The Teacher Reordering American Constitutional Law Teaching* Scott D. Gerber, College of William and Mary Constitutional law is the corner- stone of an undergraduate public law curriculum. Political scientists will therefore want to teach consti- tutional law in the most effective manner possible. To that end, there is a welcome trend to offer consti- tutional law as a two-semester se- quence, a trend reflected by text authors and publishers who are in- creasingly dividing their constitu- tional law texts into two parts (Mezey 1993, 2). I say welcome trend because, as anyone who has taught constitutional law knows, there is too much material to cover adequately in one semester. Traditional Constitutional Law Teaching: Powers First Invariably, constitutional law courses begin with constitutional powers issues: the origins and scope of judicial review, Congress and the development of national power, the powers of the presi- dency, the modern administrative state, the states and American fed- eralism, and representation, voting, and electoral politics. In two-se- mester courses, these issues are addressed in the fall. In one-semes- ter courses, they are covered in the first part of the semester. After the powers issues have been addressed, attention is then turned to constitutional rights is- sues: property rights and economic liberty, freedom of expression, as- sembly, and association, freedom of the press, religious liberty and church-state relations, criminal jus- tice, personal autonomy and pri- vacy, and equal protection. In two- semester courses, rights issues are addressed in the spring. In one- semester courses, they are covered in the second part of the semester. The rationale for teaching consti- tutional powers before constitu- tional rights seems to be, first, that the Bill of Rights and the Four- teenth Amendment, the bases for the vast majority of rights ques- tions, were not part of the original Constitution and, second, that stu- dents need a foundation in constitu- tional powers before they can un- derstand constitutional rights. In the spirit of more effective teach- ing, I would like to suggest that undergraduate teachers reverse the order in which constitutional law is taught. Although this suggestion may strike many traditionalists as heresy, it has proved to be an ef- fective pedogogical technique in my courses. In fact, I have gone so far as to require the constitutional rights course as a prerequisite for the constitutional powers course. Reordering Constitutional Law Teaching: Rights First The justification for reordering constitutional law teaching is sim- ple: students learn the material bet- ter if rights issues are taught first. This is because constitutional rights questions are more intuitive to stu- dents than constitutional powers questions. The American people— undergraduate students included— are imbued with the idea that indi- viduals have rights, an idea that is at the heart of the American politi- cal tradition. "We hold these Truths to be self-evident," Thomas Jefferson wrote in the Declaration of Independence, "that all Men are created equal, that they are en- dowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights; that among these are Life, Liberty and the Pur- suit of Happiness." With respect to constitutional law specifically, although for much of American history the Supreme Court's docket was dominated by powers questions—Marbury v. Madison (1803), M'Culloch v. Maryland (1819), Gibbons v. Ogden (1825), Cooley v. Board of Wardens (1852), United States v. E.C. Knight Company (1895), and A.L.A. Schechter Poultry Corpora- tion v. United States (1935), to name but a few of the classic cas- es—that changed in 1937 when the Court, under the threat of President Franklin D. Roosevelt's infamous "court-packing" plan, stopped striking down the New Deal and redirected its attention to protect- ing civil rights and liberties. In- deed, ever since the "switch-in- time-that-saved-nine," rights questions have far outnumbered powers questions on the Court's docket (Pacelle 1991). The late Herbert J. Storing made the point well a decade and a half ago. "[I]t seems quite plausible today," Stor- ing remarked, "when so much of constitutional law is connected with the Bill of Rights, to conclude that the Antifederalists, the apparent losers in the debate over the Con- stitution, were ultimately the win- ners" (Storing 1978, 32). As a con- sequence of the rights-oriented character of both American politi- cal culture and modern American constitutional law, I have found it easier to introduce students to the sometimes confusing subject of constitutional law, as well as to the daunting task of reading Supreme Court opinions, through issues with which they are more familiar and more comfortable: rights issues. December 1994 703 The Teacher Lessons from Contracts Law As strange as it may sound, my recommendation to reorder consti- tutional law teaching owes much to my former law school contracts teacher, Stanley D. Henderson. In his contracts course and accompa- nying casebook, Henderson takes the