Brit. ]. Phil. Sci. 40 (1989), 69-76 Printed in Great Britain Simultaneity, Conventionality and Existence* VESSELIN PETKOV ABSTRACT The present paper pursues two aims. First to show that the experiment proposed by Stolakis [1986] does not lead to absolute synchronization in a single frame of reference and therefore also to the measurement of one-way velocity of light. Second, by consecutively considering the problems of the conventionality of simultaneity and of existence to show that the simultaneity of distant events can be a matter of convention only in a four-dimensional world. 1 Introduction 2 Has the Conventionality of Simultaneity Been Refuted? 3 On the Essence of the Conventionality of Simultaneity I INTRODUCTION There have been three changes in the history of the idea of simultaneity. It has changed for the first time in the 17th century after Romer had shown that light propagated with extreme velocity. It was then clearly realized that the events we observe simultaneously at a given moment of time have in actual fact taken place at different previous moments. The idea of simultaneity was changed for the second time when the theory of relativity showed that simultaneity was not absolute, that there is meaning in speaking of the simultaneity of any events only as regards a given reference frame (or observer). The third change of view on simultaneity is connected with the elucidation of the fact that even as regards a single reference system the definition of the simultaneity of events is not absolute but is a matter of convention. The present paper is devoted precisely to elucidating the essence of the conventionality of simultaneity. The problem of the conventionality of simultaneity already stemmed from Einstein and Reichenbach and chiefly boils down to the following. Two distant clocks at the respective points A and B in a single frame of reference must be synchronized. At moment t\ a light signal is emitted from point A, is reflected * I am grateful to the anonymous referees for their useful suggestions on an earlier version of this paper. a t C o n co rd ia U n ive rsity o n Ju n e 2 8 , 2 0 1 1 b jp s.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://bjps.oxfordjournals.org/ 70 Vesselin Petkov on point B at moment £2 and returns to point A at moment (3. The times tA and 13 are measured by the clock at point A, while the time t\ is measured at point B. The question is: is there an objective criterion on the basis of which it can be determined which moment t\ of the interval (£A, t\) is simultaneous with the moment of reflection of the light signal at point B, i.e. with the moment tA? The different possibilities of this are expressed in the formula: in which 0 < e < l . . H o w e v e r , it appears that in the attempt to establish this moment, i.e. in the attempt to determine the 'real' value of e, a logical circle is obtained (Reichenbach [1958]): if we try to synchronize the clocks at points A and B by light signals we must know the one-way velocity of light; but in order to measure it the clocks should have been synchronized beforehand. The situation in the attempt to synchronize the clocks by slow transport of a third clock is analogous. This situation shows that it is not possible to determine the value of e by means of a physical experiment, i.e. it is impossible to establish which events are simultaneous at a given moment of time even as regards a single system of reference. From this the conclusion is drawn that determining simultaneous events is a matter of convention, from which it follows in particular that the answer to the question: are the back and forth velocities of light one and the same, also proves to be conventional. The latter conclusion appears to arouse the strongest instinctive resistance, because it contradicts the statement considered as an obvious one that in reality light travels at an exactly determined velocity. If this is so, we should be able to measure its velocity in one way. This dissatisfaction with the conventionality of simultaneity probably explains why ideas on measuring one-way velocity of light are persistently suggested. 2 HAS THE CONVENTIONALITY OF SIMULTANEITY BEEN REFUTED? One of the most recent suggestions for an experimental solution of the problem of the conventionality of simultaneity was made by Stolakis [1986]. The aim pursued crossed the one factually achieved. The author's efforts were directed to proposing an experimental way of measuring one-way velocity oflight, thus showing the inconsistency of the conventionality thesis. Actually, however, he proposes an experiment which had no relation to the conventionality of simultaneity but could serve to discover a possible anisotropy of spacetime in a space-like direction. The essence of the experiment proposed by Stolakis would be revealed by a more thorough analysis of the standard schema of synchronizing the clocks A and B, distant in space, set forth in Part 1. Figure 1-a shows the world lines A and B of the two clocks (at rest as regards one another) and the world line of the a t C o n co rd ia U n ive rsity o n Ju n e 2 8 , 2 0 1 1 b jp s.