key: cord-0105601-trwki1mr authors: Ellis, George F R title: The Causal Closure of Physics in Real World Contexts date: 2020-06-01 journal: nan DOI: nan sha: 8ce5ab56e57d17bc0c88017b228893bffbaec847 doc_id: 105601 cord_uid: trwki1mr The causal closure of physics is usually discussed in a context free way. Here I discuss it in the context of engineering systems and biology, where strong emergence takes place due to a combination of upwards emergence and downwards causation [Ellis 2020]. Firstly, I show that causal closure is strictly limited in terms of spatial interactions because these are cases that are of necessity strongly interacting with the environment. Effective Spatial Closure holds ceteris parabus, and can be violated by Black Swan Events. Secondly, I show that causal closure in the hierarchy of emergence is a strictly interlevel affair, and in the cases of engineering and biology encompasses all levels from the social level to the particle physics level. However Effective Causal Closure can usefully be defined for a restricted set of levels, and one can experimentally determine Effective Theories that hold at each level. This does not however imply those effective theories are causally complete by themselves. In particular, the particle physics level is not causally complete by itself in the contexts of solid state physics (because of interlevel wave-particle duality), digital computers (where algorithms determine outcomes), or biology (because of time dependent constraints). Furthermore Inextricably Intertwined Levels occur in all these contexts. It is often supposed that causal closure occurs at the micro level in physical systems, and hence prevents the occurrence of strong emergence because the macrostate supervenes on the microstate [Kim 1998 ] [Kim 1999 ]. This is discussed in [Clayton and Davies 2006] [Hohwy and Kallestrup 2008] [Macdonald and Macdonald 2010] and [Gibb et al 2019] . In contrast, [Butterfield 2011] shows by careful philosophical argument that "One can have emergence with reduction, as well as without it; and emergence without supervenience, as well as with it." Here I want to examine the issue in a different way, by dealing in some detail with the hierarchical nature of emergence in real world contexts: the cases of engineering, based in the underlying solid state physics, and biology, based in the underlying molecular biology, in turn based in the underlying physics. The context is my paper [Ellis 2020 ] that establishes that strong emergence does indeed take place in both those cases, so that the argument against strong emergence has to be wrong in those contexts. [Ellis 2020 ] examines the issue of strong emergence of properties P of macrodynamics M out of the underlying microdynamics m in the context of condensed matter physics and biology. Following Anderson's lead [Anderson 1972 ] [Anderson 1994 ] that symmetry breaking is at the heart of emergence, its method was to identify five different kinds of symmetry breaking occurring in different contexts (Section 2.3 of [Ellis 2020] ) and then to trace how broken symmetry states at the macro and micro levels interact with each other. • This spontaneously broken macro state M reaches down to create quasiparticles such as phonons at the micro level, which play a key dynamical role at that level. 1 The base microdynamics m is altered to produce an effective microdynamics m' which breaks the symmetry of the underlying physical laws L. Thus m → m' : S(m') = m. • To derive correctly the properties of macro dynamics M from the micro dynamical level, you must coarse grain the effective theory m' rather than m. • Thus strong emergence takes place in this case: you cannot even in principle derive the macrodynamics M from the microdynamics m in a strictly bottom up way, because m satisfies the symmetry S and M does not. 2 As a consequence ( [Ellis 2020 ]: Section 4.4), in the case of solid state physics, the underlying microphysics m cannot be causally complete, because by itself it cannot lead to the emergence of known properties of solids such as electrical conductivity. The lower level physics only gives the correct outcome when modified by inclusion of terms a(M) arising from the higher level state M (so S(a) = a). The same is true for living systems. That is, in both these cases, causal completeness is only attained by considering both the low level properties m and the higher level properties M (which lead to the alteration m → m') together. The real causally closed system comprises both those levels. The aim of this paper is to extend that result by investigating causal closure of physics in terms of determining dynamic properties 3 P(d) of entities in engineering and biological contexts (I use the word closure rather than completeness for reasons that become apparent below as the theme develops). A separate very interesting project would extend this to considering the dynamic emergence of entities E(d) over time, see e.g. [Carroll 2005] . Section 2 sets the context for the discussion, which is the hierarchies of emergence in the cases of engineering and the life sciences respectively ( Table 1) . It introduce the idea of an Effective Theory ET L at each level L, and discusses bottom up and top down causation in the hierarchy of emergence (Section 2.3. Section 3 introduces the idea of a Domain of Interest (DOI), and the concept of Effective Spatial Closure (Section 3.3). It is shown that in terms of spatial interactions, causal closure in engineering and biology only holds ceteris parabus. Yes of course philosophers know that this is the case; the point is that it has real consequences in real world contexts. Section 4 defines Levels of Interest (LOI) and Section 4.4 introduces the need for Restricted Domains of Interest. Section 5 introduces Interlevel Causal Closure in the case of biology (Section 5.3), Section 6 extends this to the case of digital computers and physics. Section 7 summarizes the main results of this paper, emphasizes that unavoidable unpredictability also undermines causal closure, and comments on ways people ignore the issues raised in this paper. An Appendix considers the machine metaphor (Appendix A). The novel concepts introduced are Effective Theories ET L (Section 2.2), Effective Spatial Closure (Section 3.3), Levels of Interest (LOI) (Section 4), Effective Causal Closure (ECC) (Section 5.3), and Inextricably Intertwined Levels (IIL) (Section 5.4). The context of the discussion is the hierarchy of emergence. As stated by [Anderson 1972] , "At each level of complexity, entirely new properties appear ... At each stage entirely new laws, concepts, and generalizations are necessary." In this section, I present the nature of the hierarchy (Section 2.1), and comment on Effective Theories and the Equal Validity of Levels (Section 2.2. The latter is enabled by a combination of upward and downward causation (Section 2.3), with the key feature of multiple realisability of higher levels in terms of lower level states (Section 2.4). The crucial relation between Effective Theories and Causal Closure is briefly commented on in Section 2.5. Going into more detail as regards the hierarchical structure, it is modular (Section 2.6), with the modules forming networks (Section 2.7). The emergent hierarchy is shown in Table 1 for the cases of engineering on the left and life sciences, in particular the case of humanity, on the right. The left hand side represent The Sciences of the Artificial as discussed by [Simon 2019 ]. The right hand side represents the structures and processes of biology, as discussed by [Campbell and Reece 2005] . 3 I am using the classification in Section 2.2 of [Ellis 2020 ]. [Ellis 2016 ] and [Ellis and Drossel 2019] ). This hierarchy has important aspects. • The bottom three levels L1-L3 are the same on both sides. This is one of the great discoveries science has made: inanimate matter and living matter are made of the same stuff at the bottom. Electrons are at level L3, interacting with the nucleus. • The atomic level L3 is where new properties emerge out of the underlying physics, as characterised by the Periodic Table of the Elements, another great discovery. • The components enabling complexity to arise occur at level L4. Both semiconductors and metals are crystals, and they are the key components of machines. 4 Solid State Physics covers levels L3-L4. Biomolecules such as DNA, RNA, and proteins are the foundations of biological emergence. • Level L5 is where the basic units of complexity arise, showing functional emergent properties, and being the basis for building complex entities. On the machines side, these are devices such as transistors, light emitting diodes, photodetectors, and lasers. On the life sciences side, they are cells: the basic building block of life, which come in many different types. This is the lowest level where the processes of life occur, entailing metabolism and information processing [Hartwell et al (1999) ]. • Level L6 is where on the machine side, devices are integrated into functional units, such as the Central Processing Unit in a Microprocessor , which is itself a device. On the life sciences side, organs comprising physiological systems occur. • Level L7 is where functional units occur that have an integrity of their own: they are effectively causally closed systems imbedded in a larger environment. On the engineering side, they are machines built to carry out some purpose, such as aircraft or digital computers or particle colliders. On the life sciences side, they are individuals with autonomy of action. • Level L8 is the same on both sides. Both machines and individual human beings exist in the context of a society with social, economic, and political aspects, which sets the stage for their existence and functioning. • Finally, level L9 is again the same on both sides. It reflects the fact that each society exists in a natural environment with both ecological and geophysical aspects. Note that this Table has chosen a particular set of levels to represent causation all the way from the Particle Physics Level L1 to the Environmental Level L9. However most scientific studies will be interested in a much more restricted sets of levels: the Levels of Interest (LOIs) discussed in Section 4. Given such a choice, one will in general use a more fine-grained set of levels than represented in Table 1 . Thus for example if the LOI is (L4-L6), one might divide that range into a finer set of sublevels. It is a common belief that the lower levels are more real than the higher levels, because bottom up causation from the lower to higher levels is the source of higher level properties. Arthur Eddington in On the Nature of the Physical World ( [Eddington 1929] :5-12) muses on the dual (solid macroscopic/atomic microscopic) nature of his writing desk, and concludes (page 10) that because of the scientific world view, "The external world of physics has thus become a world of shadows. In removing our illusions we have removed the substance, for indeed we have seen that substance is one of our great illusions." However this view is subject to dispute. Richard Feynman in his book The Character of Physical Law ( [Feynman 2017 ]:125-126) considers whether one level or another is more fundamental, and using a religious metaphor, argues that 'the fundamental laws are no nearer to God than emergent laws' . 5 Phil Anderson arguably had a similar view. Sylvan Schweber commented as follows [Schweber 1993 ]: "Anderson believes in emergent laws. He holds the view that each level has its own "fundamental" laws and its own ontology. Translated into the language of particle physicists, Anderson would say each level has its effective Lagrangian and its set of quasistable particles. In each level the effective Lagrangian -the "fundamental" description at that level -is the best we can do. Thus this does not recognize any level as more fundamental than any other. Recently, Denis Noble has proposed a "Principle of Biological Relativity" [Noble 2012 ]: all levels one deals with in studying emergence in biology are equally valid, there is no privileged level of causation. Effective Theories A good way to express this is that there is a valid Effective Theory 6 (ET) at each level. Elena Castellani gives this definition [Castellani 2002] : "An effective theory (ET) is a theory which 'effectively' captures what is physically relevant in a given domain, where 'theory' is a set of fundamental equations (or simply some Lagrangian) for describing some entities, their behaviour and interactions... More precisely, an ET is an appropriate description of the important (relevant) physics in a given region of the parameter space of the physical world. In parallel to the way the functioning of the Laws of Phyiscs was sketched in [Ellis 2020 ], one can characterise an Effective Theory ET L valid at some level L as follows; An Effective Theory ET L at a level L is a reliable relation between initial conditions described by effective variables v L ∈ L and outcomes o L ∈ L: in a reliable way, whether ET L is an exact or statistical law. It is important to note that an effective theory may have a randomisation element R: where R might for example produce a Gaussian distribution. Equal Causal Validity In terms of Effective Theories for emergent properties P(d), Noble's principle [Noble 2012 ] as extended in [Ellis 2020 ] can be restated: Equal Causal Validity: Each emergent level L in the hierarchy (characterised as in Table 1 ) represents an Effective Theory ET L , so each level is equally valid in a causal sense. This implies no level is a fundamental level with priority over the others, and particularly there is not a primary one at the bottom level. This is just as well, because there is no well-established bottom-most physical level to which physics can be reduced [Murugan et al 2012] . Every emergent level equally represents an effective theory. 