS-CoV-2 Transmission among Marine Recruits during Quarantine Forecasting for COVID-19 has failed Four stylized facts about COVID-19. NBER Working Paper, No. w27719 Epidemic forecasting is messier than weather forecasting: The role of human behavior and internet data streams in epidemic forecast Mutations of bacteria from virus sensitivity to virus resistance The population genetics and evolutionary epidemiology of RNA viruses 17th century variola virus reveals the recent history of smallpox Genomic reconstruction of the sars-cov-2 epidemic in england Superspreading in the emergence of COVID-19 variants Genomic epidemiology of superspreading events in Austria reveals mutational dynamics and transmission properties of SARS-CoV-2 SARS-CoV-2 variant evolution in the United States: High accumulation of viral mutations over time likely through serial founder events and mutational bursts Epidemiological and evolutionary considerations of SARS-CoV-2 vaccine dosing regimes Is seasonal vaccination a contributing factor to the selection of influenza epidemic variants? Human Vac SARS-CoV-2 variants, spike mutations and immune escape The great escape? SARS-CoV-2 variants evading neutralizing responses Striking antibody evasion manifested by the omicron variant of SARS-CoV-2 Parallel evolution of influenza across multiple spatiotemporal scales. Elife, 6:e26875 Simplicial models of social contagion Evolution of digital organisms at high mutation rates leads to survival of the flattest Genetic diversity in rna virus quasispecies is controlled by host-virus interactions Evolution of viral quasispecies during SARS-CoV-2 infection Influenza vaccination: policy versus evidence Vaccines for preventing influenza in healthy adults Influenza-like Illness Incidence Is Not Reduced by Influenza Vaccination in a Cohort of Older Adults, Despite Effectively Reducing Laboratory-Confirmed Influenza Virus Infections Increased Risk of Noninfluenza Respiratory Virus Infections Associated With Receipt of Inactivated Influenza Vaccine Integrating genotypes and phenotypes improves longterm forecasts of seasonal influenza A/H3N2 evolution. eLife Repeat vaccination reduces antibody affinity maturation across different influenza vaccine platforms in humans Cross-reactive memory T cells associate with protection against SARS-CoV-2 infection in COVID-19 contacts Life is physics: Evolution as a collective phenomenon far from equilibrium The illusions of the modern synthesis The microbiome beyond the horizon of ecological and evolutionary theory Phenotypic diversification of microbial pathogens-cooperating and preparing for the future Scent dog identification of samples from COVID-19 patientsa pilot study Stability and diversity in collective adaptation Impact of SARS-CoV-2 on the mobility behaviour in Germany Give more data, awareness and control to individual citizens, and they will help COVID-19 containment Why copy others? Insights from the social learning strategies tournament Colloquium : Criticality and dynamical scaling in living systems Finite-size scaling at the edge of disorder in a time-delay Vicsek model Epidemic psychology: a model How epidemic psychology works on Twitter: evolution of responses to the COVID-19 pandemic in the U Fear culture in media: An examination on coronavirus discourse Die Rückkehr des Kollektivismus De psychologie van totalitarisme Relative burdens of the COVID-19, malaria, tuberculosis, and HIV/AIDS epidemics in Sub-Saharan Africa Minority Games. Interacting agents in financial markets Replica symmetry breaking in the minority game Statistical mechanics of the majority game Political beliefs affect compliance with government mandates Excess mortality in Russia and its regions compared to high income countries: An analysis of monthly series of 2020 Excess mortality due to Covid-19? A comparison of total mortality in 2020 with total mortality in 2016 to The impacts of the COVID-19 pandemic and responses from various policy actors in the Czech Republic and Slovakia in 2020: An introduction to a Special Issue Wrong, but Useful": Negotiating uncertainty in infectious disease modelling Politics of expert advice: Lessons from the early history of the BSE saga Misinformation adoption or rejection in the era of COVID-19 Fighting the COVID-19 infodemic in social media: A holistic perspective and a call to arms A dataset of statecensored tweets Covid-19: Who fact checks health and science on Facebook? The covid-19 lab leak hypothesis: did the media fall victim to a misinformation campaign Open letter from The BMJ to Mark Zuckerberg. Rapid Response to: Covid-19: Researcher blows the whistle on data integrity issues in Pfizer's vaccine trial Facebook versus the BMJ: when fact checking goes wrong Methodological quality of COVID-19 clinical research No time for that now! Qualitative changes in manuscript peer review during the Covid-19 pandemic Surfing the covid-19 scientific wave Increasing politicization and homogeneity in scientific funding: An analysis of NSF grants Freedom of expression challenged: Scientists' perspectives on hidden forms of suppression and self-censorship Retraction of scientific papers: the case of vaccine research Und die Freiheit? RIVA Tobacco industry manipulation of research Inventing conflicts of interest: A history of tobacco industry tactics Publication of fake journals raises ethical questions Routledge Handbook on the Politics of Global Health Covid-19 vaccines and treatments: we must have raw data, now