bold step of teaching the rules governing remedies for breach of contract (e.g., damages, reliance, and restitution) before the rules governing contract formation (e.g., offer, acceptance, and consider- ation) (Dawson, Harvey, and Henderson 1987). Critics of Hend- erson's approach argue that a con- tracts course must begin with the rules governing contract formation. After all, the argument goes, reme- dies questions cannot arise unless a contract is formed. According to Henderson, however, it is easier for students to learn the complex world of contracts law through a remedy-centered approach. This is because students are more familiar from their everyday experience with what happens if they breach a contract than they are with the technical rules required for them to form a contract (ibid., xxii). As anyone who has had the good for- tune of taking Henderson's con- tracts course or of using his top- selling contracts casebook can attest, Henderson's unconventional approach, in which he teaches con- tracts law "backwards," works splendidly. Although contracts law and con- stitutional law have little in com- mon substantively, they have much in common pedogogically. Like the rules of contract formation, ques- tions of constitutional powers are frequently obscure and confusing to students. By contrast, like the rules governing remedies for breach of contract, constitutional rights ques- tions are quite familiar and under- standable to students, exposed as students are to discussions about abortion and the rights of those ac- cused of crime, for instance, in the everyday discourse of American life. Indeed, I venture to say that, before students step into a constitu- tional law classroom, few, if any, have been exposed to questions like whether the legislative veto is constitutional, while many have heard about—and possibly even discussed—"hate speech," to name but two typical examples of the constitutional powers/rights dichot- omy. Some Suggestions for Teaching the Rights Course My reordered constitutional law sequence does not simply entail teaching the material traditionally offered in a constitutional rights course before the material tradi- tionally offered in a constitutional powers course. Although the vast My classroom discussion of the rights-oriented character of American political culture is not limited to the American Founding. . . I also turn the class's attention to the contemporary debate over whether we are too rights-oriented in the United States. majority of what I teach in the con- stitutional rights course is tradi- tional constitutional rights materi- al—most notably, landmark cases like Lochner v. New York (1905), Schenck v. United States (1919), New York Times v. Sullivan (1964), Wisconsin v. Yoder (1972), Everson v. Board of Education (1947), Mapp v. Ohio (1961), Gideon v. Wainwright (1963), Furman v. Georgia (1972), Griswold v. Con- necticut (1965), Roe v. Wade (1973), Bowers v. Hardwick (1986), Brown v. Board of Education (1954), Frontiero v. Richardson (1973), and Regents of the Univer- sity of California v. Bakke (1978)— I spend the first several class ses- sions discussing the central place of rights in American political culture in the hopes of setting the appropri- ate mood for the course. I begin by examining the Decla- ration of Independence, the found- ing document of the American re- gime. Indeed, in correspondence with James Madison about the Uni- versity of Virginia's curriculum, Thomas Jefferson put the Declara- tion at the top of his required read- ing list for government and law stu- dents (Hellenbrand 1990, 164). While it is certainly not my objec- tive to turn the constitutional rights course into a political philosophy course, I try to give my students a general understanding of the politi- cal ideas of the Declaration—and as the students quickly come to appreciate, rights are at the heart of those political ideas. I follow the discussion of the Declaration of Independence with a discussion of the debate over the ratification of the Constitution. Here, I remind the students that the absence of a bill of rights from the proposed Constitution framed in Philadelphia in 1787 nearly led to the Constitution's defeat, a point I illustrate with some revealing quotes from leading Antifederalists like Mercy Otis Warren, Luther Martin, George Mason, and Patrick Henry. I also invoke the name and forceful language of Thomas Jeffer- son, author of the Declaration of Independence. Jefferson was ini- tially a reluctant supporter of the Constitution, I explain, and one of his most famous letters to Madison tersely said why. "[A] bill of rights," Jefferson wrote, "is what the people are entitled to against government on earth, general or particular, and what no just govern- ment should refuse, or rest on in- ference" (Peterson 1975, 430). I close my discussion of the rati- fication debate by explaining to the students that, in the end, the An- tifederalists prevailed in the debate over the Bill of Rights, and the Constitution was ratified only be- cause the Federalists promised to add a bill of rights