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://bjps.oxfordjournals.org/ Simultaneity, Conventionality and Existence t A tB { A M A B A B (a) (b) Figure 1 (c) light ray propagating between them. In standard synchronization ( E = 1 / 2 ) event R (reflecting the light ray from clock B) is simultaneous with event M. In this case space is orthogonal to the world lines of the clocks and the velocity of the back and forth light signal is one and the same. In any other choice of e (in the limits 0 < s < 1) space is not orthogonal to the world lines of clocks A and B and the velocity of the back and forth light ray is different. Therefore velocity of light in a straight direction is different from velocity in the opposite direction, owing to the fact that space is not orthogonal to A and B. This conclusion is only correct, however, if a premise (usually understood) is fulfilled, namely that space-time is isotropic. In this case (depicted in Figure 1-a) the slant (in relation to A and B) of the world line of the light ray propagating from clock A to B is equal to the slant of the world line of the light ray from B to A, i.e. the angle a,- is equal to the angle /?,-. But if space-time is anisotropic in a space-like direction (see Figure 1-b) the slant (in relation to A and B) of the world line of the light ray, propagating from clock A to clock B can be larger than the slant of the world line of the light ray, propagating from B to A, i.e. the angle 1). In this case, owing to the isotrophy of space-time, the light signals arrive simultaneously with event C2. However, this is no proof that back and forth velocity of light is one and the same, because we a t C o n co rd ia U n ive rsity o n Ju n e 2 8 , 2 0 1 1 b jp s.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://bjps.oxfordjournals.org/ Simultaneity, Conventionality and Existence 73 M N M N (b) Figure 2 can again choose to have space not orthogonal to the time axis which will lead to different values of back and forth velocity. We have no criterion (and the Stolakis experiment does not give us one) which would force us to choose space in such a way as to have events M and N occur simultaneously in it. Only if we consider events M and N as simultaneous (i.e. as being privileged in comparison with the remaining events on the world lines on which events M and N lie) could it be asserted that the one-way velocity of light has been found. The simultaneous arrival of light rays at the initial point from which they were emitted is proof alone of the fact that space-time is isotropic in a space-like direction. Figure 2-b depicts the Stolakis experiment in a case of anisotropic space- time in a space-like direction. In the case, the light signals emitted at event Ci and respectively reflected in events M and N will not arrive simultaneously at their point of emission. The reason for the non-simultaneous arrival of the light signals (i.e. the appearance of the time difference tc2c3) is, however, due solely to the anisotrophy of space-time. Even now the definition of back and forth velocity of light is a matter of convention, because once again the criterion for the simultaneity of events M and N has not been discovered. The only fact which can be established by the Stolakis experiment is whether space-time is anisotropic in a space-like direction. a t C o n co rd ia U n ive rsity o n Ju n e 2 8 , 2 0 1 1 b jp s.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://bjps.oxfordjournals.org/ 74 Vesselin Petkov Yet even if the problem of the isotropy of space-time is solved, the problem of the conventionality of simultaneity remains untouched. Thus the Stolakis experiment has no relation to the problem of the conventionality of simultaneity. The analysis of this experiment shows once again the impossibi- lity in principle of measuring one-way velocity of light and therefore of rejecting the thesis of the conventionality of simultaneity. 3 ON THE ESSENCE OF THE CONVENTIONALITY OF SIMULTANEITY The discussion on the problem of the conventionality of simultaneity would hardly have continued so long if it had been considered in close connection with the problem of existence. The joint consideration of both problems makes it possible (1) categorically to establish that the definition of simultaneous events is a matter of convention, and (2) to elucidate the essence of this convention. So that this joint consideration may be realized, from now onwards simultaneously at the present moment of time will be implicit in the use of the term simultaneity. According to the classical (pre-relativistic) view of reality only the present exists, i.e. only the constantly changing three-dimensional world at the moment 'now'. But bearing in mind the fact that the present (the three- dimensional world) is a set of simultaneous events at the present moment (i.e. the set of material objects existing simultaneously at the moment 'now') it follows that the simultaneity of events is an objective fact. Therefore, the objectivity of simultaneity is expressed in the circumstance that simultaneous events occur simultaneously, i.e. that the objects with which these events take place exist simultaneously. It is precisely the existence at the moment 'now' which objectively privileges one class of events. As is apparent a conventionality of simultaneity in this case obviously leads to an unacceptable conclusion regarding a conventionality also connected with what exists (R. Weingard [1972] says that if two events are real, their simultaneity cannot be a matter of convention). Therefore, according to the classical view of reality, simultaneous events at the present moment of time (i.e. present events) are objectively privileged in comparison with past and future events (since only present events are considered as existing), which means that simultaneity is not conventional. However, things look quite different from the point of view of the theory of relativity. The problem is additionally complicated by the fact that the problem of the dimensionality of the world has not been convincingly solved to this day. If we allow that even according to the special theory of relativity reality is a three-dimensional world (a three-dimensional space-like slice of the Min- kowski world—the present), the above-mentioned unacceptable conventiona- lity as regards what exists follows from the conventionality of simultaneity. Therefore reality cannot be a three-dimensional world if the definition of a t C o n co rd ia U n ive rsity o n Ju n e 2 8 , 2 0 1 1 b jp s.