Philosophy of science for sustainability science Vol.:(0123456789)1 3 Sustainability Science (2020) 15:1807–1817 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11625-020-00832-8 O V E R V I E W A R T I C L E Philosophy of science for sustainability science Michiru Nagatsu1  · Taylor Davis2 · C. Tyler DesRoches3 · Inkeri Koskinen4 · Miles MacLeod5 · Milutin Stojanovic1 · Henrik Thorén1 Received: 11 December 2019 / Accepted: 8 June 2020 / Published online: 22 June 2020 © The Author(s) 2020 Abstract Sustainability science seeks to extend scientific investigation into domains characterized by a distinct problem-solving agenda, physical and social complexity, and complex moral and ethical landscapes. In this endeavor, it arguably pushes scientific investigation beyond its usual comfort zones, raising fundamental issues about how best to structure such investigation. Phi- losophers of science have long scrutinized the structure of science and scientific practices, and the conditions under which they operate effectively. We propose a critical engagement between sustainability scientists and philosophers of science with respect to how to engage in scientific activity in these complex domains. We identify specific issues philosophers of science raise concerning current sustainability science and the contributions philosophers can make to resolving them. In conclusion, we reflect on the steps philosophers of science could take to advance sustainability science. Keywords Philosophy of science · Values in science · Interdisciplinarity · Transdisciplinarity · Methodology of sustainability science Introduction Sustainability science is a novel field of research in many respects. Its practical orientation, transformational ambi- tions, and inter- and transdisciplinary core require the reconfiguring of both the way science is organized and the relationship between science and practice (Clark and Dick- son 2003; Kates 2011; Jerneck et al. 2011; Bettencourt and Kaur 2011). When combined with the ethical dimensions of sustainability, this raises many serious philosophical concerns. Sustainability scientists have been hard at work in recent years developing conceptual resources and novel methodologies to address these concerns (Adler et al. 2018; Caniglia et al. 2017; Clapp 2018; Livoreil et al. 2017; Nel- son and Vucetich 2012; Lang et al. 2012), and philosophers of science have long been posing similar questions about sci- entific methodology (Winsberg 2018; Cartwright and Hardie 2012), the appropriate role of science in society (Longino 1990; Mitchell 2009), and the various ethical and epistemic issues that arise in scientific practice (Douglas 2009; Steel 2015; Koskinen and Rolin 2019). Moreover, much contem- porary philosophy of science is a continuation of science proper, as philosophers have begun to engage directly with the same theoretical questions that scientists ask (e.g. Davis et al. 2018). Accordingly, our claim here is that philoso- phers of science are uniquely positioned to contribute to the development and soundness of sustainability science, both from an outsider perspective and in partnership with sustain- ability scientists. A critical viewpoint from the philosophy of science could promote the further development of many theoretical discussions in sustainability science on one hand, while on the other, collaborative efforts could help to focus philosophical work on specific issues in the field. Collabo- rative efforts such as these have been endorsed by several academic units, including the School of Sustainability at Arizona State University, the Helsinki Institute of Sustain- ability Science at the University of Helsinki, and Purdue Handled by David J. Abson, Leuphana Universitat Luneburg, Germany. * Michiru Nagatsu michiru.nagatsu@helsinki.fi 1 Helsinki Institute of Sustainability Science (HELSUS) and Practical Philosophy, University of Helsinki, Helsinki, Finland 2 Purdue University, West Lafayette, IN, USA 3 Arizona State University, Tempe, AZ, USA 4 Tampere University, Tampere, Finland 5 University of Twente, Enschede, The Netherlands http://orcid.org/0000-0001-6566-0307 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s11625-020-00832-8&domain=pdf 1808 Sustainability Science (2020) 15:1807–1817 1 3 University’s Center for the Environment, all of which have hired philosophers of science (including some of us) to col- laborate with sustainability scientists. In the following, we identify three salient areas in which philosophers of science can readily facilitate theoretical, methodological, and ethical progress in sustainability sci- ence: (1) epistemological issues, (2) conceptual questions, and (3) the role of values. What we offer under these head- ings, however, is by no means an exhaustive or comprehen- sive account of all the ways in which philosophers could contribute to tackling the problems of sustainability sci- ence.1 We merely provide a sample selected to illustrate the general potential for such contributions. Our objective is to initiate a mutually enriching conversation between philosophers of science and sustainability scientists, thus responding to recent calls from the latter for more inclusive engagement with the humanities and social sciences (e.g. Hulme 2011; Jetzkowitz et al. 2018; Laplane et al. 2019; Díaz-Reviriego 2019). What is sustainability science? Given that neither the outer boundary nor the inner core of sustainability science has completely settled or solidi- fied, we do not wish to impose any definitions on develop- ing practices. However, it would be useful to give a broad characterization of the field to focus our discussion. Sustain- ability has a long and varied intellectual history (Caradonna 2014). Sustainability science, on the other hand, grew out of the concerns—most famously expressed in the 1987 World Commission on Environment and Development report Our Common Future (Brundtland 1987)—with tensions between balancing the needs of present generations with those of future generations without disrupting the life-support system of the planet (Shahadu 2016). As a proper field, it emerged only in the early 2000s (Bettencourt and Kaur 2011; see also Kates et al. 2001; Clark and Dickson 2003; Komiyama and Takeuchi 2006). Kates et al. (2001) is a starting point of sorts, and was perhaps the first attempt at giving the field both a name and a more tangible direction. From early on, sustainability science has been character- ized as a field devoted to studying—and ultimately trans- forming—the way human societies interact with and depend upon the natural environment (Kates et al. 2001; Kates 2011; Komiyama and Takeuchi 2006; Balvanera et al. 2017). Argu- ably, its roots lie in ecological economics, which focuses on integrative theorizing of human-nature or economy–ecology relationships (Costanza 2019) and has been defined broadly as “the science and management of sustainability” (Cos- tanza 1991).2 Although ecological economics has much in common with sustainability science, it is the latter that has made an unequivocal turn toward participatory democratic processes in knowledge production, notably inter- and trans- disciplinarity, participatory experimentation, and practice- based research (Norström et al. 2020). Two themes of sustainability science have persisted in the course of its development, although the emphasis has changed over time. The first theme concerns the dynam- ics of complex systems, the epistemological limitations and constraints such systems impose, and the wider implications for both science and practical decision-making (Kates et al. 2001; Clark et al. 2016; Ostrom et al. 2007). Early attempts at characterizing the field, such as Kates et al. (2001) (see also Kates 2011), emphasize the need for better models and modelling approaches to handle the complexity of targeted human-natural systems. This has changed, to some extent, to focus on ‘genuine’—or at least more pluralistic—interdis- ciplinarity, and finding the means for making sustainability science a more inclusive project that incorporates the social sciences and the humanities to a greater extent (Ness 2013; Isgren et al. 2017; Jerneck and Olsson 2020). The second theme concerns the role of transformation and (social) change, and the role sustainability scientists should play in their promotion. Sustainability science needs to be tightly coupled to decision- and policy-making processes, rather than being merely “curiosity-driven” (Spangenberg 2011; Clark and Dickson 2003). Although