at the first op- portunity. That promise soon was fulfilled by Madison in the first Congress, with Madison's change of heart largely being attributable to his recognizing the importance to the American people of securing 704 PS: Political Science & Politics Reordering American Constitutional Law Teaching their rights. I quote Madison's clos- ing remarks in his June 8, 1789, speech to the U. S. House of Rep- resentatives advocating the adop- tion of the Bill of Rights to demon- strate the point. " I think we should obtain the confidence of our fellow- citizens," Madison argued, "in proportion as we fortify the rights of the people against the encroach- ments of the Government" (Meyers 1983, 175). My classroom discussion of the rights-oriented character of Ameri- can political culture is not limited to the American Founding, impor- tant as that period in our history is for defining who we are as a nation. I also turn the class's attention to the contemporary debate over whether we are too rights-oriented in the United States. I discuss both the provocative scholarship of con- temporary communitarians like Amitai Etzioni (1993) and Mary Ann Glendon (1991) and the com- munitarianism of our current presi- dent, Bill Clinton. Most significantly, I alert the class to the majoritarian and com- munitarian inclinations of today's conservative Republican Court. In stark contrast to the post-1937 Roosevelt and Warren Courts, I suggest, the Republican Court ap- pears to reject the idea that the Constitution commissions the Court as the institutional protector of in- dividual rights. I use the "peyote case," Employment Division v. Smith (1990), as an example. There, Justice Antonin Scalia, writ- ing for a sharply divided Court, made the startling pronouncement that the values enshrined in the Bill of Rights—individual religious lib- erty, in particular—are not immune from definition by the political pro- cess. My objective at this point in the course is not to engage the stu- dents in an extended exegesis on religious liberty, but rather to use the case as a vehicle through which they can begin to acclimate them- selves to constitutional law, as well as to reading Supreme Court opin- ions. That foundation laid, the stu- dents are ready to enter the fasci- nating world of American constitutional law. Conclusion In suggesting that constitutional law teaching needs to be reordered, I do not mean to imply that consti- tutional powers questions are less important than constitutional rights questions. My goal is simply to help students learn constitutional law better. In my experience, the order in which constitutional law is taught does not affect students' ability to learn the constitutional rights material. For the reasons dis- cussed above, students have little trouble with the rights material, regardless of whether that material is presented first or second. With respect to constitutional powers, however, students learn that material much better if they have had an opportunity to accli- mate themselves to thinking about constitutional law and to reading Supreme Court opinions through the more accessible constitutional rights material. Hence, my ration- ale for teaching constitutional rights first. After all, our objective as teachers should be to help students learn—even if that means reorder- ing a subject as dear to political scientists as constitutional law. References Dawson, John P., William Burnett Harvey, and Stanley D. Henderson. 1987. Cases and Comment on Contracts. 5th ed. Min- eola: Foundation Press. Etzioni, Amitai. 1993. The Spirit of Commu- nity: Rights, Responsibilities, and the Communitarian Agenda. New York: Crown. Glendon, Mary Ann. 1991. Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse. New York: Free Press. Hellenbrand, Harold. 1990. The Unfinished Revolution: Education and Politics in the Thought of Thomas Jefferson. Newark: University of Delaware Press. Meyers, Marvin, ed. 1983. The Mind of the Founder: Sources of the Political Thought of James Madison. Revised ed. Hanover: University Press of New Eng- land. Mezey, Susan Gluck. 1993. "Introduction to the Law and Politics Book Review." Law and Courts Newsletter. Spring. Pacelle, Richard L., Jr. 1991. The Transfor- mation of the Supreme Court's Agenda. Boulder: Westview Press. Peterson, Merrill D., ed. 1975. The Portable Thomas Jefferson. New York: Penguin Books. Storing, Herbert J. 1978. "The Constitution and the Bill of Rights." In Essays on the Constitution of the United States, ed. M. Judd Harmon. Port Washington: Kenni- kat Press. Note •Thanks to J. Timothy Collins for helpful comments. This article is dedicated to Stanley D. Henderson. About the Author Scott D. Gerber is visiting assistant pro- fessor of government at the College of Wil- liam and Mary. He has published articles on constitutional in- terpretation, on Clar- ence Thomas, and on American political thought. His book, To Secure These Rights: The Declaration of Independence and Constitutional Interpreta- tion, will be published by New York Uni- versity Press in March 1995. December 1994 705