7 Equality of validity of effective theories at every level is possible because causation is not just bottom-up. Rather higher level properties P(d) are linked to lower levels by a combination of upwards and downwards causation ( [Noble 2012] , [Ellis 2016] , [Ellis 2020 ]), which enables emergence of effective laws at each level. Upwards emergence This has two different aspects ([Ellis 2020]: §1.1). First there is the Emergence E of a macro system from its components. In terms of levels, this corresponds to creation of a higher level LN from a lower level Ln: that is, Ln → LN, N > n. This may lead to topological non-trivial states emerging such as networks, or Quantum Entanglement may take place . The issue of phase transitions is important here. First order phase transitions occur when Spontaneous Symmetry Breaking SSB occurs leading to the emergent level ET having lower symmetries than the underlying ET. In terms of the associated micro dynamics m and macrodynamics M, if S is the symmetry set of m, then Second there is emergence P of properties of the emergent level LN out of properties of the underlying constituent level Ln once LN has come into existence. This corresponds to emergence of a higher level ET L out of a lower level one. Some form of coarse graining C of properties may suffice if the higher and lower levels have the same symmetries S, but not if their symmetries are different due to SSB (see [Ellis 2020] ). Downward causation A classification of different types of downward causation was given in [Ellis 2012] , [Ellis 2016] . Here I will rather approach the issue from an ET L viewpoint. There are essentially two kinds of downwards effects that can happen: downward alteration of lower level dynamics L via either constraints or effective potentials, and downward alteration of dynamics at level L by altering the set of lower level variables. Constraints and Effective Potentials The way downward causation by constraints works is that the outcomes P(d) at Level L depend on constraints C LI at the level L arising from conditions at a Level of Influence LI. Thus when interlevel interactions are taken into account, relation (1) is modified (see (30) in [Ellis 2020]) to Essentially the same holds if the effect of the Level of Influence LI on the level L is expressed in terms of an effective potential V (v LI ) at level L (see (9) in [Ellis 2020] ). Thus constraints act as causes [Juarrero 2002] . The constraints C LI may be time independent: ∂ C LI /∂t = 0 in which case they are structural constraints; or they may be time dependent: C LI = C LI (t), ∂C LI /∂t = 0, in which case they are signalling or controlling constraints. An important case is feedback control (engineering), which is essentially the same as homeostasis (biology). Then the constraints C LI (t) depend on goals G LI valid at level L but set at the Level of Influence LI. Similarly the potential V (v LI ) may depend on time-dependent variables v LI (t) at the Level of Influence CL. Then ∂v LI (t)/∂t = 0 ⇒ ∂V (v LI )/∂t = 0. In both cases the level L is no longer causally complete on its own; at a minimum, only the combination {L,LI} of levels can be causally complete. Altered variables The causal effect due to the level of influence LI may rather be due to changes in the variables v L at level L due to variables v LI at the higher level LI: where the new set {v ′ L } of effective variables at level L may be smaller, larger, or altered. They are smaller if they are changed by deleting lower level elements. This occurs when Downward Causation by Adaptive Selection takes place, altering or deleting selected lower level elements according to some selection criterion c. This enables alteration of structures and functions at level L so as to meet new challenges at level LI. This plays an important role in enabling by organisms to have agency and choice, enabled by stochasticity, as explained in [Noble and Noble 2018] : "Choice in the behavior of organisms involves novelty, which may be unpredictable. Yet in retrospect, we can usually provide a rationale for the choice. A deterministic view of life cannot explain this. The solution to this paradox is that organisms can harness stochasticity through which they can generate many possible solutions to environmental challenges. They must then employ a comparator to find the solution that fits the challenge. What therefore is unpredictable in prospect can become comprehensible in retrospect. Harnessing stochastic and/or chaotic processes is essential to the ability of organisms to have agency and to make choices" They are larger if for example one has downward creation of quasiparticles such as phonons via interlevel wave-particle duality ( [Ellis 2020 ] and Section 6.3), which underlies the properties of metals and semi-conductors. This is what Carl Gillett calls a "Foundational Determinative Relation" [Gillett 2019] ). The are altered if the number is the same but the properties of an element changes. When they are bound in an emergent complex their own properties may change (for example, neutrons decay in 11 minutes when free but last for billions of years when bound in a nucleus), or their interactions with external entities may change (for example electrons bound in an atom interact with light quite differently than a free electron does). Downward causation is related to Aristotle's Formal Cause, see [Tabaczek 2013 ], but I will not follow that strand here. To give these rather abstract statements flesh, see many examples given in , [Ellis 2016 ]. Downward causation in relation to the key physics-chemistry link is discussed in [Luisi 2002 ]. Multiple realisability of higher level variables at lower levels plays a key role in downward causation [Menzies 2003] . Any particular higher level state can be realised in a multiplicity of ways in terms of lower level states. In an engineering or biological cases, a high level need determines the high level effective function that needs to be realised and thus the high level structure that fulfills it. This higher structure and function is then realised by suitable lower level structures and functions, but there are billions of ways this can happen It does not matter which of the equivalence class of lower level realisations is used to fulfill the higher level need, as long as it is indeed fulfilled. Consequently you cannot even express the dynamics driving what is happening in a sensible way at a lower level. The issue is not just the huge number lower level entities involved in realising a higher level systems, as characterised by Avagadro's Number It is the huge different numbers of ways combinations of lower level entities can represent a single higher level variable. Any one of the entire equivalence class at the lower level will do. Thus it is not the individual variables at the lower level that are the key to what is going on: it is the equivalence class to which they belong. But that whole equivalence class can be describer by a single variable at the macro level, so that is the real effective variable in the dynamics that is going on. This is a kind of interlevel duality: where E L-1 (v L-1 ) is the equivalence class of variables v L-1 at Level L-1 corresponding to the one variable v L at Level L. The effective law EF L at Level L for the (possibly vectorial or matrix) variables v L at that level is equivalent to a law for an entire equivalence class E L-1 (v L-1 ) of variables at Level L-1. It does not translate into an Effective Law for natural variables v L-1 per se at Level L-1. It is important to note the following: one establishes the validity of an ET L for some chosen level L by doing experiments or making observations on phenomena occurring at that level. This involves the experimenter intervening at the level L, hence it is an interlevel interaction. For example a particle physics experiment considers Effective Laws at level L1 but involves scientists at level L7 and organisations at level L8 acting down to affect things at level L1. Consequently, one can make the following important observation: Existence and functioning of Effective Theories ET L at level L does not necessarily imply causal closure of Level L. The issue is what determines constraints C, potentials V , and effective variables v ′ LI that may occur at that level. They may be influenced by other levels. That is what Sections 5 and 6 are about. Determining an effective law at level L involves other levels then L. Looking in more detail at the hierarchy, it is a hierarchy made of modules (this section) which form networks (next section). It is a modular hierarchy for very good reasons. The five principles, applicable to both engineering and biology, are stated by him to be, 1. Hierarchic Structure: Frequently, complexity takes the form of a hierarchy, whereby a complex system is composed of interrelated subsystems that have in turn their own subsystems, and so on, until some lowest level of elementary components is reached 2. Relative Primitives: The choice of what components in a system are primitive is relatively arbitrary and is largely up to the discretion of the observer of the system. 3. Separation of Concerns: Intracomponent linkages are generally stronger than intercomponent linkages. This fact has the effect of separating the high-frequency dynamics of the components, involving the internal structure of the components, from the low frequency dynamics, involving interaction among components. Hierarchic systems are usually composed of only a few different kinds of subsystems in various combinations and arrangements. Intermediate Forms A complex system that works is invariably found to have evolved from a simple system that worked. . . . A complex system designed from scratch never works and cannot be patched up to make it work. You have to start over, beginning with a working simple system. This underlies existence of levels such that each level is equally causally effective ( §2.2). Booch says "Different objects collaborate with one another through patterns of interaction that we call mechanisms". These are what I am calling Effective Theories (ETs). The objects that collaborate are modules. Modules Modularity is the property of a system that has been decomposed into a set of cohesive and loosely coupled modules ([Booch 2006]:56). They can be represented by Abstractions, where "An abstraction denotes the essential characteristics of an object that distinguish it from all other kinds of objects and thus provide crisply defined conceptual boundaries, relative to the perspective of the viewer. An abstraction focuses on the outside view of an object and so serves to separate an object's essential behavior from its implementation." ( A feature of particular interest is that emergent systems may give rise to Effective Theories that involve topological constraints. Indeed this happens quite often because emergent complexity in both engineering and biology often involves interaction networks, and a key feature of such networks is their topological connectivity, described by graph theory. Thus for example Arthur Peacocke points out that "In electrical circuit theory there are certain topological constraints, the boundary conditions that one element imposes on another ( [Peacocke 1990 ]:74) They obviously have strongly emergent properties: their functioning does not follow from any local characteristics of the elements that make up the circuit. The electric light won't work until you change its open circuit topology (isomorphic to an open interval) when