broadly speak- ing, the centrality of this aim has been recognized from the beginning (Kates et al. 2001), many alternative ways of framing the concept have been proposed. Sustainability science has thus been thought of as a problem- or solution- oriented science (Clark 2007; Miller et al. 2014; Jerneck and Olsson 2020) focused on the usefulness of the knowledge it produces (Clark et al. 2016), an applied science (Ostrom et al. 2007), an action-oriented science (Spangenberg 2011; Cash et al. 2003; Fazey et al. 2018), and a trans-disciplinary venture (Huutoniemi and Tapio 2014; Lang et  al. 2012; Wiek et al. 2012) that achieves transformation through the 1 For example, ontology is a salient area of sustainability science to which philosophers can contribute but we do not discuss it in this paper (but see “Conceptual work for sustainability science” below). In fact, recent debates on process ontologies in sustainability sci- ence (e.g. Hertz et  al. 2020) draw heavily on the philosophy of biol- ogy (Nicholson and Dupré 2018). Social ontology is also relevant to sustainability science, in particular the performative and constructive functions of scientific models at the science-policy interface, as well as in the co-production of knowledge and governance, which phi- losophers and sociologists of science have discussed in some detail (MacKenzie et al. 2007; Zeiss and Van Egmond 2010 and references therein). 2 The International Society for Ecological Economics published the inaugural issue of the journal Ecological Economics in 1989. 1809Sustainability Science (2020) 15:1807–1817 1 3 deep involvement of stakeholders and relevant constituencies in the research process. These two themes are subject to considerable discussion and engagement within sustainability science, and they touch a range of concerns—methodological, epistemologi- cal, practical, and conceptual—that are fundamentally philo- sophical in nature. This motivates and provides an opportu- nity for deeper engagement and exchange between the two fields. In what follows, we outline three main areas in which we see particular opportunities for such exchange. They are: (1) epistemological issues, including methodology, inter- and trans-disciplinarity, and the science-policy interface, (2) conceptual work and analysis, and (3) normativity and values in sustainability science. Epistemological issues: methodology, inter‑ and trans‑disciplinarity, and science policy Epistemology in general concerns the justification and truth of beliefs. The philosophy of science focuses principally on scientific knowledge, but including the processes and con- ditions of knowledge production and application. The lat- ter range from specific research methods, relations between scientific disciplines, and broader contexts in which science as an activity takes place. In this section, we discuss these matters in turn. Rethinking the scope and character of methodologies in sustainability science Sustainability scientists have recently started discussing a range of methodological issues, including the transferabil- ity of case-based transdisciplinary knowledge (Adler et al. 2018), the taxonomy of experimentation (Caniglia et  al. 2017), evidence synthesis (Livoreil et  al. 2017), and the synthesis of scientific and non-scientific knowledge such as indigeneous knowledge (Tengö et al. 2017). These all revolve around the question of how to produce knowledge that is both epistemically reliable and practically usable. Philosophers of science have been working on these meth- odological questions for decades, scrutinizing scientific methods of theorizing, modelling, and evidential reasoning. Contemporary philosophers of science typically approach these problems by analyzing well-documented cases or epi- sodes from mature disciplines such as biology, economics, and cognitive science, attempting thereby to extract some general methodological lessons. On the other hand, sus- tainability scientists face an urgent need to develop some frameworks or heuristics to organize and guide heterogene- ous practices in their own field. As a result, typological and taxonomical frameworks proliferate, often with no critical examination or justification of how they generate reliable and usable knowledge. With this unique situation in mind, we suggest that the philosophy of science could comple- ment efforts to develop the methodology of sustainability science. Sustainability scientists are already drawing on the philosophical literature: Adler et al. (2018) cite Cartwright (2012) and Cartwright and Hardie (2012) to argue against taking randomized controlled trials as the gold standard for producing evidence for public policy, for example, whereas Caniglia et al. (2017) cite Mitchell (2009) to argue against context- and value-free ideals of science. However, such contributions could be more substantial and constructive. To give an example, Adler et  al. (2018) case for ana- logical reasoning could be further developed by building on existing methodological debates on external validity and extrapolation. Adler et al. propose using argument by anal- ogy as a means of transferring substantive knowledge from one transdisciplinary study to another. It is, therefore, cru- cial to understand whether or not two contexts are similar enough to warrant analogical reasoning, but how can one be confident that the original context and the new contexts are similar enough in relevant ways? If one already knew this, would it not make the knowledge transfer redundant? This problem, the extrapolator’s circle (Steel 2008), has been extensively discussed in the philosophical literature. Of the several methodological solutions that have been put forward, the most notable are comparative process-tracing (Steel 2008) and analogical reasoning (Guala 2005, 2010; Steel 2010). Both accounts explicitly formulate inferential strategies for operationalizing ‘relevant similarities’ to make extrapolation more reliable, and therefore, could be usefully applied in the context of extrapolation in sustainability sci- ence (see e.g. Parker 2010 for climate science). Similarly, one could enrich Caniglia et al. (2017) case for value-laden and context-dependent sustainability science by engaging with the philosophical literature on values in science (see “Normativity and values in sustainability science”). Such examples also provide an opportunity for philosophers to test and develop their analytical tools against some of the unique methodological challenges that sustainability science poses. Inter‑disciplinarity and trans‑disciplinarity Inter-disciplinary and trans-disciplinary (ID/TD) modes of scientific research are widely embraced as the modus oper- andi of sustainability science. Although there is some disa- greement and inconsistency with regard to how the concepts of transdisciplinary and interdisciplinary research are and should be formulated, many scholars, funding agencies and others have settled on defining the latter as integrative prob- lem-solving across university disciplines (Lattuca 2001). Integration is not operationally defined in the literature, but it is understood as a process of combining methodologies or practices through which novel synthesized approaches 1810 Sustainability Science (2020) 15:1807–1817 1 3 would emerge (see Huutoniemi et al. 2010). Current dis- ciplines, it is claimed, do not in themselves have effective methodologies for resolving sustainability problems. There is thus a need for methodological innovations that transgress current epistemic standards and norms within disciplines, and thereby force disciplines to aim toward specific, prob- lem-driven targets. This point serves to rationalize the need for problem-solving contexts to have effective ID. Simply combining methodologies, or applying them independently in the context of a joint research project, is usually consid- ered a form of “mere” multidisciplinarity, which is deemed less effective and efficient than ID in terms of achieving satisfactory solutions (but see Mennes 2019). Transdisciplinarity is usually treated as a variation of interdisciplinarity, requiring that integrative interactions fur- ther include extra-academic stakeholders (Jahn et al. 2012; Pohl et  al. 2011). As such, the relevant problem-context is better able to represent the interests and knowledge of stakeholders in the problem, helping the scientific process to devise more robust solutions. The literature on sustainability science has contributed substantially to