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://bjps.oxfordjournals.org/ Simultaneity, Conventionality and Existence 75 simultaneity is a matter of convention, because if it could; it follows that it will depend on our own will which three-dimensional space-like slice of the Minkowski world we are to consider as reality. This unacceptable conclusion is reached on the basis of the premises of the conventionality of simultaneity and the three-dimensionality of reality. It can only be avoided if we give up one of the premises. The impossibility of demonstrating by means of a physical experiment the privileged state (existence) of only one set of events which are to be considered as simultaneous at the present moment (i.e. the impossibility of refuting the conventionality thesis of simultaneity), shows that the premise of the three-dimensionality of the world should be abandoned. This conclusion also follows directly from the relativity of simultaneity. The fact that the observers in relative motion have different classes of simultaneous events shows that not a single class is objectively privileged. Therefore all events are equally real (Putnam [1967]), which means that it really is a question of convention which events should be considered as simultaneous for a given observer. In the contrary case—if any observer has objective grounds to examine as simultaneous exactly defined events—this would mean that, being objectively privileged, these events would be simultaneous for all observers in relative motion. In such a case, however, the relativity of simultaneity proves to be impossible. That is why it (the relativity of simultaneity) unambiguously shows that the simultaneity of distant events is conventional (from which it follows that the world cannot be three-dimensional). If we deny the view that the world is three-dimensional and consider the Minkowski world as a mathematical model of a real four-dimensional world, conventionality in the choice of a three-dimensional space-like slice of this world becomes trivial, because all slices are equally existent and the matter only concerns the convenience of which slice is to be examined as the present. In other words, since all events in a four-dimensional world exist in the same way the conventionality of simultaneity does not also lead to conventionality of existence, but is connected only with the description of the four-dimensional world in our habitual 'three-dimensional language'. The elucidation of this situation reveals the profound essence of the conventionality of simultaneity: we cannot choose one class of events among the events of the Minkowski world simply because there is no such a class of objectively priviledged events (owing to the equal existence of all events), which we might examine as simultaneous at the moment 'now'. It can now be said that the logical circle obtained in an attempt to imagine an experiment enabling us to define which events are simultaneous at a given moment of time, or to establish the one-way velocity of light, convincingly shows that we have tried, on the basis of an erroneous view of the dimensionality of the world to discover the objective content of concepts (as simultaneity and velocity), for which it appears that they have no such content according to a more adequate view of reality. This explains why the a t C o n co rd ia U n ive rsity o n Ju n e 2 8 , 2 0 1 1 b jp s.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://bjps.oxfordjournals.org/ 76 Vesselin Petkov conventionality of simultaneity does not presuppose some kind of 'agreements' concerning physical magnitudes as to which we have been intuitively convinced that they have an exactly defined objective content. And, indeed, the concepts simultaneity and velocity have no adequate content, because among the equally existing events of the four-dimensional world there is no set of events which are privileged as being simultaneous (at the present moment). We can speak of simultaneity and velocity only after the stratification of the four- dimensional world, i.e. of space-time, into space and time. However, this stratification has no objective basis (space-time is not really divided into space and time precisely because of the equal existence of all events), but is the result solely of a description of the four-dimensional world in 'three-dimensional language'. Owing to this reason it is obvious that it is indeed a matter of convention as to how to stratify space-time into space and time (of course, within the framework of the requirement 0 < e < 1). Only in this case, when we have chosen that space should be orthogonal to the time axis (i.e. with e = 1/2 and with isotropic space-time) the back and forth velocity of light is one and the same. Depending on the manner in which we shall stratify space-time into space and time (i.e. depending on the choice of e) different values of back and forth velocity of light will be obtained and the experiment will always confirm (in the supposed isotropy of space-time) the theoretically foretold result, simply because in processing the experimental data the premise on the choice of e is essentially made use of. That is why all attempts to measure one-way velocity of light are doomed to failure beforehand. Institute of Philosophy, Sofia REFERENCES PUTNAM, H. [1967]: 'Time and Physical Geometry', Journal of Philosophy, 64, pp. 2 4 0 - 7. REICHENBACH, H. [1957]: The Philosophy of Space and Time. Dover. STOLAKIS, G. [1986]: 'Against Conventionalism in Physics', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 37, pp. 2 2 9 - 3 2 . WEINGARD, R. [1972]: 'Relativity and the Reality of Past and Future Events'. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 2 3 , pp. 1 1 9 - 2 1 . WINNIE, J. [1970]: 'Special Relativity Without One-Way Velocity Assumptions', Philosophy of Science, 37, pp. 81- 99; 2 2 3 - 3 8 . a t C o n co rd ia U n ive rsity o n Ju n e 2 8 , 2 0 1 1 b jp s.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://bjps.oxfordjournals.org/