the switch is off, to a closed topology (isomorphic to a circle) when the switch is on. This macro event than reaches done to alter the flow of billions of electrons at the micro level. Networks can be physical networks, or interaction networks. [Jain et al 1996] . The case of importance in biology is the nervous system [Guyton 1977 ] and neural networks [Haykin 1994 ]. Interaction Networks Interaction networks occur due to the presence of a variety of reagents that selectively interact with each other. This requires firstly a container that keeps the reagents within interaction distance of each other, rather than just diffusing away, and second the presence of an appropriate set of reagent that do indeed interact with each other. A key role is then played by selectively letting specific reagents enter or exit the container so as to control their interaction densities. On a large scale, examples of importance in engineering are purification plants, chemical engineering reaction vessels, water treatment plants, sewage treatment plants . In biology, they arguably are the endocryne system, controlling signalling, and the digestive system, controlling metabolism at the systems level [Guyton 1977] , and on a larger scale, ecological networks [Junker and Schreiber 2011] . On a small scale, there are many interaction networks in cell biology [Buchanan et al 2010] . These are crucially dependent on the existence of cells bounded by cell walls, that serve as the necessary reaction containers. They have ion channels imbedded in those walls that control movement of ions in and out of the cells, and molecular channels controlling movement of molecules in and out. They include • Gene regulatory networks [Carroll 2005 Causation Because interaction networks are directed graphs (i.e. the edges between nodes have orientations), they represent causal effects, where causation is defined as [Pearl 2009 ] [Pearl and Mackenzie 2018] . [Hofmeyer 2018] shows how such diagrams can be used to exemplify causal entailment in a diverse range of processes: enzyme action, construction of automata, and ribosomal polypeptide synthesis through the genetic code. Their causal effects can be tested by experiment, where this is possible (vary conditions at one node and show that, ceteris parabus (i.e. conditions at other links to the node are unchanged) this results in a reliable change at another node. When this is not possible, one can use counterfactual arguments: demonstrating that as a result of the nature of the network links this should indeed be the outcome if one were to make such a change. This is the kind of argument I will use to claim that both upward and downward relations between levels are also causal ( Table 3) . Networks and strong emergence Because of their systemic properties, biochemical networks display strong emergence [Boogerd et al 2005] . In examining the issue of causal closure of properties P(d), one must have the context clearly in mind. To do so, it is useful to define the Domain of Interest (DOI) of such study. This has three quite different aspects. First, there will a specific Topic of Interest (TOI) one wishes to investigate. For example, it might be physics or engineering or chemistry or biology. In physics, one might have in mind atomic physics or condensed matter physics or plasma physics; in biology, molecular biology or physiology or neuroscience or population evolution. Or one might want to investigate relations between various of these topics. In this paper, the interest is the nature of causal closure in the relation between physics, engineering, and biology. Second, given a choice of topic of interest, the Domain of Interest DOI of a system of interest S consists firstly of interaction limits for S with its surroundings, and secondly of time limits on the duration when we are interested in the behaviour of S. Together these comprise spacetime limitations (Section 3.1), leading to Effectively Isolated Systems in the case of physics (Section 3.2) and Effective Spatial Closure in the case of biology and engineering (Section 3.3). Thirdly, there will be a choice of Levels of Interest (LOI). The issue of LOIs is the focus of this paper, and is discussed in the following Section 4). To be of physical interest, S must be spatially limited. Although they are often talked about, systems of infinite extent do not occur in the real universe [Ellis et al 2018] . 8 Space time boundaries define the time and spatial domain we are interested in in relation to S. From a spacetime viewpoint, this is a world tube of finite radius R that surrounds S, large enough to contain S and all the elements strongly interacting with it, bounded by an initial time t i and final time t f defined in a suitable way. This governs the kinds of interactions it can have with other systems. We may be interested in short or long timescales characterised by the starting time t i and ending time t f , depending on what we wish to study. We may be interested in, • Evolutionary processes E(d) whereby the family of systems of similar type to S came into existence over long timescales via reproduction with variation followed by selection; • Developmental processes E(d) whereby a specific system S came into existence through developmental or manufacturing processes, or perhaps by self assembly; • Functional processes whereby the properties P(d) of the system S considered over short timescales emerge from the underlying physics. This is the focus of this paper. Each involves very different choices of the timescale ∆t := t f − t i relevant to our study. Isolated systems Causal closure of a system S cannot happen if uncontrolled influences arrive from the surroundings: Sideways influences : {Outside ⇒ S} As these influences vary with time, they will cause changes in the the state of the system with time that cannot be predicted from a knowledge of the properties of the system alone. The system is not causally closed. Physics deals with this by introducing the idea of an Isolated system. This is usually expressed by giving limits on any incoming influences "at infinity", for example such conditions are imposed in studying electromagnetic and gravitational radiation. However, as just stated, infinity is not a valid physics concept. One should instead refer to Finite Infinity I [Ellis 2002 ]: a world tube of finite radius R I >> R chosen so that incoming radiation and matter will not seriously interfere with S. 9 The dynamics of the system will then be autonomous except for small perturbations due to incoming matter and radiation crossing I, which can be treated as small effects. Effectively Isolated Systems (EIS) What we can do is hope to find a world tube I of finite radius that serves as an effective infinity for the surface S. The dynamics of S can be treated as an autonomous system, affected by small incoming perturbations over I. However, there are two problems with this idea: one to do with physics, and one to do with engineering and biology. Causal Domains The first is that famously, in general relativity, causal domains are determined by null cones rather than timelike tubes [Hawking and Ellis 1973] . Why have I not defined the causal limits, which are basic in term of causal closure, in terms of null surfaces rather than a timelike world tube? The answer is that on astronomical scales, effective causal limits are indeed given by timelike world tubes rather than null surfaces. On astronomical scales at recent times, the dynamic effects of radiation are very small compared with those of matter. We get a very usable I by choosing R I to be about 1 Megaparsec in comoving coordinates [Ellis and Stoeger 2009] . Nothing outside there has had a significant effect on the history of our galaxy or the Solar System. Yes some radiation and matter is coming in, but it is negligible compared to the energies involved in daily life. The one form of radiation of significance for the world is light from the Sun, which comes from well within those limits: 1 Astronomical Unit might indeed suffice for local physics. The radiative energy coming from greater distances has negligible dynamical effects on Earth. A timelike world tube of radius 1AU will do just fine in terms of considering causal closure of the Solar System. Isolated systems: Laboratories However physics practice works in a different way: the key concept is an isolated system in a laboratory. It's a system that is in fact interacting strongly with the the environment (Section 3.3), but that interaction is strictly controlled so that it is highly predictable. The system is shielded from influences outside the laboratory as far as possible. This then enables the results of experiments to also be highly predictable. And that is what enables the determination of the Effective Theories ET L that hold at a Level L. Examples are the expensive isolation and cooling systems underlying the success of quantum optics experiments. Engineering and Biology as Open Systems The real problem is different. It is that no biological system can be closed: they have by their nature to be open systems. And the same is true for engineering systems. In these cases, the 'isolated system' paradigm is simply wrong. Life cannot exist as an isolated system. Biological systems are inherently open systems interacting with the environment. Arthur Peacocke states ( [Peacocke 1990 ]:10-11), "Biological organisations can only maintain themselves in existence if there is a flow of energy and this flow requires that the system not be in equilibrium and therefore spatially inhomogeneous". 10 . The effect of the outside world is not negligible. On the contrary, it is essential to biological functioning. It cannot be treated as a perturbation. The biosphere experiences incoming high grade radiation from the Sun and radiates outgoing low grade heat to the dark Sky, and this is its energy source enabling it to function thermodynamically [Penrose 1990 ]. Organisms need a flow of material in, and, because of the Second Law of Thermodynamics (essentially: as time progresses, matter and energy will be transformed from usable to unusable forms), need to dispose of waste matter and heat resulting from internal nonequilibrium metabolic processes. A living system S must take in materials and energy from the surrounding environment E and dispose of waste matter and energy to E: In summary, living systems are essentially interacting systems. The same is true for engineering systems, because they do work of some kind. Reliable Interactions They must therefore interact strongly with an environment that is stable enough that the interactions with the environment are reliable and reasonably constant so they do not disrupt the dynamics of the system over time. In physics this is the concept of a Heath Bath or Thermal reservoir. You are in contact with an environment but don't need to take its dynamics into account because it is in a state usually assumed to be static, characterised only by a constant temperature T ; and it is so large that the system S has negligible influence on it state. 