the development and advocacy of transdisciplinary research, including as a means of handling so-called “wicked problems” (Bernstein 2015). In our view, although plenty of research has been carried out to create strategies and plans for doing ID/TD (see Lang et al. 2012) or parsing these concepts in terms of taxonomies (Klein 2010), some of the basic underlying motivations have yet to be properly articulated or tested. Why, for instance, is cross-border collaboration such a preferred means for imple- menting ID, particularly given that much effective inter- disciplinary innovation has come about without strict col- laboration (see e.g. Harman and Dietrich 2013)? Arguably, ecological economics is a case in point of innovative benefits not being bound collaboratively to economists or traditional economics. Indeed many positions behind the contemporary enthusiasm for both ID and TD, in the science studies and elsewhere, seem to reflect views that are not strictly based on epistemological argument—having a principally political or ideological dimension (Godin 1998; Jacobs 2013)—and/or are not sufficiently justified in epistemological terms. More specifically, they are not justified with respect to the con- straints under which effective science happens. Such views promote speculative optimism about the potential of these integrative forms of ID and TD, which has not been borne out in practice to the desired extent (see Yegros-Yegros et al. 2015). Some of us have studied the epistemological and cognitive issues that arise in interactions between dis- ciplines, and the ways in which the disciplinary structure of science drives the development of interdisciplinarity and transdisciplinarity in practice (MacLeod and Nagatsu 2016, 2018; MacLeod 2018; Thorén and Persson 2013; Thorén and Breian 2016; Persson et al. 2018; Koskinen and Mäki 2016). These critical analyses ultimately bolster enthusiasm for ID/ TD work by providing a methodological reality check, as it were, moving beyond speculative optimism and improv- ing efficiency. Specifically, they should complement ID/TD typologies in sustainability science (Lang et al. 2012; Brandt et al. 2013), giving them a better grounding in practice. Two issues stand out in this regard. First, the discipline- free ideal championed by some proponents of transdiscipli- narity in sustainability science (Frodeman 2013; Spangen- berg 2011), which is often founded on a general commitment to the methodology of systems dynamics, underestimates the role that disciplinary knowledge and methods should play. It is not clear why a discipline-free conceptualization is ideal, or how it can produce outcomes superior to a multidiscipli- nary or interdisciplinary model (Koskinen and Mäki 2016). Moreover, given that much current empirical work evolves from formal modelling frameworks developed in established disciplines (rather than, say, systems dynamics models), the discipline-free conceptualization of transdisciplinarity seems out of step with how it is commonly practiced. This leads to the second issue, namely the relationship between natural and social science (Philipson et al. 2009). Many sustainability scientists consider it critical to over- come the obstacles generated by the different aims, con- cepts, norms, and methods that characterize these two broad fields. Indeed, some have argued that bringing the natural and social sciences together is a necessary precondition for their success (Jerneck et al. 2011; Kates et al. 2001). This applies to very general differences such as that between the goals of interpretation guiding some social sciences and the goals of explanation and prediction guiding natural science, as well as to more specific differences such as those between economics and ecology. Various philosophers have investi- gated the background assumptions and conceptual and meth- odological inconsistencies that inhibit efficient interaction across these disciplinary boundaries, such as different con- ceptions of “natural” and “artificial” (DesRoches et al. 2019; Inkpen and DesRoches 2019,forthcoming), and diagnosing such impediments is at least a first step toward overcom- ing them. Others have identified methodological options for integrating data and concepts across boundaries into formal models such as Bayesian Belief Network methods, and these methods can be collected and evaluated in terms of their capacities to do so (MacLeod and Nagatsu 2018). If observations such as these are taken into account, the hope is that philosophers, in combination with others concerned with sustainability, might help to fashion more pragmatic approaches to ID and TD that are grounded in the affordances and constraints of existing methodologies and practices. This, in turn, could foster the formulation of norms and policies that incentivize such approaches. For example, model-coupling across disciplinary boundaries may not achieve fully optimal solutions to sustainability problems given the extent to which the coupled models 1811Sustainability Science (2020) 15:1807–1817 1 3 rely on disciplinary legacy models. However, it does offer the potential for complex accounts of coupled human and natural systems to be brought to bear on difficult sustain- ability problems. Making such couplings function well is a substantial computational and mathematical problem, which demands its own theoretical work (Voinov and Shugart 2013). In contrast to most expectations of ID or TD, how- ever, this work is primarily theoretical and does not directly concern a specific sustainability problem. Nevertheless, it is inherently interdisciplinary, and arguably should be a target of funding policy. Social epistemology and science policy As noted above, sustainability and other societal problems have been strong drivers of recent policy trends toward fund- ing problem-driven, interdisciplinary research. In turn, sus- tainability science has greatly benefited from these recent policy trends. However, one needs to ask whether this makes sustainability science not only more profitable for those who obtain the grants, but also better as a scientific enterprise from the epistemic and practical perspectives. Evidence to this effect is surprisingly scarce. Meanwhile, some authors point out the negative unintended consequences of policy shifts toward inter- and transdisciplinarity (e.g. Ash 2019), and there is suspicion amongst some scientists that interdis- ciplinarity produces lower-quality outcomes (Leahey et al. 2017). It is not yet known how these policy trends affect the reliability and relevance of the knowledge produced in the long run. Philosophers of science have long recognized that the quality of scientific knowledge depends not only on individual geniuses but also on the social conditions under which science is practiced. Social epistemology is an approach in philosophy that focuses on the normative study of the social dimensions of scientific knowledge and practice,3 and on the ways interactions between individuals and groups in scientific communities affect the reliability of knowledge thus produced (Longino 1990; Kitcher 1993). These epistemic agents collaborate to find truths, but they also compete for scarce resources such as fame, funding, and tenure. Their choices and actions are restricted by rules and practices. Accordingly, by tinkering with institutional variables, science policy could have a substantial impact on the focus and outcomes of science. In recent years, too, philosophers of science have increasingly started not only to pay attention not only to the social but also to the institu- tional dimension of scientific knowledge production. This has resulted in normative work on how various institutional changes and incentives affect scientific results, for example, and on the epistemic risks that arise from different funding incentives (cf. Reiss and Kitcher 2009; Turner 2019). The perspective of social epistemology raises several questions in sustainability science, some of which relate to the epistemic quality of the research. For example, how does an emphasis on the practical impact (e.g. solution-orienta- tion, work with extra-academic partners) affect the reliability of the produced knowledge? Is there a trade-off between the immediate gain of applicable knowledge and the long- term development of general theoretical knowledge, which might turn out to be valuable later in unexpected domains (e.g. evolutionary game theory)? How does the demand for interdisciplinary collaboration affect the reliability of tradi- tional disciplinary norms and standards? How do we strike a practical balance when there are trade-offs between ethical demands such as inclusiveness, and epistemic demands such as predictive accuracy? Other questions concern the future of the field. Currently, for instance, sustainability science seems to benefit from the trends in science policy, but it is known that policy trends change. What happens to sustain- ability science and the momentum toward methodological standardization when sustainability loses its political appeal as an organizational principle for science policy? What are the risks in allowing science policy to determine a disci- pline’s course instead of letting it evolve according to more endogenous factors? These are some of the most pressing questions of social epistemology that sustainability science needs to address if it is to outlive current policy trends and develop into a mature, epistemically successful field. Conceptual work for sustainability science Scrutinizing the meanings and uses of scientific concepts is a standard, traditional activity in the philosophy of science. This includes analyzing general concepts discussed above, such as theory, model, or evidence, in an epistemological context, as well as those associated with specific disciplines such as species or gene in biology, symmetry in physics, and preference in economics. Within cognitive science, even the concept of concept has been analyzed extensively. Mean- while, sustainability scientists draw on abstract concepts from a wide range of disciplines, and develop and deploy them in new and different contexts in which they may well carry different meanings and implications. As a result, notions such as adaptive capacity, social-ecological system, complex adaptive system, self-organization, Anthropocene, ecosystem services, vulnerability, adaptation, complexity and resilience—to name a few—all qualify as potentially benefiting from philosophical analysis. There are several 3 Normativity in this context concerns both how best to arrange social conditions for robust knowledge (normative epistemology), and how to ethically evaluate certain knowledge practice in terms of justice, equity, and so on (normative ethics). We focus mainly on the former in this section. 1812 Sustainability Science (2020) 15:1807–1817 1 3 reasons to assume that such a venture could be of use within sustainability science. To begin with, sometimes there is a need to develop bet- ter, more consistent or precise definitions. This is especially true in specific situations and technical contexts, and is par- ticularly relevant to sustainability science in which concepts and terms from different disciplines frequently intersect. Among the major issues requiring conceptual clarity are the ontological, in other words, basic questions about what exists. The concept of resilience is a case in point. As a notion, it has been used in a range of disciplines, and draws from current usage in ecology, psychology, and economics (Thorén 2014,2020). Ontological subtleties have practical implications in the present context. What does it mean for a complex adaptive system to persist through time? How can one distinguish between the adaptation of a system and the transformation of one system into another? Conceptual clar- ity in such matters is crucial for operationalizing phenomena effectively, generalizing results, and extracting the correct empirical implications from abstract theories and models. Nevertheless, precise definitions providing necessary and sufficient conditions are not always desirable (Strunz 2012; see also Thorén 2014; Brandt and Jax 2007). In the context of moral psychology, for example, Stich (2018) recently argued that the concept of morality did not pick out a natu- ral kind and that, as a result, decades of work attempting to define “morality” in a principled way had been a waste of time. Others point out that concepts such as resilience and ecosystem services are boundary objects (Brandt and Jax 2007; Abson et al. 2014)—that is to say, concepts that are rigid enough to maintain identity across sites whilst at the same time being sufficiently flexible to accommodate local needs (Star and Griesemer 1989), thus better serving interdisciplinary ends. Sustainability in itself is frequently described as something like a “discursive field” (Caradonna 2014) in which the lack of a precise and commonly agreed upon definition is neither avoidable nor reason to be dismiss- ive of the notion itself. Thus, determining when concepts do require principled definitions and when they do not may well be a difficult conceptual problem in its own right, and one that philosophers are directly trained to address. Moreover, it seems that there is a wealth of thick evalua- tive concepts in the domain of sustainability, in which nor- mative and descriptive elements are inextricably intertwined (Putnam 2002; Williams 1985, cf. Gallie 1956). Questions regarding values—as we discuss in the next section—thus become unavoidable, despite the fact that they might fall beyond the scope of science. Alternatively, concepts may play other extra-scientific roles such as motivating sustain- able behavior rather than explaining it. All these issues nev- ertheless fall under the heading of conceptual analysis, as we understand it, further illustrating the fruitfulness of thinking about concepts in a thorough and rigorous way. Third, and perhaps most importantly, conceptual analysis can increase the efficiency and effectiveness of interdiscipli- nary work. Many of the most basic concepts addressed in the literature are basic precisely because of their affordance for integration across disciplinary boundaries. The concept ecosystem services was proposed to facilitate the integration of economics with ecology, for example, and many have had high hopes that the concept resilience will make modelling frameworks of population ecology available to the social sciences (see Abson et al. 2014). Although these concepts do serve to identify certain similarities shared by phenomena across contexts, there is much more to theoretical and meth- odological integration than the mere identification of simi- larities. When these concepts are operationalized in different empirical domains it is often hard to determine the explana- tory value of the similarities they pick out. For instance, the concept of resilience has been applied to many different types of systems, yielding notions of ecological resilience, social-ecological resilience, community resilience, and psy- chological resilience—to mention just a few (see e.g. Berkes et al. 2013; Thorén 2014; Fraccascia et al. 2018). However, the causal mechanisms that explain resilience in these domains are radically different, hence it is far from clear how describing them all as resilient enhances explanatory or predictive power. Genuine integration requires detailed analysis of the concepts being integrated, which is sufficient to connect abstract similarities with the concrete observa- tions that need to be explained and predicted. Finally, given the practical focus of sustainability sci- ence, it is necessary for conceptual work to facilitate the application of scientific knowledge, in addition to its pro- duction. The importance of such applications is evidenced in the growing attention given to “green nudges” in recent years (Schubert 2017). However, much of this attention is focused on ethical value rather than the ways in which sci- entific knowledge can be applied in executing green nudges effectively. Ethical work is not necessarily conceptual in the sense emphasized here. Davis et al. (2018), in contrast, drawing on the literature concerning the evolution of social norms and cooperation, develop the concept of norma- tive motivation, which they use to argue that interventions designed to promote sustainable behavior have overlooked a crucial source of motivation. Existing interventions focus almost entirely on individuals’ instrumental motivation to adopt sustainable behavior—desires based on instrumental means for achieving other goals such as reducing taxes or avoiding fines. Yet humans also possess an innate and uni- versal capacity to internalize norms, or to acquire the intrin- sic motivation to do what is right and to avoid what is wrong, regardless of the instrumental costs and benefits. Because such motives evolved precisely to perform the function of producing costly, prosocial cooperation, they are at the same time