11 Life: Interaction limits How then does one limit those interactions to those that will enable life to sustain itself? Humberto Maturana and Francisco Varela essentially dealt with this by introducing the idea of Autopoesis [Maturana and Varela 1980] , which inter alia expresses the idea of causal closure in terms of system interaction with its environment. The key point is how does one define the boundary of a system in this context. Instead of choosing a spacetime tube of some chosen radius R as in the astronomy case, one chooses a System Boundary B that characterizes the system as being effectively autonomous. This underlies the meaning of Level L8 in the hierarchy of emergence (Table 1, §2.1). A person has a skin that is her physical boundary with the outside world, but still allows interaction with it. Energy and matter transfer takes place across the boundary. A machine similarly has a boundary that defines its limits, but will have some form of energy input enabling it to do work, and in many cases complex cooling devices to get waste heat out (paradoxically, they may consume large amounts of energy). But this idea extends down to other levels, for example it holds also at the Device Level/Cellular Level L5 and the Component Level/Organ Level L6. For example, a cell is the core of biology. It exists as an entity with its own integrity, characterised by the cell wall which allows controlled ingress and egress of materials and energy, yet interacts strongly with the environment. How then does life handle functioning in this context? The environment must be sufficiently stable so as to allow effective predictability. This is the case when the system is not causally closed but has predictable interactions with the environment that makes its own functions predictable. It has an environment that can be treated as predictable up to perturbations. The environment may change with time, but if so, slowly enough to allow adaptation to the changing situation. This is often the case, and is what on the one hand allows living systems to flourish, and on the other allows biology to be a genuine scientific subject [Campbell and Reece 2005] . The exceptions But that is not always the case: take COVID-19 as an example. That started at the social level (L9) in one house, then spread worldwide via aircraft affecting life world wide and thereby affecting in a downward way all the biomolecules (L4) and electrons (L1) in the bodies of doctors and nurses and patients effected. But additionally it affected the engineering side by closing down thousands of flights across the world, thereby reaching down to affect all the billions of atoms (L3) and particles (L1) that make up those aircraft: a classic example of the interlevel causation I turn to next. As far as predictability is concerned, the system S has reliable interactions with the environment and so is predictable most of the time, except when we this is not the case. Predictability holds when all things are equal, but there is no guarantee this will be the situation. And that is the best we can do. 12 Effective Spatial Closure (ESC) Engineering and biological systems of necessity interact strongly with their environments, because that is necessary for their functioning. One can in practice usually set up a situation of Effective Spatial Closure where that interaction is by and large predictable so that the system will act in a predictable way. However there is no guarantee that this effective causal closure will always be as respected by the environment. Effective Spatial Closure is largely reliable, but holds ceteris parabus. Elaborating, Investopaedia states this concept as follows: "Ceteris paribus is a Latin phrase that generally means 'all other things being equal.' In economics, it acts as a shorthand indication of the effect one economic variable has on another, provided all other variables remain the same. ... Ceteris paribus assumptions help transform an otherwise deductive social science into a methodologically positive 'hard' science. It creates an imaginary system of rules and conditions from which economists can pursue a specific end. Put another way; it helps the economist circumvent human nature and the problems of limited knowledge'. In other words, Effective Spatial Closure works except when it doesn't. Unpredictability happens when Black Swan Events take place, possible when there is a fat-tailed rather than a Gaussian distribution [Taleb 2010] , and with major significance at the macro level. And when it doesn't work, the effects chain all the way down from Level L8 to the atomic level L3 and particle level L1 in Table 1 , as in the case of the Cornovirus pandemic. Effective Theories and Existence of Levels is discussed in Section 4.1. Levels of Interest (LOIs) are defined in Section 4.2. Sensible choices for LOIs are discussed in Section 4.3. However there is a problem: Interactions span all levels: every LOI interacts with every other level by both upwards and downwards causation, so how can one get meaningful LOIs, or indeed a meaningful level? I elaborate on this problem in Section 4.4. A practical way out is by defining Effective Causal Closure, discussed later in Section 5.3. The choices one makes relate to whether one wants to answer How questions or Why questions (Section 4.5). An Effective Theory ET L (Section 2.2) is a set of variables and equations representing interactions and constraints at a particular level L, such that initial data implies a reliable outcome at that level. It is the possibility of existence of an Effective Theory ET L (1) at each Level L (the dynamics at that level is determined at that level) that underlies the very concept of levels in the first place. As commented by Arthur Peacocke ( [Peacocke 1990 ]:10), following from [Simon 2019] "Natural hierarchies are more often than not 'nearly decomposable' -that is, the interactions among the sub-systems (the 'parts') are relatively weak compared withe the interactions among the subsystems, a property which simplifies there behaviour and description" The fact that such levels exist is a consequence of the nature of the underlying physical laws and the values of the constants of nature [Uzan 2003 ]. It allows the existence of the modular hierarchical structures that are the core foundation of complexity ( §2.1, §2.6). This is what I have taken for granted above. While it has all the levels shown in Table 1 ( §2.1), we usually do not want to consider them all at once. [Blundell 2019 ] says it thus: "Thus we take it as a given that when a portion of the universe is selected for study, be it a gas or a galaxy, we are allowed to blissfully ignore what is going on at scales that are much larger, or indeed much smaller, than the one we are considering. " That is what I am formalizing by defining the concept of Levels of Interest (LOI). They are defined as follows: Levels of Interest (LOIs) is a definition of the range of levels that will be covered by a theory where the Union sign "∪ ′′ means include all levels between TL and BL. Some studies are unilevel: TL = BL, and some are explicitly interlevel: TL > BL. • One can validly define such a LOI regardless of what levels you choose, because the levels are equally causally valid (Section 2.2). • Your choice will depend on your Topic of Interest (TOI) (see §3). It is helpful if the choice of levels is made explicit, e.g. LOI(3-5) covers levels 3 to 5 • Then one can for the purposes of studying the dynamics at those levels legitimately ignore higher and lower levels, in the sense to be explored below. • This is possible because the levels effectively decouple in the sense of allowing valid Effective Theories ET L at each level L. • However this does not give you the right to deny the validity of levels that lie outside your Levels of Interest. • There is no guarantee that causal completion will occur by including only those levels characterised by your choice of LOI. That is the topic of Interlevel Causal Closure, which I discuss below (Section 5). Are there limits on the LOIs one can choose? One can choose to investigate any desired LOIs, not investigating or take for granted the interactions that will inevitably occur from higher and lower levels. This is done to establish ET L s. For example Denis Noble in [Noble 2002 ] "Modeling the heart-from genes to cells to the whole organ" chooses to investigate the range of levels stated, namely Levels L5 to L8 in the Hierarchy of Emergence (Table 1) , and not for example on the one hand the interactions between protons and electrons that make this possible, and on the other hand the mental and social influences that will inevitably be having an effect on how the heart is functioning. What he does do is investigate the interlevel relations within the levels LOI(5-8) he has chosen, because that is the domain of physiology. Other examples are shown in Table 2 . The suitable choice of LOIs will follow. This is the context within which "causal completeness of physics" must be evaluated. Strongly Interacting Levels There is a basic problem with LOIs, however. That is the fact that, as mentioned above, every level interacts with every other level! The choices one makes relates inter alia as to whether one wants to answer How questions, Why questions, or both (Section 4.5). There is a practical way out that I discuss in Section 5.3 by introducing the idea of Effective Causal Closure. [Anderson 1972 ] [Laughlin and Pines 2000] . Nevertheless outcomes at Level L1 too must also be shaped in a downward way by engineering and biological variables, via outcomes at Level L3. But this is not the bottom. Underlying L1 is some theory of fundamental physics at Level L0, a "Theory of Everything" (TOE) [Weinberg 1994 ]: maybe String Theory/M Theory, maybe not. There are variety of competing theories on offer [Murugan et al 2012] . This is the ultimate source of the emergence of dynamic properties P(d) in engineering and biology (using the notation in §2.2 of [Ellis 2020])). It affects us every day. These lie outside the LOIs of engineers and biologists. That is just as well, as we do not know what the answer is at Level L0, even though it underlies all physical emergence. As explained above, it suffices to deal with Effective Theories that hold at higher levels. At the top: Cosmology and Existence E(d) Consider Isaac Newton seeing an apple drop. This occurs for a variety of reasons: the Law of Gravity acting on the apple, the light rays that convey this image to his retina, the analysis of the image by his brain, and so on. But there are far deeper underlying issues. Why does the apple exist? Why does the Earth exist? Why does the Solar System and the Galaxy exist? Why does the Universe exist and have the nature it does? These are all the background reasons why the apple fell, and why Isaac Newton existed for that matter. These questions of how everything came into being (E(d)) is the domain of Cosmology [Peter and Uzan 2013] . It deals with issues such as, Where do elements such as Helium and Carbon come from? How did the Galaxy, the Sun, and the Earth arise? The Philosophy of Cosmology [Ellis 2014 ] considers issues such as Why is physics of such a nature as to allow life to exist? [Sloan et al 2020] Particularly: why are the constants of nature [Uzan 2003] of such a character as to allow the hierarchical structure in Table 1 to emerge? Thus cosmology affects us every day by underlying our existence. Everyday effects of cosmology P(d) There are more immediate issues as well, in the relation of cosmology to everyday life [Ellis 2002 ]: Why is the Sky dark at night, serving as a heat sink for the Earth's waste energy? This is crucial to the functioning of the biosphere ( [Penrose 1990 ]:411-417). Why is there an arrow of time? [Penrose 1990 ] [Davies 2004 ] [Ellis and Drossel 2020] ? This is crucial to all macro level physics, biology, and chemistry. Both are due to the cosmological context. Thus cosmology affects the emergence of properties P(d) in engineering and biology today. The point then is that while it does indeed have a major causal effect on daily life [Sciama 2012], this is a rock solid relation that does not change with time. It is a fixed unchanging background that does not alter effective laws as time passes. It is thus not a case of ceteris parabus 13 (c.f. §3.3) and so can be taken for granted and not considered further when investigating causal closure in engineering, biology, and physics. How questions consider physical interactions on the one hand, and mechanisms on the other. Thus they will relate to levels L1-L7 in Table 1 , including L7 because that relates to the integration of systems to produce the organism as a whole [Randall et al 2002] [ Rhoades and Pflanzer 1989] . Why questions relate to motivation, meaning, and philosophical issues. Thus they will relate to levels L7-L8 in Table 1 , including L7 because this is the level where as well as philosophy, psychology and motivation come in [Donald 2001 ] [Kandel 2012 ]. There is of course a trend for some strong reductionists to deny that the Why questions are valid or have any real meaning. From the viewpoint of this paper, that simply means that they themselves have a restricted set of LOIs that excludes those higher levels. Because of the equal validity of levels espoused in [Noble 2012] , [Ellis 2020 ], and in this paper, that restricted set of interests does not provide a justification for denying the validity of the levels with Effective Theories outside their particular set of interests. The crucial concept in this paper is that of Interlevel Causal Closure of properties P(d). I first consider Causation and Causal Closure (Section 5.1) and the nature of biology (Section 5.2). Then I consider Interlevel Causal Closure in the case of biology (Section 5.3), because this is where it is clearest and has been discussed most. I introduce here the key concept of Effective Causal Closure. A stronger relation is the idea of Inextricably Intertwined Levels (IILs) which I discuss in Section 5.4. Causation In order to consider causal closure, one must first have a view on how one justifies claims of causal effects P(d). This has been laid out in depth by Judea Pearl in [Pearl 2009 ] and [Pearl and Mackenzie 2018] . Causal inference is based in Causal Models (directed graphs) validated by experimental intervention, or when that is not possible, by Counterfactual Arguments. Causal Models Here one consider causal models of the influences at work . In effect, the diagram of the hierarchy of Levels Table 1 in Section 2 is such a (very simplified) model, when one introduces the arrows of both upward emergence (left) and downward constraint or control (right). To develop this approach more fully, one needs to expand Table 3 to a hierarchical diagram that represents the modular nature of the hierarchy ( §2.6). This is a very worthwhile project, but I will not attempt it here. It is roughly indicated in ( [Peacocke 1990 Intervention Here one actually intervenes at Level LI and reliably observes a resultant change at level LF. This has been done both for Effective Theories EF L at each level L, and in many case for both upwards and downwards interlevel effects. One can do this also using digital computer models; for example [Fink and Noble 2008] [Noble 2012] have done this to show downwards causation occurring in computer models of heart function. Here one considers what would happen if one intervened at Level LI, and plausibly argues that this will cause an actual difference at Level LF, when upward causation takes place: LF > LI (left column BU) or when downward causation takes place: LI > LF (right column TD). This has been used to establish that downward causal effects exist, e.g. [Campbell 1974] , [Ellis and Kopel 2019] , [Ellis and Drossel 2019] . Causal Closure Consider a multilevel system S (which could have only one level). Causal Closure of the properties P(d) of a system S(BL-TL) with a bottom level BL and top level TL occurs when the set of Effective Laws EF L governing outcomes at each level L, together with the upward and downward interactions between levels, are sufficient to determine the future state o of the system S at all levels {BL-TL} (the outcome) from an initial state d (the data) given at a set of levels {LL-HL} with lowest level LL and highest level HL contained within or equal to {BL-TL}. Note that this includes the physicalist idea of causal closure where all follows from a single lowest physical level LL, for that is the case LL = HL, chosen as L1 in Table 1 . Causal Closure requires Effective Predictability on the one hand (Section 3.3), and an Effectively Causally Closed set of levels on the other, which concept I now consider. The issue: Two opposing strands • There are no isolated sets of levels, as just discussed (Section 4.4). Causal Closure as just defined is an ideal that does not occur in practice unless one takes LL = L1, HL = L9: you are giving data for the whole thing. • However there are in practice preferred restricted sets levels with a special integrity in terms of causal closure (see the comments just after Table 1 ). How do we deal with this tension? The clearest domain in which to tackle this is biology ( §5.3). The lessons from there carry over to engineering ( §6.2), and physics ( §6.4). Biological organisms have purpose, as stated by Nobel Prize winning biologist Leland Hartwell and colleagues [Hartwell et al (1999) ]: 14 "Although living systems obey the laws of physics and chemistry, the notion of function or purpose differentiates biology from other natural sciences. Organisms exist to reproduce, whereas, outside religious belief, rocks and stars have no purpose. Selection for function has produced the living cell, with a unique set of properties that distinguish it from inanimate systems of interacting molecules. Cells exist far from thermal equilibrium by harvesting energy from their environment. They are composed of thousands of different types of molecule. They contain information for their survival and reproduction, in the form of their DNA. Their interactions with the environment depend in a byzantine fashion on this information, and the information and the machinery that interprets it are replicated by reproducing the cell." Consequently, as emphasized by Peacock ( [Peacocke 1990 ]:13) "Many biological concepts and language are often sui generis and not reducible to physics and chemistry, certainly not in the form to which they apply to simpler and restricted atomic and molecular systems". In the case of biology, unless the concepts considered include purpose and function, it will miss the essence of what is going on, as pointed out by [Hartwell et al (1999) ]. You also need to introduce the concepts "alive" and "dead", which do not occur at any lower level than the cellular level in biology, and do not occur at any physics level. Without this concept you cannot for example discuss the theory of natural selection [Mayr 2001 ]. Upward and downward causation As just stated, all biological entities have purpose or function, and that controls in a top-down way what happens at lower levels [Noble 2012 ] reaching down to the underlying physical levels [Ellis and Kopel 2019] . The physics does not control the higher levels, rather -without any violation of the laws of physics -it does what the biology asks it do. This functioning occurs via a combinations of upwards and downwards causation ] [Noble 2012 ], for example gene regulation taking place on the basis of the state of the heart [Fink and Noble 2008] or the brain [Kandel 2001 ]. This dynamic reaches down to the molecular level and then the underlying electron level. The enabling factors are black boxing [Ashby 2013 ] to get higher level logic out of lower level logic, together with time dependent constraints at the lower level that are regulated by higher level biological variables [Ellis and Kopel 2019] . Together they underlie the emergent effective laws ET L at each level L in biology. The cellular level L5 is a key level in biology: cells have an organisation and integrity of their own, and are living integral entities that are the basic units of life. They interact with other cells at the same level, and react to their environment in appropriate ways. In multicellular organisms they depend on higher levels for nutrition, materials, waste disposal, and signals as to what to do. But they can be treated as modules ( §2.6) with an integrity of their own that responds to inputs and produces outputs. The associated set of biological levels, taking the underlying physics for granted, is the set of levels L4-L5. Similarly the level of individual organisms L7 again represents a level of emergent integrity. Individuals are entities that can be treated as autonomous entities that respond to environmental cues (from the levels above) and other individuals (at the same level). The associated set of biological levels, taking the underlying physics for granted, is the set of levels L4-L7. So the issue is, how does this kind of autonomy emerge at these particular levels, given that all levels are interacting? What characterizes these special sets of levels? The key point as to what occurs is organisational closure in biological organisms [Mossio et al 2009] [Mossio and Moreno 2010] : "The central aim of this paper consists in arguing that biological organisms realize a specific kind of causal regime that we call 'organisational closure'; i.e., a distinct level of causation, operating in addition to physical laws, generated by the action of material structures acting as constraints. We argue that organisational closure constitutes a fundamental property of biological systems since even its minimal instances are likely to possess at least some of the typical features of biological organisation as exhibited by more complex organisms." This is a distinct causal regime, as explained in [Mossio 2013] : "In biological systems, closure refers to a holistic feature such that their constitutive processes, operations and transformations (1) depend on each other for their production and maintenance and (2) collectively contribute to determine the conditions at which the whole organization can exist. According to several theoretical biologists, the concept of closure captures one of the central features of biological organization since it constitutes, as well as evolution by natural selection, an emergent and distinctively biological causal regime." This is developed further in [Montévil and Mossio 2015] , identifying biological organisation as closure of constraints "We propose a conceptual and formal characterisation of biological organisation as a closure of constraints. We first establish a distinction between two causal regimes at work in biological systems: processes, which refer to the whole set of changes occurring in non-equilibrium open thermodynamic conditions; and constraints, those entities which, while acting upon the processes, exhibit some form of conservation (symmetry) at the relevant time scales. We then argue that, in biological systems, constraints realise closure, i.e. mutual dependence such that they both depend on and contribute to maintaining each other." Thus biological organisation is an interlevel affair, involving downward causation as well as upwards emergence, thus enabling teleology [Mossio and Bich 2017] , [Bich et al 2020] . From the viewpoint of this paper, these authors are identifying specific sets of levels where effective interlevel causal closure occurs: the topmost level links to the bottom-most level to close the dynamic loop that leads to biological emergence. I will quote three more papers that have essentially the same view. [Hofmeyer 2017] emphasizes this property in the case of the cell: [The] property of self-fabrication is the most basic expression of biological anticipation and of life itself. Self-fabricating systems must be closed to efficient causation... I identify the classes of efficient biochemical causes in the cell and show how they are organized in a hierarchical cycle, the hallmark of a system closed to efficient causation. Broadly speaking, the three classes of efficient causes are the enzyme catalysts of covalent metabolic chemistry, the intracellular milieu that drives the supramolecular processes of chaperone-assisted folding and self-assembly of polypeptides and nucleic acids into functional catalysts and transporters, and the membrane transporters that maintain the intracellular milieu, in particular its electrolyte composition. You need all these components and levels for the thing to work. [Farnsworth 2018 ] emphasizes that multi-level homeostasis is part of the mix: Two broad features are jointly necessary for autonomous agency: organisational closure and the embodiment of an objective-function providing a 'goal': so far only organisms demonstrate both. Organisational closure has been studied (mostly in abstract), especially as cell autopoiesis and the cybernetic principles of autonomy, but the role of an internalised 'goal' and how it is instantiated by cell signalling and the functioning of nervous systems has received less attention. Here I add some biological 'flesh' to the cybernetic theory and trace the evolutionary development of step-changes in autonomy: (1) homeostasis of organisationally closed systems; (2) perception-action systems; (3) action selection systems; (4) cognitive systems; (5) memory supporting a self-model able to anticipate and evaluate actions and consequences. Each stage is characterised by the number of nested goal-directed control-loops embodied by the organism, summarised as will-nestedness. Finally [Noble and Noble 2019] argue for circular causality: "We argue that (1) emergent phenomena are real and important; (2) for many of these, causality in their development and maintenance is necessarily circular; (3) the circularity occurs between levels of organization; (4) although the forms of causation can be different at different levels, there is no privileged level of causation a priori: the forms and roles of causation are open to experimental investigation; (5) the upward and downward forms of causation do not occur in sequence, they occur in parallel (i.e. simultaneously); (6) there is therefore no privileged direction of emergence -the upper levels constrain the events at the lower levels just as much as the lower levels are necessary for those upper-level constraints to exist. Modern biology has confirmed [...] that organisms harness stochasticity at low levels to generate their functionality. This example shows in fine detail why higher-level causality can, in many cases, be seen to be more important than lower-level processes." This discussion is related to the idea of Autopoiesis -a system capable of reproducing and maintaining itself -mentioned above, and to the idea of Autocatalytic sets [Hordijk 2013 ] [Hordijk and Steel] . However I will not develop those links here. Rather my purpose is to claim that exactly the same applies in engineering systems in general, and even in physics itself, in at least some