independent of motives of self-interest and therefore 1813Sustainability Science (2020) 15:1807–1817 1 3 potentially very powerful. Moreover, in that particular nor- mative motivations are transmitted culturally through social learning, they have the potential to spread rapidly and to be maintained at equilibrium in populations by the natural dynamics of cultural evolution, without requiring govern- ments to pay the costs of monitoring and regulation. This illustrates how conceptual work within the social sciences could promote the application of scientific knowledge to the practical goals of sustainability. We thus envisage conceptual work not only as the dis- ambiguation and refinement of definitions—although this is sometimes important—but also as the development of new concepts, and the transfer of “old” concepts into “new” domains across disciplinary boundaries (experimental phi- losophers have begun this inquiry, see Robinson et al. 2019). This may well require sensitivity to and knowledge of the historical development of the science, in addition to famili- arity with current meanings, uses and applications across a variety of contexts. We take such work to be its own form of interdisciplinary endeavor, in which methods and skills from the humanities are deployed in the service of sustain- ability science. Normativity and values in sustainability science No sustainability scientist would assert that the field operates independently of values.4 On the contrary, it is, and ought to be, replete with value judgements. Wiek et al. (2011) argue that sustainability scientists should be trained to be “norma- tively competent,” to develop interventions that make the world a better—more sustainable—place. Normative com- petence is commonly defined as “the ability to collectively map, specify, apply, reconcile, and negotiate sustainability values, principles, goals, and targets. This capacity enables, first, to collectively assess the (un-)sustainability of current and/or future states of social-ecological systems and, sec- ond, to collectively create and craft sustainability visions for these systems. This capacity is based on acquired norma- tive knowledge including concepts of justice, equity, social- ecological integrity, and ethics” (Wiek et al. 2011, 209). If sustainability scientists are encouraged to become norma- tively competent, certain value judgments are explicitly and systematically integrated into the field even if they disagree on the exact nature and role of such judgements in specific contexts. Arguably, value commitments and a strong sense of urgency to resolve pressing environmental problems serve as the ultimate motivation of most sustainability scientists. They insist that values not only guide their decisions about which research projects to pursue, but also may legitimately influence some scientific inferences. For example, when the stakes are high and the consequences of being incorrect are severe or catastrophic, it seems that (non-epistemic) ethical values should influence (epistemic) decisions about what counts as sufficient evidence for accepting scientific claims. However, the putative roles of such values in science raise serious questions about scientific objectivity (Nelson and Vucetich 2012; Mitchell 2009). The standard, value-free ideal of science insists that ethical values and justice should have no influence over the reasoning of scientists, whose concerns should be restricted solely to epistemic values such as explanatory power and empirical accuracy, particularly when it comes to hypothesis testing (Douglas 2009). In the face of these well-documented worries, sustainability sci- ence will need a compelling story that explains why such non-epistemic values are scientifically legitimate. Consider, for example, the hypothesis that Equilibrium Climate Sensitivity (ECS) is between 1.5 and 4.5 ℃. Accept- ing or rejecting this hypothesis would have significant con- sequences for practical action and, therefore, one might sup- pose that the decisions to accept or reject it should depend in part on ethical value judgements that concern the wider social implications and risks of making an error. This is known among philosophers of science as the argument from inductive risk, which consists of three propositions: (1) one central aim of scientific inference is to decide whether to accept or reject hypotheses; (2) decisions about whether to accept or reject a scientific hypothesis can have implications for practical action, and when this happens, acceptance deci- sions should depend in part on non-epistemic value judge- ments about the costs of error; (3) therefore, non-epistemic values can legitimately influence scientific inference (Doug- las 2009; Steel 2015). In fact, the extent to which science is and ought to be free of non-epistemic values is hotly disputed (see Longino 1990; Brown 2013; Douglas 2013; Elliott and McKaughan 2014; Steel 2015; Winsberg 2018). Without defending a particular form of the argument from inductive risk, our point is simply to insist that it is crucial for the success of sustainability science (1) to justify how some values, including the ethical values of sustainability scientists, may legitimately enter into science, and (2) to design methods and institutions capable of countering the problematic biases that values might pro- duce (see Longino 1990; Brown 2013; Douglas 2013; Elliott and McKaughan 2014; Steel 2015). 4 We follow the standard categorization of values as epistemic and non-epistemic in the philosophy of science. The former concerns what you value in knowledge (empirical accuracy, generality, etc.); the latter concerns everything else. This conventional categorization is not meant to implicitly value knowledge more than other things we care about, but it is a useful way to organize thoughts when talking about values in the context of an enterprise (viz., science) that is fun- damentally oriented toward epistemic goals. 1814 Sustainability Science (2020) 15:1807–1817 1 3 Another way in which non-epistemic values enter sus- tainability science is through the choice of management or decision-making models. The growing use of formal deci- sion-support modelling frameworks (e.g. Bayesian network analysis methods; multi-criteria decision analysis methods; integrated assessment modelling) (see Benson and Stephen- son 2018) raises important questions regarding the trade-off between epistemic and ethical values (Vezér et al. 2018). Although the propagation and standardization of a relatively small number of modelling frameworks or templates have the methodological advantage of facilitating theoretical work and model development (Humphreys 2004; MacLeod and Nagatsu 2018), relying on the same set of models could also embed assumptions that bias outcomes and undermine reli- ability (Wimsatt 2007). Analogously, focusing on the same set of management models could produce ethical biases, implicitly prioritizing some values over others, often for epistemic reasons, without sufficient ethical justification. As such, decision-making models may face a trade-off between epistemic values (such as operationalizability, computability, and rigor) and the inclusion of relevant ethical values. Phi- losophers’ model-focused analysis, as well as case studies conducted by science and technology scholars (e.g. Zeiss and Van Egmond 2014) could enhance understanding of how such trade-offs figure in practice. Although distinguishing between epistemic and non- epistemic (including ethical) values may be very difficult in concrete cases (Schneider et al. 2019), it has significant merit in terms of illuminating different aspects of norma- tive orientation. An additional challenge related to analytic engagement with norms and values concerns the practice of sustainability science: given the complex collaborations involving diverse experts and multiple stakeholders, values are applied in pluralistic ways that may well be implicit and mutually conflicting. Although exposing implicit values and negotiating among them remains an essential task in sus- tainability research (Fazey et al. 2018), the last few decades have witnessed a proliferation of tailored ethical approaches (such as bioethics and indigenous studies), which although not always compatible, have often guided the scientific out- comes of inter- and transdisciplinary collaboration in the field. Unlike traditional philosophers of science, who are overwhelmingly concerned with keeping illegitimate non- epistemic