case. That is what I develop below. Given that it is understood I am considering causal closure in terms of Levels and LOIs, I can summarise as follows: 15 Effective Causal Closure (ECC) in Biology: We have Effective Causal Closure of properties P(d) in a biological context when the considered set of levels {BL-TL} and data {HL-BL} is large enough to allow causal closure leading to autonomous biological functioning. It is "Effective" because (i) we know other levels do indeed have an influence, but can regard those influences as inputs to an autonomous system that do not destroy its autonomy, and (ii) it is a ceteris parabus relation, as discussed in §3.3. It can be destroyed by unpredictable Black Swan events [Taleb 2010 ] that lie outside the normal operating environment. Thus this characterizes the set of levels needed for an entity (a cell or an organism) to function successfully. There is then no preferred level enabling the system to function: they all equally enable this to happen [Noble and Noble 2019] . [Green and Batterman 2017 ] argue that in such cases, while the Effective Theories ET L are contained in the range {BL-TL}, one needs different models at each level: "No single mathematical model can account for behaviors at all spatial and temporal scales, and the modeler must therefore combine different mathematical models relying on different boundary conditions" These are the different ET L s for each level. But note that one then needs data d L for each level L too. Thus the set of levels where data is given has to be the same as the set of levels where ECC occurs. Thus in the definition of Effective Causal Closure just given, one should set {BL-TL} = {LL-HL}. [Green and Batterman 2017 ] give the examples of epithelial sheets and mechanical modeling of gastrulation. To be clear: one is free to work with an Effective Theory ET L , with appropriate data for that level, at any level chosen L in the range {BL-TL}; but one only gets Effective Causal Closure by including that full set of levels and data. When does this occur in biology? There are two cases where ECC occurs in biology. • Cells The cellular level is the lowest level showing all the attributes of life. It is a case of ECC involving Levels L4-L5. • Individuals The organism level is the major coherent emergent level in life, assuming it is a multicellular organism such as a human being. This is a case of ECC involving levels L4-L7. However there is an interesting different view: that human beings are essentially social beings, so that in fact it is a mistake to view them as being capable of living on their own, as is implied by that categorisation, Thus Berger and Luckmann [Berger and Luckmann 1991] wrote about the Social Construction of Reality: our worldview -an inescapable part of our nature shaping our actions -is crucially shaped by the society in which we live. Merlin Donald's book A Mind so Rare [Donald 2001] essentially agrees, as does Andy Clark's book Supersizing the Mind [Clark 2008 ]. In short, top-down effects from society so crucially shape our being that they are not just perturbations of independent existence: they are essential, and that characterisation is wrong. The correct ECC statement is • Social human beings Human beings are essentially social, and are in fact a case of ECC involving levels L4-L8. Ignoring the lower levels A further key comment regards the other end of the scale: why is it legitimate to ignore levels L1-L3 here? The answer is the existence of quantum and classical protectorates that are governed by emergent rules and are insensitive to microscopics [Laughlin and Pines 2000] . This is another way of affirming the causal efficacy of the Effective Theories ET L at each emergent level L. . However the Effectively Causally Closed levels will reach down to determine what happens at those levels via time dependent constraints (4) [Ellis and Kopel 2019] . In summary: Interlevel Effective Causal Closure as identified here is a key feature of biological functioning, emphasized in [Bechtel 2007] and [ Moreno and Mosseo 2015] . As well as being key in terms of emergence P(d) of properties, it is also key in terms of evolutionary and developmental processes E(d), see [Carroll 2005 ] (where it is not identified as such, but is there) and [Ruiz-Mirazo and Moreno 2012] , where the relation is made explicit. A higher level may be essential to a lower level An important possibility is that the properties P(d) of two levels {BL,TL} may have an essential relationship with each other: each level cannot function without the other, as in some cases of symbiosis. Inextricably Intertwined Levels Two levels BL, TL are inextricably intertwined levels (IIL) if the effective dynamics ET BL , ET TL at each of the two levels cannot occur without involving the other. Consider an individual human being. It is no surprise that the level L7 of the individual cannot exist without the level L5 of cells, for human beings are made out of cells and depend on them for their existence and physiological functioning. But the fact is that the converse is also true: the cells cannot exist and function without the existence of the body that they comprise. The reason is that cells have specialised for specific functions, and cannot survive on their own. They are supplied with oxygen-laden blood by the lungs, heart, and indeed the entire circulatory system, without which they die in a matter of minutes (as happens if a heart attack occurs). Thus levels L5 and L6 are inextricably intertwined. But organs are part of the individual and won't function without systemic integration at that level. Hence levels {L5-L7} are in fact inextricably intertwined. Now an interesting issue arises: ECC occurs for levels L5-L7. Should I have included L4 in the inextricably intertwined levels? Certainly Level L4 is required in order that cells exist at level L5, but is the other way round true also? I believe one can claim it is, because the gene regulatory networks that control production of proteins at Level L4 are at Level L5, and they would not exist if it were not for their functioning. Thus the real inextricably intertwined set of levels is {L4-L7}: the same as the ECC set of levels. There is however this difference: the ECC relation is ceteris parabus, as explained above. The IIL relation is not, it is essential, whatever happens at other levels, these levels are crucially dependent on each other. The discussion in the last two sections makes clear a set of principles that apply equally to engineering, and that is what I will show in this section. To make the discussion concrete, I will consider the case of digital computers. But it will apply equally to other branches of engineering: automobiles, aircraft, chemical plant, water supply systems, sewerage systems, and so on. I consider the nature of digital computers (Section 6.1), where Interlevel Effective Causal Closure again occurs (Section 6.2). Inextricably Intertwined Levels again occur in computers (Section 6.3), and in physics and chemistry (Section 6.4). Table 4 : Computer Implementation Hierarchy (schematic). This is the physical context within which upward emergence and downward causation takes place in the case of digital computers. For a full discussion, see Chapter 2 of [Ellis 2016 ]. Upward and downward causation The dynamics P(d) of a computer is driven by the algorithms encoded in the programs loaded, together with the data used by those programs. Causal closure in the case of computers: In the real world, it is only the combination of physics with its logical, social, psychological, and engineering contexts (which includes the values guiding policy) that can be causally complete, because it is this whole that determines what computer programs will be written and what data utilised, hence what electron flows will take place in integrated circuits, as per the discussion in this paper This is in parallel to the interlevel causal closure that takes place in biology, as discussed in Section 5.3. [Ellis and Drossel 2019] gives a specific example: "As a specific example: the amount of money that can be dispersed to you from an ATM will be limited by an agreement you have reached with your bank. The program used to control the ATM will take into account the existence of such limits, and the specific amount you are able to take out in a given time period will be limited by a logical AND operation linking this agreed amount to the amount of money in your account. Thus these abstract variables will control electron flows in both the bank computers and the ATM dispenser mechanism. Every relevant abstract variable has physical counterparts; in other words, it?s realized by some physical properties on some relevant physical substrate." But crucially there is much more than this: there is the whole issue of the purposes computers are used for in society, from controlling manufacturing to enabling the internet, cell phones,and social media, and they way that this whole enterprise is shaped by the values of those that control the system. The book Coders [Thompson 2019] considers "the morality and politics of code, including its implications for civic life and the economy. Programmers shape our everyday behavior: When they make something easy to do, we do more of it. When they make it hard or impossible, we do less of it." All this is expressed in the flows of electrons through gates at the digital levels L2-L3. Nevertheless, just as in the case of biology, Effective Causal Closure can occur when interlevel causation results in a high degree of autonomy of operation. Analogously to the case of biology, one can state Effective Causal Closure (ECC) in Computers: Effective Causal Closure of properties P(d) in a digital computer occurs when the set of levels considered are large enough to allow causal closure leading to autonomous functioning. It is "Effective" because (i) we know other levels do indeed have an influence, but believe we can regard those influences as inputs to an autonomous system that do not destroy its autonomy, and (ii) it is a ceteris parabus relation, as discussed in §3.3. It can be destroyed by Black Swan events that lie outside the normal operating environment. The two emergent levels with their own causal integrity emerging through ECC are the integrated circuit level (L4), the equivalent of the cell in biology, with ECC given by Levels L2-L4; and the computer level (L5), the equivalent of the individual in biology, with ECC given by levels L2-L5. But just as in the case of biology one can make a case that one should really include the societal level, the same applies here too. The quotes above suggest that ECC for computers really only occurs for Levels L2-L9, including the highest level because of the effect of the World Wide Web. Engineering and Applied Physics The same kind of considerations apply to all branches of engineering, and equally to all branches of applied physics. The applications (socially determined at Level L8) determine what physical effects occur (Levels L1-L3). Inextricably Intertwined Levels (IILs) Do these occur in this case too, as they did in biology? Here there is a major difference: the transistors do not depend on the computer for their continued existence, whereas cells depend on the organism for their existence. While in biology IILs link the individual as a whole to the molecular level, here they also occur, but only at the levels L0-L1 in Table 4 . The reason for that relation is that downward emergence of key properties at the electron level L0 takes place, due to properties of the crystal level L1, as explained in detail in [Ellis 2020 ]. This is called a "Foundational Determinative Relation" (FDR) by Carl Gillett, see [Gillett 2019 ]. In more detail, quasiparticles such as phonons exist due to the broken symmetries of the emergent lattice structure. They come into being as effective particles at the lower level L0 because they are dynamically equivalent to collective oscillations of a level L1 structure (the crystal lattice) ( [Simon 2013]:82-83) , This is an essentially quantum theory phenomenon. One can think of it as an interlevel wave(macro)-particle(micro) duality. [Franklin and Knox 2018] say it this way: "Phonons [are] quasi-particles that have some claim to be emergent, not least because the way in which they relate to the underlying crystal is almost precisely analogous to the way in which quantum particles relate to the underlying quantum field theory." Stephen Blundell states the key point thus ( [Blundell 2019] :244): "So now we come to the key question: Are these emergent particles real? From the perspective of quantum field theory, the answer is a resounding yes. Each of these particles emerges from a wave-like description in a manner that is entirely analogous to that of photons. These emergent particles behave like particles: you can scatter other particles off them. Electrons will scatter off phonons, an interaction that is involved in superconductivity. Neutrons can be used to study the dispersion relation of both phonons and magnons using inelastic scattering techniques. Yes, they are the result of a collective excitation of an underlying substrate. But so are 'ordinary' electrons and photons, which are excitations of quantum field modes.' ' As a consequence, the levels {L0,L1} are inextricably intertwined. This is a proof that the solid state physics occurring in digital computers is a case where causal closure is impossible at the micro level L0 alone. It also shows that in general the set of IILs is not the same as the ECCs. While these considerations apply to digital computers, of course they also apply in particular to the solid state physics itself that underlies their operation, due to the nature of crystals. For the reasons just discussed In Solid State Physics, as a consequence of interlevel wave-particle duality, levels {L1,L4} in Table 1 are inextricably intertwined levels. However the IIL phenomenon is not confined to this case. The laser is another example ([Pezzulo and Levin 2016] : §2) "The laser involves a kind of 'circular' causality which occurs in the continuous interplay between macrolevel resonances in the cavity guiding, and being reinforced by, self-organization of the molecular behaviour ". A quite different example is Resonance Energy Transfer (RET) in the transport of electronic energy from one atom or molecule to another [Jones and Bradshaw 2019] . As described in that paper, "The individual electrons do not migrate between molecules during the transfer process, since the molecular orbitals (the wavefunctions) do not overlap, but instead move between individual electronic states within the molecules. ... energy transfer, through dipole coupling between molecules, mostly depends on two important quantities: spectral overlap and intermolecular distance" This lead to a r −6 distance-dependence for the resonance energy transfer rate in the short-distance regime. The behaviour results from interwining between the electron level L1 and the molecular level L4. Because of these interactions, Second-order perturbation theory is the minimal needed to describe RET. While this paper refers to 'molecules', RET occurs in atoms, chromophores, particles and carbon nanotubes. Its applications include nanosensors and photodynamic therapy. This raises the issue that whenever molecular physics [Buyanal 1997 ] is concerned, there is inextricable intertwining between the molecular structure at Level L4, bound by electrons, and the motions of the electrons at Level L1, controlled by that structure. This is manifest in binding energy ([Buyanal 1997 Molecular physics and quantum chemistry also exhibit IILs between levels L1 and L4, which is why chemistry is a classic example of downward causation [Luisi 2002 ]. The group theory underlying this intertwining is discussed in [Bishop and Ellis 2020] . It is believed by many that because the bottom-most physics level is causally complete, and only upward causation takes place, higher levels are purely derivative: they have no real causal validity. In this paper and its companion [Ellis 2020 ], I argue against that position. It is invalid because it treats physics in a way that ignores context, whereas physics outcomes always depend on context. In fact downward effects imply the opposite: in real world contexts, the bottom-most physics level is not by itself causally complete. In this section, I look at the contextual nature of causal closure of physics (Section 7.1), the way that unpredictability undermines causal closure of physics per se (Section 7.2), and comment on ways people ignore the issues discussed in this paper (Section 7.3). We can consider physics per se, or in relation to the natural world, or in relation to biology, or in relation to engineering. Within physics, the issue of causal closure depends on what aspects we are considering: Particle Physics, Nuclear Physics, Condensed Matter Physics, Cosmology for example. Firstly, we have no reliable tested TOE at the very bottom level L0. We don't try to reduce to that most fundamental physical level ( §4.4). Rather we reduce to a level that is convenient. That that can work is due to the existence of Quantum Protectorates, as explained in [Laughlin and Pines 2000] . But then it is common to assume that Level L1 (particle physics) is causally complete. Is that indeed so? I have argued that this is not the case in the contexts of physics and biology (Section 5.3); physics and engineering, as exemplified by digital computers (Section 6.2); solid state physics (Section 6.3); and physics and chemistry (Section 6.4). In each case the real causal closure that takes laces is an interlevel affair, as emphasized in particular in the case of biology by many perceptive writers (Section 5.3). Effective Causal Closure in real world contexts spans many levels, in the case of biology reaching down from the level of the organism to the underlying physics via time dependent constraints. This implies how it works in terms of physics in relation to society. The causal effects of the corona virus pandemic at the social level reaches down to cause major changes at the physical levels L1-L3 through a complex interaction between social behaviours, virology, and microbiology that for example has temporarily destroyed international air travel and so the trajectories of the billions of particles that make up aircraft. Causal closure only occurs when we take all these factors and levels into account. Considering only disembodied physical laws seriously misleads about the nature of causation and causal closure in real world contexts. In summary, Causal closure of physics In the real world context of engineering and biology, physics at the lowest level considered, whatever that is, is not by itself causally complete. Interlevel causal closure involving engineering or biological variables, in those respective cases, is required in order to have an effectively causally closed system. This is formalized by the concepts of Effective Causal Closure (Sections 5.3 and 6.2), and Inextricably Intertwined Levels (Sections 5.4 and 6.3). Within solid state physics itself, the lower levels L1-L3 are not causally closed by themselves because of interlevel particle-wave duality between the particle level L1 where electrons and phonons live, and the crystal level L4 where lattice vibrations take place (Section 6.3). Properties of Level L4 decouple from the lower physics levels. As stated by [Laughlin and Pines 2000] , "The crystalline state is the simplest known example of a quantum protectorate, a stable state of matter whose generic low-energy properties are determined by a higher organizing principle and nothing else." Ignoring interlevel issues, if by causal closure one means that data specified as precisely as possible leads to unique outcomes, then unavoidable unpredictability undermines the possibility of physics per se (whether quantum or classical) being causally closed. Quantum Physics Quantum effects doubly cause uncertainty in outcomes. Firstly, the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle states that the standard deviations of position σ x and momentum σ p obeys so one cannot even in principle apply Laplace's dream of setting initial data precisely at level L1. Consequently, outcomes are also uncertain. Secondly, collapse of the wave function introduces an irreducible uncertainty in classical outcomes at this level when interactions take place [Ghirardi 2007 ]. This can reach up to macro levels through various amplifiers such as photon multipliers and CCDs. In the engineering case it causes predictability issues at macro scales in terms of digital computer reliability because cosmic rays cause errors in computer memories [Ziegler and Lanford 1979] [Gorman et al 1996] , and the emission of a cosmic ray by an excited atom is a quantum event that is unpredictable even in principle. As regards biology, cosmic rays have had a significant effect on evolutionary history by causing genetic mutations [Percival 1991 ]. The Classical Case Uncertainty of outcomes occurs in this case too, because one can't set initial data to infinite precision [Del Santo and Gisin 2019] . This is an outcome of the fact that infinity never occurs in physical reality [Ellis et al 2018] . Thus physics is not causally closed in the classical case at higher levels because of chaotic dynamics (the butterfly effect), together with the impossibility of specifying initial data to infinite accuracy. This occurs for instance at the level at which fluid motion is determined. [Anderson 2001 ] puts it this way: "A fluid dynamicist when studying the chaotic outcome of convection in a Benard cell knows to a gnat's eyelash the equations of motion of his fluid but also knows, through the operation of those equations of motion, that the details of the outcome are fundamentally unpredictable, although he hopes to get to understand the gross behaviour. This aspect is an example of a very general reality: the existence of universal law does not, in general, produce deterministic, cause-and-effect behaviour " This fundamentally undermines the concept of a causally closed physical levels in the case of classical physics. As was already known to Poincare, this occurs even in the 3-body gravitational case. Microbiology In the case of microbiology, interactions take place in the context of what Hoffmann [Hoffmann 2012] has called "The Molecular Storm". Molecular machines use ratchet-like mechanisms to harness energy from that storm, and organisms use it to provide an ensemble of options from which they can choose preferred lower level states and so attain biological objectives [Noble and Noble 2018 ] (see the quote in §2.3). One has the opposite of the calm relation between initial data and outcomes supposed by Laplace. Here are some ways that the nature of causal closure as discussed in this paper is avoided. Partial reduction This is very common. Francis Crick in The astonishing hypothesis [Crick 1994] states, "You, your joys and your sorrows, your memories and your ambitions, your sense of personal identity and free will, are in fact no more than the behavior of a vast assembly of nerve cells and their associated molecules. " In other words, he is reducing L7 to {L5-L4}. Now my physics colleagues who believe that all that matters is the particle interactions at level L1 will just laugh and say, cells at Level L4 and molecules at L5 are nothing but particles interacting with each other. Thus Crick believes in the reality and effectiveness of causality at Levels L4 and L5 that for example [Hossenfelder 2019] and [Greene 2020] , who believe that all causality resides at Level L1, clearly must deny. So why did Crick emphasize causality at those levels? The answer of course is that that is those were the levels at which he worked -and experienced the effectiveness of causality in terms of the interactions between entities (molecules, neurons) at those levels. From a strictly reductionist viewpoint, this is an illegitimate move. It is however fine if you accept Noble's Principle of Biological Relativity [Noble 2012 ], as extended in [Ellis 2020 ] and this paper: then causality is real at the levels {L4,L5} he studies. But then that removes his justification for denying the reality of causation at Level L7. Taking context for granted Sometimes the existence of an important interlevel effect is so ubiquitous and unchanging that it is not just ignored: it is assumed to not exist The dominant case where this happen is the existence of an arrow of time, which does not emerge from the microphysics level L1: it is an outcome of conditions at the cosmological level L10 [Ellis and Drossel 2020] , [Ellis 2020 ]. The macro result of the existence of a unique arrow of time is known to be true, and is simply imposed a priori on solutions of the equations, even though it is not implied by them [Ellis 2020 ]. This happens for example in rejecting the advanced solutions in Quantum Field Theory and electrodynamics, and the time reversed solutions in wave phenomena. The justification is that one is looking for "physically relevant" solutions, and this ad hoc procedure gives the result one wants, in agreement with experiment, even though it cannot be justified in a bottom up way. This process is simply taken for granted. The causal link from Level L10 is hidden. Ignoring context Crucial contextual effects are simply ignored by some writers