values out of science, sustainability scientists openly accept them but have not, in general, addressed the issue of illegitimate non-epistemic values. In practice, sus- tainability scientists acknowledge the distinction between the variety of non-epistemic values held by the (1) actors or stakeholders involved, (2) sustainability scholars and scien- tists, and (3) on-the-ground decision-makers, although the roles of these non-epistemic values in sustainability research tend to be discussed only in vague terms (Horcea-Milcu et al. 2019). The resulting “messy” ethical frameworks have sometimes contributed to unclear scientific outcomes, mak- ing it difficult to align research approaches and to transfer or extrapolate results from case studies to wider research areas (Luederitz 2016; Adler et al. 2018). As mentioned above with regard to conceptual analysis, dissecting which specific values are in play and how values enter into sustainability science requires detailed attention to how epistemic and ethi- cal values are embedded in concrete scientific practices. Consider, for example, research on sustainable food sys- tems: there is a highly polarized debate between agricul- tural intensification, focusing on increased efficiency in food production, and agro-ecology, focusing on paradigm change in the design and governance of food systems. Although both sides are committed to sustainability, their scientific approaches diverge because of mutually incompatible sys- tems of values: increasing efficiency of the current system vs. a fundamental re-designing (Clapp 2018). Implicit and complex value commitments of this kind are present in the day-to-day research of sustainability scientists, and tradi- tional frameworks of ethical assessment are insufficient in terms of exposing them. Making such value commitments explicit may require alternative ethical frameworks that are specific to sustainability science, with its value-laden contexts dominated by complexity and urgency (Whitbeck 2011; Stojanovic 2019). These frameworks must be able to explicate the practical, ethical, and epistemic value judge- ments embedded in research practices, and suggest ways to integrate them in a transparent and accessible way. Conclusion Sustainability science is stepping into novel territory in its effort to achieve practical scientific outcomes in highly com- plex and context-rich problem-solving environments. This territory is not a complete terra incognita, however, in that one can consult various maps developed in the philosophy of science and its neighboring fields that have examined a wide range of diverse scientific practices, both historical and contemporary. In this overview article, we have briefly sketched three key areas in which these prior insights may contribute to the development of sustainability science. The first concerns epistemology and methodology: we illustrate how the production of reliable and usable knowledge is sup- ported by the analysis of (a) inferential strategies such as analogical reasoning, (b) new practices such as inter- and transdisciplinary research, and (c) social and institutional conditions such as science policy that incentivize new research practices. The second concerns conceptual issues: we illustrate how philosophical analysis can (a) make key concepts in sustainability science clear and precise, (b) iden- tify the functions of necessarily ambiguous and thick evalu- ative concepts, and (c) develop new concepts that are useful 1815Sustainability Science (2020) 15:1807–1817 1 3 for applying sustainability science to the practical goals of sustainability. The third area concerns normative and ethical issues, and we highlight the importance of (a) making the role of values in scientific inferences explicit and legitimate, (b) identifying and untangling tensions between epistemic and ethical values, and (c) developing context-specific ethi- cal frameworks for complex and urgent decision-making. This sampling of issues reflects the authors’ areas of expertise, and it is not meant to be an exhaustive list of ways in which the philosophy of science, let alone philosophy in general, can contribute to sustainability science. We conclude by reflecting on a few options for further developing a phi- losophy of sustainability science that sustainability scientists might recognize as relevant and useful. First, and most obvi- ously, more philosophers of science should take an interest in sustainability science. Specifically, we need to engage more with its novel and evolving practices such as ID/TD research, experimentation, and action-oriented research with explicit ethical commitments, and to develop relevant tools. Second, and more subtly, these features should be examined critically on epistemic, conceptual and normative grounds, but not as anomalies to some idealized scientific method. Philosophers of social science tell us that it is more productive to directly engage with the unique challenges in studying human behav- ior, the mind, society and so on than to decide pre-scientifi- cally whether social science can become a ‘genuine’ science like physics (e.g., Guala 2007). Philosophers interested in sustainability science should adopt a similar, complementary approach (cf. Chang 2004), remaining empirically informed about, and participating in, developments in the field. Third, this requires more constructive interactions between philoso- phers and sustainability scientists, including joint research as well as critical correspondence.5 We hope that these thoughts will stimulate productive interactions between the two com- munities in the future. Acknowledgements Open access funding was provided by University of Helsinki including Helsinki University Central Hospital. We thank three anonymous reviewers and Dave Abson for their valuable com- ments. This research received HELSUS seed funding (2019). Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attri- bution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adapta- tion, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creat iveco mmons .org/licen ses/by/4.0/. References Abson DJ, von Wehrden H, Baumgärtner S, Fischer J, Hanspach J, Härdtle W, Heinrichs H, Klein AM, Lang DJ, Martens P, Walms- ley D (2014) Ecosystem services as a boundary object for sus- tainability. Ecol Econ 103:29–37 Adler C, Hirsch Hadorn G, Breu T, Wiesmann U, Pohl C (2018) Con- ceptualizing the transfer of knowledge across cases in transdis- ciplinary research. Sustain Sci 13(1):179–190 Ash MG (2019) Interdisciplinarity in historical perspective. Perspect Sci 27(4):619–642 Balvanera P, Daw TM, Gardner TA, Martín-López B, Norström AV, Speranza CI, Spierenburg M, Bennett EM, Farfan M, Hamann M, Kittinger JN, Luthe T, Maass M, Peterson GD, Perez-Verdin G (2017) Key features for more successful place-based sustain- ability research on social-ecological systems: a programme on ecosystem change and society (PECS) perspective. Ecol Soc. https ://doi.org/10.5751/ES-08826 -22011 4 Benson AJ, Stephenson RL (2018) Options for integrating ecological, economic, and social objectives in evaluation and management of fisheries. Fish Fish 19(1):40–56 Berkes F, Ross H (2013) Community resilience: toward an integrated approach. Soc Nat Res 26(1):5–20 Bernstein JH (2015) Transdisciplinarity: a review of its origins, devel- opment, and current issues. J Res Pract 11(1):R1 Bettencourt LMA, Kaur J (2011) Evolution and structure of sustain- ability science. Proc Natl Acad Sci 108(49):19540–19545 Brand F, Jax K (2007) Focusing the meaning(s) of resilience: resil- ience as a descriptive concept and a boundary object. Ecol Soc 12(1):1–23 Brandt P, Ernst A, Gralla F, Luederitz C, Lang DJ, Newig J, Reinert F, Abson DJ, von Wehrden H (2013) A review of transdisciplinary research in sustainability science. Ecol Econ 92:1–15 (Land Use) Brown MJ (2013) Values in science beyond underdetermination and inductive risk. Philos Sci 80(5):829–839 Brundtland G. (1987). Report of the World Commission on Environ- ment and Development. Our Common Future. United Nations General Assembly document A/42/427.Oxford University Press. Caniglia G, Schäpke N, Lang DJ, Abson DJ, Luederitz C, Wiek A, Laubichler MD, Gralla F, von Wehrden H (2017) Experiments and evidence in sustainability science: a typology. J Clean Prod 169:39–47 Caradonna J (2014) Sustainability: a history. Oxford University Press, Oxford Cartwright N (2012) Will this policy work for you? Predicting effec- tiveness better: how philosophy helps. Philos Sci 79(5):973–989 Cartwright N, Hardie J (2012) Evidence-based policy: a practical guide to doing it better. Oxford University Press, Oxford Cash DW, Clark WC, Alcock F, Dickson NM, Eckley N, Guston DH, Jäger J, Mitchell RB (2003) Knowledge systems for sustainable development. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 100(14):8086–8091. https ://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.12313 32100 Chang H (2004) Inventing temperature: measurement and scientific progress. Oxford University Press, Oxford Clapp J (2018) Mega-mergers on the menu: corporate concentra- tion and the politics of sustainability in the global food system. Global Environ Politics 18(2):12–33 Clark WC (2007) Sustainability science: a room of its own. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 104(6):1737–1738. https ://doi.org/10.1073/ pnas.06112 91104 5 For example, this article was written by philosophers, but it has benefited greatly from critical comments given by anonymous reviewers who are experts in sustainability science. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ https://doi.org/10.5751/ES-08826-220114 https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1231332100 https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1231332100 https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0611291104 https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0611291104 1816 Sustainability Science (2020) 15:1807–1817 1 3 Clark WC, Van Kerkhoff L, Lebel L, Gallopin GC (2016) Crafting usable knowledge for sustainable development. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 113(17):4570–4578 Clark WC, Dickson NM (2003) Sustainability science: the emerging research program. Proc Natl Acad Sci 100(14):8059–8061 Costanza R (ed) (1991) Ecological economics: the science and man- agement of sustainability. Columbia University Press, New York Costanza R (2019) Ecological Economics 1☆. In: Fath B (ed) Encyclo- pedia of Ecology. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 258–264 Davis T, Hennes EP, Raymond L (2018) Cultural evolution of nor- mative motivations for sustainable behaviour. Nat Sustain 1(5):218–224 DesRoches CT, Inkpen SA, Green TL (2019) The eroding artificial- natural distinction? some consequences for ecology and econom- ics. In: Nagatsu M, Ruzzene A (eds) Contemporary philosophy and social science: An interdisciplinary dialogue, chapter  2. Bloomsbury Publishing, London, pp 39–57 Díaz-Reviriego I, Turnhout E, Beck S (2019) Participation and inclu- siveness in the intergovernmental science-policy platform on biodiversity and ecosystem services. Nat Sustain 2:457–464. https ://doi.org/10.1038/s4189 3-019-0290-6 Douglas H (2009) Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. Univer- sity of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh Douglas H (2013) The value of cognitive values. Philos Sci 80(5):796–806 Elliott KC, McKaughan DJ (2014) Nonepistemic values and the mul- tiple goals of science. Philos Sci 81(1):1–21 Fazey I, Schäpke N, Caniglia G, Patterson J, Hultman J, van Mierlo B, Säwe F, Wiek A, Wittmayer J, Aldunce P, Al Waer H, Battacha- rya N, Bradbury H, Carmen E, Colvin J, Cvitanovic C, D’Souza M, Gopel M, Goldstein B, Wyborn C (2018) Ten essentials for action-oriented and second order energy transitions, transforma- tions and climate change research. Energy Res Soc Sci 40:54–70 Fraccascia L, Giannoccaro I, Albino V (2018) Resilience of complex systems: state of the art and directions for future research. Com- plexity 2018(2):1–44 Frodeman R (2013) Interdisciplinarity, Communication, and the Lim- its of Knowledge. In: O’Rourke M, Crowley S, Eigenbrode SD, Wulfhorst JD (eds) Enhancing communication and collaboration in cross-disciplinary research. Sage, Thousand Oaks, pp 103–116 Gallie WB (1956) Essentially contested concepts. Proceed Aristot Soc 56:167–198 Godin B (1998) Writing performative history: the new new Atlantis? Soc Stud Sci 28(3):465–483 Guala F (2005) The methodology of experimental economics. Cam- bridge University Press, Cambridge Guala F (2007) The philosophy of social science: metaphysical and empirical. Philos Compass 2(6):954–980 Guala F (2010) Extrapolation, analogy, and comparative process trac- ing. Philos Sci 77(5):1070–1082 Harman O, Dietrich MR (eds) (2013) Outsider scientists: routes to innovation in biology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago Hertz T, Mancilla Garcia M, Schlüter M (2020) From nouns to verbs: how process ontologies enhance our understanding of social- ecological systems understood as complex adaptive systems. People Nat 00:1–11 Horcea-Milcu A, Abson DJ, Apetrei CI et al (2019) Values in transforma- tional sustainability science: four perspectives for change. Sustain Sci 14:1425–1437. https ://doi.org/10.1007/s1162 5-019-00656 -1 Huutoniemi K, Klein JT, Bruun H, Hukkinen J (2010) Analyzing inter- disciplinarity: typology and indicators. Res Policy 39(1):79–88 Huutoniemi K, Tapio P (eds) (2014) Transdisciplinary sustainability studies: a heuristic approach. Routledge, Abingdon Hulme M (2011) Meet the humanities. Nat Clim Change 1:177–179 Humphreys P (2004) Extending ourselves: computational science, empir- icism, and scientific method. Oxford University Press, Oxford Inkpen SA, DesRoches CT (2019) Revamping the image of science for the anthropocene. Philos Theor Pract Biol 11(3):1–7 Inkpen S. A., DesRoches C. T. (forthcoming). When ecology needs economics and economics needs ecology: Interdiscipli- nary exchange during the anthropocene. Ethics, Policy and Environment. Isgren E, Jerneck A, O’Byrne D (2017) Pluralism in search of sus- tainability: ethics, knowledge and methodology in sustainability science. Chall Sustain 5(1):2–6 Jacobs JA (2013) In defense of disciplines: Interdisciplinarity and specialization in the research university. University of Chicago Press, Chicago Jahn T, Bergmann M, Keil F (2012) Transdisciplinarity: Between main- streaming and marginalization. Ecol Econ 79:1–10 Jerneck A, Olsson L (2020) Theoretical and methodological plural- ism in sustainability science. In: Mino T, Kudo S (eds) Framing in sustainability science: theoretical and practical approaches. Springer, Singapore, pp 17–33 Jerneck A, Olsson L, Ness B, Anderberg S, Baier M, Clark E, Hickler T, Hornborg A, Kronsell A, Lövbrand E, Persson J (2011) Struc- turing sustainability science. Sustain Sci 6(1):69–82 Jetzkowitz J, van Koppen CK, Lidskog R, Ott K, Voget-Kleschin L, Wong CML (2018) The significance of meaning. Why IPBES needs the social sciences and humanities. Innovation. Eur J Soc Sci Res 31(sup1):38–60 Kates RW (2011) What kind of a science is sustainability science? Proc Natl Acad Sci 108(49):19449–19450 Kates RW, Clark WC, Corell R, Hall JM, Jaeger CC, Lowe I, McCarthy JJ, Schellnhuber HJ, Bolin B, Dickson NM, Faucheux S (2001) Sustainability science. Science 292(5517):641–642 Kitcher P (1993) The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. Oxford University Press, Oxford Klein JT (2010) A taxonomy of interdisciplinarity. The Oxford hand- book of interdisciplinarity. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 15–30 Koskinen I, Mäki U (2016) Extra-academic transdisciplinarity and sci- entific pluralism: what might they learn from one another? Eur J Philos Sci 6(3):419–444 Koskinen AVI, Rolin KH (2019) Scientific/intellectual movements remedying epistemic injustice: the case of indigenous studies. Philos Sci 86(5):1052–1063 Lang DJ, Wiek A, Bergmann M, Stauffacher M, Martens P, Moll P, Swilling M, Thomas CJ (2012) Transdisciplinary research in sus- tainability science: practice, principles, and challenges. Sustain Sci 7(1):25–43 Laplane L, Mantovani P, Adolphs R, Chang H, Mantovani A, McFall- Ngai M, Rovelli C, Sober E, Pradeu T (2019) Opinion: why sci- ence needs philosophy. PNAS 116(10):3948–3952 Lattuca LR (2001) Creating interdisciplinarity: interdisciplinary research and teaching among college and university faculty. Vanderbilt University Press, Nashville Leahey E, Beckman CM, Stanko TL (2017) Prominent but less produc- tive: the impact of interdisciplinarity on scientists’ research. Adm Sci Q 62(1):105–139 Livoreil B, Glanville J, Haddaway NR, Bayliss H, Bethel A, de Lachapelle FF, Robalino S, Savilaakso S, Zhou W, Petrokofsky G, Frampton G (2017) Systematic searching for environmental evidence using multiple tools and sources. Environ Evid 6(1):23 Luederitz C, Schapke N, Wiek A, Lang DJ, Bergmann M, Bos JJ, Burch S, Davies A, Evans J, Konig A, Farrelly MA, Forrest N, Frantzeskaki N, Gibson RB, Kay B, Loorbach D, McCormick K, Parodi O, Rauschmayer F, Schneidewind U, Stauffacher M, Stelzer F, Trencher G, Venjakob J, Vergragt PJ, von Wehrden H, Westley FR (2016) Learning through evaluation: a tentative evaluative scheme for sustainability transition experiments. J Clean Prod 169:61–76 https://doi.org/10.1038/s41893-019-0290-6 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11625-019-00656-1 1817Sustainability Science (2020) 15:1807–1817 1 3 Longino HE (1990) Science as social knowledge: values and objectiv- ity in scientific inquiry. Princeton University Press, Princeton MacKenzie DA, Muniesa F, Siu L (eds) (2007) Do economists make markets? On the performativity of economics. Princeton Univer- sity Press, Princeton MacLeod M (2018) What makes interdisciplinarity difficult? Some consequences of domain specificity in interdisciplinary practice. Synthese 195(2):697–720 MacLeod M, Nagatsu M (2016) Model coupling in resource econom- ics: conditions for effective interdisciplinary collaboration. Philos Sci 83:412–433 MacLeod M, Nagatsu M (2018) What does interdisciplinarity look like in practice: mapping interdisciplinarity and its limits in the environmental sciences. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part A 67:74–84 Mennes J (2019) Putting multidisciplinarity (back) on the map. Eur J Philos Sci 10:1–23 Miller TR, Wiek A, Sarewitz D, Robinson J, Olsson L, Kriebel D, Loorbach D (2014) The future of sustainability science: a solu- tions-oriented research agenda. Sustain Sci 9(2):239–246 Mitchell SD (2009) Unsimple truths: science, complexity, and policy. University of Chicago Press, Chicago Nicholson DJ, Dupré J (2018) Everything flows: towards a processual philosophy of biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford Nelson M, Vucetich J (2012) Sustainability science: ethical foundations and emerging challenges. Nat Educ Knowl 3(10):12 Ness B (2013) Sustainability science: progress made and directions forward. Chall Sustain 1(1):27–28 Norström AV, Cvitanovic C, Löf MF et  al (2020) Principles for knowledge co-production in sustainability research. Nat Sustain 3:182–190 Ostrom E, Janssen MA, Anderies JM (2007) Going beyond panaceas. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 104(39):15176–15178 Parker WS (2010) Comparative process tracing and climate change fingerprints. Philos Sci 77(5):1083–1095 Persson J, Hornborg A, Olsson L, Thorén H (2018) Toward an alterna- tive dialogue between the social and natural sciences. Ecol Soc 23(4):14. https ://doi.org/10.5751/ES-10498 -23041 4 Phillipson J, Lowe P, Bullock JM (2009) Navigating the social sciences: interdisciplinarity and ecology. J Appl Ecol 46(2):261–264 Pohl C (2011) What is progress in transdisciplinary research? Futures 43(6):618–626 Putnam H (2002) The collapse of the fact/value dichotomy and other essays. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Reiss J, Kitcher P (2009) Biomedical research, neglected diseases, and well-ordered science. THEORIA Revista de Teor ́ıa, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 24(3):263–282 Robinson B, Gonnerman C, O’Rourke M (2019) Experimental philoso- phy of science and philosophical differences across the sciences. Philos Sci 86(3):551–576 Schneider F, Kläy A, Zimmermann AB et al (2019) How canscience support the 2030 Agenda for Sustainable Development? Four tasks to tackle the normative dimension of sustainability. Sustain Sci 14:1593–1604. https ://doi.org/10.1007/s1162 5-019-00675 -y Schubert C (2017) Green nudges: do they work? Are they ethi- cal? Ecol Econ 132:329–342. https ://doi.org/10.1016/j.ecole con.2016.11.009 (ISSN 0921-8009) Shahadu H (2016) Towards an umbrella science of sustainability. Sustain Sci 11(5):777–788. https ://doi.org/10.1007/s1162 5-016-0375-3 Spangenberg JH (2011) Sustainability science: a review, an analysis and some empirical lessons. Environ Conserv 38(3):275–287 Star SL, Griesemer JR (1989) Institutional ecology, ‘translations’ and boundary objects: amateurs and professionals in Berkeley’s Museum of Vertebrate Zoology, 1907–39. Soc Stud Sci 19(3):387–420 Steel D (2008) Across the boundaries: extrapolation in biology and social science. Oxford University Press, Oxford Steel D (2010) A new approach to argument by analogy: extrapolation and chain graphs. Philos Sci 77(5):1058–1069 Steel D (2015) Philosophy and the precautionary principle: science, evidence, and environmental policy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK Stich S (2018) The quest for the boundaries of morality. In: Jones K, Timmons M, Zimmerman A (eds) The Routledge handbook of moral epistemology. Taylor and Francis Group, New York Stojanovic M (2019) Conceptualization of ecological management: practice, frameworks and philosophy. J Agric Environ Ethics 32(3):431–446 Strunz S (2012) Is conceptual vagueness an asset? Arguments from philosophy of science applied to the concept of resilience. Ecol Econ 76:112–118 Tengö M, Hill R, Malmer P, Raymond CM, Spierenburg M, Danielsen F, Elmqvist T, Folke C (2017) Weaving knowledge systems in IPBES, CBD and beyond—lessons learned for sustainability. Curr Opin Environ Sustain 26:17–25 Thorén H (2014) Resilience as a unifying concept. Int Stud Philos Sci 28(3):303–324 Thorén H (2020) Against general resilience. In: Burayidi MA (ed) Routledge handbook of urban resilience. Routledge, Abingdon, pp 26–34 Thorén H, Breian L (2016) Stepping stone or stumbling block? Mode 2 knowledge production in sustainability science. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part C Stud Hist Philos Biolo Biomed Sci 56:71–81 Thorén H, Persson J (2013) The philosophy of interdisciplinarity: sustainability science and problem-feeding. J Gen Philos Sci 44(2):337–355 Turner S (2019) Beyond the academic ethic. In: Cannizzo F, Osbaldis- ton N (eds) The social structures of global academia. Routledge, Abingdon Vezér M, Bakker A, Keller K, Tuana N (2018) Epistemic and ethi- cal trade-offs in decision analytical modelling. Clim Change 147(1–2):1–10 Voinov A, Shugart HH (2013) ‘Integronsters’, integral and integrated modeling. Environ Model Softw 39:149–158 Whitbeck C (2011) Ethics in engineering practice and research. Cam- bridge University Press, Cambridge Wiek A, Withycombe L, Redman CL (2011) Key competencies in sus- tainability: a reference framework for academic program devel- opment. Sustain Sci 6:203–218 Wiek A, Farioli F, Fukushi K, Yarime M (2012) Sustainability science: bridging the gap between science and society. Sustain Sci 7(1):1–4 Williams B (1985) Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Fontana Press, London Wimsatt WC (2007) Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: Piecewise approximations to reality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Winsberg E (2018) Philosophy and Climate Science. Cambridge Uni- versity Press, Cambridge. https ://doi.org/10.1017/97811 08164 290 Yegros-Yegros A, Rafols I, D’Este P (2015) Does interdisciplinary research lead to higher citation impact? The different effect of proximal and distal interdisciplinarity. PloS one 10(8):e0135095 Zeiss R, Van Egmond S (2010) Modeling for policy: science-based models as performative boundary objects for Dutch policy mak- ing. Sci Stud 23(1):58–78 Zeiss R, Van Egmond S (2014) Dissolving decision making? Models and their roles in decision-making processes and policy at large. Sci Context 27(4):631–657 Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. https://doi.org/10.5751/ES-10498-230414 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11625-019-00675-y https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ecolecon.2016.11.009 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ecolecon.2016.11.009 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11625-016-0375-3 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11625-016-0375-3 https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108164290 https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108164290 Philosophy of science for sustainability science Abstract Introduction What is sustainability science? Epistemological issues: methodology, inter- and trans-disciplinarity, and science policy Rethinking the scope and character of methodologies in sustainability science Inter-disciplinarity and trans-disciplinarity Social epistemology and science policy Conceptual work for sustainability science Normativity and values in sustainability science Conclusion Acknowledgements References