e.g. [Hossenfelder 2019] [Greene 2020 ]. The view is "You are nothing but a bag of particles, it's just a matter of particles interacting via a known set of forces". Context has nothing to do with it. The physicists holding this view all come from the particle physics/cosmology side, where this is to some extent true. Physicists from the solid state physics side (the largest section of the physics community) do not hold this view, see e.g. [Anderson 1972 ] [Simon 2013 ], because it is not true in those cases [Ellis 2020 ]. This leads to the large divide in the physics community between these two groups, as discussed by Sylvan Schweber [Schweber 1993 ], and the disdainful epithet "squalid state physics". In fact solid state physics is a fascinating and challenging endeavour [Anderson 1994 ]. Denying top-down causation There is a frequent denial of the possibility of top-down causation, even though it occurs in physics and cosmology. In the latter case it occurs in the context of primordial nucleosynthesis in the early universe ([Peter and Uzan 2013]: §4.3) and structure formation in the later universe ([Peter and Uzan 2013] : §5), which are both dependent on the cosmological context at level L10. That is the reason that primordial element abundances on the one hand and matter power spectra and Cosmic Background Radiation angular power spectra on the other can be used to place strong limits on the background model parameters [Aghanim et al 2018] , as discussed in ( [Ellis 2016]:275-277) . Top down causation clearly occurs in biology [Campbell 1974 ] [Fink and Noble 2008 ] . A recent example is [Pezzulo and Levin 2016] : "Top-down approaches focus on system-wide states as causal actors in models and on the computational (or optimality) principles governing global system dynamics." That paper gives fascinating examples of downward causation from morphogenesis and regenerative medicine. Downward causation is obvious in subjects other than particle physics and cosmology, and in particular in the functioning of the brain [Kandel 1998 ] [Kandel 2012 ] [Ellis 2016 ] [Ellis 2018 ]. Our minds are shaped by society, and shape society. That is the core nature of interlevel causal closure. Society does not exist without mind, and mind does not exist without society [Berger and Luckmann 1991] Another kind of reductionist explanation of biology in general and the brain in particular is a machine or clockwork metaphor: ''The brain is nothing but a machine' '. It is supposed that when one has explained things in such mechanical terms, this has now proven there is no function or purpose associated with it, and a reductionist mechanistic explanation tells everything about it. There is nothing more to say, it has been fully explained. This viewpoint is in essence the polar opposite of the "Nothing but a bag of particles" view I discussed above. However there are three issues to take into account. 1. Just like the case of life [Hartwell et al (1999) ], the idea of purpose or function is central to a machine. A clock has been carefully designed and constructed to tell the time: that is its purpose. A coffee machine has been built to make coffee. A washing machine has been manufactured to wash clothes. The mechanism has been designed for that purpose. This is all encompassed in Herbert Simon's discussion of The Sciences of the Artificial [Simon 2019 ]. When mechanisms are in place, a different kind of explanation is required than in the case of particle physics or cosmology [Wright and Bechtel 2007] [Povich and Craver 2017] , based in the existence of constraints [Winning and Bechtel 2018] . Mechanisms require closure of the kind discussed in this paper [Bechtel 2007 ]. Causal closure of digital computer function P(d) involves the logic built into algorithms. And most machines nowadays include computational components. 2. In terms of the coming into existence of machines, they are a case of Purposeful Design [Ellis 2020 ]. They would not exist if this were not the case. Thus they are an example of Strong Emergence E(d) involving an evolutionary process of trying different designs, modifying them, and selecting those that work best (See Simon and Booch's Principle 5 in Section 2.6 above). The outcomes is a machine best suited to purpose ("My coffee machine is better than yours"). Causal closure involves Levels L7 and L8. 3. Machines are strongly emergent in functional terms P(d) at both micro levels (e.g. the functioning of a transistor [Ellis and Drossel 2019] ) and at macro levels, as in the case of computers [Tanenbaum 2006 ], ( [Ellis 2016 ]:Chapter 2). There is no way their behaviour P(e) can be explained in a strictly bottom up way, because Effective Causal Closure in this case involves levels {L0-L5} in Table 4 at a minimum. Although machines have many similarities to life, I am not advocating the view that life can be regarded as simply a machine. This is of course a major contested issue ever since machines were invented, and particularly latterly with the advent of the range of technologies known as Artificial Intelligence. I will just make two relevant comments. First the functioning of the brain is essentially based on the interaction between intellect and emotions: a complex biological affair [Damasio 2006 ] [Ellis and Toronchuk 2005] . While this interaction can be simulated, that is very far from bringing affect and qualia into being. One requires an architecture that allows intentionality [Morgan and Piccinini 2018] and the causal power of thoughts to come into being [Kandel 1998 ]. Effective Interlevel Causal Closure of brain functioning at Level L7 in Table 1 involves the power of emotions [Damasio 2006 ] and rational thought ([Ellis and Kopel 2019]: §6) as well as interactions with physiology (Level L6) and society (Level L8). Secondly AI will only succeed in modeling human intelligence adequately when massive parallel processing is supplemented by the kind of randomness that allows higher levels to determine which lower level dynamics will lead to the best outcome, as explained by Raymond Noble and Denis Noble in [Noble and Noble 2018] (quoted above: Section 2.3). This is a key form of downward causation (Section 2.3). Machines must imitate life in order to behave like life. Planck 2018 results. VI. Cosmological parameters An introduction to systems biology: design principles of biological circuits More is different: Broken symmetry and the nature of the hierarchical structure of science A Career in Theoretical Physics Science: A 'dappled world' or a 'seamless web' ? Design for a Brain The origin of adaptive behaviour Biological mechanisms: Organized to maintain autonomy The social construction of reality: A treatise in the sociology of knowledge Glycemia regulation: from feedback loops to organizational closure Contextual Emergence of Physical Properties Phase Transitions, Broken Symmetry and the Renormalization Group Object oriented analysis and design with application Emergence and its place in nature: A case study of biochemical networks Networks in cell biology An introduction to effective field theory Emergence, reduction and supervenience: A varied landscape Molecular Physics Downward causation in hierarchically organised biological systems Endless forms most beautiful Reductionism, emergence, and effective field theories Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension The astonishing hypothesis: the scientific search for the soul Descartes' error The Demon in the Machine: How Hidden Webs of Information are Solving the Mystery of Life Physics without determinism: Alternative interpretations of classical physics Principles of dynamical modularity in biological regulatory networks The nature of the physical world Cosmology and local physics Physics, Complexity, and Causality Top-down causation and emergence: some comments on mechanisms On the philosophy of cosmology How can physics underlie the mind? Top-down effects in the brain Does Physics Deny Free Will How Downwards Causation Occurs in Digital Computers Emergence of time The dynamical emergence of biology from physics The physics of infinity The evolution of our local cosmic domain: effective causal limits In Consciousness and Emotion: Agency, conscious choice, and selective perception 1: 81 How organisms gained causal independence and how it might be quantified The character of physical law Noble Model Sneaking a Look at God's Cards: Unraveling the Mysteries of Quantum Mechanics The Routledge Handbook of Emergence Emergence, Downward Causation and its Alternatives: Critically surveying a foundational issue Field testing for cosmic ray soft errors in semiconductor memories Biology meets physics: Reductionism and multi-scale modeling of morphogenesis Until the End of Time: Mind, Matter, and Our Search for Meaning in an Evolving Universe Basic Human Physiology: Normal Functions and Mechanisms of Disease Effective field theories, reductionism and scientific explanation From molecular to modular cell biology The Large Scale Structure of Spacetime Neural networks: a comprehensive foundation Conceptual physics (Pearson) Life's Ratchet: How Molecular Machines Extract Order from Basic Biological Anticipation Causation, Constructors and Codes Being reduced: new essays on reduction, explanation, and causation Autocatalytic Sets: From the Origin of Life to the Economy Autocatalytic Networks at the Basis of Life?s Origin and Organization Global warming: the complete briefing Artificial neural networks: A tutorial Resonance energy transfer: From fundamental theory to recent applications Analysis of biological networks Dynamics in action: Intentional behavior as a complex system A new intellectual framework for psychiatry The molecular biology of memory storage: a dialogue between genes and synapses The age of insight: The quest to understand the unconscious in art, mind, and brain, from Vienna 1900 to the present Principles of Neural Science Mind in a physical world Supervenient properties and micro-based properties: A reply to Noordhof Computer networking: A top-down approach featuring the internet The Theory of Everything The touchstone of life: Molecular information, cell communication, and the foundations of life Emergence in chemistry: Chemistry as the embodiment of emergence On the Topic of Emergence from an Effective Field Theory Perspective Nine algorithms that changed the future Emergence in mind Quantum chemistry. (University Science Books) Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living The causal efficacy of mental states Network motifs: simple building blocks of complex networks Biological organisation as closure of constraints Towards a cognitive neuroscience of intentionality On nature and normativity: normativity, teleology, and mechanism in biological explanation What makes biological organisation teleological? Organisational Closure in Biological Organisms An organizational account of biological functions Foundations of Space and Time: Reflections on Quantum Gravity A theory of biological relativity: no privileged level of causation Harnessing stochasticity: How do organisms make choices? Biological Relativity requires circular causality but not symmetry of causation: so, where, what and when are the boundaries? The theory of almost everything: The standard model, the unsung triumph of modern physics Hierarchical thinking in network biology: the unbiased modularization of biochemical networks An Introduction to the Physical Chemistry of Biological Organization The book of why: the new science of cause and effect The Emperor's New Mind Schrödinger's quantum cat Homological scaffolds of brain functional networks Top-down models in biology: explanation and control of complex living systems above the molecular l Mechanistic levels, reduction, and emergence ". In The Routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy Eckert Animal Physiology: Mechanisms and Adaptations Hierarchical organization of modularity in metabolic networks Autonomy in evolution: from minimal to complex life Physics, community, and the crisis in physical theory The sciences of the artificial The Oxford solid state basics 2020) Fine Tuning in the Physical Universe The major transitions in evolution The Metaphysics of Downward Causation: Rediscovering the Formal Cause The fundamental constants and their variation: observational and theoretical status Arrival of the fittest: solving evolution's greatest puzzle Dreams of a Final Theory:The scientist's search for the ultimate laws of nature (Penguin Random House) Rethinking causality in biological and neural mechanisms: Constraints and control Mechanisms and psychological explanation The architecture of biological networks Effect of cosmic rays on computer memories